17
This article was downloaded by: [University of Sussex Library] On: 18 August 2014, At: 07:33 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK International Studies in the Philosophy of Science Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cisp20 Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Reza Maleeh & Parisa Amani Published online: 23 Apr 2014. To cite this article: Reza Maleeh & Parisa Amani (2013) Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27:4, 353-367, DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2013.868182 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2013.868182 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms- and-conditions

Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

  • Upload
    parisa

  • View
    212

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

This article was downloaded by: [University of Sussex Library]On: 18 August 2014, At: 07:33Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registeredoffice: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

International Studies in the Philosophyof SciencePublication details, including instructions for authors andsubscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cisp20

Pragmatism, Bohr, and the CopenhagenInterpretation of Quantum MechanicsReza Maleeh & Parisa AmaniPublished online: 23 Apr 2014.

To cite this article: Reza Maleeh & Parisa Amani (2013) Pragmatism, Bohr, and the CopenhagenInterpretation of Quantum Mechanics, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27:4,353-367, DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2013.868182

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2013.868182

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the“Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis,our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as tothe accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinionsand views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Contentshould not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sourcesof information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims,proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever orhowsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arisingout of the use of the Content.

This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Anysubstantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms &Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

Page 2: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

Pragmatism, Bohr, and theCopenhagen Interpretationof Quantum MechanicsReza Maleeh and Parisa Amani

In this article, we argue that although Bohr’s version of the Copenhagen interpretation is

in line with several key elements of logical positivism, pragmatism is the closest approxi-

mation to a classification of the Copenhagen interpretation, whether or not pragmatists

directly influenced the key figures of the interpretation. Pragmatism already encompasses

important elements of operationalism and logical positivism, especially the liberalized

Carnapian reading of logical positivism. We suggest that some elements of the Copenha-

gen interpretation, which are in line with logical positivism, are also supported by prag-

matism. Some of these elements are empirical realism, fallibilism, holism, and

instrumentalism. However, pragmatism goes beyond logical positivism in espousing

some other key elements of the Copenhagen interpretation, though imperfectly, such as

the correspondence principle, complementarity, and indeterminism.

1. Introduction

Mostly, Niels Bohr, Werner Heisenberg, and Max Born are considered the initiators of

the Copenhagen interpretation, though they never used the term as a name for their

shared ideas. Like logical positivism and pragmatism, the Copenhagen interpretation

is not a unified idea and the views of the initiators changed over time. This article is

concerned with Bohr’s ideas on the Copenhagen interpretation subsequent to the Ein-

stein–Podolski–Rosen (EPR) article.

Bohr thought of quantum mechanics as a generalization of classical physics, even

though quantum mechanics violates some of the fundamental ontological principles

Reza Maleeh is at the School of History, Philosophy, Religion and Classics, University of Queensland. Correspon-

dence to: School of History, Philosophy, Religion and Classics, University of Queensland, St Lucia, QLD 4072,

Australia. E-mail: [email protected]. Parisa Amani is at the Department of Physical Chemistry, Khajeh Nasir

Toosi University of Technology. Correspondence to: Department of Physical Chemistry, Khajeh Nasir Toosi

University of Technology, P.O. Box 16315-1618, Tehran, Iran. E-mail: [email protected]

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 2013Vol. 27, No. 4, 353–367, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2013.868182

© 2014 Open Society Foundation

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 3: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

on which classical physics rested. Bohr’s semi-classical atomic model, presented in

1913, violated the principles of continuity and determinism. The principle of continu-

ity holds that there are necessarily intervening states between every distinguished

initial and final states, through which all processes have to go. According to Bohr’s

semi-classical model, by contrast, there is no definite intermediate place through

which the electron passes in its transition from one orbit to another. In classical

physics, the principle of determinism claims that the earlier state of a system uniquely

determines the later state of that system. In Bohr’s model, however, transition between

orbits (between the ground state and an exited state) takes place based on intrinsic

chance, making it impossible to predict when the transition occurs.

Between 1913 and 1925, the above atomic model was subject to some improvement.

However, it ran into problems when one tried to apply it to spectra other than that of

hydrogen. By 1925, Heisenberg had formulated a consistent quantum mechanics,

replacing Bohr’s model by a non-classical model with the aid of principles of

quantum mechanics. However, Bohr and Heisenberg never totally agreed on how to

interpret and understand the mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics as

well as certain atomic phenomena. This is why there is no homogenous Copenhagen

interpretation. In this article, by the term ‘Copenhagen interpretation’ we refer to

Bohr’s post-EPR ideas on indeterminism, his correspondence principle, his comple-

mentarity interpretation of certain atomic phenomena, and Born’s statistical interpret-

ation of the wave function.

During the last few decades, much has been written on Bohr’s interpretation of

quantum mechanics. Some philosophers and scientists have depicted it as a positiv-

istic, subjectivistic, or operationalist philosophy. As Jan Faye (2008) puts it, today phi-

losophers have reached a consensus that Bohr’s philosophy is neither positivistic nor

subjectivistic, although it may contain some elements of these two schools. In this

article, we compare the elements shared between the Copenhagen interpretation

and logical positivism on the one hand and the Copenhagen interpretation and prag-

matism on the other. Then we will conclude that while there are positivistic and oper-

ationalist components in pragmatism, pragmatism goes beyond other schools in

supporting the Copenhagen interpretation, especially when it comes to ‘complemen-

tarity’ as the core of Bohr’s version of the Copenhagen interpretation.1

Like the Copenhagen interpretation, logical positivism and pragmatism are not

unified ideas. Within each school, apart from the change of thinkers’ views over

time, thinkers differed from one another, often sharply. By ‘logical positivism’, we

mostly mean the ideas shared among the left wing of the Vienna Circle, which

included Otto Neurath, Hans Hahn, Phillip Frank, and Rudolf Carnap. What the thin-

kers in the left wing shared was the rejection of radical verificationism, initiated by

Carnap in the mid-1930s. Such a significant change in the left wing’s position is

known as the ‘liberalization of empiricism’, the core of which is what Carnap (1937)

dubbed the principle of tolerance.

For Charles Sanders Peirce and William James, the core of pragmatism is the prag-

matic maxim, according to which the contents of hypotheses are clarified by their

‘practical consequences’. Christopher Hookway (2008) distinguishes two senses of

354 R. Maleeh and P. Amani

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 4: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

pragmatism: a narrow sense and a wide sense. The narrow sense refers to Peirce’s prag-

matic maxim (or Peirce’s principle) and to those who embrace such a principle. Peirce

and James count as pragmatists in the narrow sense. However, pragmatism can be

thought of as a tradition embracing thinkers somewhat sceptical of the maxim and

its application while holding a set of philosophical views and approaches that are

characteristic of pragmatism. Such thinkers are pragmatists in the wider sense.

In this article, we will deal with certain key elements of the thought of Peirce and

with aspects of James’s thought that are in line with those elements, that is, the prag-

matic maxim, instrumentalism, and tychism, according to which there is an objective

feature of spontaneous chance activity in nature free from the exact and necessary dic-

tates of mechanical laws. By the term ‘pragmatists’, then, we refer to those who endorse

such elements.

Section 2 deals with the shared elements between the three schools, that is, the

Copenhagen interpretation, logical positivism, and pragmatism. As stated above,

pragmatism goes beyond logical positivism in supporting the Copenhagen interpret-

ation philosophically, having more elements in common with the Copenhagen

interpretation. In section 3, we discuss such an idea. In section 4, then, we conclude

that pragmatism is the closest approximation to a philosophical classification of the

Copenhagen interpretation.

2. Shared Concepts

In what follows, we try to pin down the shared ideas between the three schools: ideas

on empirical reality and weak objectivity, fallibilism, holism, and instrumentalism.

2.1. Empirical Reality and Weak Objectivity

One of the key elements of the Copenhagen interpretation is its commitment to the

notion of ‘weak objectivity’. Weak objectivity holds that, when faced by a specified

experimental set-up, scientists can unambiguously agree on what can and what

cannot happen (Lindley 1996, 159–160). The view advocates an empirical reality

that is not independent of the observer, but is the same for all observers. In other

words, empirical reality is the reality that cannot be separated from experience and

depends on subjects in order to have the weak objectivity characterized by intersubjec-

tivity. Empirical reality rejects the concept of ‘thing in itself ’ as meaningless. For Bohr,

‘objective’ means ‘intersubjectively valid’ as distinct from the object’s pre-existing

properties (Murdoch 1987, 105). According to Bohr, the

description of atomic phenomena has in these respects a perfectly objective charac-ter, in the sense that no explicit reference is made to any individual observer and thattherefore, with proper regard to relativistic exigencies, no ambiguity is involved inthe communication of information. (Bohr 1963, 3)

According to Aage Petersen, Bohr holds that ‘there is no quantum world. There is only

an abstract quantum physical description. It is wrong to think that the task of physics

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 355

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 5: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

is to find out how nature is. Physics concerns what we can say about nature’ (Petersen

1963, 9). We will come back to the notion of empirical reality in section 2.3.

Logical positivism takes a similar attitude. The most distinguishing doctrine of the

members of the Vienna Circle was the ‘verifiability principle’ as a criterion for the

meaningfulness of statements. Logical positivists divided all meaningful statements

into two classes: analytic a priori and synthetic a posteriori. The former are true or

false in virtue of their logical forms or their meaning, whereas the truth or falsity of

the latter is ascertained only by means of experience. Thus, the synthetic statements

of the empirical sciences are cognitively meaningful if they are testable in some

sense. This way construed, statements whose truth or falsity is not in their logical

forms or meaning and which are not experimentally testable are considered

meaningless.

Logical positivism holds that all metaphysical and normative moral claims would

count as meaningless as well as statements about a ‘thing in itself ’, as there is no

way to test them experimentally in principle. In this regard, A. J. Ayer states that

the ‘originality of the logical positivists lay in their making the impossibility of meta-

physics depend not upon the nature of what could be known but upon the nature of

what could be said’ (Ayer 1959, 11). This is very close to Bohr’s attitude quoted earlier.

With regard to the meaningfulness of statements, Ayer proposes that

a sentence is factually significant to any given person, if, and only if, he knows howto verify the proposition which it purports to express, that is, if he knows whatobservations would lead him, under certain conditions, to accept the propositionas being true, or reject it as being false. (Ayer 1952, 35)

Then Ayer proceeds with more clarifications about factual propositions. According to

him, the mark of a genuine factual proposition is that, in conjunction with certain

other premises, some experiential propositions can be deduced from it, the experien-

tial propositions being not in principle deducible from those other premises alone

(Ayer 1952, 38–39). The proponents of such a view are regarded as the advocates of

‘experimental reality’, meaning that repeating an experimental procedure leads to

observing the same phenomena. As stated above, this is the view that logical positivism

advocates.

Later, logical positivism faced serious criticism regarding the impossibility of exact

verifiability of a statement. Carnap was one of the key figures of the Vienna Circle who

first noticed the impotence of verifiability. Through his ‘liberalization of empiricism’,

he substituted ‘verification’ for ‘degrees of confirmation’.2

Pragmatism also espouses the ideas of empirical reality and weak objectivity. For

Peirce and James, the core of pragmatism is the ‘pragmatic maxim’, according to

which the contents of a hypothesis can be clarified by means of tracing its practical

consequences. For a perfect clarification of our ideas about any subject, we just

need to know what imaginary practical consequences it can have and what effects

we can expect from it. In other words, for extending a mental conception, we just

need to determine to what behaviour such a conception is supposed to apply. That

behaviour, then, is the unique meaning of that conception for us. In his opinion,

356 R. Maleeh and P. Amani

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 6: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

‘our idea of anything is our idea of its sensible effects’ (Peirce [1878] 1992, sec. 2). In

Peirce’s view, we have no conception of any quality of objects, unless through the con-

ceived effects; for example, there would be a difference between a hard thing and a soft

thing only if they were brought to a test.

According to Peirce, we have to ‘consider what effects, which might conceivably

have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our

conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object’ (Peirce

[1878] 1992, sec. 2). Peirce, like James, embraced the idea of absurdity of a priori onto-

logical metaphysics as well as the absurdity of the concept of the ‘thing in itself ’. He

holds that the application of some conceptions can serve as a barrier to effective inves-

tigation. The pragmatic maxim

will serve to show that almost every proposition of ontological metaphysics is eithermeaningless gibberish—one word being defined by other words, and they by stillothers, without any real conception ever being reached—or else is downrightabsurd. . . . All such rubbish being swept away, what will remain of philosophywill be a series of problems capable of investigation by the observational methodsof the true sciences. . . . So, instead of merely jeering at metaphysics, . . . the pragma-ticist extracts from it a precious essence, which will serve to give life and light to cos-mology and physics. (Peirce 1931–1935, vol. 5, para. 523)

2.2. Fallibilism

Pragmatists advocate ‘fallibilism’, the view that in principle all beliefs and methods

could turn out to be flawed. This doctrine completely dominates Peirce’s thoughts

according to which knowledge is never certain, but is always hypothetical and suscep-

tible to correction. Fallibilism is the acceptance of the idea that since our experimental

knowledge can be altered and reconsidered by later observations, it may be that all our

current knowledge is false.

Regarding the reconsideration of our experimental knowledge, Peirce proposes that

nothing is vital for science; nothing can be. Its accepted propositions, therefore, arebut opinions at most; and the whole list is provisional. The scientific man is not inthe least wedded to his conclusions. He risks nothing upon them. He stands ready toabandon one or all as soon as experience opposes them. (Peirce 1931–1935, vol. 1,para. 635)

Bohr and logical positivists both conceded fallibilism, though they never used the

term. The Copenhagen interpretation regards theories as tools that are subject to

alteration or replacement with more practical theories with respect to the investigation

purposes and goals.3

In a similar manner, Carnap believed in the openness of scientific statements. In

1937, he remarked that there was no statement (even mathematical) immune to altera-

tion and modification:

No rule of the physical language is definitive; all rules are laid down with the reser-vation that they may be altered as soon as it seems expedient to do so. This appliesnot only to the P-rules but also to the L-rules, including those of mathematics. In

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 357

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 7: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

this respect, there are only differences in degree; certain rules are more difficult torenounce than others. (Carnap 1937, 318)

‘L-rules’ and ‘P-rules’ refer to ‘logical rules’ and ‘empirical rules’, respectively.

2.3. Wholeness and Holism

After the EPR article, Bohr gave up speaking of ‘disturbance’ in relation to the

‘uncertainty principle’, since the notion seemed to indicate that elementary particles

were classical particles with definite inherent kinematic and dynamic properties. The

post-EPR Bohr also gave up using the notion of complementary descriptions in

favour of complementary phenomena or information. ‘Phenomena’ in Bohr’s

mature view refer to experimentally observed effects of quantum objects upon

measuring instruments, not to the physical space–time properties of such objects

themselves or their behaviour. The representations of such interactions between

quantum objects and measuring instruments would then be describable and inter-

subjectively communicable in terms of classical concepts. A ‘phenomenon’ is a

measurement of the values of complementary properties that requires a complete

description of the entire experimental set-up. By using the new concepts, Bohr

emphasizes ‘the impossibility of any sharp separation between the behavior of

atomic objects and the interaction with the measuring instruments which serve to

define the conditions under which the phenomena appear’. Thus, according to

Bohr, phenomena are individual in the sense that ‘any attempt of subdividing the

phenomena will demand a change in the experimental arrangements introducing

new possibilities of interaction between objects and measuring instruments’

(Bohr 1949, 39–40).

Bohr’s notion of individual phenomena in the quantum world indicates his com-

mitment to the notion of ‘wholeness’, according to which, at the quantum level,

quantum objects are inseparable from measuring instruments. It is not possible to sub-

divide Bohr’s individual phenomena. This is the specific characteristic of experimen-

tation in the quantum domain embraced by the Copenhagen interpretation. At a

macrolevel, however, the object under observation and the measuring instrument

can count as separate entities. The notion of wholeness can further be explicated

through the Stern–Gerlach (SG) experiment.

The SG experiment, prepared and carried out by Otto Stern and his junior col-

laborator Walther Gerlach, established experimentally the so-called quantization of

angular momentum and therefore the discreteness of the magnetic moment of

atomic particles. The experiment can also be used to demonstrate the specific

role of measurement in quantum mechanics and the inseparability of quantum

objects from measuring instruments. This is what we are concerned with in this

article.

In the SG experiment, a beam of particles, say electrons, passing through an

inhomogeneous magnetic field is deflected from its initial trajectory. Electrons will

be deflected up or down, showing that they have an intrinsic angular momentum

that takes only certain quantized values, known as their spins.

358 R. Maleeh and P. Amani

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 8: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

Electrons are spin 212 particles, meaning that there are only two possible spin

angular momentum values measured along any axis, +h̄/2 and 2h̄/2. A detector, as

our observation device, will let us observe one of the two possible values, that is,

spin-up or spin-down. This can be shown by the angular momentum quantum

number j.4

Conducting the experiment along the z-axis, the corresponding angular

momentum operator will be Jz. Mathematically, all this can be formulated as follows:

C| l = c1

∣∣C j=+�h

2l + c2

∣∣C j=−�h

2l

Figure 1(a) shows a beam of electrons passing through an SG apparatus along the

z-axis with the blocked spin-down channel, resulting in spin-up detection. If the

spin-up beam of electrons is passed through a second similar SG device, it will be

observed that all electrons come out again in one beam with spin-up electrons.

Figure 1 The Stern–Gerlach experiment: (a) alignment Z+/Z; (b) alignment Z+/X; and (c) alignment Z+/X+/Z.

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 359

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 9: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

Now, as shown in Figure 1(b), if the resulting beam coming out of the first SG appar-

atus is passed through a second SG device with its magnetic field aligned with x, the

outcome will be shocking: two beams of spin-up and spin-down electrons with

equal numbers of electrons are detected as if the first SG apparatus were not present.

In the third scenario, illustrated in Figure 1(c), the spin-down channel of the second

SG device in Figure 1(b) is blocked and the spin-up beam of electrons along the x-axis is

passed through a third SG device with its magnetic field aligned with z. There will again

be a weird outcome: two beams of spin-up and spin-down electrons with equal number

of electrons are detected as if the first and the second SG devices were not present.

The moral of all this is that the behaviour of atomic objects is not separable from the

performance of a well-defined measurement in the presence of a well-defined measur-

ing instrument. In this sense, atomic objects and the measuring instruments are part of

an inseparable whole (wholeness). The notion of wholeness in the Copenhagen

interpretation is not an idea shared with logical positivism and pragmatism.

In a more general manner, however, the notion of wholeness emphasizes the idea of

empirical realism through the notion of (what we call) ‘holism’, the idea that is shared

with logical positivists and pragmatists and will be depicted as follows. Bohr, like

logical positivists and pragmatists, held that physical reality, detached from the

human mind’s perceptual capacities, is not graspable. According to Bohr, we experi-

ence (represent) the real world of external objects through our senses. This reality

exists independently of its being represented. It is the existence of such an objective

real world, common to all experiential subjects, that makes intersubjective communi-

cation possible in an unambiguous way through classical concepts.

However, as Dugald Murdoch puts it, for Bohr, while the truth value of an exper-

imental statement is independent of our knowledge and perception,

it is not also independent of our ability to know or means of knowing its truth-value, since our means of knowing are simply the experimental arrangement andthe measurement procedure which defines the preconditions of the meaningfulassertability of the sentence in question; and the truth-value is not independentof what we do. (Murdoch 1987, 215)

According to this view, Bohr is neither a naive realist nor radical empiricist, but what

we earlier called an empirical realist.5

The empirical realist component present in Bohr’s philosophy, as well as in logical

positivism and pragmatism, leads to a notion of ‘holism’, meaning that we do not have

any idea of something, e.g. a physical entity, unless it affects our senses under well-

defined experimental conditions. This requires that the entity under observation,

the measuring instrument, and the observer be parts of a whole. The way nature

appears to us depends on our investigative method and on the way we set up instru-

ments to observe it. Holism is a view common to all three schools.

2.4. Instrumentalism

Bohr holds a non-realist view when it comes to the applicability of a theory of pure

mathematics to the real physical world, seeing the value of such a theory as primarily

360 R. Maleeh and P. Amani

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 10: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

instrumental. Such a theory would be a useful tool for organizing our observations and

making predictions under well-defined conditions. Bohr is highly sceptical of the view

that the physical world can be uniquely described by some theory of pure mathematics.

By the same token, the mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics, according

to Bohr, does not give us any ‘pictorial’ representation of the world; such a formalism

includes imaginary quantities that do not have any real-world counterparts. While

parts of measuring instruments can be described by means of classical physics, it is

impossible to describe quantum objects in terms of a classical or quantum mechanical

formalism. Quantum formalism is able only to predict the outcome of experiments in

question, but is unable to describe or account for the underlying quantum processes

leading to the observable effects.

The entire formalism is to be considered as a tool for deriving predictions of definiteor statistical character, as regards information obtainable under experimental con-ditions described in classical terms and specified by means of parameters enteringinto the algebraic or differential equations of which the matrices or the wave-func-tions, respectively, are solutions. These symbols themselves, as is indicated alreadyby the use of imaginary numbers, are not susceptible to pictorial interpretation;and even derived real functions like densities and currents are only to be regardedas expressing the probabilities for the occurrence of individual events observableunder well-defined experimental conditions. (Bohr 1948, 144)

Logical positivism has a similar approach to this notion. Logical positivists hold that

scientific theories are just tools for prediction and the knowledge we acquire from

them is limited to what they predict about the observational features of observables.

Scientific theories are instruments that can be replaced by better theories where pre-

ferred. Later Carnap speaks of different language frameworks, suggesting that one

should choose a framework with respect to the specific application and usefulness

of the framework one has in mind. This led to the ‘principle of logical tolerance’,

according to which ‘everyone is free to use the language most suited to his purpose’

(Carnap 1963, 18). Projecting the ‘principle of tolerance’, Carnap emphasizes investi-

gating all practically useful forms, although it is important to distinguish between con-

structive and non-constructive definitions and proofs (Carnap 1963, 49).

Pragmatism endorses a similar idea. James believed that a scientific theory is to be

understood as ‘an instrument: it is designed to achieve a purpose—to facilitate action

or increase understanding’ (James [1907] 1975, 33). Any scientific theory is assessed

based on how well it can be used for the extension of our experiences and it can

reduce those experiences to a judgement and extend and coordinate our experiences.

James criticized the traditional view of early scientists according to which ‘clearness,

beauty, and simplification’ of their theories sufficed to think that they had discovered

the final truth (James [1907] 1975, 31). Indeed, contemporary scientists stress the

practical usefulness of theories.

Thus, no theory is the absolute transcript of reality. Each theory may be useful from

some point of view (James [1907] 1975, 33). For James, this makes concepts and the-

ories instruments whose practical usefulness depends on how well they achieve the

intended goal (Hookway 2008).

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 361

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 11: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

It is seen that the mission that Bohr and James assign to science has nothing to do

with the essence of objects. A scientific theory is to be understood as just an instru-

ment. This idea is in line with the idea projected by logical positivists.6

So far we have proposed a selection of key elements, common between the Copen-

hagen interpretation, logical positivism, and pragmatism. In what follows, it is shown

that there are some other key elements of the Copenhagen interpretation shared only

with pragmatism, not supported by logical positivism.

3. Pragmatism Goes Beyond

In this section, we see how pragmatism goes beyond logical positivism in support of

the Copenhagen interpretation. The following elements are common only between

pragmatism and the Copenhagen interpretation.

3.1. Correspondence Rule

The full correspondence rule indicates that the transition between stationary states in

atoms is permitted if and only if there is a corresponding harmonic component in the

classical motion (Bohr 1972–2008, 479). For Bohr, the rule was required for the con-

struction of a theory of quantum mechanics and further development of it in such a

way that in high quantum numbers it predicts values that are a close approximation to

the values of classical physics: ‘The whole apparatus of the quantum mechanics can be

regarded as a precise formulation of the tendencies embodied in the correspondence

principle’ (Bohr 1925, 49). However, the introduction of the non-classical concept of

spin, which did not have any classical counterpart, was a fatal blow to the correspon-

dence principle. It was not possible to reconcile classical periodic motion presumed by

the correspondence principle with the classically non-describable electron spin.

But Bohr did not give up on the principle, thinking of it as a methodological argu-

ment for establishing a coherent quantum theory. He thought of the principle as a

guideline for Heisenberg’s matrix mechanics:

A fundamental step towards the establishing of a proper quantum mechanics wastaken in 1925 by Heisenberg who showed how to replace the ordinary kinematicalconcepts, in the spirit of the correspondence argument, by symbols referring to theelementary processes and the probability of their occurrence. (Bohr 1937, 48)

Bohr sees the principle as a method whose choice is practically useful as a guide to find

a satisfactory quantum theory. Furthermore, the correspondence principle strengthens

Bohr’s ideas on the significance of classical concepts. Indeed, the rule was based on the

epistemological idea of indispensability of classical concepts in understanding physical

reality. Such an understanding is possible only when classical and quantum phenom-

ena are described in the same classical concepts, so we can practically compare differ-

ent physical experiences.

[T]he necessity of making an extensive use . . . of the classical concepts, upon whichdepends ultimately the interpretation of all experience, gave rise to the formulation

362 R. Maleeh and P. Amani

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 12: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

of the so-called correspondence principle which expresses our endeavors to utilizeall the classical concepts by giving them a suitable quantum-theoretical re-interpret-ation. (Bohr 1934, 8)

To summarize, Bohr claims that the correspondence rule is a methodology that is prac-

tically useful for symbolizing a quantum theory, as a tool. Applying such a rule allows

us to deal with our experiences within the framework of classical concepts which con-

tains theoretical sentences of quantum mechanics and classical physics. So it is fair to

claim that Bohr kept the rule for pragmatic purposes or, in other words, the rule was

kept on the basis of Peirce’s ‘pragmatic maxim’.

3.2. Complementarity

Bohr’s complementarity holds that the ‘space–time descriptions’ of the atom are

complementary to the ‘claims of causality’, where the latter are interpreted in terms

of physics as the conservation of energy and momentum. In other words, we can attri-

bute kinematic and dynamic properties to the atom only by reference to an exper-

imental outcome.

Quantum objects in Bohr’s eyes are indefinable. That is, Heisenberg’s uncertainty

relations set not only a limit to ‘the extent of the information obtainable by measure-

ments, but . . . also . . . a limit to the meaning which we may attribute to such infor-

mation’ (Bohr 1929, 18). Thus, not only cannot the exact position and momentum

of an object be measured simultaneously, but also the object cannot meaningfully be

said to have exact simultaneous values of these observables. According to Bohr, the

properties of simultaneous exact position and exact momentum cannot be meaning-

fully attributed to one and the same object, since the preconditions for the meaningful

attribution of these properties are mutually exclusive:

Indeed we have in each experimental arrangement suited for the study of properquantum phenomena not merely to do with an ignorance of the value of certainphysical quantities, but with the impossibility of defining these quantities in anunambiguous way. (Bohr 1935, 699)

Such preconditions are determined by the experimental arrangement, i.e. a measuring

instrument as a necessary condition for meaningful applicability of the physical con-

cepts. The sufficient conditions for the meaningful assertability, however, are satisfied

by a phenomenon in Bohr’s technical sense earlier described. A phenomenon is the

performance of well-defined measurement in the presence of a well-defined measuring

instrument.

This shows that Bohr’s theory of meaning includes verificationist or confirmationist

element. However, following Murdoch, we defend the idea that Bohr’s theory of

meaning is based not on logical positivism, but on pragmatism. Simultaneous attribu-

tion of kinematic and dynamic properties to quantum objects is meaningless not prin-

cipally because such properties are simultaneously unobservable, but because such

attribution has no practical consequences. Such an attribution has neither explanatory

nor predictive power. It does not do anything, as a pragmatist would put it.

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 363

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 13: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

Unverifiability of simultaneous attribution of kinematic and dynamic properties is

only one factor, among others, which makes it meaningless to assert it:

The meaning of conditions, then, is not primarily epistemic but pragmatic, havingmore to do with what we as agents can do than with what we can know. Nevertheless,for Bohr the verifiability or confirmability of a statement is a necessary condition ofits meaningful assertability; and since experimental statements are verifiable or con-firmable only by means of some physical measurement operation, his theory has anoperationalist component. The operationalist component is already present inPeirce’s theory of meaning. (Murdoch 1987, 225)

Thus, the claim here is that Bohr’s theory of meaning, regarding complementarity, is

on the basis of the pragmatic maxim. The pragmatic maxim is a rational scheme for

rational conduct that should be understood and used within the framework of the

pragmatic theory of meaning.

3.3. Indeterminism

Bohr’s mature philosophy considers Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle as the ontologi-

cal consequence of his complementarity, not as arising from epistemological limit-

ations. In other words, in Bohr’s interpretation of quantum mechanics, the mutual

exclusivity of the position and momentum in the sense of complementarity leads to

the uncertainty relations. In his view, the role of measurement makes indeterminism

a consequence of the non-vanishing value of the quantum of action h. For Bohr, this is

the way nature works in the quantum realm. Such an idea is in line with Peirce’s

tychism, the idea that there is an objective feature of spontaneous chance activity in

nature free from the exact and necessary dictates of mechanical laws. Thus, Bohr’s

way of thinking of indeterminism shares some components with tychism in Peirce’s

philosophy.

However, there are important differences between Peirce’s tychism and indetermi-

nacy in Bohr’s philosophy. Given that Peirce was not alive by the time of the com-

pletion of the quantum formalism by Heisenberg (he died in 1914), his proposal

regarding quantum indeterminacy could at best be that at the microlevel, all physical

properties are indeterminate, not complementary pairs as is in the case of quantum

mechanics.

Another difference between Peirce’s tychistic vision of a world incorporating real

absolute chance and the objective indeterminacy revealed by Bohr’s philosophy of

quantum mechanics is that in the former, laws of nature must be products of evol-

ution.7

However, in Bohr’s philosophy, there is no reason to think that the basic

physical laws, which are of an objectively probabilistic nature, must have an evol-

utionary history of the kind supposed by Peirce. Quantum mechanics predicts, in

a particular statistical way, the outcome of the effects of quantum objects upon the

measuring instruments. In doing so, there is no need to bother to speculate

whether such fundamental laws have changed over time or they have always been

as they are.

364 R. Maleeh and P. Amani

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 14: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

4. Conclusion

This article claims that, if one were supposed to classify the Copenhagen interpret-

ation, the closest approximation would be to view it as a pragmatist philosophy.

However, identifying Bohr’s reading of the Copenhagen interpretation as pragmatist

is not reductionist. Such identification differs from, for example, Mara Beller’s

(1999) reading of Bohr’s philosophy where she claims that Bohr’s statements are intel-

ligible only if we consider him as a radical operationalist or simple-minded positivist.

The reason is clear: pragmatism already includes operationalist and verificationist

components but the converse of such a claim does not necessarily hold. Such an

inclusion leads pragmatism to share some elements with logical positivism in support-

ing the Copenhagen interpretation. These elements are empirical realism, fallibilism,

holism, and instrumentalism. In supporting the Copenhagen interpretation,

however, pragmatism goes beyond other schools: its pragmatic maxim supports

Bohr’s correspondence rule and complementarity, and Peirce’s notion of tychism

has some commonalities with indeterminism as embraced by the Copenhagen

interpretation.

Acknowledgements

This article would not have been possible without the tolerance and assistance of the

editor of this journal. Also, we wish to express our gratitude to the referees of the

journal for their detailed comments, which helped us to clarify and improve several

aspects of the manuscript. Finally, the first author would like to thank Phil Dowe of

the School of History, Philosophy, Religion and Classics, University of Queensland,

for his support and supervision.

Notes

[1] In doing so, we follow Murdoch’s (1987) reading of Bohr’s notion of complementarity,defending the idea that Bohr’s theory of meaning regarding the ultimate version of comple-mentarity is based on the pragmatic maxim, which itself should be seen within the frameworkof the pragmatic theory of meaning.

[2] The later Carnap’s empiricism has some important commonalities with Bohr’s philosophy.Bohr’s philosophy distinguishes between the symbolic language of the quantum formalism,which counts as a tool for prediction, and observation sentences that are visualizable inspace and time and refer to the so-called individual phenomena. This is similar to the distinc-tion that Carnap draws between the linguistic framework, which lacks empirical content, andobservation sentences within it whose truth or falsity must be verified empirically.

[3] Bohr’s correspondence rule has found another reading among some philosophers of science,referred to as the ‘generalized (or general) correspondence principle’. Post’s (1971) account ofthe principle is as follows: ‘any acceptable new theory L should account for the success of itspredecessor S by “degenerating” into that theory under those conditions under which S hasbeen well confirmed by tests’ (Post 1971, 228). However, there is no consensus among philo-sophers as to whether such a reading can apply to the quantum–classical relation. Forexample, Post himself believes that the generalized correspondence principle does not applyto the quantum–classical relation. He maintains that ‘paradoxically, the only counterexample

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 365

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 15: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

we have been able to find to the General Correspondence Principle is the paradigm example ofthe relation of quantum mechanics to classical mechanics’ (Post 1971, 233). Radder (1991,215) rejects this claim, arguing that the generalized correspondence principle does apply tothe case of the quantum–classical relation. He sees Bohr’s correspondence principle as aninstance of the generalized correspondence principle. If Radder is correct, the principle willprovide, at least to the limited extent, a basis for a general account of theory change as arational process through ‘firstly the recognition and rejection of one of the presuppositionsof the old theory, and secondly its replacement by a new hypothesis and a new parameterwhich, when given a limiting value, enables the laws of the new theory’ (Murdoch 1987,243). It is plausible that Bohr, in establishing his correspondence rule, had the above under-standing of the general account of theory change in physics. If this is the case, then it can besaid that Bohr’s philosophy is in line with Peirce’s fallibilism.

[4] If s is the particle’s spin angular momentum and ℓ its orbital angular momentum vector, thenthe total angular momentum j is j ¼ s + ℓ.

[5] Faye (1991, 200) has a more or less similar idea. He calls Bohr’s position on realism ‘objectiveantirealism’, which just as realism operates with a notion of objectivity, and yet, unlike realism,maintains that only decidable statements possess ‘investigation-independent truth values’, notundecidable ones.

[6] However, instrumentalism as embraced by pragmatists differs from the instrumentalism in Car-napian empiricism in one major sense: whereas pragmatists do not draw any difference betweenanalytic and synthetic sentences with respect to their roles as instruments, for the later Carnaponly linguistic frameworks whose choice is a matter of practical needs are considered as instru-ments. The Carnapian version of instrumentalism does not apply to observation sentenceswhose truth or falseness must be verified empirically. In this respect, Bohr’s instrumentalismis closer to Carnapian empiricism than to pragmatism. For example, Bohr’s acceptance ofBorn’s statistical interpretation of the wave function stems from his belief that the c functionhas only a symbolic meaning and does not refer to anything real in the world.

[7] This is why Peirce’s notion of ‘synechism’ is not in line with Bohr’s philosophy: in synechism,everything is regarded as continuous.

References

Ayer, A. J. 1952. Language, Truth and Logic. New York: Dover.Ayer, A. J., ed. 1959. Logical Positivism. New York: Free Press.Beller, M. 1999. Quantum Dialogue: The Making of a Revolution. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago

Press.Bohr, N. 1925. “Atomic Theory and Mechanics.” In Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, edited by J.

Faye and H. J. Folse, vol. 1, 25–51. Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.Bohr, N. 1929. “Introductory Survey.” In Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, edited by J. Faye and H.

J. Folse, vol. 1, 1–24. Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.Bohr, N. 1934. “Atomic Theory and the Description of Nature.” In Philosophical Writings of Niels

Bohr, edited by J. Faye and H. J. Folse, vol. 1, 92–101. Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.Bohr, N. 1935. “Can Quantum-mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Com-

plete?” Physical Review 48: 696–702.Bohr, N. 1937. “Causality and Complementarity.” In Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, edited by J.

Faye and H. J. Folse, vol. 4, 83–91. Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.Bohr, N. 1948. “On the Notions of Causality and Complementarity.” In Philosophical Writings of

Niels Bohr, edited by J. Faye and H. J. Folse, vol. 4, 141–148. Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.Bohr, N. 1949. “Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics.” In Phi-

losophical Writings of Niels Bohr, edited by J. Faye and H. J. Folse, vol. 2, 32–66. Woodbridge,CT: Ox Bow Press.

366 R. Maleeh and P. Amani

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 16: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

Bohr, N. 1963. Essays 1958–1962 on Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge. New York: Interscience.Bohr, N. 1972–2008. Collected Works. 13 vols. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Carnap, R. 1937. Logical Syntax of Language. Translated by A. Smeaton. London: Kegan, Paul,

Trench, Teubner & Co.Carnap, R. 1963. “Intellectual Autobiography.” In The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by P. A.

Schilpp, 3–84. LaSalle: Open Court.Faye, J. 1991. Niels Bohr: His Heritage and Legacy. An Anti-realist View of Quantum Mechanics. Dor-

drecht: Kluwer.Faye, J. 2008. “Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Phil-

osophy, edited by E. N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-copenhagen. Accessed 15February 2013.

Hookway, C. 2008. “Pragmatism.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by E. N. Zalta.http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism. Accessed 15 February 2013.

James, W. [1907] 1975. Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press.

Lindley, D. 1996. Where Does the Weirdness Go? Why Quantum Mechanics Is Strange, But Not AsStrange As You Think. New York: Basic Books.

Murdoch, D. 1987. Niels Bohr’s Philosophy of Physics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Peirce, C. S. [1878] 1992. “How to Make Our Ideas Clear.” In The Essential Peirce, edited by N.

Houser and C. Kloesel, vol. 1, 124–141. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Peirce, C. S. 1931–1935. Collected Papers, edited by C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss, and A. W. Burks. 8 vols.

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Petersen, A. 1963. “The Philosophy of Niels Bohr.” Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists 19 (7): 8–14.Post, H. R. 1971. “Correspondence, Invariance and Heuristics: In Praise of Conservative Induction.”

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 2: 213–255.Radder, H. 1991. “Heuristics and the Generalized Correspondence Principle.” British Journal for the

Philosophy of Science 42: 195–226.

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 367

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4

Page 17: Pragmatism, Bohr, and the Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f Su

ssex

Lib

rary

] at

07:

33 1

8 A

ugus

t 201

4