20
POLICE ETHICS AND INTEGRITY Milan Pagon Professor and Dean College of Police and Security Studies University of Maribor, Slovenia ABSTRACT The paper deals with the importance of police ethics and integrity in contemporary policing. It first describes the field of applied ethics in general. It explains the basis for the structure of professional moral obligations, briefly depicts the core imperatives of applied ethics and describes the process of moral reasoning. It then defines police ethics, discusses the reasons for its relative underdevelopment, and delineates its future development in three interrelated directions: (a) applying the principles of applied ethics to police profession; (b) establishing standards of ethical conduct in policing; and (c) defining the means and content of education and training in police ethics. Next, it discusses the organisational environment that is conductive to police ethics and elaborates on the concept of integrity. The paper concludes that police ethics and integrity are of critical importance in the professionalisation of policing and the best antidotes to police corruption, brutality, neglect of human rights, and other forms of police deviance. Date: September 2003 Attribution: No prior publication Language of origin: English Filename: pg011mpa.pdf

Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

etica

Citation preview

Page 1: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

POLICE ETHICS AND INTEGRITY Milan Pagon Professor and Dean College of Police and Security Studies University of Maribor, Slovenia ABSTRACT The paper deals with the importance of police ethics and integrity in contemporary policing. It first describes the field of applied ethics in general. It explains the basis for the structure of professional moral obligations, briefly depicts the core imperatives of applied ethics and describes the process of moral reasoning. It then defines police ethics, discusses the reasons for its relative underdevelopment, and delineates its future development in three interrelated directions: (a) applying the principles of applied ethics to police profession; (b) establishing standards of ethical conduct in policing; and (c) defining the means and content of education and training in police ethics. Next, it discusses the organisational environment that is conductive to police ethics and elaborates on the concept of integrity. The paper concludes that police ethics and integrity are of critical importance in the professionalisation of policing and the best antidotes to police corruption, brutality, neglect of human rights, and other forms of police deviance. Date: September 2003 Attribution: No prior publication Language of origin: English Filename: pg011mpa.pdf

Page 2: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

INTRODUCTION

For all of us in the field of police and security studies, it has become obvious

that we are witnessing a paradigm shift. While we cannot expect this shift to

result in a uniform approach to policing everywhere in the world, we can

assume that all the various approaches will be based on the same set of

assumptions of modern policing, namely the community involvement, a

proactive approach that emphasizes prevention, professionalism, innovation,

and problem-solving, and an integrated view of criminal justice (Pagon, 1998).

In this process, policing is getting closer to professionalisation , a change long

advocated by police scholars. As several authors (e.g., Hahn, 1998;

Vicchio, 1997; Murphy, 1996; Fry & Berkes, 1983) point out, aspirations by the

police to become professionalized either create or at least re-emphasize

several requirements, such as wide latitude of discretion, higher educational

requirements, higher standards of professional conduct, and self-regulation.

At the same time, however, we have witnessed countless accounts of police

brutality and abuse of authority, some of them making the headlines, and

others taking place outside the public eye. In some countries, police corruption

has already reached epidemic proportions. It is obvious that corruption,

brutality, and other forms of police deviance go against the above-mentioned

efforts for police professionalisation and community involvement. The

community cannot trust nor attribute a professional status to deviant police

officers. No wonder then, that modern police organisations all over the world

are fighting police deviance, trying to achieve proper conduct of their

members. However, according to Sykes (1993), a brief history of these efforts

to enhance police accountability reveals that they relied on rules and

punishment. “Although each of these reform efforts had an impact, the sum

total fell short of providing assurances that they were adequate and serious

incidents continued… In short, the various rule-based systems of accountability

seem insufficient if officers hold different values or there is a subculture which

Page 3: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

nurture values different from the ideals of democratic policing” (p.2). The

author believes the answer lies in approaches based on ethics, where

accountability rests more on individual responsibility than it does on external

controls and threatened punishment.

It has become obvious that only the properly educated and trained police

officers are able to respond adequately to moral and ethical dilemmas of their

profession. Only a police officer who is able to solve these dilemmas

appropriately can perform his duties professionally and to the benefit of the

community. In doing so, he cannot rely solely on his intuition and experience.

Not only he has to be well acquainted with the principles of police ethics and

trained in moral reasoning and ethical decision-making, he also needs clear

standards of ethical conduct in his profession.

In this article, I will try to show that a proper development of police ethics and

integrity is one of the most important steps toward professionalisation of

policing, and one of the most powerful antidotes to police deviance and

neglect of human rights by the police. To introduce the field of police ethics,

however, I first have to describe the field of applied ethics in general.

APPLIED ETHICS

Police ethics is a branch of applied normative, ethics. The most well known

branches of applied ethics are medical and business ethics. The link between

‘theory’ and ‘practice’ is what makes applied ethics different from

philosophical ethics. Applied ethics is the field that holds ethical theory

accountable to practice and professional practice accountable to theory.

Therefore, the philosophers should not dictate to professionals the norms that

are supposed to govern their professional practice, without a very thorough

knowledge of that practice. On the other hand, the professionals have to

understand that their experience and intuition are insufficient for defensible

Page 4: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

judgment, and that all their constraints do not exempt their decisions from

ethical scrutiny (Newton, Internet).

Newton (Internet) believes that if ethics is about human beings, we should be

able to determine the structure of our moral obligations from three basic,

simple, readily observable facts about human beings:

- People are embodied. They exist in time and space and are subject to

physical laws. They have needs that must be satisfied if they are to

survive. They must control the physical environment to satisfy those needs.

Failure to do so leads to pain and suffering. The implication for ethics is

that the relief of that suffering and the satisfaction of those needs should

be out first concern, giving rise to duties of compassion, non-maleficence,

and beneficence.

- People are social. Whatever problems they have with their physical

environment, they have to solve them in groups, which creates a new set of

problems. They must cope with a social environment as well as the physical

one. The social environment produces two further needs: for a social

structure to coordinate social efforts, and for means of communication. The

implication for ethics is that we must take account of each other in all our

actions. We have obligations to the group in general and to other members

of the group of particular.

- People are rational. People are able to consider abstract concepts, use

language, and think in terms of categories, classes and rules. Because

people are rational, they can make rational choices, they are autonomous

moral agents. They can also realize that they could have done it differently,

so they can feel guilty and remorse and assume responsibility for their

choices. Rationality’s implication for ethics is that we have a duty to

respect this freedom of choice.

Page 5: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

From these facts about human nature, the author derives three fundamental

premises or imperatives of applied ethics (Newton, Internet):

- Beneficence. This imperative, central to any profession, holds that the

professionals must take care of, or look out for the interest of, the client.

Beneficence has several sub-imperatives conjoined in it: first, to do no

harm, second, to prevent harm or protect from harm, and third, to serve

the interests or happiness of the client.

- Respect for persons. The command to respect the autonomy and dignity of

the individuals with whom we deal, to attend to their reasons and honour

their self-regarding choices, is the command underlying all of our

interpersonal dealings. In professional relationships, however, it also limits

the boundaries of professional beneficence. The professional’s expertise

may tell him that the client’s best interests will be served by certain

services that the professional is able to provide; it may even tell him that

the client needs, on pain of loss of life or liberty, certain of his services.

But if the client chooses not to avail himself of them, and only his own

interests are concerned, the professional may not impose those services on

the client.

- Justice. This imperative demands that the professional look past both art

and client, and take responsibility for the effect of professional practice in

the society as a whole. In every profession or practice, we can find

examples of injustice. For example, in medicine, the rich get immediate

and adequate care and the poor get late and inadequate care. The demand

of justice upon the professionals is that they work within their professional

associations, and in their individual practices, to blunt the effects of

injustice in their fields. The professional who ignores this demand fails to

fulfil all the duties of professional status.

Because these imperatives are logically independent, they can be (and often

are) in conflict. Yet, as Newton says, we may not abolish one or another; we

Page 6: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

cannot even prioritize them, which leads her to conclude that applied ethics is

not the science of easy answers. As professionals are struggling to solve moral

and ethical dilemmas, the engage in the process of moral reasoning. There are

different forms of moral reasoning (Newton, Internet): the first is

consequentialist (or utilitarian or teleological) reasoning, in which ends are

identified as good (i.e. values) and means are selected that will lead to those

ends; the second is non-consequentialist (or deontological) reasoning, in which

rules are accepted as good and acts are judged right or otherwise according to

their conformity to those rules; finally. The third is virtue-based (or

ontological) reasoning, in which the type of person one is (i.e., his character),

and the type of moral community one belongs to, determines the obligations to

act.

The described core of applied ethics does not specify, for each profession, how

the imperatives should reflect in the professional practice, and what are the

values and virtues of that particular profession. These should differ depending

on the function of the profession in the community. That is why we need

branches of applied ethics, tailored to individual professions. So, let us take a

look at police ethics.

POLICE ETHICS

Police ethics applies the above-described principles to the field of policing.

Compared to medical or business ethics, police ethics is relatively

underdeveloped. There are several reasons for this, the major ones being the

paramilitary philosophy of policing and misunderstanding of the need for police

ethics (Paragon, 2000).

First, within the paramilitary philosophy of policing, police officers are

assigned the role of executors of orders from their supervisors. They are not

supposed to question those orders, so there is not much need for moral

Page 7: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

deliberations. The basic virtue of police officers within this framework is

obedience. Police leadership, on the other hand, is either not accountable to

anyone (since they are setting their own goals and can always tailor the

statistics to fit their needs) or they are accountable only to the party in power,

with which they are in a symbiotic relationship. It is not surprising that police

ethics does not thrive in such a context.

Second, some practitioners are mislead by a belief that as far as police officers

perform their work strictly by the law, they need no police ethics. Proponents

of this view also deny police officers the right of discretion. Unfortunately,

when one is faced with a moral or ethical dilemma, the laws prove themselves

to b of little use. As Newton (Internet) puts it, “our first job…in all fields of

practice, is to distinguish, in every context, between the demands of law and

the demands of ethics - between the danger the danger of being sued,

prosecuted, jailed or defrocked, and the much subtler, but more pervasive

danger of being systematically and cruelly wrong. One of our first lessons was

that we must think beyond the law and teach nervous professionals to do the

same.”

With the rise of the new philosophy of policing (i.e. community policing and

problem-oriented policing) and with the acceptance of police discretion as a

necessary part of police work, the importance of police ethics is gaining

acceptance. Nowadays it is hard to find a curriculum at a police academy or a

program in police studies at a university that does not include a subject of

police ethics. At the same time, the number of police agencies with a

department, task force, or a committee on police ethics is rapidly increasing.

The majority of police agencies also have adopted a code of police ethics, in a

more or less articulated form.

But, as I have already mentioned, police ethics is still at the beginning of its

development. A lot of courses on ‘police ethics’ are mainly dealing with

Page 8: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

philosophical ethics, while the word ‘police’ in the name simply means that

police officers or studies of police studies are the target group of the course.

Therefore, I will outline the direction of the future development of police

ethics.

Following the postulates of applied ethics, the described development should

be achieved by the joint efforts of police scholars (i.e., theoretians) and police

practitioners. This development should take place in three interrelated

directions (Pagon, 2000): (a) applying the principles of applied ethics to police

profession; (b) establishing standards of ethical conduct in policing; and (c)

defining the means and content of education and training in police ethics. This

development, of course, has to parallel other efforts for implementing

contemporary philosophy and forms of policing and for professionalisation of

police work, including the increased educational requirements for the police.

Let us now take a brief look at the proposed directions for the development of

police ethics.

a) Applying the principles of applied ethics to police profession

The above-described principles of applied ethics have to be tailored to the

needs of police profession, based on the nature of police work and the function

of the police in society. There are three main tasks to be achieved in this

context.

First, the basic imperatives (i.e., beneficence, respect for persons, justice)

have to be ‘translated’ to police language and specified. What does

beneficence mean in dealing with people who committed crimes or

misdemeanours? What does it mean in dealing with victims and other persons

who suffered a loss? Who is ‘the client’ of police work? Individuals? The

community? The state? What exactly does respect for persons mean in carrying

out the police duties? How does the imperative of justice reflect in applying

Page 9: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

police discretion? Also, the most common conflicts among basic imperatives in

policing have to be identified, so we could discuss them and prepare some

guidelines.

Second, the core values of policing need to be specified. Policing, as any other

rational activity, is directed toward achievement of a certain state or goals.

These desired states and goals represent values. Not only every society has a

somewhat different system of values, they may also differ for each individual.

Police ethics has to specify and rank the impost important values of policing,

which will then guide the police officers’ teleological moral reasoning. Such

ranking would not imply that other values are not important; it would just add

clarity in ethical decision-making in policing. For example, let us say that a

police officer, using teleological reasoning, determines that one particular

course of action would lead to increased wealth of a certain individual, while

the different course of action would lead to increased equality of the people

involved. Although both the wealth and equality are values, a hierarchy of

values would enable the police officer to opt for equality. While the choice is

obvious in this example, how about a choice between freedom and safety?

Respect for human rights and health?

Third, police ethics need to specify the core virtues of policing. While there are

commonly accepted virtues such as temperance, courage, prudence, justice,

charity, kindness, patience, forgiveness, modesty, etc. we have to - just like in

every other profession - decide which are the virtues most important for police

officers, based on the function of the police in society. In doing so, we have to

accommodate the above-described changes in philosophy of policing, which

caused some ‘traditional’ police virtues (such as obedience, uncritical loyalty,

authoritativeness) to become obsolete. In police literature, we can find some

descriptions of police virtues, which can serve as a good starting point.

Vicchio (1997) believes that if the goals of police organisation are to be met,

the following virtues must be required of police officers: prudence, trust,

Page 10: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

effacement of self-interest, courage, intellectual honesty, justice and being

cognizant of other alternatives that might be taken. Delattre (1996) describes

the importance of the following virtues for police officers: honesty,

trustworthiness, justice, fairness, compassion, temperance, courage, wisdom

and integrity.

b)Establishing standards of ethical conduct in policing

Expectations regarding ethical conduct have the greatest impact upon actual

behaviour if they are not simply assumed, but clearly and unambiguously

communicated. Based on the imperatives, values, and virtues of policy

profession, police ethics has to establish clear and unambiguous standards of

ethical conduct in policing. A code of police ethics is very important within this

context. It contains a set of clear, specific statements, expressing in

unambiguous terms the moral principles and the kind of conduct that police

profession demands of its members. The code has to be a product of

interaction between police ethicists and practitioners, based on agreed-upon

definitions of police imperatives, values and virtues. While the research shows

that the mere existence of the code of ethics positively influences employees’

ethical behaviour (Ruch & Crawford, 1991), the police management has to

devote a lot of attention to the implementation of this code.

c) Defining the means and content of education and training in police

ethics

Defining the means and content of education and training in police ethics is

also a task that has to be accomplished by a joint effort of police ethicists and

practitioners. We have to keep in mind that listening to one lecture on police

ethics or skimming through some literature on the topic will not make police

officers moral nor their behaviour ethical. A lot of time and effort need to be

put into education and training in police ethics, before police officers – when

Page 11: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

faced with a moral problem, ethical or moral dilemma – will automatically

consider all the alternatives available to them; will not make decisions based

on prejudice or impulsively; will submit their decisions to reason and change

them, if such a change seems reasonable; and will give equal consideration to

the rights, interests, and choices of all parties to the situation in question.

Furthermore, as Delattre(1996) points out, even the mastery of the process of

moral reasoning and decision-making does not, by itself, guarantee ethical

conduct, nor do all of the situations require moral reasoning and deliberation.

An individual has to have good character (i.e., appropriate virtues) to be

motivated for ethical behaviour. This realization makes two additional

requirements for police ethics training. First, in addition to teaching moral

reasoning and decision-making, training has to emphasize and develop virtues

characteristic of police profession. Second, the task of ethical training should

also be the development of moral habits, so the police officers would behave

ethically out of habit in all those situations, which do not present a moral

problem, ethical or moral dilemma, so they do not require moral deliberation

and reasoning.

So, the task of police ethics education is to teach the principles of applied

ethics in general and police ethics in particular. It has to cover the

imperatives, values and virtues of policing, the process of moral reasoning and

decision-making, moral problems, and in policing, the code of police ethics,

and the process of code implementation. Vital topics are also strategies for

managing ethical behaviour in police organisation and ethics training and

education.

The tasks of police ethics training are: (a) enable the students to recognize

moral problems and moral or ethical dilemmas; (b)train the students for the

process of moral reasoning and decision-making; (c) emphasize and develop the

Page 12: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

virtues necessary for police profession, hence developing the students’ moral

character; (d) develop moral habits of the students.

The development of police ethics, including education and training, will not

achieve its purpose, unless all organisational processes, especially the

behaviour of police managers and the top management of the organisation,

support and encourage ethical conduct of all the members.

ORGANISATIONAL ENVIRONMENT CONDUCTIVE TO POLICE ETHICS

If police officers experience inconsistent behaviour from their supervisors,

preferential treatment of some officers and/or citizens, solidarity with, and

cover-ups for, the officers who violate standards of their profession, they will

sooner or later become cynical regarding the value and appropriateness of

ethical conduct in their organisation. One cannot expect a cynical police

officer to be motivated to adhere to the rules of ethical behaviour (Pagon,

1993).

The research showed the importance of moral climate in organisation for the

behaviour of individual members. Experiments revealed, in schools and prisons,

that changing organisational processes, such as policies and procedures, could

create a positive moral atmosphere that then contributed to improvements in

individual moral development and moral judgment, as well as to reduction in

cheating, stealing and similar anti-social acts (Kohlberg, 1984). Investigations

of organisational effects on moral conduct in business firms appear to support

these observations. Firms demonstrating exemplary business practice attest to

the value of creating a positive moral atmosphere for encouraging ethical

behaviour and maintaining the firm’s reputation. Conversely, the organisational

environment can also promote unethical and criminal conduct in business firms

(Cohen, 1995). Researchers have also demonstrated that organisational factors,

such as reward systems, norms and culture, and codes of conduct can

Page 13: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

significantly decrease the prevalence of unethical behaviour in organisational

contexts (Brass, Butterfield, & Skaggs, 1998).

Cohen (1995) defines moral climate as shared perceptions of prevailing

organisational norms for addressing issues with a moral component. These

issues include (a) identifying moral problems, (b) choosing criteria for resolving

moral conflicts, and (c) evaluating the moral correctness of outcomes that

ensue from organisational decisions. Since climate is a function of how

employees collectively perceive and interpret these and other elements of the

work setting, climate can be thought of as an intervening variable. As such it

provides the necessary perceptual link between organisational processes and

employee behaviour. According to the author, there are five dimensions that

interact to determine the moral climate in the organisation: goal emphasis

(prevailing norms for selecting organisation goals), means emphasis (prevailing

norms for determining how organisational goals should be attained), reward

orientation (prevailing norms regarding how performance is rewarded), task

support (prevailing norms regarding how resources are located to perform

specific tasks). And socio-emotional support (prevailing norms regarding the

type of relationships expected in the firm).

It becomes obvious that police supervisors and top management are responsible

creating a positive moral climate within the police. The literature on corporate

strategy, organisational transformation, business ethics and corporate social

contract provides support for a claim that moral climate in the organisation

emerges mainly from the way in which key organisational processes transmit

managerial expectations about moral behaviour – the way employees should

handle issues such as responsibility, equity, or serving the interests of

stakeholders (Cohen, 1995). Therefore, police managers’ expectations about

moral behaviour of their subordinates will significantly influence moral climate

of a particular police organisation or agency.

Page 14: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

In the context of discussing ethical behaviour in police organisation, we should

also stress the importance of social relationships within the organisation.

Organisational actors are embedded within a network of relationships. These

ongoing social relationships provide the constraints and opportunities that in

combination with characteristics of individuals, issues, and organisations, may

help explain ethical or unethical behaviour in organisations (Brass, Butterfield

& Skaggs, 1998).

Social network researchers bring to our attention several factors that might

influence ethical or unethical behaviour of organisational members, such as

strength of relationships (in terms of frequency, reciprocity, emotional

intensity, and intimacy); negative relationships; multiplicity of relationships;

asymmetric relationships; status inequality; structure of relationships;

structural holes; centrality; density; cliques social contagion; and conspiracies.

The constraints and opportunities provided by relationships may be most

predictive of unethical behaviour when personal characteristics, issues, and

organisational factors present moderate or weak constraints or unethical

behaviour (Brass, Butterfield, & Skaggs, 1998).

Another important issue that influences ethical behaviour is trust among

organisational members. McAllister (1955) distinguishes two main dimensions of

trust:

(a) cognition-based trust, which relies on appraisals of others’ professional

competence and reliability; (b) affect or emotion-based trust, which is present

when people feel save to share their private feelings and personal difficulties,

knowing that the other party would respond constructively and caringly.

Emotion-based trust has been found to be more essential to effective

coordination efforts in organisations. This emotion-based trust incorporates the

virtue of benevolence, which refers to an altruistic concern for the welfare of

others and is devoid of egocentric motives (Mayer, Davis, & Schoorman, (1995).

Page 15: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

In police settings, we could extend this notion of trust to include trust between

the police and the community.

It is important to note that all of the above-described factors interact with

each other in predicting ethical or unethical behaviours. Let us take trust as an

example. In an organisation with strong moral climate, composed of individuals

of good character, and with dense social networks, it is safe to assume that

high level of trust will promote ethical behaviour. In such organisations, people

who trust others (both cognitively and emotionally) and feel trusted by them

will be reluctant to violate this trust by engaging in unethical behaviour. On

the other hand, if the moral climate is low, social networks are loose, with a

lot of structural holes and many cliques, it is very likely that high level of trust

within a deviant clique will promote unethical behaviour. In this case, people

who trust other clique members and feel trusted by them will be reluctant to

violate this trust by giving up their own unethical behaviour or even by

reporting on other members’ unethical behaviour.

Therefore, to set a climate conductive to ethical behaviour in police

organisation, police managers have to consider all of the above factors. To

summarize, they have to foster character development and moral habits of

police officers by educating and training them in police ethics; establish high

moral climate through appropriate use of goals, means, rewards, and support,

facilitate development of strong and dense social networks, extending into the

community; prevent cliques and conspiracies; and establish both cognitive-

based and affect-based trust among all organisational members and between

the police and the public.

In doing so, the managers will not only facilitate ethical behaviour of their

officers; they will also prevent or at least lessen the strength of the infamous

police subculture, so typical of paramilitary policing. In trying to achieve the

above goals, police managers will soon discover that, first, setting their own

Page 16: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

example is of the utmost importance, and second, that ethics does not only

apply to police officers’ dealings with the community, but also to their own

dealings with their subordinates. Police officers’ human rights are as important

as those of the other citizens.

I agree with Sykes (1993) that the quality of policing in a democratic society

relies on the quality of the people doing the work. This is why I believe that in

policing we should strive to achieve a virtue of integrity of all police officers

and supervisors, including top management.

INTEGRITY

Leadership theorists and researchers have found that integrity is a central trait

of effective business leaders, while interpersonal and group relationship

theorists have identified integrity as a central determinant of trust in

organisations (Becker, 1998). Delattre (1996) and Vecchio (1997) agree that

integrity is also central to the mission of policing. To Delattre, integrity is not

only the highest achievement there can be in a human life, but also the most

difficult. So what exactly is integrity?

Delattre (1996) defines as “the settled disposition, the resolve and

determination, the established habit of doing right where there is no one to

make you do it but yourself” (p.325). He believes that integrity is

“irreplaceable as the foundation of good friendship, good marriages, good

parenthood, good sportsmanship, good citizenship, and good public service”

(ibid).

Vecchio (1997) defines a person of integrity as somebody who has reasonably

coherent and relatively stable set of core moral values and virtues, to which he

is freely and genuinely committed, and which reflect in his act and speech. So,

the person’s words and actions should be of one piece.

Page 17: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

Becker (1998) subscribes to the objectivist view of integrity, namely that

integrity is loyalty, in action, to rational principles (general truths) and values.

“That is, integrity is the principle of being principled, practicing what one

preaches regardless of emotional or social pressure, and not allowing any

irrational consideration to overwhelm one’s rational convictions” (p.158).

Integrity in policing, then, means that a police officer genuinely accepts values

and moral standards of policing and possesses the virtues of his profession, and

that he consistently acts, out of his own will, in accordance with those values,

standards, and virtues, even in the face of external pressures.

Of course, not all police officers have integrity. Benjamin (1990) describes five

psychological types lacking in integrity. The first is the moral chameleon, a

person who is anxious to accommodate others, while not being resistant to

social pressure, thus willing to quickly abandon or modify previously avowed

principles. The second is the moral opportunist, whose values are also ever

changing, based on his own short-term self-interest. The third type is the moral

hypocrite, a person who has one set of virtues for public consumption and

another set for actual use as a moral code. The fourth is the morally weak-

willed who has a reasonably coherent set of core virtues, but he usually lacks

the courage to act on them. The final type is the moral self-deceiver, a person

who thinks of himself as acting on a set of core principles, while, in fact, he

does not.

Of course, “it is not a breach of integrity, but a moral obligation, to change

one’s views if one finds that some idea he holds is wrong. It is a breach of

integrity to know that one is right and then proceed (usually with the help of

some rationalization) to defy the right in practice. (Peikoff, 1991): cited in

Becker, 1998).

Page 18: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

Why do some people lack integrity? Why is it so hard to achieve it? Based on a

review of objectivist literature, Backer (1998) offers the three most common

reasons. First, not everyone is rational. Integrity requires the discipline of

purpose and a long-range course of action, selecting corresponding goals and

pursuing them fervently, carefully choosing the means to one’s ends, and

making full use of one’s knowledge. Second, a person may lack integrity

because of desires that are inconsistent with moral values. If a person, when

under temptation, fails to call upon his rational mind, acting upon a whim of

the moment instead, he will indeed lack integrity. The same is true when an

irrational fear drives behaviour. Similarly, an individual’s integrity will be

called into question if he does not put rational principles into practice simply

out of inertia. Third, probably the most common reason a person may lack

integrity is that he succumbs to social pressure. Social pressure may come from

numerous sources (e.g., co-workers, bosses, or clients) and take many forms

(e.g., physical intimidation or verbal and nonverbal disapproval). A person with

high integrity will not allow popularity to take priority over rational

convictions.

CONCLUSION

From the above discussion, it should be obvious that integrity can only be

achieved if a person strives to achieve it. Appropriate education and training in

police ethics, good moral climate in police organisation, appropriate social

networks (both within the organisation and within the community), trust and

support, can all both motivate police officers to strive for integrity and help

them achieve it. I believe that, once achieved, integrity of police officers is

one of the most important steps toward professionalisation of policing, and one

of the most powerful antidotes to police corruption, brutality, neglect of

human rights, and other forms of police deviance.

Page 19: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

Police ethics provides a compass to both police officers and police managers,

by specifying the core imperatives, values, and virtues of policing, by

delineating the process of moral reasoning and decision-making, by setting the

standards of ethical conduct, and by defining the means and the content of

police ethics education and training. Police scholars and practitioners have to

cooperate in developing police ethics. This is not an easy task for either of

them. Developing and implementing police ethics invokes changes in police

organisation. Police organisations and police officers, as we know, are very

resistant to change. Those police scholars and practitioners entrusted with

developing police ethics must, therefore, themselves be persons of high

integrity. We should not forget the Newton’s (Internet) caution of flattery. The

flatterer is a person who tells people what they want to hear, instead of what

they should hear. Flattery, in Newton’s words, “is the major corruption

available to the ethicist…the only defence against flattery is personal

integrity.” In developing and implementing police ethics, a lot of people will

have to be told the things they most definitely do not want to hear.

Milan Pagon

Biography

Milan Pagon got his doctorate (Sc.D.) in Organizational Sciences in 1990 at the University of Maribor, Slovenia. In the

period between 1990 and 1994, he was a Fulbright Scholar to the University of Arkansas, Fayetteville, where he both

studied and taught at the College of Business Administration. In 1994, he was awarded a Doctor of Philosophy (Ph.D.)

degree in Management.

During his police career, Dr. Pagon was an Educator at the Police High School, a Detective, a Deputy Commander and a

Commander of Police Station, a Police Inspector, and a State Undersecretary at the Ministry of the Interior. Outside

the police, he was an Assistant Director of the Personnel Agency of Slovenia, a Human Resource Manager at a chemical

company, a Teaching Assistant, an Assistant Professor, and an Associate Professor. In 1995, he was elected as the Dean

of the College of Police and Security Studies, a duty that he initially performed for three years. In 2001, he was again

elected as the Dean, the position that he is currently holding. In 2003, Dr. Pagon was elected to the rank of a Full

Professor. In addition to his administrative and teaching duties at the College of Police and Security Studies, he is also

a Professor of Organizational Behavior at the Faculty of Organizational Sciences, University of Maribor.

Dr. Pagon was invited in the summers of 1996, 1997, 1998, and 1999 to serve as a Visiting Professor at the University

of Arkansas, Fayetteville, where he taught Concepts of Management and Organizational Behavior and Human Resource

Management at the Sam M. Walton College of Business.

Page 20: Police Ethics Integrity Pagon

Dr. Pagon is a member of the following professional and scientific associations: Academy of Management, Honorary

Management Fraternity Sigma Iota Epsilon, International Society for Human Resource Management, Society of

International Scholars Phi Beta Delta, American Psychological Society, American Society for Criminology, Academy of

Criminal Justice Sciences, American Association of University Professors, International Police Association, and

Association of Professors of the University of Maribor.

He was a founding father and the Chairman of the Program Committee of the International Biennial Conference

Policing in Central and Eastern Europe, which was already organized four times, with the following subtitles:

Comparing Firsthand Knowledge with Experience from the West (1996), Organizational, Managerial, and Human

Resource Aspects (1998), Ethics, Integrity, and Human Rights (2000) and Deviance, Violence, and Victimization (2002).

In his research, Dr. Pagon has collaborated with some of the top international researchers in the fields of

management and police work: Dr. Daniel C. Ganster, Dr. Paul E. Spector and Dr. Carl B. Klockars from the USA and Dr.

Cary L. Cooper from the UK. These cooperation efforts have already produced papers at scientific conferences and

publications in the best international journals.

Dr. Pagon was also appointed to the editorial board of two international and one domestic journal, namely the Stress

& Health, the International Journal of Police Science and Management, and Varstvoslovje - Journal of Security Theory

and Praxeology.

He also serves as a reviewer for one international and two domestic journals, namely the Stress & Health,

Varstvoslovje, and the Organization – Journal of Management, Informatics, and Human Resources.