Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    1/100

    THE INEQUITY OF THE PROGRESSIVE

    INCOME TAX

    KIP HAGOPIAN

    A SMARTER APPROACH TO THE YUAN

    CHARLES WOLF, JR.

    AMERICAS FADING MIDDLE EAST INFLUENCE

    SHMUEL BAR

    THE EUROPEAN UNION GOES EAST

    BRUCE PITCAIRN JACKSON

    ALSO: ESSAYS AND REVIEWS BY

    JOSEPH BOTTUM, LIAM JULIAN, DAVID SHORR,PETER BERKOWITZ, HENRIK BERING

    April & May 2011, No. 166, $6.00PO

    LICYReview

    A Publ icat ion of the Hoover Inst itut ionstanford uni vers i ty

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    2/100

    the hoover institution was established at StanfordUniversity in 1919 by Herbert Hoover, a member of Stanfordspioneer graduating class of 1895 and the thirty-first president ofthe United States. Since 1919 the Institution has evolved from a

    library and repository of documents to an active public policyresearch center. Simultaneously, the Institution has evolved into aninternationally recognized library and archives housing tens ofmillions of books and documents relating to political, economic,and social change.

    The Hoover Institutions overarching purposes are:

    To collect the requisite sources of knowledge pertaining toeconomic, political, and social changes in societies at home

    and abroad, as well as to understand their causes and conse-quences

    To analyze the effects of government actions relating to pub-lic policy

    To generate, publish, and disseminate ideas that encouragepositive policy formation using reasoned arguments andintellectual rigor, converting conceptual insights into practicalinitiatives judged to be beneficial to society

    To convey to the public, the media, lawmakers, and others

    an understanding of important public policy issues and topromote vigorous dialogue

    Ideas have consequences, and a free flow of competing ideas leadsto an evolution of policy adoptions and associated consequencesaffecting the well-being of a free society. The Hoover Institutionendeavors to be a prominent contributor of ideas having positiveconsequences.

    In the words of President Hoover:

    This Institution supports the Constitution of the UnitedStates, its Bill of Rights, and its method of representative

    government. Both our social and economic systems are basedon private enterprise from which springs initiative andingenuity. . . . The Federal Government should undertake no

    governmental, social or economic action, except where local government, or the people, cannot undertake it forthemselves. . . . The overall mission of this Institution is . . .to recall the voice of experience against the making of war,and . . . to recall mans endeavors to make and preserve

    peace, and to sustain for America the safeguards of theAmerican way of life. . . . The Institution itself mustconstantly and dynamically point the road to peace, to

    personal freedom, and to the safeguards of the Americansystem.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    3/100

    POLICYReviewAPRIL & MAY 2011, No. 166

    Features

    3 THE INEQUITY OF THE PROGRESSIVE INCOME TAX

    Working harder and paying more

    Kip Hagopian

    29 A SMARTER APPROACH TO THE YUAN

    Avoid the rush to rebalanceCharles Wolf, Jr.

    41 AMERICAS FADING MIDDLE EAST INFLUENCE

    Speaking softly, wielding no sticks

    Shmuel Bar

    53 THE EUROPEAN UNION GOES EAST

    A patient policy of long-term partnership

    Bruce Pitcairn Jackson

    Books

    65 BEING T.E. LAWRENCE

    Joseph Bottum on Hero: The Life and Legend of Lawrence of Arabia

    by Michael Korda.

    70 BETTER BRAIN SCIENCE

    Liam Julian on Moonwalking with Einstein: The Art and Science of

    Remembering Everything byJoshua Foer andThe Most Human Human:

    What Talking with Computers Teaches Us About What It Means to Be

    Alive by Brian Christian.

    76 POWER AND ARROGANCE

    David Shorr on The End of Arrogance: America in the Global

    Competition of Ideas by Steven Weber and Bruce Jentleson.

    82 THE GOLDSTONE MESS

    Peter Berkowitz on The Goldstone Report: The Legacy of the Landmark

    Investigation of the Gaza Conflict edited by Adam Horowitz, Lizzy

    Ratner, and Philip Weiss.

    88 HOW PEACE GETS MADE

    Henrik Bering on How Wars End by Gideon Rose.

    A Publ i cat i o n o f th e Ho o ver I nst i tut i o nstanfo rd uni vers i ty

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    4/100

    PO

    LICYReview

    Policy Review (issn 0146-5945) is published bimonthly by the

    Hoover Institution, Stanford University. For more information,

    write: The Hoover Institution, Stanford University, Stanford ca

    94305-6010. Or visit www.hoover.org. Periodicals postage paid at

    Washington dc and additional mailing offices. POSTMASTER:

    Send address changes to Policy Review, Subscription Fulfillment,

    P.O. Box 37005 , Chicago, il 6 0 63 7 - 00 0 5 . The opinions

    expressed in Policy Review are those of the authors and do not nec-

    essarily reflect the views of the Hoover Institution, Stanford

    University, or their supporters.

    Ed i to r i al and bus i ness o ff i ces : Policy Review,

    21 Dupont Circle nw , Suite 310, Washington, d c 20036.

    Telephone: 202-466-3121. Email: [email protected].

    Website: www.policyreview.org.

    Subscription information: For new orders, call or write the

    subscriptions department at Policy Review, Subscription Fulfillment,

    P.O. Box 37005, Chicago, il 60637. Order by phone Monday

    through Friday, 8 a.m. to 5 p.m. Central Time, by calling (773)

    753-3347, or toll-free in the U.S. and Canada by calling (877)

    705-1878. For questions about existing orders please call 1-800-

    935-2882. Single back issues may be purchased at the cover price

    of$6 by calling 1-800-935-2882. Subscription rates: $36 peryear. Add $10 per year for foreign delivery. Copyright 2011 by the

    Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University.

    A p r il & May 2011, No. 166

    Editor

    Tod Lindberg

    Research Fellow, Hoover Institution

    Consulting EditorMary Eberstadt

    Research Fellow, Hoover Institution

    Managing Editor

    Liam Julian

    Research Fellow, Hoover Institution

    Office Manager

    Sharon Ragland

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    5/100

    Class Wars: A Parable

    Once upon a time in the land of America, there lived tripletbrothers named Tom, Dick, and Harry Class. They were 45

    years old, had virtually the same aptitude (skill), and were

    raised in the same home. Each was married and had two chil-

    dren. All three were employed as carpenters making $25 per

    hour, working 50 weeks a year.

    While they were almost identical in most respects, they had somewhat dif-

    ferent preferences and values. For example, Tom, who worked 20 hours a

    week, had a different work ethic from his brothers, Dick and Harry, whoeach worked 60 hours per week. Neither Toms nor Dicks wives worked,

    while Harrys wife worked 40 hours per week as an office manager making

    $50,000 per year (the same hourly rate as her husband). Tom and Dick

    The Inequity of the

    Progressive Income TaxBy Kip Hagopian

    Kip Hagopian was a co-founder of Brentwood Associates, a California-basedventure capital and private equity firm. This essay is an abridged version of a paper which is available in its entirety and for comment atwww.kiphagopian.com.

    April & May 2011 3 Policy Review

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    6/100

    4 Policy Review

    spent all of their income, and were relying on Social Security to take care of

    them when they retired. Harry and his wife, on the other hand, saved most

    of her after-tax income over many years, gradually accumulating

    $300,000. They invested this money in bonds and real estate that produced

    $25,000 a year in interest and rental income. This was the income of each

    family:

    FamilyTom Dick Harry

    Work hours per Week: 20 60 100

    Annual Wages

    Husband: $25,000 $75,000 $75,000

    Wife: 0 0 50,000Investment Income: 0 0 25,000

    Total Income: $25,000 $75,000 $150,000

    Despite their different priorities, the Class families were close; so much so

    that when a new housing tract was developed in their community, they each

    bought an equal-priced home on the same private street. Theirs were the

    only houses on the street.One day the brothers decided to pool their funds for the purpose of

    improving their street. Concerned about crime and safety, and desirous of a

    more attractive setting for their homes, the three families decided to: install a

    gate at the streets entrance to deter burglars; add lighting for safety and

    additional security; repave the streets surface to repair damage; and install

    landscaping to beautify the approach to their homes. The work was done

    for a total cost of$30,000.

    The brothers were quite happy with the outcome and felt the $30,000was a worthy expenditure given the benefits provided each family. But when

    it came time to divide up the bill, the problems began.

    Harry thought it would be simple to divide the bill. Since the benefits to

    each family were equal, each brother should pay one-third, or about

    $10,000. But Tom and Dick objected. Why should we pay the same as

    you? they said. You make much more money than we do. Harry was

    puzzled. Why is that relevant? he asked. My family makes more money

    than yours does because my wife and I work long hours and we earn extra

    money on our savings. Why should we be penalized for working and sav-

    ing? Harry looked at Tom and said, Im no smarter or more talented than

    you are. If you and your wife worked harder and saved more you would

    make as much as my family does. To which Tom replied, I dont work

    more because I value my leisure time more than I value money. And I dont

    save because I prefer the gratification of consumption today more than I will

    when Im too old to enjoy it. Tom was adamant. How could Harry, who

    was clearly rich, ask him to pay the same amount, when it was obviously

    harder for him to do so?

    Kip Hagopian

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    7/100

    Dick thought for a moment, and then said, Ive got an idea. Our aggre-

    gate income is $250,000, and $30,000 is 12 percent of that amount. Why

    dont we each pay that percentage of our income? Under that formula, Tom

    would owe $3,000 , I would owe $9,000 , and Harry would owe$18,000. Since I make three times as much as Tom, I would pay three times

    as much. Harry, who makes twice as much as me and six times as much as

    Tom would pay two times as much as me and six times as much as Tom.

    No, said Tom. No? Dick and Harry responded in unison. Why

    not? What do you propose instead? asked Harry. Tom was ready with his

    answer. Paying the same percentage of our income is not fair. Instead,

    Harry, you pay $23,450; Dick, you pay $6,550; and I will pay nothing.

    This is the only fair division. Dick was surprised at how completely arbi-trary this proposal was. He was also surprised at how disproportionate it

    was, but since his suggested share was significantly less than under his own

    proposal, he didnt object. Harry, however, was stunned. You call that

    fair?! I make only two times as much as Dick, but you want me to pay

    three-and-a-half times as much as he does. I make six times as much as you

    but you expect me to pay almost 80 percent of the total cost while you pay

    nothing. And this is despite the fact that each of us is receiving the exact

    same benefits. Where did you get such a crazy idea? he asked. From noless an authority than the federal government, said Tom as he pulled out a

    gray booklet. Its all right here in the irs tax tables. Under the current tax

    code, here is what each of us paid in income taxes last year:

    Family

    Tom Dick Harry Total

    Income $25,000 $75,000 $150,000 $250,000

    Taxes Paid

    1

    0 6,550 23,450 30,000Effective tax rate 0% 8.7% 15.6% 12%

    By an amazing coincidence, our total taxes paid were exactly equal to

    the $30,000 expended on our street improvements. This is the progressive

    income tax system all U.S. taxpayers live under, and I dont see why the

    Class families should be different. In fact, I believe all future pooling of

    funds should be divided in this way. Im in, said Dick. So, by a vote of

    two to one, the cost of the street improvements was divided as follows:

    Tom Dick Harry Total

    Dollars $0 $6,550 $23,450 $30,000

    Percentage 0% 21.8% 78.2% 100%

    April & May 2011 5

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

    1. The tax figures were calculated by The Shapiro Group, a Los Angeles tax accounting firm. The mar-ginal rates and brackets are those applicable for the 2010 tax year. These figures are for illustration pur-poses only. They do not include the effect of certain tax credits (which some would consider transfer pay-

    ments) that exist in the law. If these credits were included, Harry would pay a tax of$22,600, Dickwould pay a tax of$3,700 and Tom would receive a refundof$7,100.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    8/100

    6 Policy Review

    Also by a vote of two to one, all future pooling of funds was to be divided

    up the same way.

    Like all parables, the story of the Class brothers is designed to

    illustrate a moral principle. In this tale, Harry is required to pay a

    disproportionate amount of the cost and value of the benefits he

    derives from his mini-society, simply because his family works harder

    than the families of the societys other members. The moral question is: Is

    Harry being treated fairly? If not, how should this affect our thinking about

    progressive taxation?

    In the United States, the payment of taxes is effectively a pooling ofmoney by the nations citizens to fund the services of government. These

    services include, but are not limited to: the national defense, infrastructure,

    the judicial court system, police and fire protection (delivered at the federal,

    state, and local levels), education (delivered at the state and local level), the

    general administration of government, and support for truly needy citizens.

    Deciding how much money should be appropriated for this pool and how

    it should be spent is almost always a subject of contentious debate. The

    same is true when deciding how taxes should be apportioned. As to the lat-ter, the debate inevitably devolves into an argument over fairness and eco-

    nomic efficiency.

    The primary source of federal tax revenues (excluding Social Security and

    Medicare taxes) is a progressive tax on the earned income of individuals.2

    This essay will make the case that the progressive income tax is plainly

    inequitable. It will also review the alternatives to progression in an effort to

    identify the most equitable (or least inequitable) tax system.

    Factors that determine income

    Americas free enterprise system provides an environment

    in which the substantial majority of its citizens can realize their

    fullest earnings potential. Within that environment, individual

    economic outcomes are the product of a combination of three elements:

    aptitude, work effort, and choice of occupation.

    Aptitude.3 For the purposes of this essay, aptitude is broadly defined asthe capacity to produce, or to earn income. For the most part, it comes from

    Kip Hagopian

    2. There are several other types of taxes levied by federal, state, and city governments, including taxes oncapital gains, dividends, estates, sales, and property. These tax systems are outside the scope of this essay.

    3. As defined here, the term aptitude is similar to but distinct from other terms used in the literature todescribe capacity to earn: 1) endowment, which, in this context, is synonymous with genetic inheri-tance and is, therefore, too limiting; 2) faculty, which, like aptitude connotes capacity to earn, but is

    also used in the literature to describe financial wherewithal; and 3) ability, which, like faculty, is usedto describe either capacity to earn or financial wherewithal.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    9/100

    circumstances of birth and is distributed unequally. Aptitude may be derived

    from innate talents (cognitive, musical, artistic, athletic, etc.) or physical

    attributes (appearance, dexterity, possession of senses, etc.). Or it may be

    acquired from lessons learned from parents and other life experiences.Aptitude emanating from circumstances of birth (either innate or acquired)

    can be significantly enhanced by individual effort applied to strengthening

    ones skills (see Work Effort below). Aptitude is measured from low to

    high in accordance with the monetary value placed on it in the marketplace.

    This is a measure of earning power and is not in any way an indication of an

    individuals intrinsic worth as a human being. For most people aptitude is

    the most significant determinant of income. But it has to be understood as

    capacity; aptitude does not produce income until itis combined with individual effort.Work effort. For any given level of aptitude and

    occupation, work effort plays the decisive role in

    determining income, and in many cases may result

    in persons with lower aptitudes earning more than

    their higher-aptitude peers. For the purposes of this

    essay, the term work effort includes not only the

    number of hours worked, but also the intensity ofthe effort applied during those hours. As notedabove, it also includes work effort applied to

    strengthening ones skills.

    At every level of aptitude and in every profession,

    whether the pay is in salary or hourly wages, there

    are workers who outperform their peers in each

    hour worked. They do this by performing tasks more quickly; focusing on

    the tasks more intently; finding and completing additional tasks that need tobe done; and using some of their leisure time practicing or training to

    become more skilled. These people get more raises, larger bonuses, and

    more promotions than their peers. Thus, greater work effort can produce

    higher income whether the person is paid by the hour or earns a salary.

    In addition to producing higher income in its own right, work effort

    applied to strengthening ones skill resulting in learned or enhanced

    aptitude can make a substantial contribution toward increasing income.

    The rough carpenter who spends nights and weekends developing the

    skills necessary to qualify as a more highly valued finish carpenter will

    move up the wage scale by doing so. Professional athletes, musicians,

    singers, and other performers can enhance their innate aptitudes substantial-

    ly through extensive practice, and a great many are renowned for having

    done so. A classic example is Hall-of-Famer Jerry Rice, who is generally rec-

    ognized as the best wide receiver in nfl history. He was one of the highest

    paid players in pro football for twenty years, an achievement largely credited

    to his intense practice and workout regimen. Perhaps the most effective way

    of enhancing aptitude is through increased study in school. Whether it is

    April & May 2011 7

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

    Paying the same

    percentage of

    our income is not

    fair. Instead,

    Harry, you pay

    $23,450; Dick,you pay $6,550;

    and I will pay

    nothing.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    10/100

    8 Policy Review

    grade school, high school, vocational school or college, for any particular

    tier of aptitude, those who study the most almost always get the best grades,

    matriculate to the best colleges, and secure the best jobs.

    Choice of occupation. Choice of occupation is also important in deter-mining income. Had Bill Gates decided to finish Harvard and become a highschool math teacher, he almost certainly would have been successful, but he

    would not have become a multi-billionaire.

    Earned income is determined by a mix of the three factors described

    above, and the relative contribution of each varies by individual.

    Understanding the primary determinants of income and the implications of

    each for tax policy are essential to designing the most equitable tax system.

    Surprisingly, the literature contains only infrequent and oblique references tothis crucial aspect of tax theory.

    Alternative income tax systems

    There is a consensus among economists and tax theorists that the

    best tax system is one that strikes the optimum balance between

    economic efficiency and equity. An efficient tax system is one thatdoes the least to distort the allocation of resources in the economy, thus

    maximizing overall production. Accordingly, taxes that might alter con-

    sumer or investor behavior should be eschewed. As to equity, there is virtual-

    ly unanimous agreement among scholars that the tax system should be

    fair. Unfortunately, there is great disagreement as to which system best

    meets this criterion.

    There are basically four systems of income taxation described in the liter-

    ature:A per-capita, or head tax, which would require each person to pay hisor her per-capita share of the costs of government. (Technically a per-capita

    tax is not an income tax, but it is almost universally accepted as the most

    economically efficient tax system.)

    A proportionate or flat tax, which would tax each dollar of income ata single rate. Embodied in virtually all proportionate tax proposals is a sub-

    stantial broadening of the tax base through the elimination of most tax

    deductions, credits, and preferences, which has the benefit of simplifying the

    tax code and reducing the cost of compliance. The purest form of this sys-

    tem is a single-rate tax levied on all earned income from the first dollar, but

    different variations on this theme have been proposed.

    A degressive tax, which is a proportionate tax only on income above acertain threshold or exemption. The exemption makes the system progres-

    sive, but typically much less so than a system of graduated rates.

    A progressive tax, which taxes incremental income at higher marginalrates as income rises, resulting in an increase in taxes as a percentage ofincome as income increases.

    Kip Hagopian

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    11/100

    Each of these systems will be examined as part of the analysis of progres-

    sive taxation.

    The case for progression

    Progression has been in use somewhere in the world for

    more than two thousand years. And it is safe to say the debate on

    its merits goes back just as far. At present, the substantial majority

    of nations employ some form of progressive taxation.

    The first time a federal income tax was imposed in the United States was

    in 1861 as a means of financing the Civil War. The tax rates were decreasedafter the war and the income tax was allowed to expire in 1872. The con-

    cept of an income tax was legally quite controversial; so when a new income

    tax was levied in 1894, it was challenged in the courts, and in 1895 was

    found to be unconstitutional. It was not until 1913, with the ratification of

    the 16th Amendment to the Constitution, that the first constitutionally sanc-

    tioned income tax was enacted (which, incidentally, was progressive).

    Throughout history, many arguments have been advanced both for and

    against the progressive income tax. One of the most comprehensive exami-nations of the subject in the 20th century was a book published in 1953

    and reissued in 1963 , The Uneasy Case for Progressive Taxation, byProfessors Walter J. Blum and Harry Kalven of the University of Chicago

    Law School. This book is an exhaustive review of the prior literature on this

    topic, interspersed with the authors own analyses and critiques of the argu-

    ments presented. In their words, the book is, an effort to explore what

    might be called the intellectual case for progression.4 Another particularly

    useful source of information and analysis was a book-length article pub-lished in 1908 in the American Economic Association Quarterly,Progressive Taxation in Theory and Practice, by the noted economist and

    tax historian, Edwin R.A. Seligman.5

    According to Blum and Kalven, the most rigorous analysis of progres-

    sion came only after the idea had become a political reality . . . whatever the

    reasons, it is clear that the political history affords little insight into the mer-

    its of the principle of progression.6

    The arguments in supportof progression tend to fall into three main cate-gories:7 economic efficiency, fairness, and reduction of income inequality.

    April & May 2011 9

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

    4. Edward Blum and Harry Kalven, The Uneasy Case of Progressive Taxation (University of ChicagoPress, 1953).

    5. Edwin R.A. Seligman, Progressive Taxation in Theory and Practice (Princeton University Press, 1908).

    6. Blum and Kalven, 14 .

    7. Some advocates of progression argue that a progressive income tax is needed to offset the putativelyregressive nature of the payroll taxes that fund Social Security and Medicare. The conflation of these

    revenue streams is ill-conceived, inasmuch as each has a different purpose. Income taxes are used to funda broad range of government services as described above, while payroll levies are collected for the express

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    12/100

    Economic efficiency. The argument is that progressive taxation increasesworker productivity, yielding greater economic efficiency and higher aggre-

    gate incomes. The study of the impact of tax policy on economic efficiency

    and growth has for centuries been a fertile ground for economists, who haveproduced numerous analyses on the topic without reaching clear consensus.

    Since the focus of this essay is on the issue of tax equity, the economic effi-

    ciency arguments will not be discussed beyond noting that logic and the

    weight of empirical evidence appear to favor less progression rather than

    more.

    Fairness. The argument for progressive taxation on fairness grounds hasthree main strains.

    The benefits principle. Taxes are payments made in return for govern-ment services and protections. People with higher incomes have dispro-

    portionately more to lose; therefore, they should pay disproportionate-

    ly more for the protections afforded them by government;

    Sacrifice theory and the marginal utility of money. Taxes are a burdenon society that should be shared in an equitable manner. Burden is

    defined as the sacrifice made by the individual when he or she pays

    taxes. Since the marginal utility of a dollar declines as income rises,higher-income people should pay enough more in taxes to equalize

    their sacrifice relative to the sacrifice of lower-income peers.

    Ability to pay. A fair tax system is one in which those with the greatestability to pay should pay the most.

    Reducing Income Inequality. In this view, inequality is a social injusticethat can be remedied or mitigated by a progressive tax system. It is often

    proffered as an argument for basic fairness, but since proponents haventunited around a specific principle of fairness in its support, we will consider

    it separately.

    We will now examine each of the three fairness arguments in detail, then

    turn to the question of income inequality.

    The benefits principle

    The benefits principle of taxation holds that the government

    provides benefits to its citizens that should be paid for in taxes by

    each beneficiary in accordance with the value he or she receives

    Kip Hagopian

    purpose of providing income supplements and medical care during retirement. More specifically, SocialSecurity levies are a form of forced savings, and Medicare levies are effectively prepaid medical insurancepremiums. Neither of them finances government services per se. Since Social Security benefits when paidout are tied to the aggregate amount paid into the system by each beneficiary, it is inaccurate to call thelevies regressive. In the case of Medicare, the amount paid into the system is proportionate to income

    while the benefits (paid health care) are essentially the same for each beneficiary; consequently, the systemis redistributive.

    10 Policy Review

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    13/100

    from government services. As a basic foundation for taxation, the benefits

    principle also called give and take or quid pro quo has probably

    received more examination and comment than any other. As we will see, the

    statement of the principle payment of taxes in return for benefits lendsitself to widely varying interpretations.

    Historically, the use of the benefits principle to advocate progression

    relied on the protection theory of benefits, which asserts that the govern-

    ments primary function is the protection of property. The theory focuses on

    income as property, and analogizes the protections of government to an

    insurance company that insures property against loss. Those who cite pro-

    tection theory as an argument for progression assert that individuals with

    higher incomes should pay a disproportionately greater share of the cost ofgovernment than lower-income individuals because the higher-income groupwould have disproportionately more to lose if the protections of government

    were withdrawn. Implicit in this interpretation of the principle is not just

    that the value of benefits received from the government increases as income

    increases, but that it increases more rapidly than the rise in income. As wewill see, the statement of the principle payment of taxes in return for ben-

    efits lends itself to widely varying interpretations.

    When examined carefully, the protection theory interpretation of thebenefits principle falls short in five different ways.

    First, the basic premise of the protection theory is flawed. Government

    protections extend to much more than property. The Founding Fathers made

    clear their vision for America in the Declaration of Independence when they

    spoke of the unalienable rights of all Americans to life, liberty and the

    pursuit of happiness. There is no basis for believing that a low-income per-

    sons life is worth more or less to an individual(as contrasted with an insur-

    ance actuary, an economist, or a jury assessing damages in a wrongful deathcase) than the life of a high-income person. The same is true for liberty and

    the pursuit of happiness. The American military and other protective agen-

    cies and institutions of government exist to protect and preserve these rights

    for all Americans equally, regardless of how rich or poor they are.

    Second, there is no persuasive support in the literature for the claim that

    higher-income people derive a disproportionately greater value from govern-

    ment protection of property than lower-income people. Some progression

    advocates have argued that government exists in large part to protect rich

    people from poor people, while poor people need no such protection. Thus,the value of the rich persons protection is disproportionately greater than

    that afforded the poor. Perhaps this was true centuries ago in some feudal

    nations, but it is not now and never has been generally true in the United

    States. Others argue that insurance is priced according to risk as well as

    value, implying that high-value property is at greater risk of loss. While this

    notion has conceptual merit, it does not follow that property owned by

    high-income people is at greater risk than property owned by low-income

    people. In fact, the rich are more likely to engage in self-protection (e.g.,

    April & May 2011 11

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    14/100

    12 Policy Review

    build protective walls, install security systems, hire guards, etc.), which

    would result in reduced, not greater, risk. Seligman, Blum and Kalven, and

    others have examined the property protection arguments for progression

    and dismissed them as either untenably weak or without merit.Third, this interpretation of the benefits principle overlooks the principle

    of marginal utility. If, as virtually all economists agree, the marginal utility of

    a dollar of income declines as income increases, then people would place a

    lower value on protecting their income as it rises. To accept protection theo-

    ry as an argument for progression, one would have to assert that each addi-

    tional dollar of income earned is worth more than the previous dollar ofincome, which is nonsensical.

    Fourth, even if the protection argument had merit, it would, at best, arguefor a proportionate rather than a progressive tax. To argue otherwise

    requires a belief that the price of property insurance increases faster than the

    value of the property (in this case, income), which is observably untrue. If the

    insurance analogy were applied, those with two times as much income or

    property would pay two times as much tax, which would be proportionate,

    not progressive. Its no accident that historically almost all exponents of

    benefit theory employed it to support proportion as against progression.8

    Fifth, the analogy to an insurance company is specious. The costs of themilitary and police and fire departments are not equivalent to property and

    casualty insurance, in which the policy is priced in accordance with the value

    of the property insured. There is no material difference in the cost of protect-

    ing persons with high incomes or high-value property than that of persons

    with low incomes or low-value property. (In fact, the cost might be less,

    since persons with high income tend to reside in low-crime areas.)

    Accordingly, there would be no difference in the cost of these protections

    based on property value. Thus, under the protection theory, the fairest taxsystem would more logically be per capita.

    A second interpretation of the benefits principle, and one that appears

    clearly to have more substance and more scholarly support, is that govern-

    ment benefits redound roughly equally to all people regardless of their

    income. More specifically, and as noted in the preceding paragraph, the value

    of benefits relating to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness, including the

    protection of property, is essentially the same for all citizens. Thus, each per-

    son should share the costs of government equally, in which case the fairesttax would be per capita. This is essentially what Harry proposed to hisbrothers as the fairest way of dividing the costs of their street improvements.

    There is yet another interpretation of the benefits principle that is

    arguably superior to the others, because it comes closest to placing a true

    value on the benefits of government. This interpretation posits that the ulti-

    mate benefit of government is the overall well-being each person derives

    from its services.

    Kip Hagopian

    8. Blum and Kalven, 38 . .

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    15/100

    The Class Wars parable imagined a society in which all of the members

    had the same aptitude. But in the broader society, aptitudes are distributed

    widely and unequally. This changes the picture substantially, as we can see

    by means of a simple thought experiment: Assume the societys populationhas a normal (bell curve) distribution of aptitudes. Assume also that all of

    the persons in this society work exactly the same number of hours and at

    exactly the same intensity, resulting in incomes that correlate closely with

    aptitudes. In this hypothetical situation, and within each occupation,

    incomes would vary across a distribution curve almost identical to the apti-

    tude curve. Accordingly, persons with more highly valued aptitudes would

    earn more income than their lower-aptitude counterparts, and thus derive

    greater value from government. It follows, therefore, that, all things beingequal, higher-aptitude people should pay more in taxes than lower-aptitude

    people not because they have more to lose (or to protect), but because

    they receive greater value from their government. Blum and Kalven touchedobliquely on this concept when they noted:

    Another approach [to the benefits theory] is more ingenious. It is found-

    ed on a double assumption: first, that the well-being of men, while not

    caused by the government, is dependent upon it in that government is a

    necessary condition for its existence; second, that the only aspect of well-being which is measurable is wealth or income and that it is therefore

    appropriate to take either of these as an index of the benefits flowing

    from government.9

    It is noteworthy that this ingenious approach is entirely consonant with

    the greater-value interpretation of the benefits principle.

    The greater-value interpretation of the benefits principle is at odds with

    the cost-sharing concept described above (which suggests a per-capita tax),inasmuch as it argues that higher-income people should pay a higher price

    for their benefits because they have received greater value from their govern-

    ment, largely because of a more highly valued aptitude (which is a gift at

    birth) or some other good fortune. The merit of this notion can be inferred

    by imagining that aptitudes could be purchased on the open market. If such

    a thing were possible, it is certain that the more highly valued aptitudes

    those that would produce higher incomes would be bid up to amounts in

    excess of the per-capita cost of government.

    But how much more should higher-income people pay? The major fallacy

    in the use of the benefits principle as an argument for progression is the

    implicit premise that the value of government benefits increases more rapidly

    than income. Under the greater-value theory, since income a proxy for

    well-being is what each individual receives from the economic system,

    income is a reasonable measure of the value each individual receives from

    government. It is reasonable to conclude, therefore, that the fairest tax sys-

    April & May 2011 13

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

    9. Blum and Kalven, 37 . .

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    16/100

    14 Policy Review

    tem is one in which each person pays tax in proportion to his or her income.

    It makes no difference whether the income is derived from aptitude (as

    defined), financial windfalls, random events, or privilege. In all of these

    cases, the tax should be levied in proportion to the value of the benefitsreceived. Thus, a person who earns 10 times as much income as another

    would pay 10 times as much tax, while someone making 100 times as

    much would be taxed 100 times as much.

    A new and important contribution to the debate over fairness emerged in

    the mid-19th century when proponents of proportionate taxation realized

    there were both practical and intellectual reasons for exempting a portion of

    income from taxation. The practical reason was simply the futility of taxing

    that portion of a persons income that was needed for survival. To do sowould be self-defeating, since the hardship imposed would deprive the state

    of production. The intellectual basis for the exemption, from the point of

    view of the state, emanated from the notion that income needed for subsis-

    tence constituted an expense of production, while income above this amount

    was surplus or clear income, i.e., net of production costs (an insight

    attributed to the economist David Ricardo). From the point of view of the

    taxed, government benefits only have real value when the taxpayer earns a

    surplus of income over what is needed for subsistence. Most scholars whosupported a proportionate tax system concluded that taxing only clear

    income was both practical and fair to both the individual and the state. This

    enhancement to the benefits principle, which introduced a mild degree of

    progression by comparison to a pure proportionate tax (a tax from the first

    dollar of income), became known as a degressive tax. It is important to

    note that, among the proponents of the degressive tax, there was clear con-

    sensus that the income exempt from tax should be set no higher than the

    level of subsistence. To do otherwise would be arbitrary and in the opinionof many, inequitable.

    The greater-value interpretation of the benefits principle stands as a rejec-

    tion of a per-capita tax system and as a compelling case for either a propor-

    tionate or a degressive system.

    Sacrifice theory and the marginal

    utility of money

    Sacrifice theory is perhaps the most historically prominent and

    persistent argument in favor of progressive taxation. Stated simply,

    the theory posits that the fairest tax is one that extracts from each

    taxpayer an equal or proportionate sacrifice. The theory rejects the quid-

    pro-quo notion that taxes are remitted in return for government benefits and

    instead treats taxes simply as a burden that must be shared in the most equi-

    table way. Sacrifice theory is dependent upon the economic principle that

    Kip Hagopian

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    17/100

    holds there is a marginal-utility curve for money to the effect that the more

    money one earns, the less utility (or satisfaction) will be derived from the last

    dollar earned. Thus, if you plot a chart in which the vertical axis is units of

    marginal utility a person gets from money, and the horizontal axis is theamount of money the person earns, the curve will eventually have a down-

    ward slope. A downward slope indicates, for example, that an incremental

    $1,000 has greater utility to a person earning $10,000 a year than it has

    to someone earning $100,000.

    The economic principle of marginal utility on which sacrifice theory

    depends is sound. However, there are several difficulties with the sacrifice

    theory itself that render it untenable as an argument for progression.

    First, the basic premise of sacrifice theory is conceptually flawed. Thenotion that taxes are simply a burden that must be tolerated rather than a

    payment for benefits raises the question: Why would the citizens of a democ-

    racy vote to impose taxes on themselves if they did not expect benefits in

    return? And if the government does provide benefits (which of course it

    does), why would the payment of taxes be considered a sacrifice rather than

    a fair payment for value received? Did the Class brothers not receive benefits

    from their street improvements? If they did, what would be the logic of a tax

    based on proportionate sacrifice rather than one based on shared cost orvalue received? On conceptual grounds alone, sacrifice theory appears to be

    a very weak foundation for tax policy.

    Second, the validity of the theory depends on more than just the existence

    of a downward sloping marginal-utility curve. For progression to be justified

    under a theory of equal sacrifice, the curve must not only decline, but

    decline more rapidly than income rises. In the view of British economist

    Arthur Pigou and others, there is no way to prove this is true:

    All that the law of diminishing utility asserts is that the last 1 of a1000 income carries less satisfaction than the last 1 of a 100 income

    does. From this datum it cannot be inferred that, in order to secure equal

    sacrifice . . . taxation must be progressive. In order to prove that the

    principle of equal sacrifice necessarily involves progression we should

    need to know that the last 10 of a 1000 income carries less satisfac-

    tion than the last 1 of a 100 income; and this the law of diminishing

    utility does not assert.10

    Seligman credits the Dutch economist A.J. Cohen-Stuart with debunking

    the notion that there is a universal marginal-utility curve that dictates pro-

    gression. Here Seligman quotes Cohen-Stuart: It is perfectly possible . . . to

    construct tables [curves] which lead not to progression, but to proportion

    and even to regression.11

    April & May 2011 15

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

    10 . Arthur C. Pigou, A Study in Public Finance (Macmillan, 1951), 85-86. .

    11 . Seligman, 219..

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    18/100

    16 Policy Review

    Third, the sacrifice argument for progression is dependent upon the addi-

    tional assumption that the marginal-utility curves of all persons are essential-

    ly the same. While it is well accepted that marginal-utility curves will eventu-

    ally slope downward, it is by no means true that all curves have the sameslope. In fact, in comparing the marginal-utility curves of Tom, Dick, and

    Harry Class, there are any number of reasons why Harrys marginal utility

    curve might decline less steeply than Toms and Dicks. Imagine, for exam-

    ple, that Harry has a learning-disabled son who needs costly special educa-

    tion, or that Harrys wife has an illness that requires expensive medication

    not covered by insurance. Or perhaps Harry has an obsession with saving

    enough money to send his two children to the best private secondary schools

    and universities. Now consider Toms and Dicks situation: Knowing thatHarry is the most industrious of the brothers and was unlikely to need their

    help, Harrys parents made it clear that when they died they would leave all

    of their rather significant estate to the less industrious brothers, leaving

    nothing to Harry. In this event, Toms and Dicks marginal-utility curves are

    affected by their knowledge that they dont need as much income to secure

    their future. Thus, Toms and Dicks marginal-utility curves may have steep-

    er downward slopes than Harrys, even though Harry earns much more

    income. Seligman calls this the very core objection to sacrifice theory:The imposition of equal sacrifices on all taxpayers must always

    remain an ideal impossible of actual realization. Sacrifice denotes some-

    thing psychical; something psychological . . . Two men may have the

    same income, which they may value at very different rates. The one may

    be a bachelor, the other a man with a large family dependent upon him;

    the one may be well, the other ill . . . the one may earn his income, the

    other may receive it as a gift . . . The attempt to ascertain a mathematical

    scale of progression, so as to avoid a charge of arbitrariness, is fore-doomed to failure.12

    This inability to prove the sameness of the marginal-utility curves of dif-

    ferent people troubled Blum and Kalven to the point that they dismissed sac-

    rifice theory as a theory on which to base a fair tax system:

    The error lies in trying to translate money, which can be measured in

    definite units, into corresponding units of satisfaction or well-being. In

    the end satisfaction in the sense of happiness defies quantification. Utility

    is a meaningful concept; units of utility are not. It is in the face of this

    difficulty that, even waiving all other objections, the whole elaborate

    analysis of progression in terms of sacrifice and utility doctrine finally

    collapses.13

    Kip Hagopian

    12 . Seligman, 222-223. .

    13 . Blum and Kalven, 63..

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    19/100

    If there is no accurate way to draw any individuals marginal-utility curve,

    there is no way to compare the curves of different persons. The only things

    that can be stated with confidence are that all persons have marginal-utility

    curves that are ultimately downward sloping and that the slopes of individ-ual curves are determined by many factors in addition to income. And even

    if, as a general proposition, the curves are similar (as intuition would sug-

    gest), there are sufficient variations in them that sacrifice theory could not be

    applied without resulting in the inequitable treatment of an unacceptably

    large portion of the population.

    Fourth, for a substantial (but indeterminate) number of workers

    those who work because they need the money rather than because they

    enjoy it the number of hours they choose towork is determined by the marginal utility of the

    income they earn from that work. Thus, for these

    workers, work effort has its own marginal-utility

    curve that is essentially the same as the marginal-

    utility curve for income. To illustrate: Harrys fami-

    ly chooses to work 100 hours a week, while Toms

    family chooses to work 20 hours a week. Harry

    and his wife work these long hours because themarginal utility of the income produced from the

    extra hours is greater than the marginal utility of

    leisure (up to that point). Conversely, Toms family

    has decided to work only 20 hours per week

    because the additional utility of the income from

    the 21st hour is sufficiently low to him that he

    chooses to forgo it in favor of leisure. In this entirely plausible scenario,

    the marginal utility of one extra dollar to Harry might be equal to themarginal utility of one extra dollar to Tom. It is also plausible that the

    marginal utility of another dollar to Harry is even greater than it is toTom, in which case, under its own logic, sacrifice theory would call for

    taxing Harry less than Tom. In either of these scenarios, taxing Harry at ahigher marginal rate than Tom (as required by a progressive income tax)

    would be inconsonant with sacrifice theory, and by its own standard,

    inequitable.

    Fifth, the application of sacrifice theory would be plainly unfair to the

    people in a society who work the hardest. Among people whose aptitudesare the same, the only way one person can earn more than a peer is byworking harder. But progression has the perverse effect of reducing average,

    after-tax hourly wage or salary rates as work effort increases. Consider theClass brothers: While Toms average, after-tax hourly wage was $25 (hepaid no tax), Dicks was $22.82 , and Harrys was only $21.10 (this

    assumes the tax on Harrys $75,000 in labor income was $11,725 or 50

    percent of the familys total tax of$23,450). To put this into perspective,

    imagine you are interviewing for a job. When you ask what the job pays,

    April & May 2011 17

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

    Among people

    whose aptitudes

    are the same,

    the only way

    one person can

    earn morethan a peer is

    by working

    harder.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    20/100

    18 Policy Review

    your prospective employer says, Well that depends on how hard you

    work. You say, Good, because I am a hard worker. To which the

    employer responds, You dont understand. If you work 20 hours a week, I

    will pay you $25 per hour. But if your family works 100 hours a week andhas income from savings, I will pay you about $21 per hour. The more

    hours you work, the less average hourly wage I will pay you. John Stuart

    Mill gave full voice to this apparent injustice when he denounced progressive

    taxation as a penalty on those who worked harder and saved more than

    their neighbors and a mild form of robbery.14

    On the surface, sacrifice theory appears to be a respectable argument for

    progression. But on close examination, it seems clearly without merit as a

    rationale for a fair tax system. By far the most compelling condemnation ofsacrifice theory is not the argument over the slopes of the marginal-utility

    curves, but the unfair penalty it would impose on the hardest working and

    most productive people in society.

    Ability to pay

    The notion of ability to pay is most often identified with KarlMarx (from each according to his ability, to each according to his

    needs), even though the basic concept was considered by scholars

    long before Marx was born. While the phrase says nothing about progres-

    sion, it has often been used to advocate it.

    Ability-to-pay has been the subject of considerable debate on

    definitional grounds alone. For example, a review of the literature on tax

    theory does not turn up a generally accepted definition of the word

    ability. What does according to his ability really mean? Does it mean(as some suggest) the financial wherewithalwith which to pay taxes which might come from either assets or income? Or does it mean the innate

    or learned ability to earn income, which would equate to aptitude?

    Both of these interpretations have been discussed in the literature. Either

    way, ability could as easily dictate proportion as it could progression.

    If the word means the financial wherewithal with which to pay taxes pro-gressively, the basic concept lacks an underlying principle of fairness to sup-port it. (Proponents of this meaning of ability-to-pay often draw on

    sacrifice theory for intellectual support, but as shown above, the applica-

    tion of sacrifice theory results in inequitable outcomes.) If the word

    ability means the innate or learned capacity to earn income, it is synony-

    mous with aptitude, in which case, the greater-value interpretation of

    the benefits principle should be applied. This would lead to proportionate

    taxation.

    Kip Hagopian

    14 . John Stuart Mill, Principles of Political Economy with some of their applications to social philoso-phy, Vol. II(D. Appleton and Company, 1894), 99, 401.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    21/100

    Reducing income inequality

    One of the most persistent arguments in favor of progressive taxa-

    tion is that it reduces income inequality. For example, University of

    Chicago economist Henry Simons writes:

    The case for drastic progression in taxation must be rested on the case

    against inequality on the ethical or aesthetic judgment that the pre-

    vailing distribution of wealth and income reveals a degree (and/or kind)

    of inequality which is distinctly evil or unlovely.15

    To be sure, inequality exists in the United States as it does to a greater or

    lesser extent in all other nations. But why should we care? If it is social jus-

    tice we are concerned about, what is the evidence that the level of American

    inequality is unjust?

    There are at least five methodologies used for measuring income inequali-

    ty. The most commonly used measure is the Gini coefficient, developed by

    the Italian statistician Corrado Gini. The Gini coefficient is a method of

    measuring the statistical dispersion of (among other things) income, con-sumption, and wealth. The figure of merit for the Gini coefficient ranges

    from zero to 1.0, where zero equals total equality (all persons have identical

    incomes) and 1.0 equals total inequality (one person has all of the income).

    By this measure, the U.S. has higher income inequality than almost all other

    industrialized nations. In 2009, the U.S. Gini was .468, while the average

    Gini for the 27 European Union nations was .304, a ratio of1.54:1.

    Interestingly, the per capita gdp in the U.S. in 2008 was $47,400, while

    the average per-capita gdp in the eu nations in that year was $32,900, asimilar ratio of1.44:1. The point is that strong economic performance can

    coexist with higher levels of income inequality (and vice versa).

    It is important to note that the U.S. income figures cited above come from

    the Census Bureau, which uses what it calls money income (income before

    taxes, excluding the value of non-cash benefits). Money income is the

    income definition most often used when citing income inequality mea-

    sures,16 even though this definition of income does not include many vari-

    ables that might affect inequality and standard of living, such as transfer

    payments, taxes, employer-provided fringe benefits (primarily retirement

    benefits and health insurance, which can amount to as much as 30 percent

    of income17), capital gains, dividends, imputed rent from owner-occupied

    April & May 2011 19

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

    15 . Blum and Kalven, 72 . .

    16 . Gini coefficients cited herein come from The CIA World Fact Book 2010, the Census Bureau reporton Income, Poverty, and Health Insurance Coverage in the United States: 2009 and other U.S. govern-ment publications, and Eurostat, the official statistical office of the European Union.

    17 . Bureau of Labor Statistics, Employer Costs for Employee Compensation: December 2010.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    22/100

    20 Policy Review

    housing, size of household, increases in the value of home equity and other

    investments, etc. Consequently, the value of using money income to measure

    either standard of living or inequality is quite limited.

    It has been widely reported that income inequality in the U.S. has beenrising for decades, and by implication, that the rise is ongoing. These

    reports are arguably misleading. From 1967 to 2008 the Gini for moneyincome rose from .397 to .468 (17.9 percent), about four-fifths of whichoccurred from 1967 to 1993 . Roughly three-tenths of this increase

    occurred between 1992 and 1993 due to a change in the way data were

    collected. This change in methodology biased the Gini calculation upward.

    Accordingly, figures from the period before 1993 are not directly compara-

    ble with the period from 1993 to the present.During the 16 years between 1993 and 2009, the

    Gini increased from .454 to .468 (3.1 percent),

    and from 2001 to 2009 there was virtually no

    change in income inequality as measured by the

    Gini coefficient.

    A more comprehensive measure of income yields

    a very different picture. The Census Bureaus so-

    called 15th measure of income adds to moneyincome, transfer payments, insurance supplements,

    capital gains, Medicare, Medicaid, net imputed

    return on equity in owned homes, and subtracts

    taxes. This measure indicates that inequality

    declined1.8 percent during the last 16 years (1993to 2009) from a Gini of .395 to a Gini of .388.

    In any event, the consensus view among economists is that the best mea-

    sure of living standards over the long term is consumption (determined notonly by income but by savings, home ownership, borrowing, barter, regionof domicile, and other factors), suggesting that consumption inequality is the

    inequality that counts the most. A 2005 study conducted by the Bureau of

    Labor Statistics found that in 2001 (the most recent year for which data are

    available) the Gini coefficient for consumption was .280,18 indicating that

    inequality with respect to this measure of U.S. living standards is relatively

    modest. It also appears that consumption inequality has barely changed in

    recent years. During the period 1986 to 2001, the consumption Gini went

    down slightly, from .283 to .280.19 Since the Gini for money income was

    virtually unchanged from 2001 to 2009, it is quite possible that the Gini

    for consumption was also relatively flat during that period; in which case,

    consumption inequality has not increased for 23 years or more. Support for

    Kip Hagopian

    The consensus

    view among

    economists

    is that the

    best measure

    of livingstandards over

    the long term is

    consumption.

    18 . David S. Johnson, Timothy Smeeding, and Barbara Boyle Toney, Economic Inequality Through thePrisms of Income and Consumption, Monthly Labor Review (Bureau of Labor Statistics, April 2006),available at http://www.bls.gov/opub/mlr/2005/04/art2full.pdf.

    19 . Johnson, et al., Economic Inequality.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    23/100

    this latter surmise comes from a 2010 study which concluded that in the

    2000s overall consumption inequality shows little change.20

    In addition to Americas substantial superiority in gdp per capita (which

    is a measure of the performance of the economy without regard to howincome is distributed), the U.S. has a much higher standard of living than

    virtually all of the most advanced European and Asian countries. According

    to the Luxembourg Income Study (which uses a very comprehensive mea-

    sure of income) median disposable personal income in the U.S. in 2002 was:

    19.3 percent higher than Canada; 68 percent higher than Finland; 45 per-

    cent higher than Germany; 59 percent higher than Italy; 31 percent higher

    than Norway (despite its vast oil and gas wealth); 73 percent higher than

    Sweden; and 31 percent higher than the UnitedKingdom. It should be noted that the figures forgdp per capita and median income understateAmericas advantage because the median age of

    Americas population (about 36.8 years) is about

    four years lower than the average of the median ages

    in Western Europe and almost eight years younger

    than Japan. Age (a proxy for experience) is one of

    the most significant contributors to income and isalso, therefore, one of the most significant contribu-

    tors to income inequality. In addition to higher

    median incomes, Americans have higher median net

    worths, which add further to the standard of living differential.

    There is no question that until the recent recession, the U.S. economy

    performed well in both absolute and relative terms over the 25-year period

    from 1983 to 2008 . During this period, real compound annual gdp

    growth in the U.S. was 3.3 percent, substantially greater than the growthof its g-7 counterparts, which on a weighted-average basis (using either

    population or gdp), grew only 2.3 percent per year. Thus, the U.S. econo-

    my grew 43 percent faster per year than the non-U.S. g-7 countries.

    Moreover, in the recent recession, the U.S. economy contracted less than

    the worlds other advanced economies. For example, U.S. gdp shrunk 2.6

    percent in 2009, substantially less than the 4.1 percent contraction experi-

    enced in the Euro area. In 2010, the U.S. grew 2.8 percent compared with

    only 1.8 percent growth forecast for the Euro area by the International

    Monetary Fund.

    Another common claim is that incomes in the U.S. have been stagnant for

    decades. But this claim is at odds with data from the Congressional

    Budget Office, which uses a measure of household income that, like the

    Luxembourg measure, is quite comprehensive, taking into account transfer

    April & May 2011 21

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

    The U.S economy

    performed well

    in absolute and

    relative terms

    over the 25-year

    period from1983 to 2008.

    20 . Bruce D. Meyer and James X. Sullivan, Consumption and income inequality in the U.S. since the

    1960 s (2010) working paper, available at http://harrisschool.uchicago.edu/faculty/web-pages/Inequality60s.pdf

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    24/100

    22 Policy Review

    payments, health and retirement benefits, profits from retirement accounts,

    imputed interest on owner occupied homes, differences in household size,

    and taxes paid. Using this more meaningful definition of income, from 1983

    to 2005 real median household income in the U.S. rose by 35 percent,which can hardly be considered stagnant.

    The presentation of these facts is not meant to suggest that income

    inequality causes higher living standards or gdp growth. But it is clear thatit can co-exist with both high and low national living standards. Those who

    advocate redistribution of income on grounds of social justice should consid-

    er that Americas standard of living is higher and has grown faster than vir-

    tually all of the nations exhibiting lower measured inequality. This suggests

    that the most notable economic inequality in the world is that betweenAmericans and the citizens of all other countries.

    The most compelling argument against the use of the progressive income

    tax to redistribute income is simply that it is inequitable. Blum and Kalven

    noted that when the tax system is used to redistribute income,

    the welfare of one group in a society has been increased at the expense

    of the welfare of a different group. Stated this way there is no general

    welfare; there is only the welfare of the two groups and the wealthy

    receive no counter-balancing benefits for their surrender of income orwealth.21

    As contrasted with the benefits principle and sacrifice theory, each of

    which relies on conceptions that purport to enhance equity, income redistri-

    bution is simply a coercive transfer of wealth from one group to another

    without an equity principle to support it. Note that $13,450 of Harrys

    income was distributed to Tom and Dick. (This is the difference between

    Harrys one-third share of the cost of the street improvements ($10,000)and the $23,450 he was forced to pay.)

    Ironically, a progressive income tax can even have the extraordinary

    effect of increasing rather than reducing income differences. Again, our

    parable is instructive: Assume that Harrys boss is a construction foreman

    who works 40 hours a week at $37.50 per hour, thus earning $75,000

    per year (which is the entirety of the family income). The foremans hourly

    rate is commensurate with his aptitude as a manager, while Harrys $25

    per-hour rate is commensurate with his aptitude as a carpenter. They both

    make $75,000 per year, but Harry does it working 60 hours per week

    and his boss does it working 40 hours per week. Under the current pro-

    gressive tax system, Harrys after-tax income will be $63,275 (after$11,725 in tax, which assumes that, since Harrys labor income is 50

    percent of his total family income, the tax attributable to him is 50 per-

    cent of the $23,450 tax paid by the family). His boss will take home$68,450 (after $6,550 in tax). Thus, a disproportionate amount of

    Kip Hagopian

    21 . Blum and Kalven, 75 . .

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    25/100

    Harrys income has been taken from him and redistributed, simply because

    his family worked harder.

    As noted by Blum and Kalven, and illustrated by our parable, redistribu-

    tion requires that money be taken from some and given to (or not takenfrom) others. What is the equity principle that justifies this taking?

    Redistribution has been justified by some as a means of rectifying social

    injustice in the economic system. But proponents of this view have not pro-

    vided a convincing argument that such injustice even exists.22

    There is no persuasive evidence that reducing income inequality will

    increase economic well-being for the majority of people; in fact, Americas

    superior median standard of living relative to the other advanced economies

    is evidence to the contrary.

    The case against progression

    The strongest arguments againstprogression are the rebut-tals to the arguments for progression. To wit: The pro-progressioninterpretation of the benefits principle is invalid because it depends

    on the untenable assumption that the value of government benefits increasesmore rapidly than the rise in income; on the surface, sacrifice theory is a

    respectable argument for progression, but on closer examination, it is clear

    that its application produces an inequitable outcome (this is most obviously

    so when applied to income derived from greater work effort); the ability-to-

    pay argument lacks an equity principle (other than sacrifice theory) on

    which to base a fair tax system; and redistributing income through a pro-

    gressive tax system is inequitable.

    These rebuttals to the arguments for progression, should be sufficient tosettle the case. But there are other important reasons to reject progressivetaxation.

    Political irresponsibility. In 2008 , the top 1 percent of taxpayers inAmerica earned about 20 percent of all personal income and paid roughly

    38 percent of federal income taxes; the bottom fifty percent of taxpayers

    currently pay only 2.7 percent of income taxes,23 and it is estimated that

    46.9 percent of workers paid no federal income tax for the 2009 calendar

    year.24 Inasmuch as only a minority of taxpayers is affected by rises in tax

    rates, there is a built-in incentive for the majority to act in its self-interest,

    which opens the door to inequitable treatment of the minority.

    April & May 2011 23

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

    22 . To be sure, there are people in America who are needy or disadvantaged, in some instances grievouslyso. For such people the most effective remedy would be through direct spending programs. But the fund-ing for such programs should come from a tax system that is equitable.

    23 . Mark Robyn and Gerald Prante, Summary of Latest Federal Income Tax Data, Fiscal Fact249(Tax Foundation, October 6, 2010), available at http://www.taxfoundation.org/news/show/250.html.

    24 . Roberton Williams, Who pays no income tax?, Tax Notes (June 29, 2009), available athttp://www.taxpolicycenter.org/Uploaded pdf/1001289_who pay.pdf.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    26/100

    24 Policy Review

    Arbitrariness. Establishing a graduated rate scale and setting the top mar-ginal rate on that scale are inherently arbitrary tasks. Scottish economist J.R.

    McCullough condemned this arbitrariness in the strongest of terms:

    The moment you abandon . . . the cardinal principle of exacting from all

    individuals the same proportion of their income or their property, you

    are at sea without rudder or compass, and there is no amount of injus-

    tice or folly you may not commit.25

    The progressive tax system rests on a very slippery slope, making the term

    fair share so subjective as to be an invitation to abuse. Did Harrys broth-

    ers pay their fair share?Fomenting dissension. One of the inherent characteristics of the U.S. sys-tem of government (and that of all Western nations) is the tension that exists

    between the political system (majoritarian) and the economic system (free

    enterprise). Most Western nations are experiencing the effects of this tension,

    which manifests itself in vigorous disputes over tax and welfare policies.

    Many of those who favor income redistribution assert that inequality

    foments dissension. Whether this is true or not, dissension is just as likely to

    be caused by tax laws that are deemed unfair by those being taxed. By itsnature, a system that taxes people progressively without the support of an

    accepted equity-based principle may breed resentment, particularly when so

    many pay no tax at all. The deepest resentment will most likely be among

    those whose tax rates differ solely because of their work effort.

    A new doctrine of fairness?

    There is no perfectly fair tax system. But based on an examina-

    tion of the various tax principles and theories described in the liter-

    ature, together with a critical analysis of the arguments supporting

    and opposing progression, its possible to put forward a new doctrine of

    fairness. It is based on five principles:

    The most equitable tax system is one based on the value of benefitsreceived.

    Income is the most equitable (or least inequitable) measure of the valueof benefits; thus taxes should be levied in proportion to income. Well-being is the ultimate benefit of government and income is a reasonable

    proxy for well-being. Whether income is derived from aptitude (as

    defined), a financial windfall, a random event or privilege, it is fair (or

    less unfair) that it be taxed in proportion to value received. This princi-

    Kip Hagopian

    25 . J. R. McCullough, A Treatise on the Principles and Practical Influence of Taxation, or the FundingSystem (The Lawbook Exchange Ltd., 2007), 143-145.

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    27/100

    ple serves as a rejection of a per-capita tax system and establishes the

    affirmative case for proportion.

    Only clear income defined as income above the level of subsis-

    tence should be taxed. From the point of view of the state, an indi-viduals earned income up to the level of subsistence is effectively the

    governments cost of production and should not be taxed. From the

    point of view of the taxed, government benefits only have real value

    after the taxpayer earns a surplus of income over what is needed for

    subsistence.

    The progressive taxation of income from work effort is inequitable.

    Income is derived primarily from a combination of aptitude and workeffort. All things being equal, people with high-value aptitudes earn

    more than those with low-value aptitudes. Each tier of aptitude

    (whether there be 100 or 10,000 such tiers) comprises a mini-soci-

    ety in which differentials in income between the members are derived

    almost solely from work effort. Under a progressive tax system, work-

    ers whose work effort is above the median in their aptitude tier will

    pay higher average taxes per hour than those below the median. As a

    result, at any one point in time, an unacceptably large percentage of the

    total work force will earn less average, after-tax income per hour than

    their peers, simply because they worked harder. This is inequitable on

    its face.

    The progressive taxation of income from aptitude is inequitable.Whereas the most equitable tax system is one based on the value of

    benefits received from government; and whereas the value of govern-

    ment benefits does not increase more rapidly than income, there is no

    equitable basis for taxing income progressively. Thus, even if it wereassumed that income was derived solely from aptitude, progression

    would be unfair.

    Implicit in this fairness doctrine is that taxation in excess of a proportion-

    ate share of the value of benefits (defined as clear income) is an inequitable

    confiscation of property.

    Critique of the doctrine

    There are weaknesses in the logic of this doctrine that make

    the fairness of a proportionate or degressive tax system less than

    perfect. First, some have argued that the benefit derived from eco-

    nomic well-being (as measured by income) should be considered separately

    from the benefits derived from government protection of life, liberty, and

    property. This alternative view has induced some scholars (John Stuart

    April & May 2011 25

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    28/100

    26 Policy Review

    Mill, for one) to suggest that two types of tax should be imposed: a pro-

    portionate tax to pay for economic well-being and a per-capita tax to pay

    for the protection of life, liberty, and property. Putting aside the measure-

    ment difficulties of such a scheme, if this alternative quid pro quo principlewere applied, and the two tax rates were blended to reflect the different

    values of the benefits, the most equitable tax would be somewhere between

    per-capita and proportion. Thus, a proportionate or degressive tax as pro-

    posed, would favor lower-income persons at the expense of higher-income

    persons.

    Second, a proportionate tax would only be fair if all income were derived

    from aptitude, when in fact a substantial portion of income is derived from

    work effort. The inequity of this is demonstrated in the Class Wars parable,in which Harry paid more than a per-capita share of the cost of the street

    improvements despite the fact that his benefits were exactly the same as his

    brothers. (Note that in this all-too-common circumstance, where both apti-

    tudes and benefits are equal, even a proportionate or degressive tax is redis-

    tributive with respect to the hardest workers.) Thus, a proportionate tax

    favors people who work less over people who work more.

    Third, the merit of the clear income theory is somewhat undermined with

    respect to hard workers. Again this can be seen in our parable: Using adegressive tax system and assuming the subsistence level of income was

    $25,000, Tom would not have to pay any tax, even though he could easily

    pay his share of a proportionate tax simply by working three more hours

    per week. Thus, the degressive tax favors people who work less at the

    expense of those who work more.

    Since there is no perfectly equitable tax system, the goal must be to design

    the least inequitable system. This doctrine of fairness uses sound principles

    of equity to reject both the progressive and per-capita tax systems. At thesame time, it establishes the affirmative case for a degressive system as being

    the least inequitable. Lastly, where the logic of the doctrine is flawed, in each

    case it errs on the side of taxing lower-income people less, regardless of the

    reason their income is lower.

    Seeing income clearly

    The flaw in virtually all of the intellectual arguments on the issue

    of the progressive income tax (both pro and con), is a lack of

    appreciation for how income is determined. Because of this, the

    crucial implications of the distinction between income derived from aptitude

    and income derived from work effort have been left out of the debate. When

    the importance of work effort is considered, the inequity of progression

    becomes clear.

    While the title of Blum and Kalvens book appears to indicate that the

    authors analysis led them to become uneasy proponents of progression, the

    Kip Hagopian

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    29/100

    reality is more nuanced (and more uneasy). At the conclusion of the book,

    they wrote:

    The case for progression, after a long critical look, thus turns out to be

    stubborn but uneasy. The most distinctive and technical argumentsadvanced in its behalf are the weakest. It is hard to gain much comfort

    from the special arguments [in favor of progression], however intricate

    their formulations, constructed on the notions of benefit, sacrifice, abili-

    ty to pay, or economic stability. The case has stronger appeal when pro-

    gressive taxation is viewed as a means of reducing economic inequalities.

    But the case for more economic equality, when examined directly, is

    itself perplexing.

    The authors seem to be saying that the only argument for progression

    that could not be dismissed was the value they ascribed to reducing income

    inequality. And even that argument left them uneasy.

    But it is clear from a careful reading of the book that Blum and Kalven

    did not appreciate the implications of how income is determined, specifically

    the special nature of income derived from work effort. If they had, they

    almost certainly would have realized that taxing such income progressively

    is inequitable. In the event, their uneasy case for progression would havebecome an easy case for its rejection.

    April & May 2011 27

    The Inequity of the Progressive Income Tax

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    30/100

    Hoover Institution Press, Stanford University, Stanford, California 94305-6010

    www.hooverpress.org

    New from Hoover Institution Press

    Death GripLoosening the Laws Stranglehold overEconomic Liberty

    By Clint Bolick

    Slaughter-House is the case academics left and right love

    to hate, but the Supreme Court refuses to reconsider. This

    book explains why: returning to anything close to the

    original meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment would

    upset too many judge-made doctrines.

    Michael McConnell, the Richard and Frances MalleryProfessor of Law at Stanford University and senior fellow

    at the Hoover Institution

    In Death Grip, Clint Bolick masterfully explains why a100-plus-year-old Supreme Court case provides the context

    for some of the most important constitutional issues of our

    day. Combining history and current controversies, along

    with constitutional theory and real-world litigation experi-

    ence, Death Grip is an essential read for those interested in

    all of the rights guaranteed by the Constitution.

    Scott Bullock, senior attorney at the Institute for Justiceand lead attorney in Kelo v. City of New London

    Clint Bolickis a research fellow at the Hoover Institution and

    also serves as the director of the Goldwater Institute Scharf-

    Norton Center for Constitutional Litigation in Phoenix. He has

    written many books, most recently Leviathan: The Growth of

    Local Government and the Erosion of Liberty(2004) andDavids Hammer: The Case for an Activist Judiciary(2007).

    March 2011, 90 pagesISBN: 978-0-8179-1314-4 $19.95, cloth

    To order, call 800.621.2736

    w v

    rth GDeaoosening thL

    onomic Libc

    E

    u

    pangleholdtrs SwLa

    tr

    ervo

    o cn

    -HouseerghtSlau is

    , but the Sueo ha

    :xplains wh

    nal meaning og

    y juoo man

    ichaelM

    pset t

    r

    book e

    y

    anthe case academics lef

    oeco refuses tt roureme Cr

    ything closning tetur

    mendmeth Aeenourthe F

    .inestr-made docge

    onnellMcC d andicharthe R

    evt loighr

    hisT.nsider

    o thet

    ouldwn

    yes Mallerancro essor or

    nI GripeathD ClSold-ear100-plus-

    moheofsomeorf

    hiombiningC.da

    onstitutionalcwith

    y anersn vaw a an or

    at the Ho

    xefullyermastolickBinvidoprcaseourCemeupr

    onstitutionalcttanmporst

    randst

    litildorweal-randyheor

    wsen or e o

    er Institutionv

    ayhlainstxetoncthes

    ourofssues

    along,ersies

    ixpereiona -

    ,

    ts guaighall of the r

    ott BullocSand

    t BinC iolick ess a r

    es as the divalso ser

    onstitutioy the Ceed banr

    ck orney at the Instsenior attorney in

    lead att y oit. CKelo v

    ner Ivt the Hoow aelloch far

    nstier Iaoldwor of the Gtec

    .

    ee for Justictutondonf New L

    titution and

    f-chare Sut

    booksen manittwr

    ernment avoal GcoLTHammeravidD

    ch 2011, 90MISBN: 978-0-817

    lyenecmost r eviathan: TL

    terosion of Libd the Er (2004

    ytivist Judiciarcase for an AC

    y

    pages-1314-4 $19.95, cloth

    .

    wth ofoGr

    ) and(2007).

    rvooH nUdrofnatS,sserPnoiuitsnI

    .hooww

    crdT

    ainroilaC,ronaS,ytisrevi

    gss.orprr

    63716008l

    106-534

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    31/100

    The best law schools and public policy graduate schools

    inculcate in their students an ability to make the strongestpossible case in favor of a position or policy with which

    they disagree. The test of whether the lesson has been truly

    learned is whether those who favor the position would

    accept its rendition as a fair and effective representation of why they favor it.

    With this in mind, I present below the argument for the U.S. stance favor-

    ing a substantial rise in the undervalued Chinese yuan. The U.S. position has

    been repeatedly stated, albeit in abbreviated and nuanced form, by President

    Obama and Treasury Secretary Geithner. It is also reflected in the large

    bipartisan majority in the House of Representatives that approved legisla-

    tion to allow a retaliatory tariff on Chinas exports to the U.S. unless China

    revalues its currency. It has been expressed more vociferously and combat-

    ively by key leaders in the Senate, and by politically-charged commentators

    including Paul Krugman.

    A Smarter Approach

    to the YuanBy Charles Wolf, Jr.

    Charles Wolf, Jr. holds the corporate chair in international economics at theRAND Corporation, and is a professor in the Pardee RAND Graduate School.He is a senior research fellow at the Hoover Institution.

    April & May 2011 29 Policy Review

  • 8/7/2019 Policy Review, April & May 2011, No. 166

    32/100

    30 Policy Review

    Once the case for this pro position has been presented fairly and fully, I

    will explain why I think it is fundamentally wrong. I will then go on to sug-

    gest measures that would be more appropriate and effective in contributing

    to a rebalancing of Chinas international accounts as well as those of theU.S. than would a revaluation of the Chinese yuan.

    In early January, when President Hu Jintao met in Washington, D.C.,

    with President Obama, the agenda for the meeting deftly acknowledged the

    presidents disagreement on the currency issue without discussing, let alone

    resolving, it.

    The case for revaluing the yuan

    The Chinese yuan (also known as the renminbi, or peoples

    currency) trades in foreign exchange markets at a rate of approxi-

    mately 6.7 yuan per dollar (equivalent to about fifteen U.S. cents

    per yuan). Another measure that accords the yuan a considerably higher

    value is based on the goods and services the yuan can buy within China

    compared to what these same goods and services would cost in the U.S. This

    rate is referred to as the yuans purchasing power parity (ppp). The ppp val-uation of the yuan is roughly two or three times higher (between 2.2 and

    3.4 yuan per U.S. dollar, or between 30 and 40 U.S. cents per yuan) than

    the market exchange rate.

    Associated with the yuans value in foreign exchange markets is the fact

    that the value of Chinas global exports of goods and services perennially

    exceeds by large amounts the value of its imports. Indeed, this exc