Platonic Myths and Straussian Lies

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Platonic Myths and Straussian Lies

Citation preview

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES:THE LOGIC OF PERSUASION

    Kenneth Royce Moore1

    Abstract: This article undertakes to examine the reception of Platonic theories offalsification in the contemporary philosophy of Leo Strauss and his adherents. Theaim of the article is to consider the Straussian response to, and interaction with,Platonic ideas concerning deception and persuasion with an emphasis on the argu-ments found in the Laws. The theme of central interest in this analysis is Platosdevelopment of paramyth in the Laws. Paramyth entails the use of rhetorical languagein order to persuade the many that it is to their advantage to obey certain laws. It doesso without explaining in detail why a given law is ethically correct and its use assumesthat the audience, on the whole, is not capable of understanding the finer philosophicalunderpinnings of the law. The so-called noble lie of the Republic is also consideredin this context. The crucial issue, for Plato if not for Strauss, is whether or not aninstance of falsification, however minor, for the purposes of persuasion containstruth-value, that is, whether it is morally justifiable in terms of ends and means. Interms of Strausss reception of Plato, such issues as ancient Hebrew mysticism,Medieval Jewish and Islamic scholarship and Heideggerian Phenomenology figure inthe argument. Ultimately, the article finds that Strauss and his followers have con-structed a particular view of Platonic ideas that, while unique, is not compatible withtheir original signification.

    Introduction: Virtuous FictionsIn the Republic and the Laws, Platos narrators discuss the prospect of official

    story-telling for the purposes of moral edification. The so-called noble lie is

    one example of this. The use of legal preambles, or paramyth, is another.

    These will be explored in detail along with the poetic and other influences on

    the dialogue form itself. Integral to the modern reception of Plato is Leo Strausss

    interpretation of these phenomena, with its inherent assumptions and influ-

    ences, along with the further interpretation of them by the Straussians, based

    on the teaching and writings of Strauss. The latter read every text as dialogic,

    entailing both argument and action.

    Leo Strauss advanced the somewhat unusual position that Thrasymachos

    argument to the effect that Justice is the interest of the stronger was in fact a

    major theme of the Republic. He also maintained that Platos philosophy was

    expressed in an exoteric manner but guided by an esotericism that differed

    intrinsically in character. Strauss apparently regarded Thrasymachos, and not

    Socrates, as the official spokesman for Plato in the Republic. He saw this

    fictional antagonist as speaking the truth to the effect that there is no such

    thing as natural justice only the right made by might, as Drury indicates,

    POLIS. Vol. 26. No. 1, 2009

    1 20 Melbourne Place, St Andrews, Fife, Scotland, KY16 9EY. Email: [email protected]

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • apparently Socrates tells him (off stage) that his views are true but too

    dangerous for public dissemination.2 The so-called noble lie, then becomes

    a ready means of smoothing over dangerous truths that the populace may not

    be prepared to accept. They are thus permitted to go on believing in such

    things as natural rights and justice.

    This interpretation of the Republic and of Plato is not typically upheld by

    classicists and it earned Strauss ridicule from his peers. There is, nonetheless,

    evidence of his narrators various recourses to esotericism in Platos dramatic

    dialogues and especially in the Republic and the Laws. The so-called noble

    lie (or virtuous fiction) is the example that springs readily to mind and one

    that most interested Strauss. The legal preambles of the Laws are another.

    Both Platonic utopian visions entail an esoteric society in charge, e.g. the

    Philosopher Kings/Queens of the Republic and the Vigilance Committee, of

    the Laws who are comparable in many ways to their counterparts in the

    kallipolis.3 The second-best polis of Magnesia, outlined in the Laws, reveals

    degrees of esotericism at all levels of society and even appears to refer to more

    potential esoteric connections, in a meta-dramatic way, outside the text itself

    and involving other Platonic dialogues.4

    It is perhaps not surprising, then, that Strauss, who advocated the applica-

    tion of ancient political theories in modern politics, also considered the Laws

    to be the most political of all of Platos works. As he says:

    The Republic and Statesman reveal, each in its own way, the essential limi-tation and therewith the essential character of the city. They thus lay thefoundation for answering the question of the best political order But theydo not set forth that best possible order. This task is left for the Laws. Wemay then say that the Laws is the only political work proper of Plato.5

    90 K.R. MOORE

    2 S.B. Drury, Leo Strauss and the American Right (London, 1997), p. 101. ForStrausss (exoteric) view on Thrasymachos, see Leo Strauss, City and Man (Chicago,1964), pp. 75 ff.

    3 Laws 908a, 909a, 951d ff., 961a ff. and 968a. Unless otherwise specified, all ancienttexts are cited from the Loeb Classical Library (Harvard, 2002) and all translations aremy own. For a similar Nocturnal Council of Atlantis, see Critias 120a ff. Cf. Rep. 484,537b ff., where dialectics are described, as R.G. Bury says, as a kind of induction whereby the mind ascends from the many particulars to the one univer-sal concept or idea: a comprehensive view of the whole that marks the dialectician( ) (Plato, The Laws, vols. 12, trans. R.G. Bury (Suffolk,1999), p. 555, n. 3). See too K. Moore, Sex and the Second-Best City (London and NewYork, 2005), ch. 2.

    4 Laws 811a1b5, 957cd. See K.R. Moore, , Hybris and Mania: Love andDesire in Platos Laws and Beyond, Polis, 24.1 (2007), pp. 11233, pp. 124 ff; and alsocf. C. Bobonich, Compulsion and Freedom in Platos Laws, Classical Quarterly, 41.2(1991), pp. 36588, p. 370.

    5 L. Strauss, Plato: Laws, in History of Political Philosophy, ed. L. Strauss andJ. Cropsey (Chicago, 2nd edn., 1972), pp. 5163. Strauss repeats this statement of the

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 91

    Strauss sees Platos political philosophy as evolving toward the best possible

    order which culminates in Magnesia, in the Laws, a planned society like the

    kallipolis of the Republic but with marked differences.

    Before turning to Platos usage of lying or storytelling in these texts, it is

    first necessary to draw some distinctions about their Straussian reception. In

    doing so, it would be remiss not to differentiate between Leo Strauss, the clas-

    sicist and political philosopher, and those Straussians who are comprised of

    his immediate students, their students and adherents.6 And we must also bear

    in mind that what has been said or done in Strausss name, comparable to the

    state of affairs concerning Plato and many other notable teachers, is not his

    own doing nor even necessarily an accurate representation of his ideas.7

    In any case, the application of Straussian philosophy entails there to be a

    public salutary teaching and behind it an acknowledgement of an unspeakable

    truth.8 The Straussian line of reasoning goes like this:9 The philosopher-

    statesman possesses an enlightened understanding of the correct ways that

    society ought to function along with that which is best for it as a whole. The

    majority of people do not possess this enlightened understanding. In order

    to preserve the good of society, the knowledge held by the philosopher-

    statesman is expressed in both an inner, or esoteric, manner, for and by the

    philosopher-statesmen amongst themselves, and an exoteric, or outer manner,

    for the benefit of hoi polloi. This is because hoi polloi are not able to fully

    appreciate the esoteric version (the whys and wherefores entailed by illumi-

    nated philosophical reason) and require a message that is appropriate to their

    level of understanding. In the course of pursuing the enlightened good of the

    state, the philosopher-statesman may be required to present a fictional version

    of events to hoi polloi in order to justify the undertaking of some action

    deemed necessary from their enlightened perspective. The necessary action

    in question might include the engagement of military activities with another

    state in war or some kind of forceful intervention of which hoi polloi may not

    Laws politicality in L. Strauss, The Argument and the Action of Platos Laws (Chicago,1975), p. 1.

    6 See K. Weinstein, Philosophic Roots, the Role of Leo Strauss, and the War in Iraq,in I. Stelzer, The Neocon Reader (New York, 2004), pp. 20112, pp. 2056; andA. Norton, Leo Strauss and the Politics of the American Empire (New Haven and Lon-don, 2004), p. 6; see pp. 14 ff. for a more complete list of prominent Straussians.

    7 This distinction is a major subject of Nortons Leo Strauss and the Politics of theAmerican Empire and is well discussed therein. As she says (p. 2) there is the story of theStraussians, which is properly two stories: the story of the philosophical lineage of LeoStrauss, and the story of a set of students taking that name, regarded by others andthemselves as a chosen set of initiates into a hidden teaching.

    8 Ibid., p. 64.9 See T. Pangle and N. Tarcov, Epilogue: Leo Strauss and the History of Political

    Philosophy, in History of Political Philosophy, ed. Leo Strauss and J. Cropsey (Chi-cago, 1987), pp. 90738.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • readily approve. The focused purpose of the exoteric message in such circum-

    stances is to persuade the populace that this apparently questionable action is

    in fact correct.10

    Leo Strauss was acquainted with Husserl and was a student of Heidegger.

    His approach, influenced by the latters phenomenology, was not the assess-

    ment of mere objects of perception; rather the full thing which entailed both

    primary and secondary characteristics as well as values such as the sacred or

    the profane.11 Society, he thought, had failed to recognize the significance of

    such an approach. Strauss considered Western civilization as he understood it

    to be in a state of crisis. He identified some of the main causes of this crisis

    with Moral Relativism, Nihilism and Historicism.12 He evidently blamed

    these dangerous -isms for the turmoil of Weimar Germany, where he spent his

    youth, and the Nazi terror that followed. He fled to the USA before the perse-

    cution of Jews could reach him.13 As an antidote for this crisis, Strauss made

    recourse to the ancient philosophers of the past not assuming that their ideas

    were shaped or limited by the times in which they lived.14 The difficulty in

    overcoming the crisis of modernity lies in the nature of modernity as a con-

    structed reality, a second cave, borrowing from Platos myth of the cave in

    the Republic.15 This approach was a rather significant departure from the stan-

    dard scholarly procedure of Strausss day which gave credit where due to the

    past but regarded the then modern prevailing theories to be an improvement

    over it.

    Strauss was especially interested in the medieval Islamic philosopher al

    Farabi (c.870950) and the medieval Jewish philosopher Moses Maimonides

    (11351204).16 Both used esotericism in their philosophies and both learned it

    from more ancient sources. In his commentary on Plato, al Farabi asserted that

    92 K.R. MOORE

    10 Mary Wakefield, at that time editor of the Spectator, in an article in the Daily Tele-graph (9 January 2004), wrote: Strauss was a champion of the noble lie the ideathat it is practically a duty to lie to the masses because only a small elite is intellectuallyfit to know the truth. Politicians must conceal their views, said Strauss, for two reasons:to spare the peoples feelings and to protect the elite from possible reprisals.

    11 L. Strauss, Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy (Chicago and London, 1983),p. 31; cf. too Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tbingen, 1949), sect. 21, pp. 989.

    12 As Robertson indicates: Strauss follows Nietzsche and Heidegger in seeing a cri-sis of nihilism at the heart of modernity which opens up the possibility of a return to aprinciple forgotten or lost the recovery of the lost principle involves a return to theancients who are now able to speak to us free from the distorting effects of modernassumptions. N. Robertson, Leo Strausss Platonism, Animus: A Political Journal ofOur Times, 4 (1999), pp. 19, p. 1 (www.mun.ca/animus/1999vol4/roberts4.htm).

    13 Weinstein, Philosophic Roots, pp. 2049.14 Ibid., p. 209.15 Robertson, Leo Strausss Platonism, p. 2.16 See in particular L. Strauss, The Literary Character of the Guide for the Per-

    plexed, in Essays on Maimonides: An Occidental Volume, ed. S.W. Baron (New York,

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 93

    Plato did not reveal his fullest teaching to everyone, choosing instead to con-

    ceal his most important secrets.17 The need for, and practise of, exoteric/

    esoteric doctrines in antiquity could be seen with regard to the politically

    charged atmosphere of Athens in the wake of the Peloponnesian wars and

    especially around the time of the trial of Socrates, but not limited by any

    means to these. Esotericism also had its uses in the Middle Ages when schol-

    arship could be regarded with suspicion. Keeping their innermost ideas a

    secret known only to a select group could perhaps protect philosophers from

    public persecution and superstition, since the public lacked a deeper under-

    standing of philosophy, whilst securely training the few individuals who were

    deemed capable of dealing with it. Or, to put it more cynically in Mary

    Wakefields turn of phrase, the philosopher cum politician lies in order to

    spare the peoples feelings and to protect the elite from possible reprisals.18

    Strausss reception of Plato was deeply coloured by the influence of these

    medieval philosophers as well as by ancient Hebrew esoteric conventions. He

    seems to have sought to unify the ancient Greek and Hebrew traditions,

    symbolically joining Jerusalem and Athens, though clearly not unaware of

    their differences too, saying:

    On the divine concern with mens justice and injustice, the Platonic teach-ing is in fundamental agreement with the biblical teaching; it even culmi-nates in a statement that agrees almost literally with biblical statements.19

    He does acknowledge that Athens and Jerusalem are ultimately at odds on

    account of the opposition of the God or gods of the philosophers to the God

    of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob, the opposition of Reason and Revelation.20

    However, he asserted that the truth is the synthesis of the teaching of Plato

    and that of the prophets.21 Athens and Jerusalem are thus unified, albeit with

    caveats and necessary restrictions. The argument has been taken up recently

    that Strauss needed to assert an unbridgeable chasm between Athens and

    1941), pp. 3792. On Maimonides use of secret teachings, see pp. 48 ff.; on the use ofrepetition in Plato and Maimonides to convey true teachings, see p. 62, n. 79.

    17 Weinstein, Philosophic Roots, p. 209; see too Robertson, Leo Strausss Platon-ism, p. 3.

    18 See note 10 above.19 Strauss, Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, p. 166. He cites Laws 905a4b2,

    where the Athenian Stranger discusses metaphysical justice, saying: Make yourselfever so small and hide in the depths of the earth, or soar high into the sky; this sentencewill ever be at your heels, and either while you are still alive on earth or after you havedescended into the House of Hades or been taken to some even more remote place, youwill pay the proper penalty for your actions. Strauss then compares it with Amos 9:13and Psalms 139:710. He goes on to discuss some of the more significant differencesbetween the Platonic tradition and the biblical.

    20 Strauss, Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, p. 166.21 Ibid., p. 167, emphasis in original.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • Jerusalem since they would thereby both be united, as it were, in equal oppo-

    sition to National Socialism.22

    Strauss was also heavily influenced by the Kabbalah, which maintained

    that the secrets of the Torah were dangerous and had to be kept from those

    unfit or unworthy to receive them. Strauss Persecution and the Art of Writing,

    according to Drury, insists that all the great authors of the Western tradition

    are esoteric writers for exactly the same reasons as the Kabbalists.23 He also

    held that certain ancient philosophers, and a few modern ones, had received

    some kind of divine revelations akin to those of the Old Testament prophets.

    By way of Spinoza, as Pangle puts it, he learned from Maimonides and

    eventually from Farabi that the heart of revelation is the phenomenon of the

    prophet, the human lawgiver who orders the community and the nation

    or nations in the name of divine authority.24 The difficulty of refuting

    Strausss hermeneutic is comparable to the difficulties of refuting psycho-

    analysis. Both point to an object only accessible to those who practise an art

    that requires as its premise the prior acceptance of the existence of that object,

    that is, the hidden text or the unconscious mind.25 Or, as Trevor Saunders, a

    renowned expert on Plato in general and the Laws in particular describes it,

    Strauss confusing and deplorable habit is due to his treacherous assumption

    that what is not in the text is as much a part of the subject matter as what is.26

    One can seen some similarity between the Straussian position and the

    divine authority of Platos philosopher kings/queens who have supposedly

    experienced the Form of the Good and are thus capable of rendering Just deci-

    sions.27 Certainly there are elements of Platos writing that seem to allude to a

    hidden agenda. The dialogue form lends itself well to esotericism. The set-

    ting, characters and actions, amongst other features, all provide a backdrop

    against which the authors intent can be gauged.28 They also provide a ready

    94 K.R. MOORE

    22 This is taken from an unpublished article titled The Disappearance of Davos: AnAdventure in the History of Ideas, by an independent American scholar on Strauss by thename of Will Altman with whom I have had some correspondence on this. He writes(p. 43) that Strausss irrational choice for Athens over Jerusalem, on the other hand, isprecisely the reciprocal annihilation of both; it is the triumph of the will, the crest ofmodernitys third wave, and the last word in decisionist nihilism.

    23 Drury, Leo Strauss and the American Right, pp. 601.24 T. Pangle, in his introduction to L. Strauss, Studies in Platonic Political Philoso-

    phy (Chicago and London, 1983), p. 21.25 Robertson, Leo Strausss Platonism, p. 3.26 T. Saunders, review of The Argument and the Action in Platos Laws by Leo

    Strauss, Political Theory, 4 (1976), pp. 23942, p. 241, emphasis in original.27 See Strauss, The Literary Character, p. 87, n. 155, on a contrast between ancient

    Hebrew prophets as statesmen and the philosopher kings/queens of Platos Republic andcf. p. 39, n. 9, on the use of official secrecy in terms of the metaphysical truths underlyinglaw in Moses Maimonides with which Strauss contrasts passages in Laws X.

    28 Weinstein, Philosophic Roots, p. 209.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 95

    means of literary obfuscation that can conceal the authors actual intent. How-

    ever, Platos narrators are especially concerned with lies and their relative

    truth- or logos-value.29 In order to explore this further, with regard to Straussian

    lying, I shall now turn to Platos usage of fiction, first in a broader literary and

    mythological sense, before returning to the subject of paramyth in the Laws.

    Of course, what many modern readers (and translators) forget about the so-

    called noble lie in Plato is that it is not necessarily a lie per se in the con-

    temporary sense of the word.30 It has more in common with the archaic English

    lay, which is the origin of the modern term lie, and is more appropriately a

    story, fiction or myth.

    IPlatonic Myths and Paramyths

    Throughout the Platonic corpus, myths in various forms are employed by

    Platos narrators toward specific philosophical ends and effects. Yet there is

    something peculiar about a philosopher inserting mythical elements into his

    equally peculiar, and not to mention fictional, dramatic dialogues. The latter

    represent a literary genre which has its own rules and conventions. The dramatic

    dialogue is intimately connected with myth. The range of mythologizing in

    Plato includes both traditional myths, typically in a variant form from that of

    the mainstream, along with historical interpretations of these and with other

    events comparably related. This section considers some of the salient exam-

    ples of the deployment of this topos in the Laws and other dialogues and

    examines the ends for which they were conceived.

    The subject and treatment of myth in the works of Plato is complex. One

    might ask, in a manner rather like that of Socrates, what is meant by the term

    and how, therefore, should one discuss it? Graves gives a list of that which he

    considers to be not true myths, amongst which are philosophical allegory,

    political propaganda, moral legend and realistic fiction.31 This is a con-

    servative reckoning and excludes any would-be myths about whose literary

    inception, as works of fiction, something is known. It also accepts and

    includes a number of myths whose origins are historically obscure and appar-

    ently the definition is based in no small part on that obscurity itself.32 A more

    inclusive version may be obtained. Burkerts definition of myth considers it to

    29 Strauss is not unaware of logos-value in the Laws, but omits it from his discussionof the legal preambles; see Strauss, The Argument and the Action in Platos Laws, pp.589, 60.

    30 See G. Liddell and R. Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon (Oxford, 1992) s.v. .31 R. Graves, The Greek Myths (London, 1960), p. 12. All of which fit the spectrum of

    Platos mythologizing.32 Homer and Hesiod apparently qualify as true myths since the authors seem to

    have fashioned their literary works based on pre-existing myths and presumably did notoriginate the mythic tales themselves.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • be a traditional tale with a secondary, partial reference to something of

    collective importance.33 This is broad enough to include Platonic mytholo-

    gizing. However, it hinges on precisely when a fable or tale becomes tradi-

    tional. The collective importance of Platonic myths may be taken as a given,

    but even this is not beyond equivocation.

    Instances of Platonic mythologizing occur at points where he has chosen to

    adapt certain traditionally cultural tales by modifying them according to a

    philosophical agenda. There are also some myths that Plato appears to have

    originated (whether unique creations or peculiar adaptations) specifically for

    his own ends. Those that he originated or modified may not have been tradi-

    tional when he composed his dialogues. The fact that many Platonic myths

    (such as that of Atlantis) have become traditional since Platos lifetime further

    problematizes the issue of defining what is meant by a traditional tale. But

    we may grant that his myths are now certainly part of an existing tradition.

    Plato himself has also played a role in the definition of myth. He drew the

    distinction between a story that may or may not contain relevant philosophical

    or truth value and stories with an essential quality that determines their

    philosophical worth.34 Plato may thus be said to have taken significant steps

    towards systematizing the distinctions between muthos and logos. Muthos is

    regarded as unverifiable discourse and logos as verifiable. Muthos is a story

    and logos is a rational argument.35 However, Platos method for classifying

    myths according to their value does not appear entirely consistent. For exam-

    ple, the types of tales that are to be banned from the kallipolis in the Republic

    are referred to as logoi. But these also include the sort of muthoi that are told

    to children under the broader designation of logoi.36 More on this will follow.

    Given the nature of the dialogue form, Plato is under no obligation to be

    totally systematic across diverse dialogues.

    The techn of mythologizing for Plato the writer and philosopher amounts

    to a sort of tool with which he can shape an argument and deploy it for specific

    reasons. In the Laws for example, this technique is deployed purposely to

    affect Magnesian social values. Many myths that belong to the traditional

    canon of the ancient Greeks find their way into the Platonic corpus and, as

    such, serve a variety of philosophical ends. These often come from the works

    of Homer or Hesiod and Platos narrators frequently have some critical com-

    96 K.R. MOORE

    33 Quoted in Interpretations of Greek Mythology, ed. J. Bremmer (London, 1987),p. 1.

    34 See Phaedrus 275b3c2 for a discussion of this principle of veracity as a touch-stone for determining the difference between logos and muthos.

    35 R. Buxton, Imaginary Greece: The Contexts of Mythology (Cambridge, 1995),p. 12. Cf. L. Brisson, Platon, les mots et les mythes (Paris, 1982), pp. 11112.

    36 Rep. 376e6377a8.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 97

    ment to make about them or through them.37 Such poets are deemed to lack the

    appropriate understanding to correctly utilize their myths. The philosopher,

    as Murray says, is aware of the approximate status of his myths, whereas the

    poet is not.38 Platos Sokrates criticizes the use of myths that miss the mark in

    terms of truth-value e.g. that portray the gods and divine heroes as ugly or

    immoral.39 The perceived danger of such myths is that they present potentially

    harmful models for ordinary people who lack the proper philosophical train-

    ing to make the necessary distinctions. Here is an example of Platos recourse

    to a kind of esotericism as picked up by Strauss. The imitation of these harm-

    ful models must be curbed. In short, as Morgan says, only myths conducive

    to virtue will be allowed, as when Odysseus commands his heart to endure in

    difficult circumstances.40

    There are myths that Plato appears to have originated himself for the

    express purpose of forwarding his philosophical agenda. Some of these

    include, for example, the Fable of the Cave, the Divided Line, the Metals, the

    ancestor of Gyges of Lydia (the tale of the ring of invisibility), the metaphysi-

    cal Myth of Er, the Two Horses of the Phaedrus, the Myth of the Age of

    Kronos and the Puppets of the Gods in the Laws.41 Some of these (e.g. the

    Myth of the Metals) may be considered noble lies or exhortatory fables

    designed to persuade. They represent another pharmakon, a deceit that sup-

    plements the partially or fully deceitful drugs of philosophys many competi-

    tors.42 It is clear in all of these instances of tale telling that certain situations

    make lying a moral necessity for Platos narrators.43 This is justifiable since

    they are designed not only to persuade, but also to affect moral correction.

    A broader type of Platonic mythmaking may also be seen in the undertak-

    ing of such works as the Republic or the Laws. The whole business of produc-

    ing an artificial, utopian society in literature is itself a sort of mythologizing

    on a grand scale. The creation of the Republic was so vast and complex a pro-

    37 Such as his modification of the myth of Ganymede at Laws 636d as well asSokrates critique of the myth of Kronos and Zeus at Rep. 378a2.

    38 P. Murray, What is Muthos for Plato?, in From Myth to Reason? Studies in theDevelopment of Greek Thought, ed. R. Buxton (Oxford, 1999), p. 261.

    39 Rep. 377d9e3.40 K.A. Morgan, Myth and Philosophy from the Presocratics to Plato (Cambridge,

    2000), p. 162.41 See Republic 514 ff., 532b ff., 539e on the Cave; Republic 509d513e, on the Line;

    Republic 41415 on the Metals; Republic 359d ff. on Gyges; Republic 614b ff. on Er;Phaedrus 246 ff., 253c ff. on the Two Horses; on the Ages of Kronos, cf. Laws 713b ff.,on the puppets of the gods, 644d ff., 658c, 803c ff.

    42 M.A. Rinella, Revisiting the Pharmacy: Plato, Derrida and the Morality of Politi-cal Deceit, Polis, 24.1 (2007), pp. 13456.

    43 J.P. Hesk, Deception and Democracy in Classical Athens (Cambridge, 2000),p. 152; cf. pp. 153201 on Platos use of so-called noble lies and see below.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • ject that it marked one of the major stylistic changes in Platos writing.44 It

    might be fair to regard the Republic and Laws as on a par with Homers Iliad

    or Odyssey. They are all consequently epic-length fictions that, in describing

    mythical events and persons, entail a comparable level of sophistication.

    Whereas Homers myths belong to ages past, Platos transpire in a speculative

    future. Both are vehicles of moral and metaphysical guidance.

    Plato has appropriated myth from the hands of the poets and reconstructed

    new myths that serve the interests of his philosophy.45 The emphasis, as we

    have seen, lies with logos-value (truth-value in terms of philosophical worth

    and instructive potential) as opposed to muthos-value (story- or entertainment-

    value or persuasive value devoid of acceptable instructive potential). These

    Platonic myths might not be completely truthful, but they need not be. The

    ends are deemed to justify the means. Platonic myths are intended to fulfil

    their function of imparting higher, philosophical truths to those who are able

    to accurately interpret them.46 When employed on a hypothetical populace

    (whether Magnesia of Kallipolis), they entail specific agendas and have been

    calculated to inculcate these philosophical truths with effective persuasiveness.

    Platonic myths fall into several recognizable categories.47 According to

    Morgan, there are three distinguishable classes: traditional myths such as

    those told by the poets, educational myths that are designed to exercise some

    specific level of social control and philosophical myths that are conjoined

    with a given line of logical analysis.48 Even these distinctions may be too

    rigid. How, for example, might one label an instance of myth told by the poets

    but altered or amended by Platos narrator? Are not all Platonic myths some-

    how tied to logical analysis anyway? All of his myths appear to serve a dis-

    tinct philosophical purpose. They also tend to traverse the boundaries of

    artificially imposed categorization.

    A prominent use of myth in Platos works concerns the theme of philosophi-

    cal play. This can be a childish game, an educational tool, or a metaphor for

    philosophical activity.49 The educational programmes of the Republic and

    the Laws depend on types of structured play () in order to ensure psy-chic harmony and intellectual development along specific lines. The games

    that Platos narrators propose that children should play are designed to pro-

    mote the attainment of an idealized state of the . This is one level of

    98 K.R. MOORE

    44 See below.45 Murray, What is Muthos for Plato?, p. 257.46 This also serves to distinguish Platonic (or philosophical) mythologizing from the

    methods employed by the sophists. The contrast, says Morgan (Myth and Philosophy,p. 166), is not between truth and falsity or verifiability and non-verifiability, butbetween well-intentioned philosophical persuasion and sophistic browbeating.

    47 Such as Frutigers context-driven categorization of allegorical, genetic and para-scientific myths; see Morgan, Myth and Philosophy, p. 161.

    48 Morgan, Myth and Philosophy, p. 162.49 Ibid., p. 168.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 99

    play as mythologizing inasmuch as it becomes a vehicle, like a myth, for

    delivering a philosophical message.

    At another level, not unlike noble lies or paramyth, play becomes a sort

    of secondary metaphor concealing complex theoretical underpinnings. Role-

    playing can be an effective method of philosophical argumentation.50 This

    sort of play may embody critical seriousness and examine an issue by utiliz-

    ing a type of logical analysis. As Morgan says, in this respect it is analogous

    to philosophical myth.51 A prominent example occurs in the complicated

    discussion on whether or not same-sex relations should be permitted in Mag-

    nesia.52 The discussion appears to be largely hypothetical and it is worked out

    through logical analysis but there is some question as to the Athenian Strangers

    seriousness on the subject.

    It is perhaps a rather monolithic role-playing game in which Plato engages,

    but not perhaps role-playing in the modern sense of Dungeons & Dragons or

    corporate strategizing; rather, the participants engage in a philosophical game

    of what ifs? led by the narrator in which an important issue is explored. The

    theme of play as a kind of philosophical exercise, especially in contrast to

    the seriousness that such play might imply, may be seen throughout the

    Platonic corpus.53 In fact, play as a means of approaching a problem or

    administering philosophical pharmaka has much in common with other

    instances of mythologizing in Plato.54 Not unlike the creative works of the

    Republic or the Laws, in Platonic play at large an imaginary something is

    called into existence and then used to advance a philosophical agenda.

    The Myth of the Metals in the Republic provides a well-known example of

    Platonic mythologizing, being the major instance of the so-called noble lie.

    It is a lie that serves the ostensibly beneficial purpose of exercising positive

    social control of a specific type. Myths of this category, as Hesk says, are not

    to be criticised if the untruth of the story conveys a deeper moral truth.55 As

    the narrative Socrates says in the Republic:

    The pseudos in words does no more than imitate what the pseudos does inthe soul. It bears only a shadowy resemblance to the pseudos in the psychand is not altogether false.56

    The fouler pseudos is not that in words, but that which is present in the psych.

    That is to say, [l]ies in words are imitations, shadows, resemblances; lies in

    50 See Laws 887e8888a7.51 Morgan, Myth and Philosophy, p. 169.52 Laws 636c16. He says: whether one ought to regard these things in a playful way

    or seriously ( ); this passage is discussed in considerabledetail in Moore, Sex and the Second-Best City, ch. 7.

    53 See e.g. Rep. 424e5425a1, Meno 79a7, Crito 46d45.54 See Hesk, Deception and Democracy, pp. 151 ff.55 Ibid., p. 154.56 Republic 382bc.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • the soul, in contrast, have every appearance of being indelible.57 What miti-

    gates a pseudos in words is its logos-value. Beneath the Myth of the Metals

    there is a meaningful philosophical argument, grounded in dialectic analysis

    and inspired by the Good, on the manner in which an idealized human com-

    munity ought to be governed. The myth may be little more than a clever

    encouragement designed to persuade people to follow the rules based on the

    merits of a fable, yet it has logos-value inasmuch as the ends that are antici-

    pated are identified as virtuous and therefore are considered to justify the

    somewhat duplicitous manner of their implementation. It is not moral relativ-

    ism if the guiding principle is no less than the unchanging, metaphysically

    sound Good itself, however it may be known.

    Fables of one particular sort play a prominent role in the Laws. They will

    be employed propagandistically as a means of social control to effect mass

    persuasion. The use of fables in this way, akin to the noble fictions of the

    Republic, corresponds both to known (or at least reputed) Athenian and Spar-

    tan practices from which Plato may have taken his cue.58 It becomes the chief

    business of the Magnesian government to mould the characters of its subjects

    and the Laws interlocutors deem the employment of logos-laden fables to

    this end as morally justifiable. In this utopian vision, as Strauss indicates, the

    perfect legislator will persuade or compel the poets to teach that justice goes

    with pleasure and injustice with pain [the] perfect legislator will demand

    that this salutary doctrine be taught even if it were not true.59

    It is nowhere suggested that Plato has overturned the basic tenet, elsewhere

    espoused and extolled, that only the one who knows what Justice is can be

    just. The Athenian Strangers policies, however totalitarian they may seem to

    a modern audience, are said repeatedly throughout the Laws to aim for the

    hypothetical Magnesians maximum attainment of and, thereby, happi-

    ness. Behind the moral fables, which are informative, is the threat of compul-

    sion for those who disobey the law. As Bobonich says, Law still has a penalty

    or sanction attached to it and Plato is willing to use force and the threat of

    100 K.R. MOORE

    57 J. Mitchell, Platos Fable: On the Mortal Condition in Shadowy Times (Princeton,2006), p. 38. A pseudos in words, with logos-value, may be used out of necessity in orderto inculcate the young or uneducated into the correct manner of behaviour; see Rep.378de on the malleability of young minds.

    58 A. Powell, Plato and Sparta: Modes of Rule and Non-Rational Persuasion in theLaws, pp. 273322, in The Shadow of Sparta, ed. A. Powell and S. Hodkinson (London,1994), p. 284. He says that Spartan official deceit included not only lying to helots as towhether they would be rewarded or killed, and misleading other enemies in wartime (apractice which Xenophon commended explicitly to non-Spartans), but also lying to theirown citizens about the outcome of battles involving Spartan forces. See Hesk, Decep-tion and Democracy, pp. 136, 15762 on this and see below.

    59 Strauss, Plato: Laws, p. 54.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 101

    force on those who are not rationally persuaded to obey.60 Subtler methods

    are preferable, however, and milder, effective persuasion is deemed more

    desirable in civilized society than coercion. The Athenian Stranger insists on

    relying on persuasion rather than repression because to use the latter is to

    admit defeat, which is implied by a lack of respect for the law.61

    Enter paramyth. Platos narrator uses this term to describe preambles to the

    citys laws that will be regularly read aloud to the Magnesians. Paramyth,

    may be loosely defined as encouragement or persuasion, andits use here combines philosophical, rhetorical and mythical qualities.62 The

    legal preambles possess a kind of mythological resonance and thus fall into

    the broader category of Platonic mythologizing.63 The Athenian Stranger

    indicates that the lawgiver should not threaten the populace with rules or

    merely prescribe his philosophically sound decrees, but that he should give

    encouragement () backed by appropriate degrees of legal force.64

    The legislator will deliver a convincing fiction that is grounded in a truth. It

    differs from a work of pure fiction (muthos) inasmuch as the discourse of the

    Magnesian legislator, unlike that of a poet, must be non-contradictory and

    based on logos.65 In addition to its mythic qualities, paramyth is also a special

    type of rhetoric to which I shall presently turn.

    Paramyth is seen to have a positive effect inasmuch as it is undertaken for

    the good of the subjects in question and the society as a whole. Many of these

    subjects will be unable to engage in the more complex philosophical discus-

    sions that underpin the laws. Non-citizens, such as slaves and resident aliens,

    will be affected by the oral recitation of the preambles in a way different from

    that of the citizens. The Magnesian citizens will study the text of the laws in

    school, along with their preambles, and will be expected to have gained an

    albeit limited comprehension of the inner mysteries of philosophy and civic

    ideology that underscore them by the time they reach adulthood.66

    Platos method of presenting his philosophical discourses in dramatic dia-

    logues connects significantly with his uses of myth and poetry. He establishes

    these fictional dialogues in a purely dramatic form, and sometimes in quasi-

    dramatic form, enclosed within a narrative framework.67 He has borrowed

    60 C. Bobonich, Persuasion, Compulsion and Freedom in Platos Laws, ClassicalQuarterly, 41.2 (1991), pp. 36588, p. 382.

    61 L. Brisson, Plato the Mythmaker, ed. and trans. G. Naddaf (Chicago, 1994), p. 120.62 See Liddell and Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon, s.v. .63 Brisson, Platon, les mots et les mythes, pp. 2002. They are also reminiscent of

    philosophical exhortations found in the Republic.64 720a12. See Bobonich, Persuasion, Compulsion, pp. 365 ff., for a broader dis-

    cussion of many of the linguistic issues represented by this passage.65 Laws 719bc. See Brisson, Plato the Mythmaker, pp. 1201.66 See Bobonich, Persuasion, Compulsion, p. 370.67 K. Dover, The Greeks (London, 1980), p. 105.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • from a number of literary and dramatic traditions in formulating the genre.68

    As with many of the myths that he employs, he did not originate the dramatic

    dialogue. Precedent for it may be found in Homeric dialogues, the Melian dia-

    logue and others of Thucydides, the Dissoi Logoi of the sophists and Athenian

    stage drama. There is every reason to believe that these were all important

    influences.

    Thucydides dialogues express what Immerwahr calls philosophical truths

    couched in historical theories and interpretations.69 The Dissoi Logoi does so

    even more self-consciously.70 Both package their messages in the accessible

    medium of the dialogue form. The feature of accessibility is an important

    aspect of it. Drama has a much wider appeal than dry dialectic. It also has

    advantages in terms of producing a more formal approach to philosophy. The

    dramatic dialogue allows Platos narrators to deal with a problem from many

    angles. They are able to set out opposing theories, showing that neither side is

    wholly right, and often conclude that the matter needs more thought.71 This

    represents a major stepping-stone to more sophisticated levels of philosophi-

    cal analysis.

    The Platonic dialogues demand certain imaginary concessions on the part

    of the reader or auditor to the effect that a fictional event, related to drama,

    epic and myth, is transpiring. It is within the imposed context of such a fic-

    tional event (the dialogue) that Platos narrators and characters undertake to

    philosophize. The Platonic tradition of employing myths and parables in

    order to provide reasoning by analogy may therefore be extended to the

    mythic framework of the dialogue itself. It is a kind of fictional episode out of

    which one is invited to derive some philosophical experience. One may inter-

    act with a Platonic dialogue through ones own independent thoughts as well

    as by imitation () of the methods and virtues presented. It is left to the

    audience to take away what they will, although their thoughts are typically

    encouraged, as we have seen, along specific lines.

    Some causal factor for Platos choice of literary style may be derived out of

    Socrates preference for dialogic discourse in his pursuit of wisdom. Socrates

    had employed oral discussion as his characteristic mode of philosophical

    activity. As a Platonic character, he has variously expressed the limitations of

    the written word inasmuch as it cannot answer questions or engage in interactive

    102 K.R. MOORE

    68 See R. Blondell, The Play of Character (Cambridge, 2002), who deals in greaterdetail with many of the literary aspects in Platos dialogues discussed below.

    69 H.R. Immerwahr, Pathology of Power in the Speeches in Thucydides, in TheSpeeches in Thucydides: A Collection of Original Studies With a Bibliography, ed.P.A. Stadter (Chapel Hill, 1973), pp. 1631, p. 23. See C. MacDonald, Plato, Laws704a707c and Thucydides II.3546, Classical Review, 9 (1959), pp. 1089, for a com-parison between these two passages.

    70 See R. Thomas, Herodotus in Context (Cambridge, 2000), pp. 88 and 1301.71 W. Guthrie, The Greek Philosophers: From Thales to Aristotle (New York, 1978),

    p. 16.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 103

    discussions with a living audience. This sort of interaction was the living Soc-

    rates philosophical modus operandi.72 Unlike his teacher, Plato devised a

    more formal means of getting his messages across. His approach is striking.

    Even the earlier dialogues, which are largely conversations with Socrates,

    indicate Platos involvement with philosophy in a more technical sense.73

    Other philosophers such as Parmenides, Solon, Pythagoras and Empedokles

    of Akragas had utilized the artistic medium of poetry in order to convey their

    ideas.74 Platos dramatic dialogue form would appear to represent a quantum

    leap beyond the methods of these others.

    As indicated, the dialogue form has the advantage of involving and engag-

    ing the reader/auditor in a very direct way precisely because of its dramatic

    qualities. This aids in its persuasiveness. The vividness of the scenes (i.e. two

    or more persons in a setting having a discussion) draws the observer into the

    dialogue in much the same way that one is vicariously drawn into a play being

    performed or, today, a film being screened. Philosophy presented this way,

    as Rutherford says, is more accessible, more enticing, than formally pre-

    sented system-building or ex cathedra exposition.75 Platos method contrasts

    sharply with the oracular style of Heraklitos, the divinely inspired utter-

    ances of Empedokles or the mind-teasers of Zeno of Elea while incorporat-

    ing certain elements from all of them. There are oracular pronouncements of

    a sort in Plato. These come as philosophical truths and the higher virtues

    imparted by metaphysical entities such as the Forms. There are also a number

    of poetic influences in Plato as well as a fair share of mind-teasers.76

    The dramatic dialogue form reveals other literary borrowings that contrib-

    ute to its total effect. Plato has incorporated other works and genres apart from

    those already mentioned. Examples include the transplantation of texts in

    whole or in part (as in the funeral speech in the Menexenus which echoes other

    examples of this genre and the many quotes from Homer and other poets

    throughout the Platonic corpus) along with incorporation by allusion (as in

    the many allusions to Euripides Antiope in the Gorgias). Plato can target a

    specific genre by incorporating the language, topoi, or themes that are pecu-

    liar to it and clearly identified as such. For example, when Callias slave slams

    72 As Thomas indicates, Platos authoritarian scheme in the Laws, intended to con-trol every aspect of citizens lives, does not, so far as I can see, think entirely in terms ofwritten laws (R. Thomas, Literacy and the City-State in Archaic and Classical Greece,in Literacy and Power in the Ancient World, ed. A. Bowman and G. Woolf (Cambridge,1994), pp. 3350, p. 37). See Laws 822d ff., 788b, 793ad.

    73 C.H. Kahn, Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of the Liter-ary Form (Cambridge, 1996), p. 53.

    74 Some of the most influential of those whom we now categorise as early Greekphilosophers wrote in verse (P. Murray, Plato on Poetry (Cambridge, 1996), p. 18).

    75 R. Rutherford, The Art of Plato (London, 1995), p. 8.76 See e.g. the closing passages from the Euthyphro as well as the slave boys geom-

    etry lesson in the Meno.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • the door in Socrates face at the beginning of the Protagoras, we are con-

    fronted by a topos from the genre of comedy.77 Numerous poets are quoted in

    the dialogues as authorities on ethical matters.78 When cited, Platos charac-

    ters metapoetically recite the piece in question as part of their dialogue.

    This technique of incorporating literary borrowings appears to play an

    important and practical role in the presentation of Platos philosophy. It may

    be the case that the audience or reader is meant to hear both a version of the

    original utterance as the embodiment of the speakers point of view (or

    semantic position) and the second speakers evaluation of that utterance

    from a different point of view.79 A probable end of such novelistic hybridiza-

    tion, as Nightingale and others call such intertextual borrowings, is the

    illumination of one literary discourse by means of another. As usual, his

    incorporation of works of poetry, speeches and comedic techniques are

    employed in order to advance a philosophical agenda and, crucially, to per-

    suade. Strauss sees the poetic influence as more profound. He states that in

    the sub-Socratic context of the Laws, the only kind of wise men apart from

    the legislators are the poets and he further asserts that the poet does not con-

    tradict himself by making different characters contradict one another.80 The

    difference is that the legislator, unlike the poet, must not speak with irony.

    However, this alleged subtext remains to be demonstrated. It undoubtedly is

    the case, as Strauss also says, that the Magnesian legislators must learn cer-

    tain things from the poets, especially about the great variety among the

    natures and habits of the souls.81

    This brings us back to the subject of paramyth and legal preambles. In addi-

    tion to these other poetical borrowings, the dramatic dialogue form in the

    Laws also adapts and incorporates certain techniques from rhetoric.82 This

    appears in the preambles to Magnesias code of laws that, as discussed above,

    are to be read before the assembled public largely as a means of persuasion.83

    All speeches, writes Strauss, need artfully composed preludes which move

    the audience toward the reception and acceptance of the speeches themselves

    104 K.R. MOORE

    77 A.W. Nightingale, Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy(Cambridge, 1997), p. 6.

    78 Murray, Plato on Poetry, p. 18. Such instances include, but are not limited to,Republic 331a, 331d, 334ab; Protagoras 339a341e, 343d347a; Meno 95c96a.

    79 Nightingale, Genres in Dialogue, p. 6.80 Strauss, The Argument and the Action in Platos Laws, p. 61.81 Ibid., p. 62; cf. Laws 650b69.82 Statesman 303e304e. Rhetoric is described as a subsidiary aspect of the science

    of politics but it persuades through mythological speeches and not through instruction.The Laws would seem to represent a new level to which this sort of mythologizing hasbeen taken.

    83 Laws 718b723a.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 105

    and this applies in particular to laws.84 The Athenian Stranger indicates that

    he obtained the idea for these legal preambles from the practice of delivering a

    proem before a main musical piece or oratorical speech.85 He says that, as with

    both music and rhetoric, the preamble serves as a kind of artistic preparation

    useful for the further development of the subject.86

    Why should the subject require preparation in order to be more receptive

    to the dictates of the laws? Written law, and perhaps bald philosophizing too,

    as the Athenian stranger says (and Strauss agrees), is a tyrannical prescrip-

    tion (722e); it orders and threatens like a tyrant or despot who writes his

    decrees on the wall and is done with it.87 The lawgiver can soften the impact

    of these with recourse to persuasive preambles the language of which is

    more exhortatory than prescriptive.88 Strauss describes the functions of the

    legal preambles saying that the proper mixture of coercion and persuasion, of

    tyranny and democracy, of wisdom and consent, proves everywhere to be

    the character of wise political arrangements.89 The basic structural differ-

    ences between Magnesia and the kallipolis of the Republic perhaps reveal the

    necessity for this recourse to rhetoric in the Laws.90 As in the Republic, only a

    small minority will meet the criteria of philosophical illumination.91 They

    will, however, be more educated than the denizens of the Republic and this is

    out of necessity. Magnesia is to be a limited democracy; however, the major-

    ity of people will be directed and exhorted to follow the laws without question

    rather than making or changing them. The rhetorical qualities of the legal pre-

    ambles are designed to aid the Magnesian government in keeping the popu-

    lace in order and presumably to encourage their democratic decision making

    along certain lines.

    Each preamble represents a piece of calculated rhetoric. Failure to take the

    advice offered in the preamble and, thence, breaking the law will incur

    severe penalties of a punitive as well as psychological nature. A Magnesian

    lawgiver will address himself/herself to the hypothetical populace, reciting

    84 Strauss, The Argument and the Action in Platos Laws, pp. 645.85 722d, 723cd.86 722d.87 859a46. Strauss, The Argument and the Action in Platos Laws, p. 64, says: Is

    therefore not, as Aristotle understood Socrates to have meant, the correct regime amixture of tyranny and democracy? See Aristotle, Politics 1266a13, and cf. Laws693d25 and 712d5.

    88 See A. Nightingale, Platos Lawcode in Context: Rule by Written Law in Athensand Magnesia, Classical Quarterly, 49.1 (1999), pp. 10022, p. 117, for comparisonswith the Statesman; and G. Morrow, Platos Cretan City: A Historical Interpretation ofthe Laws (Princeton, NJ, 1960), pp. 55260 for more on this aspect of the preambles.

    89 Strauss, Plato: Laws, p. 58. Cf. Aristotle, Politics 1266a, 13.90 Murray, Plato on Poetry, p. 212.91 Laws 691cd, 713c, 874e875d and see above. However, they will be educated in

    the workings of political theory, see below.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • the preambles and stating the laws and injunctions and these will then be pub-

    licly inscribed.92 Strauss lays out some of the difficulties that the lawgiver will

    have to address:

    He will preface the laws with preambles or preludes setting forth the rea-sons for the laws. Yet different kinds of reasons are needed for persuadingdifferent kinds of men, and the multiplicity of reasons may be confusingand thus endanger the simplicity of obedience. The Legislator must thenpossess the art of saying simultaneously different things to different kindsof citizens in such a way that the legislators speech will effect in all casesthe same simple results: obedience to his laws. In acquiring this art he willbe greatly helped by the poets.93

    This recourse to poetry is reflected in the literary and rhetorical nature of

    the preambles. However, as we have seen, they are not merely there to per-

    suade. They are also to instruct and function as one of many forces in the mass

    education and inculcation of the citizens.94 The fact that the Laws itself is

    required reading for the hypothetical Magnesians underscores the persuasive

    effects of the written text, in concert with living speech, as a kind of drug

    (pharmakon) acting on their psychai.95

    Platos narrator describes the legal preambles with recourse to an analogy

    to a doctor of slaves who prescribes his treatments without explanation

    and the doctor of a free man who provides an adequate (albeit incomplete)

    explanation as to why the medicine or treatment is beneficial to the patient.96

    This analogy breaks down somewhat as the lawgiver does not engage in a

    one-to-one dialogue with the citizens, but addresses them en masse. As Night-

    ingale says, the good lawgiver creates his preludes and his legal prescriptions

    long before he comes across any patients.97 Through his deeper compre-

    hension of the science of medicine, the free doctor is at once instructing and

    persuading the patient. The Magnesian lawgiver, with his/her deeper under-

    standing of the science of politics, delivers the preambles as persuasive pieces

    of instructive advice to a populace that, on the whole, lacks the lawgivers

    specialized . There is even a sense in which the majority of the

    106 K.R. MOORE

    92 Laws 822e823a.93 Strauss, Plato: Laws, p. 57. Cf. Laws 719b720e.94 H. Yunis, Taming Democracy: Models of Political Rhetoric in Classical Athens

    (Ithaca, NY, 1996), p. 214. See too Moore, Sex and the Second-Best City, ch. 3.95 See Nightingale, Platos Lawcode in Context, pp. 11718 and Hesk, Deception

    and Democracy, p. 1524 on Platos pharmacy and cf. Moore, Sex and the Second-BestCity, ch. 3.

    96 Laws 719e723c. What he is actually favouring is a combination of the two. TheMagnesian lawgiver will dispense justice just as surely as the slave doctor prescribes histreatments (and the populace will be equally subject to them) but, like the free doctor, theMagnesians receive some persuasive explanation as to why the treatment must beundertaken.

    97 Nightingale, Platos Lawcode in Context, p. 118.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 107

    Laws itself, given more to discussion about law than actual laws themselves,

    represents a kind of preamble for the purposes of preparing the Magnesian

    subjects.

    Despite lengthy discussions on the nature of paramyth by the Athenian

    Stranger, he gives few concrete examples of its use, preferring instead to

    leave such details to later Magnesian lawgivers to develop. However, there is

    one notable instance that strikes a particular chord with current Straussian

    philosophy which argues for the naturalness of a human institution.98 It con-

    cerns the laws and customs of marriage. Marriage in Magnesia, as in the real

    world, is an artificial construct of society designed largely, though perhaps

    not exclusively, to promote specific norms of sexual behaviour and to pro-

    duce an economic effect in terms of the transmission of property and inheri-

    tance. In encouraging monogamous, mixed-sex marital relationships (very

    unlike the model of breeding centres in the Republic),99 Platos narrator

    makes recourse to examples from the behaviour of animals in his proposed

    speech to the Magnesians. The Athenian Stranger suggests an ideal mode of

    conduct for his hypothetical populace in terms of marital fidelity. He asserts

    that the citizens standards should not be lower than those of the beasts and

    birds that are, apparently, all monogamous.100

    Whether this analogy reflects true conditions of nature or only common

    beliefs about it is not the point.101 It is a pharmacological model propa-

    gandistically embraced by Magnesias authorities.102 Citizens are expected to

    98 See Norton, Leo Strauss, pp. 837; she quotes Hadley Arkes, a prominentStraussian, who insists that Marriage cannot be detached from what some might call thenatural teleology of the body; namely, the inescapable fact that only two people, notthree, only a man and a woman, can beget a child, p. 84.

    99 Republic 416d ff., 420a, 422d, 464b ff., 543b.100 when they arrive at the appropriate age, a husband is wedded to a wife, as a

    matter of personal preference ( ), and a wife to a husband, and for theirremaining time they live piously and justly, being staunchly true to their first love-contracts (840d6e1). Cf. Euripides, Helen, 190.

    101 See Herodotus, Histories, 2.64 and 4.180 for a contrasting animalistic analogy. At2.64 he indicates that only the Egyptians and the Greeks do not behave like animalssince they forbade sexual intercourse in temples (e.g. unlike the Babylonians and otherbarbarians). At IV.180 he discusses the savage Machyles and Auses (tribes near Libya)who share their women in common like animals. See M. Rosellini and S. Sad, Usagesde Femmes et Autres NOMOI Chez les sauvages dHrodote: Essai de LectureStructurale, in Annali della Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa, classe di lettere efilosofia (series 3), 7.3 (1978), p. 965, on Herodotos slanted ethnography of savagepromiscuity amongst foreign peoples; and cf. Moore, Sex and the Second-Best City, ch.7, for more on this analogy in Plato. One interpretation of Egyptian archaeology suggeststhat they placed less emphasis on virginity and same-sex intercourse than the Atheniansof Platos era.

    102 See Hesk, Deception and Democracy, pp. 1536, 15962 on Platonic pharmaka.In contrast to Plato, Diogenes the Cynic, in his hypothetical constitution, considered

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • engage in proper sexual relations only within state-approved marriages between

    members of the opposite sex.103 Consider Philebus 67b, where Platos Socra-

    tes states that the many prefer to use such arguments from the natural world

    as authoritative fact rather than divining deeper truths from philosophy.104

    The many are seen to look on animal behaviour, perceived through com-

    mon sense, as in some ways paradigmatic of how they ought to behave.

    Platos use of this argument from animal nature in the Laws is a powerful

    rhetorical device that will have a serious effect on his citizens and possibly

    nothing more.105 To this he adds another persuasive tale. The Athenian

    Stranger exhorts his hypothetical citizenry to marry saying that one must nat-

    urally hold onto the everlasting by always leaving behind children and grand-

    children after one that they may render services unto the gods.106 It is

    , the primal force of reproduction that grants humankind a necessaryfoothold on immortality.107 It should be noted, still, that this concern of

    Platos narrator is almost obsessively dictated by the need to preserve a stable,

    fixed population and, as such, it may be less (metaphysically) moral than

    108 K.R. MOORE

    promiscuity with mutual consent to be the most satisfactory sexual arrangement and heregarded the sexual act (as with eating, masturbation and excretion) as not especially pri-vate (Diogenes Laertes VI.72, 97). On comparable modes of sexual propaganda seeXenophon, Constitution of the Spartans, 1.79, for alleged Spartan wife-swapping and,again, on Herodotus who portrayed barbarian cultures as being sexually promiscuous, cf.1.203, 3.101, 4.180 and also Rosellini and Sad, Usages de Femmes et Autres, pp.95566.

    103 Ideally no man, says the Athenian Stranger, would dare to have sexual relationswith a respectable free-woman other than his wedded wife, nor would he dare to sowunacceptable and bastard seed among concubines, nor sterile seed in males contrary tonature, Laws 841d15. Cf. Moore, Sex and the Second-Best City, ch. 6, on the issue ofsame-sex liaisons.

    104 In the Philebus passage cited above, Socrates is discussing pleasure and arguesthat one ought not to derive ones way of thinking on the matter from the beasts and birds.This does not necessarily exclude the possibility that one might draw logical conclusionsabout pleasure from animals should their actions happen to be in accord with philoso-phy but this is not what is said in the text in this instance.

    105 M. Nussbaum, Platonic Love and Colorado Law, Virginia Law Review, 80.7(1994), pp. 15151651, p. 1631.

    106 773a5774a1.107 The Athenian Stranger says that is the principal process whereby human-

    kind may render service to the Good, the supreme object of religious worship (

    728d1). He indicates that those who render service to the Highesthave contact with !, which corresponds to true, indestructibleBeing. At 903c, he says that every fashions an instrument for helping to securethe happiness of the universe as a whole. This would seem consistent with Diotimasthesis at Symposium 206e25 where is described as both a longing for offspring inaccordance with the Good and, at 207a34, as the longing for the Immortal. SeeMoore, Sex and the Second-Best City, chs. 4 and 5.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 109

    material in its design.108 If the exhortation based on has purelymaterial motivations and no real metaphysical basis, then it would appear to

    uphold the Straussian position on Platonic exotericism. However, this remains

    to be seen.109

    The preambles are clearly meant to render the audience favourably disposed

    toward the speaker and to instruct, in albeit a superficial way thus facilitating

    general acceptance, about the virtue of the particular law being introduced.

    The lawgiver who will read the preamble is being cast in the role of a teacher.

    He/she is compared to a loving and intelligent father or mother whom the

    law also stipulates must be honoured.110 The lawgiver may be seen as a paren-

    tal figure (a sort of good shepherd) that, through the benefits of greater wis-

    dom, seeks to help others. The evangelical connotations of this have not

    been overlooked and are not purely the transference of modern prejudices.

    Platos legal preambles, fictional though they be, have entered a fourth state

    of rhetoric beyond the traditional modes of the deliberative, the judicial and

    the epideictic. They might possibly represent the first systematized example

    of preaching as a rhetorical form.111 They do, in fact, exhort the Magnesian

    subjects to obey the laws through the backing of religious authority.112 Not

    unlike later Christian preaching, Platos employment of calculated, instruc-

    tive discourse is also designed to communicate divine matters in common par-

    lance. The need for mass-appeal directs their verbal packaging. This, along

    with Platos adaptation of the dialogue form, constitutes a significant and

    influential innovation.113

    108 Laws 745a ff. The law must encourage families to produce sufficient heirs toinherit estates lest the number of households change from a stable 5040; cf. 457a ff. onhow having twelve artificially established kinship groups makes a convenient divisionof the 5040. Aristotle, in the Politics (1265a13), criticizes Plato for suggesting such alarge number of citizens, saying that we cannot overlook the fact that such a numberwould require the territory of Babylon or some other comparably large country toaccommodate. At 1276a29, he points out that Babylon was so large that it had been cap-tured for two whole days before some of the inhabitants knew of the fact.

    109 I posit here, as an aside, that Strausss statement in The Argument and the Actionin Platos Laws, p. 64, to the effect that by not marrying, Plato did what according to himthe poets do: he contradicted the law and thus himself is itself immaterial to this discus-sion. Like Strauss, Plato is not obliged to be consistent between or outside his texts although the latter appears to be more so than the former. Also, we do not know for cer-tain that Plato did not marry.

    110 859a; see 923ac for this propagandistically parental theme and cf. too Moore,Sex and the Second-Best City, ch. 5.

    111 Yunis, Taming Democracy, pp. 22930.112 Laws 715e716b.113 The general impression, as Yunis, Taming Democracy, p. 236, indicates, is that

    religious experience was conveyed through texts only among esoteric groups such asOrphics and Pythagoreans.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • Myth, rhetoric and persuasion are interconnected in Platonic thinking both

    within and without the Laws. By selectively deploying these devices, Plato

    has made forays into new genres of literature and philosophy. This has

    entailed the creative revision of myth and history, tailored to rhetorically pro-

    mote specific values. The difference from the traditional usages of these

    before and during Platos era is that he has re-combined them as a means to his

    own ends not guided by the whims of poets or the expedients of a given

    political moment, but as a scientifically organized method of affecting social

    control along specific philosophical lines.

    IIStraussian Lies

    Recollect the Straussian argument in favour of Thrasymachos position in the

    Republic to the effect that Justice is the interest of the stronger (338c2343c ff.).

    Thrasymachos was regarded by the fictional Socrates as being deranged for

    holding such a view. However, this position recurs in the Laws (714bd).

    Here it is acknowledged that this is a political attitude that infects most

    regimes and constitutions in existence. Actual instances from antiquity are

    too numerous to recount but I will mention a couple. Spartan official deceit,

    for example, included not only lying to the helots about whether they would

    be rewarded or killed, misleading other enemies in wartime (which was a

    practice that Xenophon commended explicitly to non-Spartans), but also mis-

    informing their own citizens about the outcome of battles involving Spartan

    forces.114 Athens and other ancient Greek poleis most certainly followed suit

    in their practices of official deceit. This was par for the course in a world

    where, as Platos Cretan and Spartan interlocutors agree and Strauss summar-

    izes, by nature every city is at all times in a state of undeclared war with every

    other city.115 Any government that accepts the Thrasymachean view would

    not hesitate, ipso facto, to lie to its subjects whether as a pretext to war, to

    protect criminals that might exist amongst its elite classes or in other ways in

    like manner.

    That is the state of the real world and the effectual basis of Machiavellis

    later doctrine of Political Realism.116 But it amounts to a rejection of Platos

    views as they are generally understood. A significant difficulty with the asser-

    tion that justice is the interest of the stronger is that it does not apply to cer-

    tain specific political arrangements, namely, those in which the laws are

    110 K.R. MOORE

    114 Powell, Plato and Sparta, p. 284. See too Hesk, Deception and Democracy, pp.136, 15762 on this. Cf. Thuc. 4.80.3 ff., Xen. Ages. 1.17, Hellenica, 1.6.36 ff., 4.3.13 ff.On the so-called noble lie, again, cf. Plato, Rep. 398bd, 414bc, 415c and 459c.

    115 Strauss, Plato: Laws, p. 52.116 Strauss repeatedly defends the political realism of Thrasymachus and Machia-

    velli; cf., for example, L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1953), and esp.p. 106.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 111

    designed to reflect a common good that transcends sectarian rivalries and con-

    sequently poses a moral reason to be obeyed.117 Magnesia is envisioned as

    a polis with precisely that type of legal system (715bd). While there can be

    little doubt that the social arrangements of Sparta and Crete left a positive

    impression on Plato, he seems to have regarded them as being, as Rawson

    says, on the right lines but too obsessed with war.118 Strauss himself makes

    Platos case well, saying:

    For if victory in war is the condition of all blessings, war is not the end: theblessings themselves belong to peace. Hence the virtue of war, courage, isthe lowest part of virtue, inferior to moderation and above all to justice andwisdom.119

    Magnesia is to be explicitly unwarlike. It is our object to avoid war entirely,

    if we can, declares the Athenian Stranger, so soldiers must get their training

    in sham-fights and the like (829a8b1). There is never any mention in the

    entire discussion on paramyth, or in the Laws itself, about having to lie to the

    people as a pretext for war. Magnesias laws and institutions are grounded in

    Justice for the common good and presided over by truly Just individuals. It

    will not need to manipulate its populace in morally questionable ways in

    any Platonic sense, that is.

    Still, Magnesias martial readiness is beyond doubt and the injunction to

    avoid war entirely, if we can seems to beg the question: what if we cannot?

    Might paramyth be used to convince the Magnesians to go to war? It will be up

    to the nukterinos to interpret the ethical character of the law under such circum-

    stances. The Athenian Stranger has not accounted for any eventuality that

    might lead to that specific course of action. The nukterinos would have to be

    convinced that the decision to lie to the people of Magnesia as a pretext to war

    would itself be justified in terms of both its benefit to the common good and its

    compatibility with actual Justice as they are meant to understand it. For a

    non-imperialist, self-sufficient polis such as the one about which Plato has writ-

    ten in the Laws, it is difficult to imagine that sort of scenario ever taking place.

    It is difficult to reconcile the difference between the view, advanced by

    Strauss, that the Thrasymachean doctrine to the effect that justice is the inter-

    est of the stronger is correct and there is no such thing as natural justice or

    inalienable rights, and the view, also explicitly maintained by Strauss, that

    moral relativism is a danger to society and that true philosophy is divinely

    117 C.J. Nederman, Giving Thrasymachus his Due: The Political Argument ofRepublic I and its Reception, Polis, 24.1 (2007), pp. 2642, p. 37.

    118 E. Rawson, The Spartan Tradition in European Thought (Oxford, 1969),pp. 656.

    119 Strauss, Plato: Laws, p. 52. See Laws 631bd.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • inspired.120 The latter is clearly an instance of a moral absolute, that is, if it is

    really what Strauss believed. In addition to his Thrasymachean interpretation

    of the Republic, he has also left a telling comment as to his own beliefs, via

    Plato, in the form of a correspondence with Alexandre Kojve, the Russian-

    born, French philosopher who read Hegels philosophy of consciousness

    through the twin lenses of Marxist materialism and Heideggers temporalized

    ontology of human being (Dasein), and can rightly be said to have initiated

    existential Marxism. In their correspondence, Strauss writes to him that the

    astrolatry of the Tim-, Laws X, Epinomis is either purely ironical, or

    forged (by the Eudoxian Speusippus), or preached to the people for rea-

    sons of state.121 This astrolatry refers to metaphysical statements about the

    gods,122 the soul and afterlife. Strauss is saying that this is an extension of the

    official deceit espoused by Platos esoteric philosophy but excluded from the

    exoteric teachings.

    This Straussian interpretation begs a couple of questions at the least. Mag-

    nesia of the Laws will have many religious ceremonies123 and, as part of the

    legal preambles, an encomium to the gods, ancestral spirits and parents is

    included.124 We have seen that the citizens of Magnesia will study the Laws so,

    presumably, they will come to understand the rhetorical effects implicit in

    paramyth. It stands to reason, then, that paramyth must be aimed at Mag-

    nesian citizen children prior to their educative induction, citizens whose edu-

    cation is more limited, resident aliens and other foreigners who may not be

    subject to the Magnesian education and, of course, the ubiquitous slaves.

    There will be no masses in the second-best polis apart from these. If the

    Athenian Strangers astrolatry then is interpreted as being purely rhetorical

    and persuasive, the product of exoteric doctrine, and the Magnesians also

    study the Laws and other Platonic texts, then the rhetorical effects of such

    exercises will be lost on the citizen population. Why undertake the teaching of

    this astrolatry unless it is regarded as being metaphysically beneficial and,

    in a sense, genuine? It is not incompatible with knowledge of the Good, which

    most people will not obtain, and may be the closest that they come to philo-

    sophical illumination. There is clearly some level of esotericism working here

    and the religious ceremonies, as with paramyth, serve as agents of social

    112 K.R. MOORE

    120 To further complicate matters, he seems to come down in favour of naturalrights when he indicates that originally, one can say with some exaggeration the naturaland the genuine were the same (cf. Plato, Laws 642c8d1, 777d56; Rousseau, DuContrat Social 1.9 end and 2.7, third paragraph); Nietzsche prepares decisively thereplacement of the natural by the authentic, in Strauss, Studies in Platonic Political Phi-losophy, p. 186 and see too p. 139.

    121 L. Strauss, On Tyranny, ed. V. Gourevitch and M.S. Roth (Chicago, 2000), p. 289.122 See Laws 896e ff.123 On Magnesian religious festivals, see Laws 828c56 ff., on ceremonies honour-

    ing deceased ancestors, 958e8960a2 and ff.124 See Laws 717a6d4.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 113

    control and moral inculcation, but it would appear that there is no need to

    divorce Plato from his metaphysics here.

    Strauss has been accused of being a closet Nietzschean or Heideggerian

    and, while this remains to be proven, there is some evidence to suggest just

    that sort of philosophical inclination on his part.125 He appears to read Plato

    phenomenologically, that is, without regard for his metaphysics. Strauss

    either ignores Platonic metaphysics altogether or, as in the quote above,

    seems to regard them as part of an exoteric programme of official deceit

    designed to conceal the true teachings that are not for the masses. This

    brings us back to Strausss reception of both al Farabi and Plato and the use

    of official deceit. Whilst al Farabi never declared the esoteric position that

    Platos theory of Forms and the immortality of the soul are exoteric teach-

    ings, Strauss can discover this in Plato by a careful reading premised on

    the esoteric/exoteric distinction which Strauss also discovers in Farabis

    writings.126 Strausss use of this exoteric/esoteric distinction parallels Hei-

    deggers use of etymology. Both methods permit the interpreter to dis-

    cover a contemporary concern in ancient texts.127 Thereby Strauss can

    produce a reading of Plato devoid of metaphysics and with the implicit

    advocacy of official deceit.

    What is missing from the equation is the esoteric part of Straussian philosophy,

    namely, because it happens to be esoteric. Some have argued that there is no real

    hidden teaching to which Strauss and his followers have recourse that it is a

    Trojan horse or chimera concocted to fool the masses.128 If one assumes that there

    is a secret doctrine, then it could be the case that Strausss apparent agreement

    with Thrasymachos in the Republic, along with his comments on astrolatry, are

    part of the exoteric Straussian philosophy and the reasons behind upholding such

    a view publicly fall within the esoteric realm. Strauss, like Plato, is not obliged to

    present a systematic account of his philosophy in any extant text. It may be sur-

    mised, however, based on the known interests of Strauss, that his esotericism is

    connected with ancient Hebrew mysticism. He has been accused of blending

    Jerusalem, and its tradition of divinely inspired prophets, with Athens and Platos

    125 See S. Drury, The Esoteric Philosophy of Leo Strauss, Political Theory, 13.3(1985), pp. 31537; and S. Drury, The Political Ideas of Leo Strauss (New York, 1988);L. Lampert, Leo Strauss and Nietzsche (Chicago, 1996); P. Levine, Nietzsche and theModern Crisis of the Humanities (Albany, 1995); on Strauss as a Heiddegerian seeL. Ferry, Political Philosophy I: Rights The New Quarrel Between the Ancients andthe Moderns, trans. F. Philip (Chicago, 1990).

    126 Robertson, Leo Strausss Platonism, p. 3.127 A. Slner, Leo Strauss: German Origin and American Impact, in Hannah

    Arendt and Leo Strauss, ed. P.G. Kielmansegg, H. Mewes and E. Glaser-Schmidt (Cam-bridge, 1995), pp. 12137, p. 126; also see above on Strauss as a closet Heideggerian.

    128 For a particularly scathing view on Strausss esotericism (or lack thereof), see M.F.Burnyeat, Sphinx Without a Secret, New York Review of Books, 32.9 (1985), pp. 306.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • philosopher kings/queens, also divinely inspired albeit in a somewhat different

    manner. This may clarify his position to a point.

    Strausss tack has been described as zetetic, in some ways like Socrates,

    ever searching for alternative teachings. He is also dogmatically anti-

    dogmatic, pointing to the need for movement beyond the cave but declaring

    that this is ultimately unobtainable.129 Therein may lie his Achilles heel,

    though, since his claim to reject dogma has itself become a dogma of a kind.

    His historical hermeneutic does not entail the interpretation of philosophers

    of the past in their own context, however limited may sometimes be our

    apprehension of that context. Rather, he is importing contemporary concerns

    and assumptions into these in spite of ostensibly, perhaps exoterically, oppos-

    ing just such an imposition.130

    It seems clear that Strauss, al Farabi, Moses Maimonides and probably

    Plato all made recourse to esoteric doctrines. It remains unclear, in all cases,

    what these doctrines actually entailed. All we have are their writings which, if

    we acknowledge their supposed esotericism, are explicitly exoteric in nature

    and do not reveal the whole truth. What does it mean to partake of the Form of

    the Good? What does it mean to receive a prophetic revelation? In the words

    of Thomas Pangle, a Straussian in the truer sense as well as a student and col-

    league of Strauss:

    Every attempt by any philosopher to refute the claim, and hence the com-mands, of any revelation fails, or can be shown to relapse into logical fal-lacy as Strauss was wont to point out, there is only one indisputable,logical procedure by which the philosopher can achieve a decisive refuta-tion of the claims of piety or revelation : he can show that in principle hehas a clear and exhaustive explanation of how and why everything in theentire cosmos is as it is and behaves as it does.131

    Only then can the philosopher assert that there is no quarter of the entire cos-

    mos for the miraculous, no room for philosopher kings/queens or revelatory

    prophets. But the burden of proof cuts both ways and as yet there remains no

    definitive proof that the miraculous ever did or does occur. Scepticism is the

    default position of science and most academic philosophy and will remain so

    until proven otherwise. Still, we have to accept that this morally and metaphysi-

    cally absolutist position was one held by many in the past, is held by many in

    the present and will be held by many in the future. It is a significant part of our

    wider discourse and, whether we agree with it or not, is likely to remain so.

    As for Platonic esotericism, there is every reason to believe that, whatever

    he has not told us in his dramatic dialogues, his esoteric views must surely be

    114 K.R. MOORE

    129 Robertson, Leo Strausss Platonism, p. 5.130 This is ostensibly contrary to Strausss stated position. See On a New Interpreta-

    tion of Platos Political Philosophy, Social Research, 13.3 (1946), pp. 32667.131 Pangles introduction to Strauss, Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy,

    pp. 223.

    Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010For personal use only -- not for reproduction

  • PLATONIC MYTHS AND STRAUSSIAN LIES 115

    related to the process of becoming a philosopher king or queen and the

    apprehension/partaking of the Good rather than its use as a bluff for the

    masses to convince them of the philosophers higher authority. Given the in-

    depth discussions on metaphysics in the Republic, Timaeus and elsewhere,

    and the amount of significance placed on philosophical illumination, it appears

    unlikely that all of it is merely an exoteric ruse calculated to mesmerise the

    many whilst power is seized and exercised according to the interest of the

    stronger. Plato, as we have seen, is certainly no stranger to calculated dis-

    course and persuasive dialogic, but his narrators deploy these as tools to sway

    the masses who are unable to grasp the deeper metaphysics underlying the just

    actions of the philosophically enlightened. The argument that it has all been a

    trick for the purposes of the attainment of political power undermines the

    essence of Platonic metaphysics, on which his whole philosophy is based.

    And yet, it is a tantalising position to consider, that the whole business of the

    Good, the Forms and immortal souls was all a hoax that fooled countless gen-