27
Northern PSA Postgraduate Conference Edinburgh, 6 June 2008 Volha Piotukh [email protected] PhD student, School of Politics and International Studies (POLIS) The University of Leeds Supervisors: Dr. Deiniol Jones and Prof. Alice Hills Title: “Humanitarian Action and the War on Terror: Some Preliminary Thoughts on a New Biopolitical Nexus” Abstract As the War on Terror begins to receive the scholarly attention it deserves, its impact on humanitarian action, with a few notable exceptions, remains largely unexplored. This paper is attempting to fill in this gap by ‘reading’ this new relationship biopolitically. The paper briefly addresses the nature of the environment in which humanitarian actors have been finding themselves since the beginning of the War on Terror and then proceeds by considering the implications that this environment has for humanitarian action. It argues that not only has the War on Terror reinforced earlier trends in the evolution of humanitarian action associated with the so-called ‘new’ humanitarianism, but it has taken them further still by

Piotukh Paper

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Piotukh Paper

Northern PSA Postgraduate Conference

Edinburgh, 6 June 2008

Volha Piotukh

[email protected]

PhD student, School of Politics and International Studies (POLIS)

The University of Leeds

Supervisors: Dr. Deiniol Jones and Prof. Alice Hills

Title: “Humanitarian Action and the War on Terror:

Some Preliminary Thoughts on a New Biopolitical Nexus”

Abstract

As the War on Terror begins to receive the scholarly attention it deserves, its impact on

humanitarian action, with a few notable exceptions, remains largely unexplored. This paper is

attempting to fill in this gap by ‘reading’ this new relationship biopolitically. The paper briefly

addresses the nature of the environment in which humanitarian actors have been finding

themselves since the beginning of the War on Terror and then proceeds by considering the

implications that this environment has for humanitarian action. It argues that not only has the

War on Terror reinforced earlier trends in the evolution of humanitarian action associated with

the so-called ‘new’ humanitarianism, but it has taken them further still by incorporating

humanitarian action into the war effort and blurring the lines between aid and security, the latter

being understood as ‘homeland’ security. Building on Foucault’s theorising on biopower and

biopolitics, and its further interpretation by Agamben, as well as recent work on the War on

Terror as a biopolitical enterprise, the paper suggests that within a new biopolitical nexus of war

and humanitarianism the latter’s role has been transformed further from mitigating violence to

facilitating it. This transformation cannot be easily reversed, and it is probably more damaging to

the humanitarian enterprise than it has been recognised so far.

NB. Draft – not to be cited.

Page 2: Piotukh Paper

The Global War on Terror as the new environment for humanitarian action

Although almost two decades have passed since the end of the Cold War, its impact and

importance are still to be fully understood and appreciated. The much more recent Global War on

Terror (GWOT) is just beginning to get the scholarly attention it deserves. The importance of

considering the GWOT in terms of its implications for humanitarian action is emphasised by

Macrae and Harmer, who point out that it “constitutes not only a series of actual and potential

armed conflicts, but also a framework within which international and national policy, including

humanitarian aid policy, will de defined and implemented” (Macrae and Harmer, 2003 p. 1).

Following the September 11, 2001 attacks on the World Trade Center in New York and the

Pentagon in Washington, the US declared a new war, the war on terrorism, one with no clear

targets and no clear limits. The potentially unending character of the war, as well as the divisions

it created, allowed many to suggest clear parallels with the Cold War (see, for instance, Macrae

and Harmer, 2003 p. 4; Minear, 2002 p. 191). The ‘either with us or against us’ approach proved

detrimental for independent humanitarian space (see, for instance, Donini, 2004 p. 38).

GWOT clearly caused some damage to the UN and to multilateralism in general, which was

reflected not just in the absence of the UN Security Council sanction in Iraq (not unprecedented,

as we know), but also in the way the UN was treated by the Occupying Power (see, for instance,

de Torrente, 2004; Donini, Minear and Walker, 2004). By working through bilateral

relationships, the U.S. Administration managed to overcome existing constraints on international

decision-making, and the coalition it created has been effectively used as a vehicle for promoting

U.S. foreign policy agendas (Macrae and Harmer, 2003 p. 2). Within the framework of GWOT

any alternative, non-military, counter-terrorist approaches are not seriously considered (Jackson,

2005), and even humanitarian action is seen as an essential part of the war effort, its second front

or force-multiplier (for evidence see Minear, 2002; de Torrente, 2004; Vaux, 2006; Hoffman and

Weiss, 2006). Therefore, GWOT not only builds on the ‘coherence’ agenda1 of the previous

years, but also takes it further in a very particular way.

1 Coherence in this context is understood as “the attempt to bring together, cohere or join up political action in peace operations with other actions including humanitarian and human rights. As pursued by the UN system and key donor governments, it is the attempt to bring together all elements of a multi-dimensional peace operation to serve the UN’s central objective to make, maintain or build peace and security in [a particular] country” (the Henry Dunant Centre for Humanitarian Dialogue, 2003 p. 24).

2

Page 3: Piotukh Paper

The disrespect for International Law in general (take, for instance, the so-called doctrine of pre-

emptive self-defence), and International Humanitarian Law (IHL) in particular (for a useful

account see Beyani, 2003), has increased the overall vulnerability of civilians caught in the

ongoing GWOT campaigns, and has contributed to the worsening of security of humanitarian

workers (see, for instance, Donini, 2004; Donini, Minear and Walker, 2004). Two 2003 attacks

on UN and the International Committee of the Red Cross (ICRC) headquarters in Iraq that took

37 lives, including Sergio Vieira de Mello, the then Secretary-General’s Special Representative

in Iraq, are representative of this trend.

Finally, GWOT has further blurred the lines between aid and security, while shifting the priorities

in favour of homeland security, and contributed to further reinforcement of containment policies2.

As Duffield and Waddell note in this respect, “[r]ather than prioritising the security of people

living within ineffective states (a key manoeuvre in human security) the security of ‘homeland’

populations has moved centre-stage” (Duffield and Waddell, 2006 p. 19).

Further evolution of the ‘new’ humanitarianism

Even before GWOT, important post-Cold War developments in the international environment,

such as unequal ‘erosion’ of state sovereignty, increased disengagement of the North from the

South accompanied by the policies of containment, ‘new’ wars and ‘new interventionism’ all had

an impact on the humanitarian action. The analysis of various accounts on the ways the

humanitarian enterprise responded to these new challenges and opportunities allows one to

identify a number of major developments. These include the proliferation of humanitarian actors,

aid privatisation and an increased competition for funds; further institutionalisation of

humanitarian action through the establishment of coordination structures; the demise of 2 I refer to a set of policies which make it increasingly difficult “for people to get out of, or stay out of, their home countries” (Macrae, 2002 p. 6). The containment measures range from the strengthening of borders through imposing restrictions on the numbers of asylum seekers and refugees and the increased use of refoulement (involuntary return to the country where security of refugees would be jeopardised) and even expulsion, to reengagement with the violent conflict through the ‘new’ interventionism. The ‘new’ interventionism, in its turn, is operationalised through such measures as the imposition of sanctions, provision of support and protection to conflict-affected populations in situ (Duffield, 1997; Borton, 1998; Macrae, 2002), and forceful ‘humanitarian’ interventions. Therefore, what may seem as a genuine paradox, in fact is probably not, as closure of borders and ‘new interventionism’ can be seen as two sides of the same coin. Thus, according to Bennet, “Intervention is disengagement, for it is associated with containment which supports populations in war zones, discourages refugee flows and internalises causes and consequences” (Bennet quoted in Dubernet, 2001 p. 19). For Duffield “[…] humanitarian intervention is part of a wider trend towards separate development within the global economy and the containment of the associated instability” (Duffield, 1997 p. 338).

3

Page 4: Piotukh Paper

development assistance and subsequent promotion of the relief-development continuum resulting

in the concept of ‘developmental relief’; a shift from traditional humanitarian principles to a

rights-based approach; a shift to consequentialist ethics in response to the mounting critique of

the ‘dark side’ of humanitarian action, accompanied by extensive ‘soul-searching’ within the

humanitarian enterprise; increased ‘bilateralisation’ and securitisation of humanitarian assistance

and its increasingly technological nature; and ‘militarisation’ of humanitarian assistance in

conflict environments.

Although changes in donor policies and the humanitarian enterprise itself should not be seen as

representing a break with previous policies and practices, but rather as a set of shifts, they are

significant and pervasive enough to warrant the label ‘new’, as well as our special attention. I

offer the following definition of the ‘new’ humanitarianism: a set of shifts in humanitarian

policies and practices, which have taken place since the 1990s towards the increased

prominence and intrusiveness of humanitarian action and its use as a foreign policy tool by,

predominantly, Western states, in addressing conflicts and other crises or instability. This

kind of humanitarian action is broadly construed, better resourced and more institutionalised than

before, and it is carried out by a considerable number of different actors. While the use of

humanitarian action as a foreign policy tool of donor states is not, in itself, new, the extent of

such use, some of its objectives, as well as some of the ways in which it is carried out, are novel.

In its turn, GWOT not only reinforced earlier trends in the evolution of humanitarian action

associated with the ‘new’ humanitarianism, but it has taken them further still. It is believed to

“[have] triggered a deleterious quantitative and qualitative shift in the inclusion of humanitarian

action into Northern political agendas” (Donini and Minear et al., 2006 p. 6). As it has already

been stated, both in Afghanistan and Iraq, humanitarians were treated as part of the combat team

responsible for “hearts and minds”. According to Rieff, in the case of Afghanistan, “[a]lmost

from the moment the bombing started, U.S. officials went to considerable lengths to point out

how the military mission and the humanitarian were parts of the same campaign” (Rieff, 2002 p.

233). At the start of the Iraq campaign, Natsios, USAID Administrator, told humanitarian NGOs

that by being funded by the U.S. government they were effectively its arm (Natsios quoted in De

Torrente, 2004 pp. 19-20)

The Iraq experience can also serve as a rather extreme example of a differentiation of response to

crises which is far from being needs-based. Indeed, in 2003 and 2004 Iraq received a larger share

4

Page 5: Piotukh Paper

of DAC3 humanitarian assistance then any other single country over the past ten years

(Development Initiatives, 2006 pp. 14-15), in spite of the fact the humanitarian need itself was

not great (Smillie and Minear, 2004 p. 194; Donini, Minear and Walker, 2004 p. 196).

Importantly, the dependence on funds trumped all other operational considerations of

humanitarians, as even those agencies whose services were not essential chose to stay engaged,

even in the face of an increased threat of instrumentalisation.

However, NGOs found themselves competing for funds, and not just with other NGOs and other

humanitarians, like the UN agencies, which had become the norm in the post-Cold War

‘humanitarian marketplace’, but also with military or commercial contractors. According to

Feinstein International Famine Center report (2004 pp. 68-69), “[i]n both Afghanistan and Iraq,

the U.S. government has chosen to channel substantial amounts of funds to private, for-profit

contractors for reconstruction work. (…) The U.S. has also been in the vanguard of suiting up

military personnel for humanitarian tasks”.

Finally, while “[t]he explicit linkage of the security and humanitarian agendas” is not new and

“has been shaping responses to complex political crises for at least a decade” (Macrae and

Harmer, 2003 p. 11), with the GWOT “the balance has tipped [away from an arguably more

universalistic notion of human security of the 1990s] in favour of a ‘harder’ version of security

which prioritizes homeland livelihood systems and infrastructures” (Duffield and Waddell, 2006

p. 3). This shift has important implications, as priorities now seem to lie with “coercive, short-

term strategies aimed at stopping attacks by cutting off financial, political or military support and

apprehending possible perpetrators” and not with those “addressing the underlying causes related

to inequality, exclusion and marginalization, and aggression by states as well as people” (the

Commission for Human Security quoted in Duffield and Waddell, 2006 p. 13) characteristic of

the human security approach, which is arguably more development and human rights-friendly.

Even this brief overview allows one to suggest that overall GWOT has already made a profound

impact on the humanitarian enterprise which cannot and should not be ignored. I would like to

suggest that the relationship between GWOT and humanitarianism can be read ‘biopolitically’,

i.e. using Foucault’s theorising on biopower.

3 DAC stands for the Development Assistance Committee (DAC) of the Organisation for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD) and represents the major ‘donor club’.

5

Page 6: Piotukh Paper

Biopolitics as ‘the politics of life itself’

Foucault

As Reid comments “[t]he works of Michel Foucault and other major political and social thinkers

influenced by him are among the most under-utilised and yet over-abused resources of

International Relations theory. Work within International Relations influenced by Foucault has

generally been accused of irrelevance to disciplinary concerns” (Reid, 2006 p. x). He further

suggests that “[t]hrough Foucault it is possible to pose questions and develop modes of analysis

of the relations between war and the development of liberal societies that take us some way

beyond the ordinary limits of studies derived from existing traditions of IR” (Reid, 2006 p. x).

Although it is true that “little is actually done with Foucault’s work on power” (original

emphasis) (Kendall and Wickham, 1999 p. 49), recently there has been a resurgence of interest in

it, especially in Foucault’s theorising on biopower and biopolitics as presented in his The History

of Sexuality, Society Must Be Defended, Security, Territory, Population and The Birth of

Biopolitics. There have been attempts to use his perspective in approaching various IR concerns4.

In The History of Sexuality Foucault argues that, since the classical age, power has undergone a

profound transformation where “the right to take life or let live” was replaced by the right “to

foster life or disallow it to the point of death” (Foucault, 1990 p. 138). In other words, the

sovereign power, capable of inflicting death, was replaced by a new power, taking care over life,

with death turning into its limit. In Society Must Be Defended Foucault make an important

clarification that it is not that “sovereignty’s old right – to take life or let live – was replaced, but

it came to be complemented by a new right which does not erase the old right but which does

penetrate it, permeate it. (…) It is the power to ‘make’ live and ‘let’ die” (Foucault, 2003 p. 241).

In The History of Sexuality Foucault suggests that from the 17th century onwards, this new power

evolved in two basic forms: discipline centred on the individual body as a machine, associated

with the emergence of such institutions as medicine, education, and punishment; and control,

focused on the population (birth and mortality, level of health, life expectancy and longevity, 4 For instance, security (Campbell, 2007); security, liberal and network wars (Dillon, 2002; Dillon and Reid, 2001); war on terror (Reid, 2005 and 2006; Dauphinee and Masters, 2007); security and development (Duffield, 2005 onwards); postcolonial transitions (Sylvester, 2006); the AIDS pandemic (Elbe, 2005); human rights (Orford, 2007); genocide (Savage, 2007); refugees, asylum seekers, visa regimes and borders management (Muller, 2004; Ajana, 2005; Salter, 2006; Isin and Rygiel, 2007).

6

Page 7: Piotukh Paper

etc.). In Society Must Be Defended he clarifies that the second of these forms emerged in the

second half of the 18th century, and, “unlike discipline, which is addressed to bodies, the new

nondisciplinary power is applied (…) to man-as-living-being; [and] ultimately, (…) to man-as-

species” (Foucault, 2003 p. 242). Unlike discipline, which is individualising, this power is

massifying, it is concerned with human-as-species, so, following the establishment of an

anatomo-politics of the human body, a ‘biopolitics’ of the human race was established (Foucault,

2003 p. 243). Thus, the politics of the state, exercising power over living being as living beings,

becomes biopolitics. The concept of the population is key to understanding this new technology

of power, as “[b]iopolitics deals with the population, with the population as a political problem,

as a problem that is at once scientific and political, as a biological problem and as power’s

problem” (Foucault, 2003 p. 245).

Biopolitics as a technology of power introduces and relies on mechanism different from

disciplinary ones; its mechanisms include forecasts, statistical estimates and alike. They are not

aimed at modifying events or individuals, but rather at establishing equilibrium, maintaining an

average and compensating for variations at the level of population. Crucially, then, “security

mechanisms have to be installed around the random element inherent in a population of living

beings so as to optimize a state of life” (Foucault, 2003 p. 246). Importantly, unlike discipline,

security is “centrifugal, it widens and continuously integrates new elements” (Lazzarato, 2006),

and while “discipline wants to produce order, (…) security wants to guide disorder” (Foucault

quoted in Agamben, 2002). It is thanks to this legacy that the modern state has security as “its

only task and source of legitimacy”, and it does not take much effort to realise that such a state is

“a fragile organism” as “it can always be provoked by terrorism to turn itself terroristic”

(Agamben, 2002).

Foucault then poses a question: given that the basic function of the new power “to improve life,

to prolong its duration, to improve its chances, to avoid accidents, and to compensate for

failings”, how can a power like that kill? (Foucault, 2003 p. 254). This question exposes a

paradox of biopolitics, which has to do with the fact that the care of life can become the

administration of death (Enoch, 2004 p. 54), or that “the reverse side of biopolitics is

thanatopolitics” (Foucault, 2000 p. 416).

7

Page 8: Piotukh Paper

Foucault addresses this question by turning to the concept of racism. For him, it is the emergence

of biopower that inscribes racism in the mechanisms of state. Racism in this context is

understood as “a way of introducing a break into the domain of life that is under power’s control:

the break between what must live and what must die” (Foucault, 2003 p. 254). It is, in essence, a

way of “separating out the groups that exist within a population” (Foucault, 2003 p. 255).

Another important function of racism is the establishment of a positive relation of the type: “The

very fact that you let more die will allow you to live more”. While it is a familiar relationship of

war: “In order to live, you must destroy your enemies”, Foucault argues that it functions in a new

way. He explains: “The fact that the other dies does not mean simply that I live in the sense that

his death guarantees my safety; the death of the other, the death of the bad race, of the inferior

race (…) is something that will make life in general healthier (…) and purer” (Foucault, 2003 p.

255). Therefore, it is not a military, but a biological relationship. In this kind of relationship the

enemies who need to be eliminated are threats, either external or internal, to the population; and

racism is the precondition for exercising the right to kill (Foucault, 2003 p. 256). ‘Killing’ in this

context does not have to be limited to murder as such, it can be anything from exposing someone

to death to political death, expulsion and so on. Finally, as “[r]acism is bound up with the

workings of a State that is obliged to use race, the elimination of races and the purification of the

race, to exercise its sovereign power”, “the most murderous States are also, of necessity, the most

racist” (Foucault, 2003 p. 258).

Agamben

Agamben has further developed Foucault’s theorising on biopower. However, unlike Foucault,

who apparently treated sovereign power and biopower as more or less separate, Agamben

considers them to be parts of the same power. His analysis, he argues, is focused on the point of

intersection between the two (Agamben, 1998 p. 6). He also uses Schmitt’s account of

sovereignty (i.e. as capable of deciding on the exception), and Benjamin’s concept of ‘mere life’

(i.e. as life that is a product of violence exerted by the law), to come up with his concept of Homo

Sacer, someone who cannot be sacrificed, but can be killed, while his killing will not constitute a

homicide. The status of Homo Sacer is defined by being excluded from both the divine and from

the human, thus being included into the sovereign sphere of indistinction between sacrifice and

homicide: “The sovereign sphere is the sphere in which it is permitted to kill without committing

homicide and without celebrating a sacrifice, and sacred life – that is, life that may be killed but

not sacrificed – is the life that has been captured in this sphere” (Agamben, 1998 p. 83).

8

Page 9: Piotukh Paper

For Agamben, Homo Sacer is a biopolitical body that serves both as a result of, and a source of,

sovereign power. In other words, Homo Sacer represents life in between natural life and political

life. It exists in the sovereign sphere, a sphere of indistinction between outside and inside, a

sphere of exception created by the sovereign rule that applies to it only by no longer applying,

abandoning it. What is therefore crucial for Homo Sacer is that “regardless of whether it lives a

life of happiness or misery, [it] is defined by its dependence upon sovereign power for its status”,

which itself “emerges by capturing life in the exception” (Caldwell, 2004).

Agamben also proclaimed that it is ‘the camp’ that represents “the fundamental biopolitical

paradigm of the West” (Agamben, 1998 p. 181). The camp is created in a state of exception.

Since the distinction between the rule and the exception is blurred, “[t]he camp is the space that is

opened when the state of exception begins to become a rule” (Agamben, 1998 p. 169). The camp

as a space of indistinction serves as an embodiment of the sovereign sphere where the biopolitical

body, Homo Sacer, is trapped. In this space, set outside the law, a new law is adopted which

legitimises extreme forms of violence. It is in the camp that life can be kept at the threshold of

death.

GWOT as a biopolitical enterprise

As we have seen, for Foucault it is the race war discourse that brings together sovereign and

biopower, as it allows the state, whose primary concern is to make live, to retain its right to kill.

As Mutimer explains,

The population must be made to live, and, precisely because of that, it must be defended against the biological enemies that threaten it. It is because of the importance of this defense to the very possibility of biopolitics that the sovereign can still order people to their death to provide for that defense (Mutimer, 2007 pp. 168-169).

Mutimer also suggests that GWOT, just as the Cold War before it, represents an expression of the

race war discourse. What makes him come to this conclusion? First of all, he points out to the

fact that as the race war discourse reconciles the central contradiction of the biopolitical state, it

also depends on the unending nature of the war, because the war cannot be won for the

9

Page 10: Piotukh Paper

contradiction to remain unexposed. We know that an important feature of the way GWOT is

envisaged is its potentially permanent nature, as the danger is both out there and in here, and only

the state can defend the society against it. At the same time, I would suggest, for GWOT it is also

true that “Wars are no longer waged in the name of a sovereign who must be defended; they are

waged on behalf of the existence of everyone; entire populations are mobilised for the purpose of

wholesale slaughter in the name of necessity”(Foucault, 1990 p. 137). The following quote could

be used to illustrate the point.

“[O]ur security will require all Americans to be forward-looking and resolute, to be ready for preemptive action when necessary to defend our liberty and to defend our lives” (Bush, 2002 quoted in Weber, 2007 p. 116).

GWOT is also cast in oppositional, binary “either with us or against us” terms, which allows no

middle ground and no solution other then the eradication of those “against us”. As we have seen,

Foucault does consider this opposition. Secondly, Mutimer argues that the terrorist enemy is the

one who will not give up or cannot be beaten, and therefore represents a permanent threat. This

nature of the threat allows for the constant expansion of the more-intrusive security measures in

the name of defending society.

Finally, within GWOT the enemy is extensively racialised, of course, not explicitly in the Nazi

sense, but rather in a sense of appearance. In other words, anyone who looks like the race enemy

represents a potential threat. Consequently, many members of the society that the state is

supposed to defend are rendered less and less secure by its very practices of security. Mutimer

quotes Beck who argues that,

[Under these conditions] the citizen must prove that he or she is not dangerous, for under these conditions each individual finally comes under the suspicion of being a potential terrorist. Each person must thereby put up with submitting to random ‘security’ controls (Beck quoted in Mutimer, 2006 p. 173; original emphasis).

I would suggest that theorising on biopower and biopolitics can provide useful insights not only

at the macro, but also at the micro level, as particular practices can also be ‘read’ biopolitically,

including what euphemistically was termed ‘detention and interrogation techniques’ in

Guantanamo and Abu Ghraib. I believe that what matters most for such a reading is not the

torture as such, or the persistent denial of such facts by the U.S. Administration, or the hypocrisy

10

Page 11: Piotukh Paper

of its rhetoric stressing the full respect for human rights and fundamental freedoms, or even the

double-standards inherent in accusing other countries of resorting to torture and similar practices,

but the fact that torture has become legitimised and even subject to regulation.

Referring to Foucault’s concept of biopower as a power that fosters life or disallows it to the

point of death, Wadiwel suggests that it “can (…) capture and subject life, for an indefinite

duration, to a measured violence (…) In this violence – a frictional violence – the sovereign

reveals a commitment to life, a life whose time is measured by pain” (Wadiwel, 2003 p. 124).

Torture, therefore, can be considered as an ugly form of life preservation. A torturer has to

maintain life, to not let death prevent the continued infliction of pain, which can become life long

(Wadiwel, 2003 p. 117). Thus, the Nazi ‘Protective Custody’ directive of October 26, 1939

contained the following condition: (..) the duration of detention in a concentration camp must

always be indicated as ‘indefinite’” (Wadiwel, 2003 p. 124). The detainees of detention camps

scattered all over the world, share the same fate, as they have been promised release only upon

cessation of GWOT, which, as we know, is a war with imprecise objectives, and no definite end.

This indefinite detention itself becomes a form of torture.

Agamben’s theorising can also provide useful insights. For example, the tortured were those

categorised as ‘unlawful’ or ‘enemy’ combatants – terms unknown in international law. These

definitions allowed the U.S. Administration to deprive these people of the protection provided by

either IHL or human rights law. Moreover, they could not appeal to the U.S. national courts as,

given the location of the camps, the courts would not have jurisdiction to consider appeals of

foreigners captured and held abroad. Thus, these people were turned into Homo Sacer, stripped of

anything that could stand between them and the torturer as a personification of bio-power, caught

in the state of exception where law does not apply in any other way than by no longer applying.

Anything becomes possible, including the decisions that practices that ‘only’ amount to cruel,

inhuman or degrading can be tolerated, anything up to the point when “tortured are finally left

with nothing but their own living being, felt only through an endless suffering” (Wadiwel, 2003

p. 120).

Conclusion: Humanitarian action and GWOT: a new biopolitical nexus

11

Page 12: Piotukh Paper

Humanitarian action, both normative and material, has its roots in several traditions, one of the

most important of which is assistance to and protection of war victims. Since the 19 th century

when the first Geneva conventions were negotiated and the Red Cross established, till the present

day humanitarianism has had a very special relationship with war and violence. As Hoffman and

Weiss put it,

War and humanitarianism may have distinct logics and values, but historically they are intimately linked. Swords trigger humanitarian crises and responses; violent conflicts cause casualties and displace people, which require salves. [In its turn,] [h]umanitarian action (…) alters how wars are fought and affects their outcomes. It is impossible to draw exact, let alone, causal relations between war and humanitarianism, but each has clear consequences for the other (Hoffman and Weiss, 2006 p. 10).

According to Slim, from its inception the humanitarian project has been one that “legitimates

violence by mitigating it”, but only with respect to the way the wars are fought (jus in bello)

(Slim, 2001 p. 327). However, with the new interventionism of the 1990s humanitarianism has

been also used as a justification for wars (jus ad bellum). It is worth pointing out in this respect

that even though neither the intervention in Afghanistan in 2001, nor in Iraq in 2003 were

presented as humanitarian per se, humanitarian considerations featured prominently during both

campaigns (for instance, Macrae and Harmer, 2003 p. 7; Rieff, 2002 with respect to the

intervention in Afghanistan; for a more detailed account see Breau, 2005 pp. 149-177).

What I would argue is that with GWOT a new biopolitical nexus of war and humanitarianism has

been established. Within this nexus the latter’s role has been transformed further from mitigating

violence to facilitating and justifying it. After all, within a series of military and other campaigns

waged in the name of defending some societies against others, which is what GWOT is all about,

humanitarian rhetoric features prominently and humanitarians themselves are treated as a force-

multiplier, a part of the combat team. This transformation, although not all-encompassing and

clearly incomplete, cannot be easily reversed, if ever, and it is probably more damaging to the

humanitarian enterprise than it has been recognised so far.

It should be noted that the above deliberations represent only preliminary thoughts, and are

designed to encourage discussion with a view to their further development.

References

12

Page 13: Piotukh Paper

1. Agamben, G. 1998. Homo Sacer: sovereign power and bare life. Stanford: Stanford

University Press.

2. Agamben, G. 2002. Security and terror. Theory and Event, 5(4) [online]. [Accessed 1 January

2006]. Available from World Wide Web:

<http://muse.jhu.edu/cgi-bin/access.cgi?uri=/journals/theory_and_event/

v005/5.4agamben.html>.

3. Ajana, B. 2005. Surveillance and biopolitics. Electronic Journal of Sociology [online].

[Accessed 1 January 2006]. Available from World Wide Web:

<www.sociology.org/content/2005/tier1/ajana_biopolitics.pdf>.

4. Beyani, C. 2003. International law and the ‘war on terror’. In: J. Macrae and A. Harmer,

(eds.). Humanitarian action and the ‘global war on terror’: a review of trends and issues.

HPG Report 14. London: Overseas Development Institute, pp. 13-24.

5. Borton, J. 1998. The state of the international humanitarian system. Refugee Survey

Quarterly, 17(1), pp.16-23.

6. Caldwell, A. 2004. Bio-sovereignty and the emergence of humanity. Theory and Event,

[online]. 7(2), [Accessed 1 January 2006]. Available from World Wide Web:

<http://muse.jhu.edu/cgi-bin/access.cgi?uri=/journals/theory_and_event/

v007/7.2caldwell.html>

7. Campbell, D. 2007. The biopolitics of security: oil, empire, and the sports utility vehicle. In:

E. Dauphinee and C. Masters, (eds.). The logic of biopower and the war on terror: living,

dying, surviving. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 129-156.

8. Dauphinee, E. and C. Masters, (eds.). The logic of biopower and the war on terror: living,

dying, surviving. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

9. De Torrente, N. 2004. Humanitarian action under attack: reflections on the Iraq War. Harvard

Human Rights Journal, 17, pp.1-29.

10. Development Initiatives. 2006. Global humanitarian assistance 2006 [online]. [Accessed 20

February 2008]. Available from World Wide Web:

<http://www.globalhumanitarianassistance.org/gha2006.htm>.

11. Dillon, M. 2002. Network society, network-centric warfare and the state of emergency.

Theory, Culture and Society, 19(4), pp. 71-79.

12. Dillon, M. and J. Reid. 2001. Global liberal governance: biopolitics, security and war.

Millennium, 30(1), pp. 41-66.

13

Page 14: Piotukh Paper

13. Donini, A. 2004. Taking sides: the Iraq crisis and the future of humanitarianism. Forced

Migration Review, 19, pp. 38-40.

14. Donini, A., L. Minear, et al. 2006. Humanitarian agenda 2015: principles, power, and

perceptions. Preliminary Report. Tufts University: Feinstein International Centre.

15. Donini, A., L. Minear and P. Walker. 2004. Between Cooptation and Irrelevance:

Humanitarian Action after Iraq. Journal of Refugee Studies, 17(3), pp. 260-272.

16. Dubernet, C. 2001. The international containment of displaced persons: humanitarian spaces

without exit. Aldershot: Ashgate.

17. Duffield, M. 1997. Humanitarian intervention, the new aid paradigm and separate

development. New Political Economy, 2(2), pp.336-340.

18. Duffield, M. 2005a. Getting savages to fight barbarians: development, security and the

colonial present. Conflict, Security and Development, 5(2), pp.141-160.

19. Duffield, M. 2005b. Governing the borderlands: decoding the power of aid. In: R. Wilkinson,

(ed.). The global governance reader. Oxford: Routledge, pp. 204-216.

20. Duffield, M. 2006. Racism, migration and development: the foundations of planetary order.

Progress in Development Studies, 6(1), pp. 68-79.

21. Duffield, M. and N. Waddell. 2006. Securing humans in a dangerous world. International

Politics, 43, pp. 1-23.

22. Elbe, S. 2005. AIDS, security biopolitics. International Relations, 19(4), pp. 403-419.

23. Enoch, S. 2004. The contagion of difference: identity, bio-politics and National Socialism.

Foucault Studies, 1, pp. 53-70.

24. Foucault, M. 1990. The history of sexuality. Volume 1: The will to knowledge.

Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

25. Foucault, M. 2003. Society must be defended: Lectures at the College de France, 1975-76.

London: Penguin Books.

26. Foucault, M. 2007. Security, territory, population: Lectures at the College de France, 1977-

78. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

27. Foucault, M. 2008. The birth of biopolitics: Lectures at the College de France, 1978-1979.

Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

28. Hoffman, P.J and T.G. Weiss. 2006. Sword and salve: new wars and humanitarians crises.

Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield.

14

Page 15: Piotukh Paper

29. Isin, E.F. and K. Rygiel. 2007. Abject spaces: frontiers, zones, camps. In: E. Dauphinee and

C. Masters, (eds.). The logic of biopower and the war on terror: living, dying, surviving.

Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 181-203.

30. Jackson, R. 2005. Writing the war on terrorism: language, politics and counter-terrorism.

Manchester: Manchester University Press.

31. Kendall, G. and G. Wickham. 1999. Using Foucault’s methods. London: Sage.

32. Lazzarato, M. 2006. Biopolitics/bioeconomics: a politics of multiplicity [online]. [Accessed

14 May 2008]. Available from World Wide Web:

<http://www.generation-online.org/p/fplazzarato2.htm>.

33. Macrae, J., (ed.). 2002. The new humanitarianisms: a review of trends in global humanitarian

action. HPG Report 11. London: Overseas Development Institute.

34. Macrae, J. and A. Harmer. 2003. Humanitarian action and the ‘war on terror’: a review of

issues. In: J. Macrae and A. Harmer, (eds.). Humanitarian action and the ‘global war on

terror’: a review of trends and issues. HPG Report 14. London: Overseas Development

Institute pp. 1-11.

35. Minear, L. 2002. The humanitarian enterprise: dilemmas and discoveries. Bloomfield:

Kumarian.

36. Muller, B. 2004. Globalization, security, paradox: towards a refugee biopolitics. Refuge:

Canada's Periodical on Refugees, 22(1), pp. 49-57.

37. Mutimer, D. 2007. Sovereign contradictions: Maher Arar and the indefinite future. In:

Dauphinee, E. and C. Masters, (eds.). The logic of biopower and the war on terror: living,

dying, surviving. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 159-179.

38. Orford, A. 2007. Biopolitics and the tragic subject of human rights. In: E. Dauphinee and C.

Masters, (eds.). The logic of biopower and the war on terror: living, dying, surviving.

Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 205-228.

39. Reid, J. 2005. The biopolitics of the war on terror: a critique of the ‘return of imperialism’

thesis in international relations. Third World Quarterly, 26(2), pp.237-252.

40. Reid, J. 2006. The biopolitics of the war on terror: life struggles, liberal modernity, and the

defence of logistical societies. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

41. Rieff, D. 2002. A bed for the night: humanitarianism in crisis. London: Vintage.

42. Salter, M.B. 2006. The global visa regime and the political technologies of the international

self: borders, bodies, biopolitics. Alternatives, 31(2), pp. 167-189.

15

Page 16: Piotukh Paper

43. Savage, R. 2007. “Disease incarnate”: biopolitical discourse and genocidal dehumanisation in

the age of modernity. Journal of Historical Sociology, 20(3), pp. 404-440.

44. Slim, H. 2001. Violence and humanitarianism: moral paradox and the protection of civilians.

Security Dialogue, 32(3), pp.325-339.

45. Smillie, I. and L. Minear. 2004. The charity of nations: humanitarian action in a calculating

world. Bloomfield: Kumarian.

46. Sylvester, C. 2006. Bare life as a development/postcolonial problematic. The Geographical

Journal, 172(1), pp. 66-77.

47. The Feinstein International Famine Center. 2004. Ambiguity and change: humanitarian

NGOs prepare for the future [online]. [Accessed 8 December 2007]. Available from World

Wide Web:

<http://nutrition.tufts.edu/docs/pdf/famine/ambiguity_and_change.pdf>.

48. The Henry Dunant Centre for Humanitarian Dialogue. 2003. Politics and humanitarianism:

coherence in crisis? [online]. [Accessed 10 December 2007]. Available from World Wide

Web: <http://www.hdcentre.org/publications?page=15>.

49. Vaux, T. 2006. Humanitarian trends and dilemmas. Development in Practice, 16(3), pp.240-

254.

50. Wadiwel, D.J. 2003. The sovereign whip: flogging, biopolitics and the frictional community.

Voicing Dissent: New Talents 21C, Journal of Australian Studies, 76, pp. 117-125.

51. Weber, C. 2007. Securitizing the unconscious: the Bush doctrine of preemption and Minority

Report. In: Dauphinee, E. and C. Masters, (eds.). The logic of biopower and the war on

terror: living, dying, surviving. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 109-129.

16