32
Koch, Adrew M. "Power, "Text," and Public Policy: The Political Implications of Jacques Derrida's Deconstructive Method” The Southeastern Political Review, 26(1) 155- 179. March 1998 DOI: 10.1111/j.1747-1346.1998.tb00475.x Version of record (Wiley- Blackwell) at http://www3.interscience.wiley.com/ Power, "Text" and Public Policy: The Political Implications of Jacques Derrida's Deconstructive Method Andrew M. Koch ABSTRACT This paper seeks to clarify the distinction between positivist/scientific and interpretive approaches to public policy using the critical framework of Jacques Derrida. Derrida s deconstructive method helps to clarify the relationship among state power, public policy, and the cultural "text" of "subjectivity." It is asserted that the positivistic approaches to policy formation rely on a representation of subjectivity that does not contain sufficient epistemological validity to stand as a foundation for the imposition of norms and values through policy process. This approach to public policy extends, or seeks to extend, the normative grammar that is contained in the dominant discourse through the establishment of a system of rewards and punishments for behavior that conforms, or fails to conform, to that grammar. Public policy, therefore, initiates pressure toward uniformity in the content of "subjectivity." Derrida s deconstructive methodology shows the often hidden ideological content in public discourse, raising questions about the imposition of any fixed definition of subjectivity through public policy. Following Derrida, policy must be more open to a plurality of different modes of existence that can be accommodated by a positivistic approach

Power, 'Text' and Public PolicyThis paper explores what Derrida's critique of Western logocentrism means for the concept of political communities and their artifacts, public policy

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    0

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • Koch, Adrew M. "Power, "Text," and Public Policy: The Political Implications of

    Jacques Derrida's Deconstructive Method” The Southeastern Political Review, 26(1) 155-

    179. March 1998 DOI: 10.1111/j.1747-1346.1998.tb00475.x Version of record (Wiley-

    Blackwell) at http://www3.interscience.wiley.com/

    Power, "Text" and Public Policy: The Political Implications of

    Jacques Derrida's Deconstructive Method

    Andrew M. Koch

    ABSTRACT

    This paper seeks to clarify the distinction between positivist/scientific and interpretive

    approaches to public policy using the critical framework of Jacques Derrida. Derrida s

    deconstructive method helps to clarify the relationship among state power, public policy,

    and the cultural "text" of "subjectivity." It is asserted that the positivistic approaches to

    policy formation rely on a representation of subjectivity that does not contain sufficient

    epistemological validity to stand as a foundation for the imposition of norms and values

    through policy process. This approach to public policy extends, or seeks to extend, the

    normative grammar that is contained in the dominant discourse through the establishment

    of a system of rewards and punishments for behavior that conforms, or fails to conform,

    to that grammar. Public policy, therefore, initiates pressure toward uniformity in the

    content of "subjectivity." Derrida s deconstructive methodology shows the often hidden

    ideological content in public discourse, raising questions about the imposition of any

    fixed definition of subjectivity through public policy. Following Derrida, policy must be

    more open to a plurality of different modes of existence that can be accommodated by a

    positivistic approach

  • 2

    ARTICLE

    Introduction

    The passage of welfare reform legislation in the United States suggest a "new"

    approach to the issue of public assistance. Dubbed as "behavior modification" by both its

    proponents and critics, this program grants public support as a reward for the

    modification of actions that have been identified as impediments to self-reliance,

    productivity, and personal responsibility. Proponents of this strategy argue programs

    such as "Learnfare," "Workfare," and "Bridefare" are necessary to break the "culture of

    poverty." Critics argue the plans have not been successful in state sponsored

    experiments, and they represent little more than a cynical attempt by both political parties

    to appeal to an angry middle class that sees its own economic prospects in decline.1

    In academic circles criticisms of such policies have traditionally taken two forms.

    One criticism has the character of a normative critique of the role played by state power

    in controlling the poor. In the interest of "stability" the state regulates the behavior of

    those classes and interests too weak to resist.2 The second criticism of government

    intervention cites the connection between state power and capitalist economics. In this

    critique the state uses its power to discipline the population into the order of employment

    established by entrepreneurial capitalism and the needs of production.3

    Over the last decade, however, a new criticism of the processes and methods of

    public policy analysis has emerged using a different epistemological paradigm.

    Exemplified in the works of Murray Edelman (1988), Deborah Stone (1988), Andrew

    Polsky (1991), Neil Postman (1992), Michael Shapiro (1992), and others, this paradigm

    suggests that the content of such policies as workfare, bridefare, etc. are generated from a

    broader cultural context that defies a simple normative, scientific, or economic critique.

    Following an epistemological paradigm that is interpretive rather than scientific, these

    authors stress the ideological character of the policy process at its very inception, where

  • 3

    assumptions and presuppositions are adopted. After assumptions are made, the formation

    of policy is largely a deductive process.

    This paper will explore this new paradigm in the light of the critique of Western

    philosophy offered by the French poststructuralist, Jacques Derrida. Derrida's method,

    called "deconstruction," raises questions about: the validity of a closed epistemological

    system; the value of deductive logic in the study of social phenomenon; and the process

    of creating representations of subjectivity as a precondition for social analysis and

    normative critique. Derrida's challenge to the modern paradigm of knowledge and the

    reliance on the scientific method to uncover “truth” establishes an epistemological basis

    for these new critiques of the policy process.

    While not the first to claim that a dominant culture will assert its “interests” in

    policy (such arguments can be found within the Marxist tradition as well as elite theorists

    such as C. Wright Mills), Derrida’s deconstructive method explores the mechanics of the

    method by which context is translated into public action. Further, Derrida moves beyond

    a specific focus on economic interests and operates within a context of “culture” that

    includes the ideas, cultural norms and assumptions that provide the background for policy

    construction. Transformed into legal statute, the norms and interests of the culture are

    imposed through the power of the state. From this standpoint, "behavior modification" is

    revealed as the aim of all public policy. The imposition of "community standards," the

    inculcation of "mainstream values," "strategic interventions," etc. represent the

    "normalizing" tools of collective power that operate on a cultural level. All are

    extensions of state power under the rhetorical sway of a dominant ideology. While

    perhaps less subtle than other public policy areas, welfare reform reflects the extension of

    the dominant ideology. To put it another way, policy mirrors the "normative grammar" of

    the dominant culture, reflecting an ideal characterization of "subjectivity." From the

    perspective of deconstruction, such constructions of subjectivity have no foundational

    standing. Therefore, the effect of public policy is not the extention of some natural truth,

  • 4

    but the expansion of institutional power through extending the domain of the dominant

    discourse on the subject. The strength of Derrida's general epistemological critique is to

    unmask the tentative and ideological character of such an enterprise. In arguing that

    "truth" is plural, Derrida undercuts any agenda that would seek to impose a singular

    discourse on the subject.

    This paper explores what Derrida's critique of Western logocentrism means for

    the concept of political communities and their artifacts, public policy. However, unlike

    Deborah Stone (1988), this paper will not seek to push Derrida in the direction of a

    reconstitution of community. The implications of the poststructuralist's epistemology

    suggest such a reconstitution is epistemologically unsound.4 The concept of

    "community" itself suggests a bifurcated universe of members and nonmembers, a fixed

    system of identities that carry a totalitarian potential. As a result, Derrida's approach

    provides a rationale for resistance to the imposition of a singular discourse on subjectivity

    by any political community. Ultimately, this reveals an irresolvable tension between

    philosophic validity and collective action.

    I. The Public Policy Tradition

    A. Modernity and the Scientific Paradigm

    Public policy is a social artifact. (Wildavsky, 1979, p. 395.) Its linkage to a social

    and historical context, therefore, cannot be severed. As a social artifact, however, public

    policy reflects more than the dominant moral and ideological beliefs present in a

    particular culture. As Michel Foucault suggested, the dominant ideology of any age also

    reflects a set of presuppositions about the limits and conditions of knowledge. (Foucault,

    1973)

    If this is the case, the model of policy formulation that focuses on the scientific

    discovery of truth as a foundation for policy prescriptions reflects the bias of what

    Deborah Stone calls the "rationality project." (Stone, 1988 4-7.) This project has sought

  • 5

    to impose a model of knowledge taken from the natural sciences onto the social sciences.

    In the area of public policy, this positivistic model has as its most common form the

    following: 1) identifying a problem, 2) establishing a set of presuppositions and

    hypotheses that will guide the investigation, 3) generating and evaluating alternatives, 4)

    choosing the best option to address the problem, 5) implementing the policy, 6)

    evaluating the outcome.5

    Like the natural sciences, this model employs a syllogistic reseasoning, judging

    both the soundness of premises and the logic of conclusions derived from those premises.

    (Paris and Reynolds, 1983) The outcome of the process is the product "policy X."

    Policy X is considered valid if it reflects the methodological presuppositions,

    classificatory schemes, epistemological assumptions, and biases about human nature that

    were granted in step 2 of the policy process. As Gordon Tullock and Richard Wagner

    suggest, public policy begins with "first principles" of human action and then proceeds

    deductively. (Tullock and Wagner, 1978, p. ix.) This is the case for all “scientific”

    approaches to public policy, whether defined as positivism, behavioralism, rational choice

    theory, or cost benefit analysis. This epistemological pattern is designed after the natural

    sciences, where the empirical findings are used to validate (or invalidate) the assumptions

    of an hypothesis. In that sense, policy is considered rational if it reinforces the biases that

    were accepted as the foundation for it own inception.

    But what has this procedure really proven? It is an illusion to think that

    ideological premises can produce a non-ideological result. The strength of Derrida’s

    deconstructive method is to reveal the multiple interventions that undemonstratable

    assumptions have had in the construction of collective decision making. In this sense, a

    “rational choice” is little more than a choice that reflects the dominant norms of the

    society. It does not reveal some fundamental human truth.

    B. The Interpretive Model

  • 6

    As Christopher Lasch claimed, the scientific approach to policy making began to

    collapse along with much of the Enlightenment tradition. As a result, the search for

    scientific certainty in the social sciences only survives by narrowing the range of

    discourse to technical questions that can be solved quantitatively. (Lasch, 1995) In

    contrast to this tradition is a broad array of work that includes hermeneutics, aesthetics,

    and elements of the Marxist tradition. What these different schools of thought share is

    the understanding that the “truth” of public policy is formulated out of historical context.

    Within this perspective Derrida’s work is extremely important in providing an intellectual

    framework for analysis.

    The interpretive framework is exemplified in the work of Deborah Stone (1988),

    Murray Edelman (1988), Andrew Polsky (1991), Niel Postman (1992), Michael Shapiro

    (1992), and others. Generally, these authors oppose this scientific paradigm of public

    policy analysis. While each emphasizes a different aspect of the problem with the

    scientific method, the these authors share a perspective that stresses the significance of

    interpretation in the analysis of politics and public policy.

    The interpretive framework does not follow the strict syntax of scientific

    statements. The scientific paradigm focuses on causality and predictability under strict

    rules of verification. The interpretive model is more open, having as a presupposition the

    historical nature of understanding. "Understanding" is viewed as a construction, not as a

    fixed, eternal "truth." This paradigm challenges the deductive system used in traditional

    policy analysis. It takes as its focus the very issues that the scientific model cannot

    address: the validity of the classificatory schemes; the truth value of various

    characterizations of human subjectivity; and the link between the normative content of

    policy alternatives and political power.

    By denying the claims of the scientific method - that truth has a unidimensional

    character and follows linear causality - power, policy, and cultural reproduction cannot be

    separated from one another. Public policy, as a part of generalized politics, involves

  • 7

    commitment, belief, passion, and symbolic identification. Public policy, as politics, is an

    activity driven by emotion and passion, not science. (Stone 1988) Logical deduction is

    possible only after categories and definitions are established. It is precisely this

    commitment to the process of defining that defies the rationality project.

    Edelman's assertions lead in a similar direction. For Edelman, politics is a

    symbolic activity in which various material and ideological interests seek to mobilize a

    generally passive public by the use of emotionally charged metaphors. Therefore, politics

    is about the construction and maintenance of myths and beliefs. Public policy serves to

    enhance and reinforce these beliefs. In particular, the mythology of the poor in the United

    States as worthless and lazy parasites makes their control and oppression appear as

    rational behavior by the state. (Edelman 1971) According to Edelman, assumptions

    regarding human nature, "appropriate" conduct, and rational politics are simply

    reflections of different ideological positions conveyed through language. These cannot be

    validated by science because the language itself is a reflection of the historical and

    political context in which the text is discussed. (Edelman 1988)

    State power and the role of belief in politics is a theme also developed by Andrew

    Polsky. Following Foucault's strategy for a genealogical inquiry into French penal and

    mental institutions, Polsky examines the history of what he terms the "therapeutic state"

    in the United States. He claims that policy is constructed in order to inculcate

    "mainstream" values, especially to a suspicious underclass. (Polsky 1991) Clients of the

    state are pushed to change child rearing habits, find new residences, maintain sexual

    abstinence, and adopt different spending habits. Refusal results in the breakup of family

    units or incarceration. (Polsky 1991) He concludes that the fusion of power with

    assistance has led to the imposition of a dominant ideology on those who lack formal

    powers to resist and whose compliance is deemed necessary for the functioning of an

    advanced industrial economy.

  • 8

    Michael Shapiro, drawing heavily on Michel Foucault, argues that the contingent

    nature of interpretive knowledge makes public policy a political not a scientific

    undertaking. Practices develop historically and “reside in the very style in which

    statements are made, in the grammatical, rhetorical, and narrative structures that compose

    even the discourses of the sciences. (Shapiro 1988) The entire apparatus of power can be

    brought to bear on those who do not conform to expectations, even though the specific

    direction of state coercion is largely arbitrary.

    The interpretive approach asserts that policy is an artifact of culture and context.

    As a cultural "text," policy cannot be separated from the assumptions that underlie its

    content. Therefore, policy is a reflection of cultural bias, not the uncovering of "truth" in

    the arena of public affairs. As such, it always serves the system of power reflected in the

    dominant ideology of subjectivity.

    The scientific model of knowledge operates according to the parameters of

    syllogistic reasoning. This form of deductive reasoning must be built on assumptions.

    But where do those assumptions come from? Derrida elaborates the contextual nature of

    foundational assumptions, raising doubts about the essential condition for deductive

    policy making. Derrida's claims call into question the linearity of this deductive process

    and his ideas raise doubts about the validity of the “truth” that emerges as an outcome.

    These claims, if taken seriously, must shake the very foundations of traditional public

    policy analysis.

    II. Deconstruction and the Problem of Meaning

    A. Text, Meaning, and the Metaphysics of Subjectivity

    Derrida's critique of Western philosophy is based on the idea that there is

    continuity among the central philosophic tenets of this tradition, from Plato to Kant and

    Hegel. Following Heidegger, Derrida asserts that a consideration of “being” has been at

    the core of the Western tradition. Heidegger claimed that the West has lost its link to true

  • 9

    “Being.” (Heidegger 1977) However, Derrida is suspicious of the onto-theology of

    “Being” suggested by Heidegger’s formulation. Therefore, Derrida rejects Heidegger’s

    metaphysics, but assimilates Heidegger’s notions of language and power as they are

    linked to the articulation of “Being.”6 Derrida concludes that there is a link between

    constructions of the subject and the exercise of political power.

    This metaphysical mask around the concept of being is very powerful in Western

    philosophy. Derrida argues that the task of capturing "being," described as "presence,"

    has been carried out by the formulation of a text that claims to represent the essential

    nature of "being." From Plato to the modern period, Western philosophy has postulated

    "being" as a transcendent category, separated from sense impressions. The result of this

    formulation is the creation of an ontological dualism that separates mind/matter,

    being/sensing, and subject/object.

    This ontological distinction has also provided the foundation for Western

    epistemology since Plato. "Knowledge" has been considered to be the result of a

    relationship between "subject," that which describes, and "object," that which is

    described. There has been, therefore, continuity between the "doctrine of the forms," the

    ontological dualism that made Plato's epistemology possible, and the notion of a "thing in

    itself," as the transcendental category of "being" postulated by Kant. Both presuppose a

    transcendental realm of "being" that lies beyond the human ability to "know." The

    proposition that one transcendental realm of "being" exists in which objects and events

    have their "true" character suggests there is universal subjectivity and a universal

    normative grammar based on that representation of the subject.

    In "Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences" Derrida

    describes the Western Philosophic tradition. This mode of interpreting the world "dreams

    of deciphering a truth or an origin." (1978a, p. 292.) It seeks to affirm "being" by creating

    an "onto-theology" in which the possibility of the subject, "being," remains decipherable

    within the context of a closed epistemological framework. It creates the conditions for

  • 10

    humanism, an elaboration of history as "the being who," as a foundation for a totalizing

    metaphysics, in which the notion of "being" validates itself through an indirect and

    circular logic of affirmation. Subjectivity reflects back on itself to validate the content of

    "being."

    But there is another form of interpretation in Derrida's work, one that reflects

    Derrida's own position. In the bulk of Derrida's writings the focus is on an affirmation of

    the "noncenter," the end of center as the affirmation of the "play of the world." Derrida

    asserts that our discourse about the world refers only to other discourses. Discourse

    cannot, therefore, affirm being because it cannot return to an origin. There is only the

    play of difference, the substitution for the substitution, the play of the noncenter in

    discourse. The result is "the affirmation of a world of signs without fault, without truth,

    without origin..." (1978a, p. 292.)

    To the exploration of this idea on "text," Derrida has assigned the term

    "deconstruction." Deconstruction is the attempt to push at the margins of "logos" which

    Derrida claims is at the heart of Western philosophy. The project is not anti-

    philosophical, as has been claimed, but is an attempt to examine the bias upon which the

    Western philosophic tradition is based. By implication, the philosophic underpinnings of

    a cultural process of reproduction, in all its forms, must be included in the deconstructive

    enterprise.

    A deconstructive reading of text requires that the metaphysical underpinnings of

    text be unmasked by a reading that takes the text to the edge, the margins of metaphysics.

    In practical terms, this requires that the notion of "authorship" and "intention," as

    representations of closed systems of meaning, need to be superseded by an open reading

    in which authorial intentions give way to non-intentional contexts. To read text as

    conveying "only" the author's intentions is to read text within the metaphysical confines

    of "self-presence." All text, within this view, reinforce the presence of being through the

    very act of authorship. (Derrida 1976, 159)

  • 11

    Derrida concludes that Western philosophy engages in a circular logic in which

    the premises upon which the metaphysics of presence are based represent the essential

    precondition for the generation of propositions within the logocentric system. It is,

    therefore, quite understandable that Derrida sees Hegel at the pinnacle of Western

    logocentrism, identifying "logic" with a generative ontology. (Derrida 1976, 24) Being

    replicates itself in the process of coming to the realization of self.

    Derrida explores this claim in his deconstruction of the methodological strategies

    of Claud Levi-Strauss and Jean Jacques Rousseau. In his discussion of Rousseau Derrida

    claims that Rousseau created a hypothetical time before language in order to demonstrate

    where society had gone "bad." Derrida asks if such a presupposition makes sense. Is it

    possible to ascertain the pre-social, pre-linguistic origins of language? (Derrida 1976,

    252) This assumption makes Rousseau's critique of society possible, but it is built on an

    epistemological foundation that Derrida claims is insupportable. If the foundational

    premises upon which the analysis is built and from which the conclusions are logically

    deduced are speculative and arbitrary, can the conclusions have any validity? The

    premises are only reinforced by the act of drawing a conclusion, not through an external

    source of verification. Ideology is extended, not philosophically validated, through this

    process.

    In deconstructing the methodological strategy of Levi-Strauss, as in Rousseau,

    Derrida seeks to show the logical impossibility of what is being asserted. The

    natural/social opposition which creates the foundation for Levi-Strauss' enterprise is part

    of a binary metaphysical scheme passed down in the Western philosophic tradition. In

    response to the claim that writing had a degenerative effect on the Nambikwara, Derrida

    claims that the concept of generating a text, as Derrida defines it, must have already

    existed in the Nambikwara prior to the introduction of phonetic writing by the

    anthropologists. Otherwise, its adoption in the reinforcement of social hierarchy could

    not have been possible. (Derrida 1976, 129)

  • 12

    In the discussion of Levi-Strauss Derrida is also trying to make a broader

    epistemological point. Levi-Strauss represented the extension of logocentrism to

    anthropology. At the roots of structural anthropology Derrida finds a central tenet of

    Western philosophy characteristic of late modernism. Levi-Strauss was critical of

    totalizing concepts in discussions of human behavior. His reasoning, similar to Weber's,

    suggests that totalizing concepts in the study of human society are not possible because of

    the infinite range of possible expressions by and about human beings.7

    This is not Derrida's claim. Like Levi-Strauss, Derrida argues totalizing concepts

    have no epistemological foundation. However, Derrida asserts that within a linguistic

    system possible expressions are finite. It is the substitutions of meaning for any textual

    statement that are infinite. (Derrida1978a, 287) Derrida's argument represents a shift in

    reasoning. The idea that subjects can create an infinite array of statements is a defense of

    a particular type of subjectivity that protects the sanctity of the author. To suggest that a

    finite number of statements exist, and that the impossibility of a total truth stems from not

    being able to decide among them, shifts emphasis away from the subjectivist bias of the

    Western culture.

    Derrida's main impetus is the desire to uncover the metaphysical character of the

    concept of "hierarchy" in general. Hierarchy is undermined if authoritative assertions

    regarding texts and their interpretation cannot be generated. Even the author of a "text"

    cannot be judged to be the final arbiter. "Text" combines author's intentions, the author's

    social context, personal milieu, and the epistemological and linguistic structures in which

    text is created. In using the term "text" Derrida attempts to open the interpretive field that

    has been dominated by the traditional notions of authorship and speech/writing as the idea

    of "being" reflecting upon itself.

    Derrida's deconstructive method, therefore, undermines any totalizing theory of

    knowledge. Deconstruction performs this task as it reveals the logical inconsistencies,

    paradoxes, and unintended meanings in the reading of text. By de-centering any text, a

  • 13

    deconstructive reading shows the metaphysics of self-presence that underlies the idea of

    authorship, origin, and intention in the Western tradition. The "play" of deconstruction is

    the disruption of that presence.

    By shaking the epistemological foundations upon which the authority of policy

    choices rest, Derrida's analysis raises important questions about the construction and

    assessment of policy outcomes. Public policy generated out of a modern, scientific bias

    functions by assuming an authority that is not there. If the meaning of subjectivity cannot

    be authoritatively determined, the substance of public policy and the circular process by

    which policy outcomes are measured must be abandoned. Following Derrida's

    epistemological critique, the outcome of the policy process is shown to be nothing more

    than arbitrary choice backed by the power of the state.

    B. Identity, "Differance," and the Grafting of Text

    The decentering of "being," the opening of "play," is not simply a rhetorical

    device. Removing the center of "being" is accomplished by revealing the contingent

    nature of truth. All of Western metaphysics revolves around the "column of being" which

    is itself not there. (Derrida 1981a, 352) This is the case because all the representations of

    "being" are closed, complete, as is the notion of "being" itself, a notion of closed self-

    sufficiency. "Being" should be written with a line through the letters in order to signify

    the impossibility of "being's" independence, of "being" standing alone. (Derrida 1981a,

    354)

    To demonstrate this claim, Derrida suggests a shift in thinking about the way in

    which objects receive their identities. Western epistemology has centered on building

    foundations for positive statements about "being."8 Identity is formed through the use of

    a differentiating scheme for categorizing the diversity of experience. "Being" reflects

    upon itself through making assertions about its "identity." However, if there is no

  • 14

    transcendental realm of "being" that informs the content of "identity," all such statements

    are insupportable.

    To put this problem in slightly different terminology, the "signified," as that which

    is to be represented, and the "signifier," as that sign which is to represent the signified,

    stand in opposition. This opposition manifests itself as the difference between the

    sensible and the intelligible. (Derrida 1978a, 281) Derrida questions the system which

    supports the difference between signifier and the signified. The traditional notion of the

    sign, as "being" reflecting back on itself, is rejected. Identity is not formed by the idea of

    self-presence.

    Derrida asserts that identity is generated from what a signifier is not, rather than a

    positive, metaphysical formulation of being. This Derrida refers to as "differance."

    Identity is formulated out of the play of differences, which forbids any element from

    referring only to itself. (Derrida 1981b, 26) No sign can be immediately present to itself,

    but gains meaning from the play of differences between itself and other elements.

    Derrida's idea of "differance" presents the possibility for a radical shifting of

    ground within the Western philosophic tradition. If identity is established by what a

    signified is not, two conclusions are immediately apparent. First, the interconnectedness

    of text is demonstrated as an epistemological necessity for the creation of new texts, and

    secondly, the question of determining the truth value of statements is complicated by the

    infinite interconnectedness of contexts. Both of these topics require some elaboration.

    If a signified is not complete in itself, but only in relation to that which it is not,

    and that which it is not is infinite, then the contingent nature of truth and the problem of

    textual interpretation is obvious. (Derrida 1981a, 304..) Philosophy cannot achieve

    closure. (Derrida 1981a, 353) There must always be an opening, a thing left open, an

    element unsaid.

    Derrida is not asserting that there is no truth, or that there is no possibility of truth.

    That is not the direction of his argument, even though this position is often mistakenly

  • 15

    attributed to him. Derrida's argument seeks to demonstrate that there is not "one" truth.

    Truth is plural. (1982b, 103) Deciding among the truths, to pick one truth, is the

    impossible task.

    To Derrida, Western philosophy has forgotten its metaphysical origins, forgotten

    that it has based its truths on metaphors, the signifier and the signified, in a cyclical

    process of epistemological regeneration. Representation, the result of the process of

    signification, is the creation of structural illusion. (Derrida 1981, 297)

    Text does not convey "being" but instead represents a chain of metaphors about

    "being." The story of events validate themselves only through repetition, in which text

    turns back on itself, eventually losing sight of its contingent origins. Born of repetition,

    the text reproduces the process of its own triggering. (Derrida 1981a, 292)

    Without the column of truth around which to organize closure, there is only text.

    The creation of text is always the transformation of other texts. It is a grafting. To write

    is to graft onto a text that already exists. (Derrida 1981a, 355) There is no origin, nothing

    prior to text. There is only the bottomless, endless, transformation of text. (Derrida

    1981a, 333-334)

    Philosophy is a great discourse governed and limited by the resources and

    organization at is disposal. (Derrida 1982a, 177) As a contingent reflection of

    experience, the discourse of philosophy requires features not present in the experience

    itself. There must be a structure which makes the creation of text possible, which allows

    for the experience to have meaning. (Derrida 1982a, 326) Previous texts provide the

    conditions and the limitations for new texts. (Derrida 1982a, 189) Every text has "traces"

    of other texts as its presupposition. Every text is a trace of a trace. (Derrida 1981b, 26)

    There is nothing before the text, no original author, no origin that is itself not text.

    (Derrida 1981a, 333) Language does not convey the signifier, but a metaphor. (Derrida

    1982a, 178) As metaphors, all terms remain ambiguous. Metaphors are open to shades

    of subtlety, leaving the "true and proper" meaning undecidable.

  • 16

    All text is unclear, out of context, by the very nature of its becoming text. To

    forbid closure, to open dissemination, is to end "Meaning" and substitute "meanings," as

    contingent forms of "knowing" derived from structures. Text emerges as the result of the

    grafting on the metaphor of a metaphor. Thus, text does not verify "being," but reflects

    back onto other texts. Presence makes its appearance as the activity of the textual

    apparatus reflecting back upon itself. (Derrida 1981a, 299)

    When applied to issues of politics, these ideas alter the understanding of collective

    action. Derrida is suggesting that textual validity is a cultural product, not a reflection of

    transcendental truth. Textual repetition provides the illusion of universals. If the text on

    subjectivity is constructed through this process it will reflect norms and biases that are

    undemonstrateable except by reference to other texts on the subject. Through the traces

    of previous texts contained within them, public policies adopt an air of legitimacy.

    Derrida reminds us that political legitimacy is fundamentally different than philosophic

    truth.

    C. Limits, Knowledge, and "The Scission"

    Derrida defines the limits of knowledge by suggesting that we are trapped within

    the structures and metaphysics that provide the means of discourse. We cannot move

    outside, to a meta-text, divorced and unrelated to the existing text. Nothing can have its

    basis beyond the structure itself. If the production of text is a grafting, then the graft must

    be attached to something. And, claims Derrida, there is no place outside of text from

    which to view it. (Derrida 1981a, 290) We cannot escape metaphysics. (Derrida 1981b,

    17) There is no way to make a destructive proposition that is not formed out of the logic

    that it seeks to contest. (Derrida 1978a, 280) This was the dilemma faced by Nietzsche,

    Freud, and Heidegger, according to Derrida.

    If an epistemological reconstitution outside of metaphysical discourse is not

    possible then what is Derrida's point? Derrida wants to show how the concepts,

  • 17

    presuppositions, and structural limits of philosophy can be turned against themselves.

    (Derrida 1981b, 24) Any text can be shown to collapse through the elaboration of its

    possibilities for infinite substitution. Every philosophic system can be pushed until it

    slides to the point of exhaustion. (Derrida 1981b, 6)9

    Text can neither capture "being" nor provide "truth." How can we speak of

    "truth" when every statement of "truth" is dependent on a speculative and theoretical

    account? (Derrida 1978b, 141) Text cannot even convey meaning, if meaning is the

    recapturing of the infinite relations of identity and non-identity within an ever evolving

    plurality of contexts.

    What remains Derrida terms the "scission." The scission is a cut out of the

    infinity of substitutions and the plurality of contexts. When you cannot undertake the

    infinite commentary, then "take a cut of it." (Derrida 1981a, 300) The pure present is

    untouchable fullness. (Derrida 1981a, 301) It appears in discourse only as myth.

    (Derrida 1981a, 303) The present can appear only by taking a cut of itself, giving itself a

    beginning and an end, limiting the space and providing closure. Unity is the myth of

    reconstituted scission. Paradoxically, the unity is achieved only with the dissemination of

    the plural.

    In Derrida’s critique of Levi-Strauss, in "Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse

    on the Human Sciences," Derrida comments on the results of his view of knowledge for

    social inquiry. If knowledge is the assemblage of scission, the ad hoc arrangement of the

    fragment, then any totalizing theory of knowledge is impossible. Knowledge is

    interpretation, a myth imposed on the scission. Human science is reduced to a series of

    alternative mythologies. (Derrida 1978a, 287-288) The substance of traditional "social

    science" is, therefore, rhetorical and ideological.

    Derrida’s position provides support for the interpretive approach to social inquiry.

    What lies behind the "scientific paradigm", exemplified by positivism, behavioralism,

    rational choice theory, and cost benefit analysis, is the view that a singular, non-

  • 18

    ideological "truth" is possible. This position asserts that a specific set of rules govern

    human activity and that those rules are unaffected by context. The "truth" governing

    human behavior can be "discovered" if only the instruments are sufficiently refined.

    However, if truth is plural the application of the scientific paradigm to social

    issues is problematic. These “scientific” approaches to public policy are formed in a

    "scission," a cut of the plurality. Derrida's analysis reveals the bias that emerges with this

    approach to policy making.

    III. The Politics of the Scission

    If we take Derrida seriously we need to radically rethink politics, both as a

    scholarly enterprise and as the practice of collective action. If traditional political theory

    creates representations of the human character, and representation has the structural role

    of depicting "being" within the scission, than traditional political theory is a deductive

    extension of metaphysics. Political theory is the collected anthropologies of the "subject"

    produced out of the scission.

    Political practice also emerges from the scission. Political practice cannot be

    separated from the myth that informs behavior. To the extent that political theories have

    provided the presuppositions necessary for a deductive policy formulation, they have

    served to extend speculative metaphysics into the arena of collective action. Hence, the

    struggle of politics is the struggle for control over the "archive" that has the power to

    determine the content of "subjectivity."

    A. The Onto-Theology of the Subject as the Foundation for Collective Action

    Derrida resists the idea that his aim is to reduce all writing to myth. (1981b, p.

    52.) The distinction between "logos" and "mythos" is a logocentric opposition that he is

    unwilling to accept. Deconstruction can only take place between texts, not from outside.

  • 19

    The only reference of a signifier is another signifier. Writing is only compared to other

    writing. (Derrida 1981b, 53) However, within the writing of text, myth can be created

    and disseminated. The myth of subjectivity is particularly important to Derrida.

    Derrida stated that the goal of his project is not to destroy the subject, but to show

    that what we call the "subject" and "subjectivity" are references to specific historical and

    structural constellations in which those terms find their meaning. (Derrida 1981b, 88)

    Subjectivity is historically bound. In that sense deconstruction allows for the peeling of

    the cultural layers, the traces of previous texts, that provide the apparent validity of any

    particular ontology that serves as the basis for political action. In that sense, Derrida

    suggests he opens the possibility of a materialism that is more conscious of its speculative

    and teleological problems than Marxist materialism. (Derrida 1981b, 74)

    To the extent that the human sciences engage in a methodological quest for

    representation they are engaged in an enterprise that is potentially destructive. As people

    are turned into representations, positive identities that can be characterized, measured,

    and defined, they also become objectified, as the subjects in service of the categories of

    definition. Derrida suggests that as representations, people can become replaceable,

    expendable, objects, units in mass production, police computers, and concentration

    camps. (Derrida 1982c, 317)

    The methodological foundation of deductive political theory is the objectification

    of "being.” In positive political theory the goal is to produce "objectified" facts which

    serve to categorize subjectivity. In this tradition of political analysis one begins with

    ontological presuppositions regarding the "identity of being" and then proceeds logically

    to "objective" conclusions. In a reciprocal process, the definition of the "subject"

    reinforces the onto-theology of "being" when action dependent on that presupposition

    takes place.

    Derrida states his work will end the idea that ideology is somehow an effect or

    reflection of being itself. (Derrida 1981b, 90) Derrida seeks to prevent any concept from

  • 20

    representing a center, or summary, from which it can govern due to a theological

    presence. (Derrida 1981b, 14) Here we can begin to see the political significance of

    Derrida's deconstructive enterprise. If the structural foundation that underlies the

    formation of "text" determines the direction of discourse, then the control of that structure

    is a political activity.

    If political life is reflected in the signs of the culture and in the structures for the

    generation of those signs, and if the signs that are generated are the presuppositions

    underlying political action, then control over the generation of signs takes on a political

    character. Political power serves as a gatekeeper over what is admitted to the archive.

    Once a sign is admitted into discourse it has the power of dissemination. It becomes a

    trace, an origin for future discourse, and a point for the expansion of its territory within

    the totality of discursive activity.

    If knowledge is something that is created, rather than discovered, then the

    direction taken by the knowledge creating enterprise, as a textual grafting, has a political

    dimension. This political observation represents a point of convergence among the

    poststructuralists. Lyotard in The Postmodern Condition, Foucault in Power/Knowledge,

    and Derrida in No Apocalypse, Not Now (as well as other places), all claim the

    generation of knowledge is directed by the structure of power.

    B. The Politics of the Graft: The "Subject" and Public Policy

    Derrida shares the view, common to the poststructuralist enterprise, that any

    representation of the "subject" is speculative, metaphysical, and the reflection of the

    power that dominates the cultural archive. The content of "subjectivity" is a result of the

    particular constellation of traces and grafts that have been "accepted" within the dominant

    discourse on the "subject." "Subjectivity" is, therefore, something that is created, not

    discovered. It is a cultural product.

  • 21

    The construction of subjectivity is part of a larger process of social reproduction.

    In this historical, contextual process the signs and symbols of the dominant discourse are

    appropriated and reapplied to emerging contexts and conditions. This is why, within

    modernism, the construction of "subjectivity" retains a continuity, even within changing

    constellations of events and interests.

    Derrida's critique of Western epistemology challenges the notion, exemplified by

    Kant's Universal History, that there can be "one" history, "one" normative grammar, and

    "one" subjectivity. The deconstructive enterprise provides a means to negate the validity

    of any definition of subjectivity that claims a privileged status. Not only is this the case

    because of the historical and relative nature of ontological claims, but as discussed above,

    a positive assertion regarding "human nature" must take place within a closed

    epistemological system, a condition that, logically, must result in the contingent nature of

    any such claims. The construction of "subjectivities," the premises of deductive policy

    analysis, reflects the limits of the cultural archive, not the content of human nature.

    The significance of this position for public policy cannot be overstated. If public

    policy can be shown to serve the "myth" of a specific definitional content of subjectivity,

    a myth that reflects the dominant discourse on subjectivity that has origins in the archive,

    not in "being," then public policy is a means for the dominant culture to extend and

    enlarge its influence. Public policy becomes, therefore, a disciplinary tool in the hands of

    the interests that control the institutions of power.

    While Derrida’s analysis may seem to parallel the Marxist tradition, the

    “interests” that exercise power are conceived in a much broader sense. Economics is

    reduced to only one component of a constellation of particulars that constitute a dominant

    culture. Derrida’s analysis also applies across different institutional forms of political

    life. Neither democracy nor totalitarianism can necessarily be assumed to legitimate and

    incorporate multiple definitions of the subject. When a deductive procedure is used in

    the creation of policy quite the contrary is likely to occur. In that case, public policy is

  • 22

    successful to the extent that it has been able to extend its definition of the subject into

    alternative cultural archives. To the extent that it fails, public policy has been unable to

    break the alternative definitions of the subject held by competing systems of normative

    grammar.

    To put this in schematic terms, all public policy using a positivist epistemology

    follows the same basic form: given the character of the human subject (X), policy (Y)

    should bring about desired condition (Z). However, following Derrida's logic, the

    historically contingent nature of the process through which the content of (X) has been

    formulated suggests that there are clear epistemological problems generated by a static

    conception of (X). In addition, there are clear problems that relate to matters of power

    and political practice. The content of subjectivity delineated by the (X), as a reflection of

    archival parameters, only has correspondence with policy (Y). For outcome (Z) to be

    expected from policy (Y) the content of subjectivity (X) must be firmly established.

    Deconstruction suggests that the power to impose a definition of subjectivity

    operates as a necessary condition of the positivistice models of policy making. From that

    perspective, the problem of making policy are technical. Once subjectivity has been

    constructed the creation of a system of measurements allows for the monitoring of

    “success.” In addition, the deductive form of policy analysis prevents the representation

    of diversity, even where there are preexisting alternative definitions of the self.

    Government policy tends to reflect the biases of the majority culture or the most powerful

    groups within the state. Policy results are, therefore, exclusive rather than inclusive. The

    process will have the effect, if not the stated purpose, of homogenization.

    Alternative discourses have marginal political power, making resistance to the

    imposed conception of subjectivity difficult, if not impossible. This results from the

    conditional nature of the policy process. Benefits are sucured by adopting behavior that

    resembles that prescribed by the dominant ideology. Assuming that behavior reflects the

    content of subjective consciousness, behavior changes are sufficient for the validation of

  • 23

    a strategy’s success. Thus, in the "wedfare" program an increase in the numbers of

    marriages is an indicator of the success of the initiative.

    This form of policy making is governed by a circular logic. The “truth” of the

    prevailing view of subjectivity is revieled in the states ability to force compliance with its

    demands. To put this another way, policy serves an "ideal subject" reflected back from

    the dominant archive through the policy process. Policy redefines the content of

    competing definitions of the subject in the process of empowering its own effectiveness.

    The power of the state, reflecting the dominant ideological position on "subjectivity," is

    brought to bear on the alternative definitions of the self.

    A problem emerges if the policy process should try and account for multiple

    discourses on "subjectivity." If policy (Y) corresponds only with subject (X), how can the

    policy process account for (X1), (X2), (X3), etc.? This condition would require (Y1),

    (Y2), (Y3), etc., a condition that is impossible if the outcome (Z) remains a singular

    reflection of the dominant normative ideal. Within the bureaucratic model of state

    intervention, such complexity would be difficult, if not impossible, to manage.

    Therefore, multiple definitions of subjectivity represent a problem for the modern state, in

    general, regardless of the structure of decision making.

    Following from Derrida's deconstructive logic, the point is not that no community

    is served by policy, but that policy represents an extension of one form of subjectivity

    that, following modern universalism, intrudes into a social context that is plural, with

    multiple discursive fields. The "velvet glove" of policy should be most effective on those

    who share the dominant definition of "subjectivity" that informs policy. Policy should be

    least effective for those who do not subscribe to the dominant discourse. As a result, the

    "iron fist" of disciplined compliance becomes "rational" for those who fail to follow the

    dominant normative grammar.

    Policy based on the identity (X) will not speak to (X1), (X2), (X3), etc. Further,

    policy (Y) will reflect the content of "subjectivity" contained in the normative grammar of

  • 24

    (X), extended through the institutions of power into the policy arena. From the

    perspective of Derrida, the real result of the policy process is the extension and

    replication of (X) through policy (Y).

    If the definition of "subjectivity" that informs the policy process is demonstrated

    to be a historical phenomenon (as Derrida suggests), not a representation of a

    transcendental universal "self," then Derrida has effectively laid the foundation for a

    critique of public policy. Policy based on the identity (X) may ignore the needs (material

    and ideal) of (X1), (X2), and (X3). In general, policy based on (X) may violate the sense

    of "justice" contained within alternative normative grammars. With one universal

    definition of "subjectivity," justice is reduced to ethnocentric bias and the power to

    enforce it.10

    Derrida's critique of modern epistemology, and the "subjectivity" contained

    within it, explain the resistance of (X1), (X2), and (X3) to policy (Y). If policy (Y)

    requires the adoption of the normative grammar, identity, and ideals of (X) in order to be

    effective, then (Y) is rationally resisted by all who would not seek to become (X).

    C. Public Policy as "Text": Defending the Normative Ideal Through Intervention

    Public policy, simply stated, is what government does. As described above,

    Derrida describes the mechanism by which text validates behavior through grafting onto

    other texts. There is, however, a reciprocal process that takes place in this relationship

    among "subjectivity," policy, and normative goals. The parameters of government action

    are drawn by the content of "subjectivity" within the dominant, power controlling,

    culture. But government action also shapes the content of "subjectivity" by creating a

    disciplinary structure of rewards and punishments within the collective. Behavior that is

    consistent with the dominant normative grammar finds rewards, behavior that is not finds

    punishment.11

    In more subtle ways, however, the text of "subjectivity" shapes government

    activity. Tax systems that reward private capital, home ownership, and the nuclear family

  • 25

    have their foundation within the onto-theology of the subject. Where such goals are not

    embraced or pursued through explicit forms of behavior, the strategy known as

    "intervention" is used.

    Intervention is designed to alter patterns of activity in the targets of the

    intervention. It is a strategy used by the state to homogenize a plurality of alternative

    conceptions of the self. In what Polsky has identified as the growth area for intervention,

    the underclass, interventionist strategies take the form of eliminating those behaviors that

    are outside the norm. (Polsky 1991, 203) Targets for intervention are pressured to modify

    behaviors not consistent with the mainstream. (Polsky 1991, 16.) The intervention may

    take the form of guidance or coercion, but both are reinforced by various forms of

    surveillance.

    Once the dominant social pattern is established the state can sanction agents as the

    protectors of the archival values. Intervention is warranted against all who do not share

    the normative ideal. They are to be directed to "healthy" practices that will better assist

    them in "realizing their potential."12

    (Bermant and Warwick, in Bermant, Kelman, and

    Warwick, 1978, 382) The decision to alter a subjects behavior can be made by any of

    society's agents, including: teachers, therapists, police, contracting agencies, the courts, or

    other "legitimate" arms of intervention. (Stolz in Bermant, Kelman, and Warwick, 1978,

    40)

    Because it devalues personal autonomy, the practitioners of intervention suggest

    the ethics of interventions must be considered before interventions takes place. The

    inequality of power between the intervener and the target, however, is not the central

    issue. That is taken as a given. (Bermant and Warwick in Bermant, Kelman, and

    Warwick, 1978, 378) The "legitimacy" of the agents of interventions must be assured if

    the intervention is to be considered ethically justified. (Kelman and Warwick in Bermant,

    Kelman, and Warwick, 1978, 17) Who is it that confers legitimacy within the modern

  • 26

    state? It is the state itself, as the keeper of the idealized subject, a reflection of the norms,

    values, and aspirations of the dominant culture.

    Government policy both represents the dominant form of subjectivity found in the

    society and acts as a repository and gatekeeper for changes and challenges manifesting

    themselves within the culture. Public policy organizes and legitimates the selection

    process of the ideas to be transmitted through the cultural institutions such as schools,

    business practices, the military, and the media. As the regulator of the process, the state

    can effectively delegitimate ideas that question the status quo. The "truth" of the ideas

    being transmitted through the cultural mechanism is demonstrated by the "success" of the

    icons that emerge at the top of the economic hierarchy. The message is that those who

    conform find success, measured at the very least by employment, and those that do not

    can "rationally" be made to do so through any means necessary. In this sense, the "truth"

    of the dominant definition of "subjectivity" is "proven" by the economic rewards it

    produces for the believers.

    The process of "self-validation" also produces other cultural manifestations as the

    dominant text on "subjectivity" digests and eliminates other competing definitions. In the

    United States this subtle (and often not so subtle) form of imposing the homogenization

    of cultures results in the irony of Native Americans and African Americans celebrating

    European culture and worshipping European gods. The processes involved in the

    promotion of "wedfare" or "bridefare," as part of the welfare reform proposals of the

    1990's, are not structurally different from these other forms of discipline that have been

    imposed on alternative texts of the "subject."

    The institutional structure that maintains the power to define the metaphors, the

    linkages, and the traces that are the elements of any political discourse will have effective

    political control over the outcome of public debate. Even in a democratic state the ability

    to make the scission one way rather than another determines the outcome of the policy

    process. Deconstruction serves as a method to both peel away the layers of previous

  • 27

    traces and to demonstrate the linkages of any sign to the other signs from which it derives

    its meaning. Therefore, it is a method to uncover structures of power that underlie the

    public policy and the way in which this power is used to reinforce the norms, symbols,

    and "truth" contained in the dominant culture.

    Conclusion: Community, Identity, and the Totalitarian Potential

    In challenging what he considers the logocentrism of the Western tradition,

    Jacques Derrida argues that the fixed identities of objects that are supposedly given to us

    by language are not that at all. Language is a play of signs in which signs refer only to

    other signs. The transcendental signified, the pure "being" to which signifiers supposedly

    refer, is a speculative metaphysical premise that has served in the role of providing a

    foundation for the construction of a deductive system of knowledge. On that foundation a

    logocentric tradition was built that allowed the exercise of political authority. Derrida's

    method reveals how the system of positive knowledge reinforced itself through the

    process of its own transmission. Sign was laid upon sign, the traces of traces,

    representing the history of the process of signification within the Western culture. When

    read as the text of the Western world, the traces can be peeled back, as an anthropology of

    the sign.

    If Derrida's assertions are considered, and the truth they contain is an absence of

    any one truth, then the deconstructive enterprise uncovers the prejudices, biases, and

    ethnocentrism of the language that informs political behavior. As collective institutional

    behavior, public policy is linked to a reciprocating activity in which the production of

    signs reinforces the foundations which make particular institutional patterns, normative

    grammars, and disciplinary activities appear as rational. To Derrida, peeling back the text

    to uncover the pattern of traces carried from previous texts makes evident the claim that

    the "column of truth," does not exist.

  • 28

    The issue raised by Derrida's deconstructive method, that politics extends the

    myth of subjectivity through the use of coercive power, has implications beyond the

    specific historical constellation of power found in the modern nation state. The

    deconstructive method can be equally applied to all forms of collective association. In

    delineating the mechanism by which historically contingent definitions of the subject

    become the foundational basis for public action, Derrida exposes the tension between

    majoritarian democracy and the idea of plurality as another form of the tension between

    the community and the individual. If there is nothing other than "text," there is also no

    singular "truth" to validate collective behavior in any form. In drawing us to that

    conclusion, Derrida raises serious questions about the possibility of politics being

    anything other than the imposition of ideology through the use of overt and covert forms

    of coercion.

    This conclusion clearly raises questions about the reconstitution of the political

    community. Taking into account the conditions that surround the construction of public

    policy it does not appear that the concept of community has a benign nature.

    Communities are organized around singularities, not pluralities. The content of

    community myths, metaphors, and ideals have persuasive force as a result of their

    distinctive character. They carry power by the very fact of what they are not. They

    delineate, separate, and distinguish one group from another. In that sense, political

    communities are exclusive.

    The exclusivity of the community is the corollary of the inclusive nature of

    internal policy. Policy seeks to draw all into the community, its norms, values, and

    processes. It seeks to make all part of its exclusive domain through the strategy of

    homogenization. The power to impose a singular definitional content onto the human

    being is the power to control the lives and destinies of all who fall within the domain of

    the political life. Public acquiescence is secured through the combination of rhetorical

    illusions and the exercise of collective force.

  • 29

    Is public policy possible in the wake of a Derridean deconstruction? It must be

    assumed that govenments will always engage is some form of collective action, so the

    real question is what should public policy look like in the wake of this critique.

    Governments must recognize that there is not one right way to live that can be supported

    either by scientific technique or a notion of transcendental truth. They need to take into

    account that there are multiple definitions of subjectivity that produce different forms of

    the “good life.” Can this be reconciled with the bureacratic form of state organization?

    That appears unlikely. Positivistic approaches to policy promote a bureaucratic form of

    social life, not personal freedom. The outcomes of such a process serve institutional

    requirements for the orderly administration of individuals, not individual need. The result

    is a system of manipulation and control. Derrida’s analysis reveals the paradox hidden in

    the Western democracies that pursue such a singular approach to policy making. The

    attempts to impose a correct way to live incorporate a totalitarian ethos even though the

    decision making process may be carried out with democratic procedures.

    Accounting for plurality is the challenge for the postmodern political world. As

    long as organized authority believes it can impose a singular answer to the question of

    “how to live” through legal statute, institutions will be perceived as the arm of oppression

    by marginalized groups. In that sense, the recent welfare reforms represent a step

    backward as the disciplinary authority of the state aims at imposing a way of life rather

    than allowing each community and each individual the power to seek their own answers

    to the questions posed by life.

    Selected References Bermant, Gordon, Herbert Kelman and Donald Warwick. 1978. The Ethics of Social Intervention. Washington: Hemisphere Publishing. Braybrooke, David. 1987. Meeting Needs. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • 30

    Conniff, Ruth. 1992. "Punishment is no Cure of Poverty." Los Angeles Times. January 10. Caraley, Demetrios 1996. “Dismantling the Federal Safety Net: Fictions versus Realities” Political Science Quarterly, 111:2 Derrida, Jacques. 1976. Of Grammatology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Derrida, Jacques. 1978a. Writing and Difference. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Derrida, Jacques. 1978b. "Coming into One's Own." in Geoffrey H. Hartman, ed. Psychoanalysis and the Question of the Text. Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press. Derrida, Jacques. 1981a. Dissemination. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Derrida, Jacques. 1981b. Positions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Derrida, Jacques. 1982a. Margins of Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Derrida, Jacques. 1982b. Spurs: Nietzsche's Styles. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Derrida, Jacques. 1982c. "Sending: On Representation." Social Research. 49:294-326. Derrida, Jacques. 1983a. "The Principle of Reason: The University in the Eyes of its Pupils." Diacritics 19:3-20. Derrida, Jacques. 1983b. "Geschlecht - Sexual Difference, Ontological Difference." Research in Phenomenology. 8:65-83 Derrida, Jacques. 1984. "No Apocalypse, Not Now." Diacritics. Summer Derrida, Jacques. 1987. The Post Card. Chicago: University of Chicago Press Dews, Peter. 1987. Logic of Disintegration. New York: Verso Press Dolbeare, Kenneth M. 1982. American Public Policy. New York: McGraw-Hill Company. Edelman, Murry. 1971. Politics as Symbolic Action. San Diego: Academic Press. Edelman, Murry. 1988. Constructing the Political Spectacle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Fischer, Frank and Carmen Sirianni. 1984. Critical Studies in Organization and Bureaucracy, Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Foucault, Michel. 1973. The Order of Things. New York: Vintage Foucault, Michel. 1980. Power/Knowledge. edited by Colin Gordon. New York: Pantheon Frank, Manfred. 1989. What is Neostructuralism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press

  • 31

    Hoy, David. "Jacque Derrida." in Quentin Skinner, ed. The Return of Grand Theory in the Human Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Ingwerson, Marshall. 1992. "Wisconsin Leads Welfare Reform." Christian Science Monitor. April 19. King, Wayne. 1992. "Carrots, Sticks and 363,000 People's Lives." New York Times, February, 10. Koch, Andrew M. 1993. "Poststructuralism and the Epistemological Basis of Anarchism," The Philosophy of the Social Sciences 23:3 Lasch, Christopher. 1995. The Revolt of the Elites and the Betrayal of Democracy. New York: Norton Lindblom, Charles. 1965. The Intelligence of Democracy. New York: Free Press. Llewelyn, John. 1988. "The Origin and End of Philosophy." in Hugh Silverman, ed. Philosophy and Non-Philosophy Since Merleau-Ponty. New York: Routledge. 191-210 Mason, Richard O. and Ian I. Mitroff. 1981. Challenging Strategic Planning Assumptions. New York: John Wiley and Sons. Macdonell, Diane. 1987. Theories of Discourse. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Norris, Christopher. 1987. Derrida. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Offe, Claus. 1987. "The Structural Foundations of Neoconservative Political Opportunities." Political Theory. 15:4 501-537. Page, Clarence. 1992. "The Flip Side of Welfare Reform." Chicago Tribune. February 9. Paris, David adn James F. Reynolds. 1983. The Logic of Policy Inquiry. New York: Longman. Piven, Frances Fox. Cloward, Richard A. 1971. Regulating the Poor: The Functions of Public Welfare. New York: Vintage. Polsky, Andrew. 1991. The Rise of the Therapeutic State, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Postman, Neil. 1992. Technopoly: The Surrender of Culture to Technology, New York: Knopf Sallis, John. ed. Deconstruction and Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press Shapiro, M. J. 1988 The Politics of Representation: Writing, Practices in Biography, Photography, and Policy Analysis. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Shapiro, M. J. 1992. Reading the Postmodern Polity: Political Theory as Textual Practice. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Stein, Herman D. 1968. Social Theory and Social Intervention. Cleveland: Case Western Reserve Press.

  • 32

    Stone, Deborah. 1988. Policy Paradox and Political Reason. Glenview, Illinois: Scott Foresman and Company. Tullock, Gordon and Richard E. Wagner. Editors. 1978. Policy Analysis and Deductive Reasoning. Lexington Mass.: Lexington Books. Wildavsky, Aaron. Speaking Truth to Power. Boston: Little Brown. Wolin, Sheldon. 1987. "The Political and Theoretical Connection Between Staatsraeson and Wohlfarhtsstaatsraeson." Political Theory 15:4 467-500.

    1 For a discussion of the various issues and positions on welfare reform see: King (1992),

    Page (1992), Conniff (1992), and Ingwerson (1992), Caraley (1996). 2 See Piven and Cloward (1971), Moynihan (1968), Wolin (1988).

    3 See Fischer (1984), Offe (1988), Dolbeare (1982).

    4 See Andrew Koch, "Poststructuralism and the Epistemological Basis of Anarchism,"

    The Philosophy of the Social Sciences, volume 23:3, September 1993. 5 Versions of this can be found in Mason and Mitroff (1981), Stone (1988), Wildavsky

    (1979). 6 For a discussion of the link between the Being and political power in Heidegger see

    “Letter on Humanism (Heidegger 1977) 7 One finds a parallel expression in Paris and Reynolds in the "underdetermined" nature

    of rational ideologies. (1983, p. 210.) 8 These positive assertions take the character of "representations" of truth, whether within

    the classical episteme of "appearance" or in the modern episteme of "function." See Foucault, The Order of Things 9 Derrida admits that this would also make his own text undecidable. (1982b, p. 137.)

    10 Here it should be noted that the Paris and Reynolds claim that "rational ideology" may

    be plural is incoherent. A plurality of ideological presuppositions must produce conflicting policy prescriptions and interventionist strategies. 11

    The disciplinary power of the system of rewards and punishment finds some of its most obvious manifestations in the pre-modern prohibitions on so-called "victimless crimes." Systems of punishment for actions such as prostitution, drug use, gambling, etc., deny the voluntarism that is part of the modern, Enlightenment definition of the "subject." It is clearly ironic that voluntarism is denied in these areas but is stressed in regard to the poor taking responsibility for their poverty. 12

    It is also suggested by Bermant and Warwick that if the problem is defined properly an explanation of why intervention was necessary should not be required.