Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    1/17

    A Note on Zeno's ArrowAuthor(s): Gregory VlastosSource: Phronesis, Vol. 11, No. 1 (1966), pp. 3-18Published by: BRILLStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4181773.

    Accessed: 15/08/2013 19:30

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    BRILLis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Phronesis.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=baphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4181773?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4181773?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=bap
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    2/17

    A note nZeno'sArrow.

    GREGORY VLASTOS

    [1]

    For if,

    he

    says,

    [a]

    everything

    is

    always

    at rest when it is at a place equal

    to itself

    (6r=v

    1f

    xa'r&

    r

    aov),2

    [b]

    and the moving object

    is always [sc. at a place equal

    to

    itself]3

    in the

    "now"

    (Iatv 8' acxE o

    yep6F,evov

    &v r7 v5v), then the

    arrow in motion

    is mo-

    tionless. (Aristotle,

    Phys.

    239B5-7;

    for the text see Ross 657-58).

    1

    I

    shall

    deal only

    with the main

    topics, and with these

    far from exhaustively.

    For

    more

    thorough treatments of

    the subject

    the reader may consult

    works

    listed

    in the bibliography at the

    end

    of this article

    (to

    which

    reference

    is made

    in

    text and notes by the name

    of

    author

    only).

    For

    more extensive references to

    the

    scholarly literature

    see M. Untersteiner,

    142 ff.

    Readers who may

    be familiar

    with the account of the Arrow in the chapter on Zeno I contributed to Philosophic

    Classics, Vol. I, edited

    by

    W. Kaufmann

    (Englewood

    Cliffs, N.J.,

    1961),

    27ff.

    at

    40-41,

    are

    hereby

    advised that the present

    Note is meant to supersede

    it

    completely.

    That chapter

    had been prepared

    on short

    notice to fill an

    urgent

    pedagogical

    need

    and,

    as

    I

    explained at

    the time (27,

    n. 1), presented

    "purely

    provisional

    results of work-in-progress."

    The

    present

    Note incorporates

    results

    I

    have

    reached in a more

    thorough

    study of the Arrow

    made possible by

    a grant

    for research on Zeno from the

    National Science Foundation,

    to which

    I

    wish to

    express

    my

    thanks.

    2

    I follow

    the

    usual translation of

    this peculiar

    phrase (cf.

    e.g. Burnet,

    "when

    it

    occupies a space

    equal

    to itself.") I assume

    that

    if Zeno had used

    this ex-

    pression, his expansion of it would have been xawr Tov laov kaotcu 'r6nov,

    since

    r6noq

    would have been the only

    word

    he is

    likely

    to have

    used

    in

    this

    connection: cf. '67rov

    &XXicramv

    n

    Parmenides,

    frag. 8,

    41 (Diels-Kranz).

    However,

    Zeno is more

    likely to have written

    &v

    cp

    law

    kavr&

    'r6nc

    for the

    context

    suggests strongly

    that the construction

    with

    xawr&

    s Aristotelian.

    Aristotle

    starts

    talking of a

    mobile being xaoX tL as

    far back

    as

    239A25,

    using

    the

    phrase

    again at 30,

    34,

    35 and (twice) at 239B3.

    Uninterested

    in

    conserving

    the mention of

    'r670oq

    n his summary of the puzzle

    (t67roq

    plays

    no role

    in

    the

    analysis

    of

    its

    reasoning presupposed

    by

    his

    refutation),

    it would be

    natural

    for

    him

    to change

    &v

    T' rfa kmuvr

    nto xxra. 'r taov

    in

    conformity

    with his 6 uses

    of

    xacrci

    t

    in

    the

    preceding

    15

    lines.

    3

    For the expansion cf. the commentators (Simplicius, Philoponus, Themistius:

    Lee

    #

    30 to

    #

    34. Lee

    puts the expansion

    into the

    text (he writes:

    &v

    rij

    vUV

    xm'd&

    r6

    taov),

    but on

    frail MS.

    authority.

    3

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    3/17

    [2]

    Zeno

    argues

    thus:

    [a]

    A

    moving thing

    moves either

    [A]

    in the place

    in which it is or

    [B] in

    the

    place

    in which

    it is not.

    [b] But

    it moves

    neither [A]

    in

    the

    place

    in which

    it is,

    nor [B] in the

    place

    in

    which it is

    not.

    Therefore,

    nothing

    moves. (Epiphanius,

    Adv.

    Haer. 3,

    11; H. Diels, Doxo-

    graphi

    Graeci, 590).

    brieferversion

    of [2],' practically

    dentical

    with its part

    [b],

    is

    ascribed

    to

    Zeno

    by Diogenes

    Laertius

    (Vitae

    Philos. 9,

    72) in a

    passage in which he appears to be following a good source: all

    citations

    in 71-73

    are

    reliable

    and most

    of them are

    letter-perfect.

    Of

    the two versions

    this

    is the one

    likely

    to be the closer

    to the

    original:

    the longer

    one in

    Epiphanius

    ooks like

    an expansion

    of

    this one

    to

    make

    it

    "compl[y]

    with the

    rules and

    conventions

    of

    post-Aristotelian

    syllogisms"

    (Frankel

    7).

    In

    any

    case,

    the ascription

    of

    [2b]

    to Zeno

    has

    the backing

    of both

    Diogenes

    and

    Epiphanius,

    and

    I know of no

    good

    reason to

    doubt

    it. It

    is true that

    Sextus,

    reporting

    on three

    separate

    occasions (Pyrrh.

    Hyp.

    2,

    245 and

    3,

    71;

    Adv. Math.

    10,

    86-89)

    the

    use of [2] (with variations) by Diodorus Cronus,& ever mentions its

    Zenonian

    authorship.

    But

    neither does

    he

    say

    that

    Diodorus was its

    originator;

    he seems

    to

    imply

    the

    very

    opposite,

    as

    Frankel (7,

    n.

    20)

    has

    observed, by

    introducing

    the argument

    in one

    passage

    with the

    remark

    that

    Diodorus '6v

    7rpLpopij'nx6v uvep'rq

    X6oyov

    sr s'r

    '

    xtveLaOoE

    C(A

    dv. Math.

    10,

    87;

    cf.

    Frankel

    7,

    n.

    20).6

    Sextus' failure

    to cite Diodorus

    as the inventor

    of this

    argument

    could hardly

    count

    against

    its

    authenticity:

    he

    is as silent

    concerning

    the

    authorship

    of

    the

    other

    argument

    whose

    use

    by

    Diodorus

    he

    reports

    in the

    same

    connection7- that if time consists of indivisibles "has moved" will be

    true of things

    of which "is

    moving"

    was never

    true - which

    we know

    as

    one

    of

    Aristotle's

    cleverest

    and most characteristic

    creations (Phys.

    231

    B

    20ff.).

    4

    Printed

    as frag.

    4 in

    Diels-Kranz,

    with

    no defense of

    the editorial

    decision.

    5

    Also

    in Pyrrh.

    Hyp.

    2, 242,

    without

    ascription

    to Diodorus

    or to

    anyone

    else.

    S

    Just

    before,

    at 86,

    Sextus

    had given

    a fuller

    account

    of the reasoning

    by

    which

    Diodorus

    had

    supported

    [2bA]

    and [2bB].

    It would

    be hard to believe

    that,

    when

    he goes

    on to

    cite

    the

    whole of [2]

    in the next paragraph,

    he

    should

    refer

    to it in the above terms (note specially the force of auvepc.r), if he had thought

    of

    [2] as

    a Diodorean

    invention.

    7

    Adv.

    Math. 10,

    48 and

    85; it

    is connected closely

    with

    [2b]

    in

    the

    latter

    passage.

    4

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    4/17

    Once

    we decide that on the evidence

    [2b]

    was

    Zeno's

    (the

    sense,

    if

    not the exact wording), we should face the question: Could it really

    have

    been

    a

    self-contained

    composition, independent

    of

    [1],

    as

    the

    editors have

    generally

    assumed?

    Suppose

    it were.

    What

    would

    we

    then make of Aristotle's remark that "there are four

    arguments

    by

    Zeno that give trouble to those who

    try

    to refute them"

    (239B

    9-11)?

    On the

    hypothesis, [2b]

    would have been a fifth.

    Why

    then

    did

    Aristotle

    ignore

    it? Because he

    thought

    it a

    silly

    puzzle,

    not

    worth

    solving,

    or too

    easily

    solved? This would

    be hard to

    square

    with

    the

    fact

    that

    Diodorus,

    connoisseur of fine

    arguments,

    thought

    so well of

    it.

    Nor is it likely on aesthetic grounds that a construction trenching so

    closely

    on the Arrowshould

    have

    appeared

    n Zeno's book as a

    separate

    puzzle.

    And there is a

    third,

    still

    stronger,

    reason for

    rejecting

    the

    hypothesis:

    As

    [2b]

    now stands it makes

    at

    [A]

    a

    challenging

    claim

    -

    that a

    thing

    cannot move

    'V

    4)

    ar.L

    rO'6rca without

    putting

    up

    the

    slightest

    defense for it.

    To realize how

    badly

    it

    does need

    defense

    one

    need

    only

    recall that it

    would

    be

    quite

    consistent with

    general

    usage

    in

    Zeno's time

    (and

    for a

    long

    time

    after)

    to

    think

    of the

    r64os

    n

    which

    a

    thing

    is as the room or

    region

    within which

    it stands or

    moves

    -

    i.e.,

    as its locale, rather than its precise location.8 Hence to be told out of

    the blue that

    a

    thing

    cannot

    move

    "in

    the

    place

    in

    which it is"

    would

    only provoke

    the

    retort,

    'And

    why

    not?

    Why

    cannot the

    dog move in

    the

    kennel,

    the

    man

    in

    the

    courtyard,

    the

    ship

    in

    the

    bay?'

    If

    we

    take

    another look at

    [1 a]

    with

    this

    in

    mind,

    its

    aptness

    as an answer

    to

    just

    this

    objection leaps

    to the

    eye:

    Its

    strategy

    is to cut down the

    thing's

    "place" to

    a

    space

    fitting

    so

    tightly

    the

    thing's

    own

    dimensions (just

    "equal"

    to

    its

    own

    bulk)

    as to leave

    it

    no

    room

    in

    which

    to move.

    Thus

    [

    a]

    locks

    neatly

    into

    [2bA]

    in

    point

    of

    logic,

    while

    if

    it belonged

    to a separateargumentwe would have to supposethat Zeno had built

    into the

    original

    of

    [2]

    some other

    backing

    for

    [2bA]

    -

    and what

    would

    that be? In

    three

    of the

    passagesg

    n which

    [2]

    turns

    up

    in

    Sextus the

    backing

    for it

    is

    just,

    "for

    if it is

    in it

    [sc.

    the

    place

    in

    which it

    is], it

    rests there." This would be

    very lame

    -

    a

    patent

    begging

    of the

    question

    -

    unless

    here

    again

    the

    equivalent

    of

    [

    a] were

    being pre-

    supposed.

    And

    that this is in

    fact the

    case

    appears from

    a fourth

    passage

    in

    Sextus

    (A

    dv.

    Math.

    10, 86),

    where

    the

    equivalent

    of [la]

    8 Many

    examples of the wider

    usage

    in

    Liddell

    &

    Scott, s.v.

    r67rog.

    9

    Pyrrh. Hyp. 3, 71 and Adv. Math. 10, 87; also in Pyrrh. Hyp. 2, 242 (cf. n. 4

    above);

    but not in

    Pyrrh.

    Hyp. 2, 245,

    where the

    argument

    is tailored to fit the

    joke.

    5

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    5/17

    is

    given

    as

    Diodorus'

    reason for

    [2bA]:

    "and

    that is

    why

    [the

    body]

    moves neither in it [i.e. the place which containsit]

    -

    for it fills this up,

    while

    it needs

    a

    largerplace

    in

    which

    to

    move -, nor

    etc."

    The

    fact

    that

    the

    cited

    argument

    is

    loaded

    with

    the

    special

    assumptions

    of

    Diodorean

    physics (the

    body

    is

    an

    indivisible

    which,

    if

    it

    could

    move,

    would

    have

    to

    move

    through

    a

    space

    composed

    of

    indivisibles)

    in

    no

    way

    affects

    the point

    at

    issue,

    i.e.

    that

    Diodorus

    too,

    when

    filling

    out

    the

    argument

    in

    [2bA] to

    make

    it

    fully

    convincing,

    resorted

    to

    precisely

    the

    same

    reasoning

    as

    is

    provided,

    more

    tersely,

    at

    [1a]

    in

    the

    Aristotelian

    sum-

    mary

    of the Arrow.This

    being

    the

    case,

    and

    taking

    also

    into

    account

    the

    first two reasons above against the hypothesis that [la] and [2bA]

    belonged

    to

    separate

    puzzles,

    we

    have

    good

    warrant for

    rejecting

    it

    in

    favor of the

    assumption

    -

    on

    which

    the

    rest of this

    Note

    will

    proceed

    -

    that both

    [1 a]

    and

    [2

    b]

    belonged

    to

    the

    Zenonian

    original

    of

    the

    Arrow.

    Their

    subsequent

    separation

    in

    Diogenes

    Laertius

    and

    Epiphanius

    (or

    their

    sources)

    could

    be

    accounted

    for

    easily:

    in

    the

    former,

    a

    truncated

    version

    of the Zenonian

    original;

    in

    the

    latter

    an

    expansion

    of that

    fragment.

    Nor

    would

    it

    be

    hard

    to

    account,

    on

    the same

    assumption,

    for

    Aristotle's quite differentversionof the Arrow.We need only suppose

    that

    he

    recognized

    n

    [1a]

    and

    [1 b]

    the

    significant

    part

    of

    the

    argument,

    and

    scornfully

    ignored

    the rest:

    witness

    his

    drastic

    abbreviation

    of

    the

    Race

    Course

    n

    the

    same

    passage (239

    B

    11-13).10

    That

    he

    should

    have

    kept

    [1 a]

    is

    understandable:

    on

    any

    reconstruction

    of

    the

    puzzle,

    this

    is

    the

    heart

    of

    its

    reasoning.

    As for

    [1

    b],

    all

    of

    this

    too

    might

    well

    have

    figured

    in

    the

    original

    as

    the

    sequel

    to

    [2bA] duly

    backed

    by [1

    a]

    (see the

    conjectural

    reconstitution

    of

    the

    argument

    below),

    except

    for

    its mention

    of

    the viv

    at

    the

    end.1' This is

    one

    of

    Aristotle's

    favorite

    technical terms. He used it commonly as a name for the durationless

    instant;12

    but

    occasionally,

    in

    controversial

    contexts,

    he

    also

    allowed

    o

    ?

    Cf. this with

    the

    considerably fuller,

    though

    still

    abbreviated,

    account

    of the

    same

    argument

    at

    263 A

    5-6.

    11

    Cf.

    Calogero 131-38.

    la How

    much

    of

    an Aristotelian innovation

    it is

    one

    can

    see

    by

    comparing

    Platonic

    usage.

    For

    Plato

    the

    "now" remains

    an

    interval; he

    uses 'z

    viv

    as short

    for 6

    v5v

    Xp6voq

    Parm.

    152

    B5).

    The

    closest he

    comes to

    Aristotle's

    instantaneous

    "now"

    is

    in

    something

    he

    calls the

    kocv(v "this

    queer

    thing situated

    between

    motion and rest, not itself in any time [Cornford, Comparing Nic. Eth. 1174B8,

    'it occupies no

    time

    at

    all,'

    i.e.

    has

    no

    temporal

    stretch], while to it and

    from

    it

    the

    moving changes

    to

    a state

    of

    rest

    and

    the

    resting

    to a

    state

    of

    motion"

    6

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    6/17

    himself to use it to denote the atomic

    quantum

    of

    duration, integral

    multiples of which would make up all larger temporal intervals, if

    time were

    discontinuous.13

    Since neither of these two

    uses of

    viv

    have

    any known

    precedent,'4

    t would be most unsafe

    to assume

    that

    Zeno

    had

    anticipated

    one

    of them

    acrossa

    gap

    of a

    hundred

    years

    or

    more.

    Its presence

    here is

    explicable

    as an

    Aristotelian

    plant: by

    sticking

    it

    into his account of the

    puzzle

    Aristotle makes it

    all

    the easier

    for his

    readers to feel the

    appositeness

    of his

    refutation,

    which centers in

    the

    claim that "it

    [Zeno's

    argument]

    assumes that time

    is

    composed of

    'nows':

    if

    this were not

    granted,

    the

    argument

    would not

    be

    valid."'5

    If it did not have this function, it is doubtful that Aristotle would

    have

    found a

    place for it in his

    ultra-compressedaccount

    of the

    puzzle,

    even

    if it had

    figured

    in the Zenonian

    original. How

    expendable

    it is

    becomes

    apparent

    in a

    number

    of

    the summaries of

    the argument

    in

    the Aristotelian

    commentators:

    though

    undoubtedly

    dependent on

    our

    present

    Aristotelian

    passage,

    they drop the

    "now", probably

    not even

    aware that

    they have done

    so,

    and

    certainly

    not

    expecting that

    their

    (Parm. 157 D6-E

    3). Thus

    Plato's

    k(aqtpsvr

    s a

    limit of

    temporal extension,

    itself

    extensionless,

    and one

    might wonder

    if

    this,

    in all

    but

    the

    name,

    is the

    Aristo-

    telian "now."

    But there are

    great

    differences: Plato does not

    explicate

    in

    rigorous

    terms the

    concept

    he has in

    mind,

    does not

    elucidate

    it as the

    temporal

    analogue

    of the

    geometrical

    point (so

    fundamental

    for

    Aristotle's analysis

    of the

    "now"

    Phys. 231 B

    6 ff.

    et

    passim), does not

    specify its formal

    properties

    (especially the

    crucial

    one, of

    non-consecutive

    succession, so

    clearly identified

    by Aristotle

    for the

    "now", 218

    A

    18

    et

    passim).

    Aristotle is at pains to

    distinguish

    his V5V

    from the

    &

    xEpvij,

    remarking (perhaps

    with

    implied

    opposition to Plato's

    use of

    the

    term)

    that the

    latter

    refers

    to what

    happens

    in

    an

    imperceptibly

    small

    [stretch of] time. Phys. 222B15. Cf. Owen 2, 101 ff.

    18

    For this

    second usage

    (united

    with the first

    by the fact

    that the

    durationless

    "now"

    is also

    indivisible,

    but never

    confused with it

    by

    Aristotle

    to

    my know-

    ledge) see e.g.

    the argument

    against the

    thesis that time

    and

    motion (no less than

    spatial

    extension) "are

    composed

    of

    indivisibles,"

    231B18ff.:

    at

    its conclusion

    he

    represents

    the refuted

    thesis as

    holding that time

    "is

    composed of

    'nows'

    which

    are indivisible"

    (232A19).

    14

    There is no hint of

    the

    latter

    in

    Plato

    (Parm. 152

    Aff.; 155 D)

    and

    certainly

    none of

    the former

    (cf. n. 12

    above).

    "I

    239B31-33; cf. B8-9. That "time is

    not

    composed of indivisible

    'nows"'

    (loc. cit.) is the

    very

    foundation of

    Aristotle's

    theory

    of

    the

    temporal

    continuum.

    He announces it (218A8) early in the second paragraph of his essay on time

    (Phys.

    IV,

    217B29ff.) and

    reintroduces

    it

    in

    the

    first chapter of

    Physics VI:

    cf. n.

    13

    above.

    7

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    7/17

    readers would

    miss it.16

    It becomes

    quite superfluous to the sense

    and to the force of the reasoning when [1 a] and [lb] (the latter with

    modifications) are spliced

    into

    [2b],

    with a transitional sentence

    added

    to smooth out the

    reasoning:

    The arrow could

    not move in the place in which it is not

    (= [2 b

    B]).17

    But neither could

    it move in the place in which it is (= [2bA]):

    For this is a place

    equal to itself [supplied];

    And

    everything

    is always at rest when

    it is in a place equal to itself

    (=

    [1 a]).

    But the flying arrow is always in the place

    in

    which it is

    ([1 b]

    with

    modifi-

    cations).

    Therefore,

    the flying arrow is always at

    rest.

    Pending

    a

    fuller,

    or better grounded,

    utilization of our textual

    data,

    it is

    reasonable

    to assume

    that

    some such

    argument

    was

    the

    origi-

    nal of the Arrow.18

    II

    Why

    should Zeno have thought [1 a]

    true? There are two

    possible

    answers, depending

    on

    how we read its "when"

    (Cf.

    Black

    128

    and

    144-46). Is Zeno saying

    (I) that everything

    is at rest

    for any temporal

    interval during

    which it is "at

    a

    place equal

    to

    itself",

    or

    (II)

    that

    everything

    is at rest

    for

    any (durationless)

    instant"I

    in which it is

    "at

    a

    place equal

    to itself" ?

    16

    Of the three summaries

    of

    the Arrow in Simplicius,

    the longer one

    (Phys. 1011,

    19ff.

    =

    Lee #

    31) includes the "nows",

    but the

    shorter ones

    (1015,

    19ff.

    =

    Lee # 30; 1034,

    4ff.

    =

    Lee

    # 32) do not. Philoponus

    (Phys. 816, 30ff.

    =

    Lee # 33) conserves the "now". Themistius does not in Phys. 199, 4ff. = Lee

    #

    34

    or in

    200,

    29ff.

    7

    It is entirely possible

    that a reason

    may have

    been given for this

    proposition,

    such

    as the one

    in the versions of

    [2]

    which Sextus

    ascribes

    to Diodorus

    in

    Pyrrh. Hyp.

    3, 71 and 3, 89: "for it can neither do nor

    suffer

    anything

    where it is

    not."

    IL

    A

    trivially

    different version, sticking

    more

    closely to Aristotle's

    [1 b]

    at the

    price

    of a slight roughness

    in

    the transition from

    [2 bA] to [1 a],

    would repeat

    the first two premises

    as above

    and then

    proceed

    as

    follows:

    For everything

    is always at rest

    when it is in

    a place equal to itself

    (-= [1 a]).

    And the flying arrow

    is always

    in a place equal to

    itself (= [I b]

    without

    I vu3v).

    Therefore, the

    flying arrow is always

    at rest.

    19

    Hereafter

    I shall always mean 'durationless

    instant'

    when I

    say

    'instant.'

    8

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    8/17

    Could (I)

    be the

    right

    reading?

    Its

    linguisticplausibility

    is

    so

    great

    that

    the second sense of

    6Tov

    might not even occur to one here,20 as it

    apparently

    did

    not to Aristotle: he seems

    to have taken it for granted

    that

    the

    68av

    in

    [la]

    would refer

    to a stretch of time.20a But there

    is

    a

    strong

    objection

    to this reading:

    it would

    require

    us to debit Zeno

    with

    a

    gratuitous

    fallacy.

    For

    only

    if we know

    that an

    object

    is in the

    same

    place for

    some

    stretch of

    time,

    would we be

    entitled

    to infer that it is

    at rest during

    that stretch. And

    that is

    just

    what we

    do

    not know

    in

    the

    case of the arrow.

    To all

    appearance

    t is never in the same place

    in

    the

    course

    of its

    flight during any

    sizeable

    period.

    Is

    there

    then

    any

    reason

    to think that it would be in the same place during smaller periods?

    On the

    face

    of

    it,

    none whatever: there

    is no more reason a

    priori

    why

    the flying

    arrow should

    be

    in the same

    place

    for a billionth of a second,

    than

    for a whole second. So if Zeno wanted us to believe the contrary,

    he would have to give

    us his

    reason. Otherwise,

    he would be begging

    the

    very question

    to be

    proved

    -

    that the arrow,moving

    by hypothesis,

    is in fact resting

    -

    and to beg

    it for smaller periods

    would not make

    the offense to

    logic

    the smaller.2'Now on

    the present reconstruction

    of

    20Cf. the behaviour of Liddell & Scott. Elucidating the "when, at the time

    when" sense of 6'e

    (&8av

    =

    6're

    &v),

    he

    authors say that

    it

    is

    used

    in the

    indicative

    with imperfect or

    aorist "to denote

    single events or actions in past time," with

    present

    "of a

    thing

    always happening

    or

    now going

    on,"

    etc.

    They

    make no

    provision here or subsequently in any

    of their statements

    or examples

    for

    sense

    (II) above, i.e.

    for

    the

    use

    of

    85e to refer not to an event or a

    period

    but to

    an

    instantaneous limit of an event or

    period, e.g. to the start or finish of a

    race.

    This rarer, but

    perfectly authentic,

    sense of

    6Te

    has evidently not occurred

    to

    the

    original

    authors or later

    editors of

    the dictionary.

    '0a

    I

    think we may

    infer

    from

    the context (239 B 1-4) that

    the "indivisible nows"

    which

    Aristotle

    believes (ibid. 8-9; 31-33) are being

    "assumed" by

    Zeno's

    argument are atomic stretches, not extensionless instants (i.e. that he is using

    the

    v5v

    in the

    second of

    the two senses in which he

    employs the term:

    cf. n.

    13

    above).

    For since

    he says that there

    is neither motion nor rest in a "now" in

    239B1-4,

    where

    he

    is

    using

    "now" in

    the sense of

    instant,

    the

    assumption

    that

    time

    consists of

    instants would have warranted in his

    view the conclusion

    that

    the

    flying arrow

    is

    neither moving nor

    resting. But he says

    (ibid. 30-32) that

    the

    assumption warrants the conclusion

    that the arrow is resting. So unless

    he is

    being very careless,

    he must be

    thinking of the "nows" of the supposed

    assump-

    tion not as

    instants,

    but as atomic durations.

    21

    I am not

    implying

    that the hypothesis is that the arrow

    is moving over

    every

    interval, however

    small. It would be quite legitimate to

    hold that the hypothesis

    is, as such, non-committal as to motion over micro-intervals and does not exclude

    a

    priori the possibility that motion

    might be

    discontinuous after all. But

    to

    assert (I) Zeno would have to go

    much further than profess agnosticism

    as to

    9

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    9/17

    Zeno's

    argument there

    is

    absolutely nothing

    -

    not one word

    -

    to

    say,

    imply, or even suggest, that he was offeringus some reasonfor believing

    that the

    flying arrow stays put for tiny

    intervals. Hence the

    only

    possibleway

    of

    bringing

    any such premise nto the argument

    would be

    to assume that

    this is something which Zeno's reader

    already believes,

    so

    that Zeno does not

    have to

    argue

    for

    it,

    or even mention

    it: he can

    just take

    it

    for

    granted.

    Under the

    influence

    of Paul

    Tannery

    (249ff.)

    a

    number of

    distin-

    guished scholars have made

    just

    this

    assumption.

    Supposing (T, i)

    -

    "T"

    n

    honour of the father of this

    hypothesis

    -

    that Zeno's

    arguments

    were directed against Pythagoreans whom they supposed (T, ii) to

    hold

    a

    remarkable

    doctrine,

    called "number-atomism"

    by

    Cornford,

    these

    scholars

    have

    also

    supposed (T, iii)

    that Zeno's

    opponents

    believed that

    time,

    no less than matter and

    empty space,

    was

    made

    up

    of indivisible

    quanta.

    Elsewhere22 have

    argued against (T, i)

    and

    (T, ii).

    This is

    not the

    time to resume that argument. But it

    might

    be

    just

    as well

    to

    remind the reader that that

    protest (preceded

    by

    such

    fundamental

    work

    as

    that

    of

    Heidel, 21ff., Calogero

    115ff. and

    van der Waerden

    151ff.)

    has been sustained

    in

    several later

    contri-

    butions (includingOwen 1, 211ff.; Booth 90ff.; Burkert37ff., 264ff.;

    Untersteiner

    197ff.)

    However, (T, i)

    and

    (T, ii)

    were at least

    put

    forward

    on the basis

    of

    presumptive

    textual evidence. In this

    respect

    they

    are in a

    totally

    different

    category

    from

    (T, iii),

    for

    which

    not a

    single

    item of

    positive

    textual evidence

    has ever been offered.

    Aristotle's

    last-cited remark

    does not

    constitute such evidence. For neither

    here

    (i.e.

    239B8-9 and 31-33) nor anywhere else does

    Aristotle

    say,

    or even

    suggest,

    that this

    or

    any

    other

    argument

    of Zeno's was directed

    against

    Pythagorean philosophers.23

    Nor does Aristotle tell

    us

    here that Zeno

    said (or claimed, maintained, etc.) that time is composed of "in-

    divisible nows." His remarkcan be read

    perfectly

    well

    as

    only

    tracking

    down the

    assumption

    which,

    in Aristotle's own

    judgment,

    was

    logically

    entailed

    by

    Zeno's

    argument,

    and would have to be added to its

    premises,

    to validate the conclusion.24

    f

    I

    were to

    say,

    'In

    arguing

    that

    motion or rest over micro-intervals; he would have to assert

    rest;

    and this would

    be begging the question.

    22Gnomon 25 (1953), 29-35 at 31ff.; Philos. Review 68 (1959), 531-35 at 532ff.

    23

    Nor is any such thing said, or suggested, by Eudemus or by any other ancient

    authority.

    84 This, I trust, is all Lee (78) means

    in

    saying that Aristotle here "points

    out...

    the

    necessary presupposition

    of the

    argument."

    10

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    10/17

    P entails

    Q,you

    are

    assuming

    the truth of

    R,'

    I would not be

    implying,

    and might not even wish to suggest, that you already believe R.

    All

    I

    could

    be, strictly,

    understood to

    imply

    is

    that,

    since 'P entails

    Q'

    entails

    R, you

    cannot

    maintain

    the former

    unless

    you

    are also

    prepared

    to stomach the latter.

    Therefore,

    if one wished to cite Aristotle as a

    witness

    of Zeno's

    profession

    of the

    discontinuity

    of

    time,

    one

    would

    have to produce

    other evidence

    tending

    to show that

    Aristotle

    wished

    us to understand

    his

    remark as

    ascribing

    such

    a

    doctrine

    to

    Zeno.

    Such evidence does not exist. That the

    quantization

    of

    time was

    espoused

    by

    Zeno himself or

    by

    his

    Pythagorean

    contemporaries

    thus

    remainsa pureconjecture,25 nd a most implausibleone: so abstruse a

    speculation

    as the

    replacement

    of

    the

    temporal

    continuum

    by

    an

    atomic

    conception

    of

    temporal

    passage

    could not have

    been

    seriously

    entertained,

    let alone

    professed,

    until

    well

    after the much

    more

    concrete

    hypothesis

    of the atomic constitution of

    matter had become

    thoroughly

    assimilated

    by

    the

    philosophical

    imagination,

    i.e.

    well

    after

    Zeno's

    time.26

    So we can be

    confident that

    if

    Zeno had

    expected

    his

    readers

    to concur with

    (I),

    he could not

    have

    presumed

    on

    their

    doing

    so

    because of their

    antecedent

    philosophical

    commitments;

    he

    wouldhave

    had to producean argumentfor (I), if that is what he was assertingby

    means

    of

    [la].

    Since there is no trace

    of

    such

    an

    argument, we

    have

    good

    reason to discount

    this

    first

    reading

    of the

    "when."

    (II), on the other

    hand, allows

    a

    viable,

    and

    very

    simple,

    explanation

    of

    the

    fact

    that

    Zeno

    thought

    [1

    a] true,

    and so

    plainly true

    that he felt

    no need to

    argue

    the

    point or

    even so much as

    mention it as

    his reason

    for

    [

    a];

    If we think of the arrow as

    occupying

    a

    given

    position for

    a

    time of zero

    duration,

    it will

    be obvious

    enough

    that

    it

    cannot

    be

    moving just

    then: it

    will

    have

    no

    time

    in

    which to

    move.27

    To derive

    [la] we will then requireonly the following additionalpremise:

    H.

    If the arrow is not

    moving

    when it is

    "at a

    place

    equal to itself,"

    it must be

    at

    rest

    at that

    place.

    26 For the

    "suggestion" that this was

    "a

    Pythagorean

    formulation,

    arising out

    of their

    point-atom

    theory"

    see

    Lee

    105-06.

    26

    For this

    reason

    among

    others I

    would

    reject the

    interpretation

    of the

    fourth

    Zenonian

    paradox

    of motion

    as an

    argument

    against

    temporal

    indivisibles.

    Cf.

    p.

    43,

    n.

    31, of

    my

    essay cited

    in

    n.

    1

    above;

    and note that

    this

    interpretation

    of

    the

    paradox is unheard

    of

    in

    antiquity,

    and

    goes flatly

    against

    the

    one which

    all of our ancient authorities take to be the obvious sense of the paradox.

    27

    Cf.

    Black

    133-34, the

    first

    four

    paragraphs

    of

    his

    exposition of

    what he calls

    "a

    modem

    version of the

    paradox."

    11

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    11/17

    This hypothetical is the crucial

    tacit premiseof the puzzle. If

    this were

    granted, [1 a] would certainly follow, and the success of the whole

    argument

    would

    be assured28.

    How then

    would H have struck Zeno?

    Would

    it

    have

    looked to him

    a hazardous inference in need

    of argu-

    mentative

    support? I shall try to convince the

    reader

    -

    if he

    does need

    to

    be convinced

    -

    that, on

    the

    contrary, it would have

    seemed to him

    trivially

    true.

    Let

    me

    begin

    by pointing

    out that even today most people

    (perhaps

    even

    some

    readers of

    this

    journal )

    would think it so.

    Here is

    one

    example

    from

    a

    distinguished

    modern

    philosopher:

    "If

    a

    flying arrow

    occupiesat each point of time a determinate point of space, its motion

    becomes

    nothing

    but

    a

    sum

    of rests"

    (James

    157)

    -

    presumably

    because

    occupying

    a

    point

    of

    space

    at

    a

    point

    of

    time entails

    the

    antecedent

    of

    H

    and therefore ts

    consequent. Evidently

    it

    has not

    occurred

    to

    James

    that

    H

    involves

    a

    substantial inference

    -

    and an

    invalid

    one.29

    Yet

    James had at

    his

    disposal tools

    of

    analysis by means

    of

    which he could

    easily

    have

    satisfied

    himself

    that

    H,

    so

    far

    from

    being

    tautologously true,

    is

    certainly

    false.

    Its antecedent

    is

    indeed true:

    the

    arrow

    does

    not

    move

    when

    (i.e.

    in

    the instant

    of

    zero duration

    at

    which) it occupies a space equal to its own bulk. But its consequentis

    false (in

    the

    broader

    sense

    in

    which

    "false"covers senseless

    statements

    no

    less

    than

    significant falsehoods):

    to

    say

    that the

    arrow

    is

    at rest

    for

    an

    instant is, strictly

    speaking,

    senseless.

    This can

    be

    established,

    S

    for

    example,

    by

    means

    of the familiar

    v

    formula

    (v,

    velocity; s,

    distance; t,

    time).

    Since a

    body

    at rest

    has zero

    velocity

    and covers

    no

    distance,

    the

    values

    required

    for

    v

    and s

    to

    represent

    the state

    of rest

    will be

    zero. On

    the

    hypothesis

    that

    the

    body

    is

    at rest

    in an

    instant,

    0the value of t willalso be

    zero,

    and we will then

    get

    v

    =

    ,

    i.e. arithmeti-

    28

    It might be thought

    that [1 a] could be granted

    and the conclusion escaped by

    arguing that even if at

    rest in each instant the

    arrow need not be at rest during

    the whole of its flight. This would be a mistake.

    If we conceded sense and truth

    to

    the

    statement that the arrow is at rest

    in

    each

    instant of its flight, we would

    be admitting that the

    whole period of the flight can be accounted for in terms

    of rest, which would

    be only another way of saying that the arrow

    is at rest

    throughout the whole

    period. Cf. Owen 1, 216-17.

    '9

    A good, clear statement of its error in Chappell

    203: "What

    is at rest is

    motionless, but we cannot infer that what is motionless is at rest without the

    added premise that it is motionless through

    a

    period

    of

    time,

    or

    at

    more than

    one

    moment [= instant]: for a single moment there

    is neither motion nor rest."

    12

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    12/17

    cal

    nonsense. The

    only

    way

    to

    get

    the

    required

    v

    =

    0

    is

    to

    assign

    a

    value greaterthan zero to t, i.e. to representthe body as being at rest

    during

    some

    temporal

    nterval,

    however

    short.30

    In

    Physics

    VI

    (234A32-B7;

    239A11-17)

    Aristotle reached

    an

    equivalent

    result

    without benefit of

    algebra by

    a

    conceptual analysis

    of the "now". He demonstrated

    that,

    since

    "resting

    consists in

    being

    in

    the

    same

    [place]

    in

    some

    [interval

    ofl

    time"

    (239A26), it follows

    that

    (1)

    in

    any

    "now"

    there can be neither motion nor rest: it is

    only

    true

    to

    say

    (2)

    that

    [any body,

    whether

    moving

    or

    resting]

    is not

    moving

    while

    it is

    over against

    something [i.e.

    while

    having

    a determinate

    position]

    in a

    "now";

    but (3) it would not be the case that [any body, whether moving or resting]

    could

    be

    over

    against

    a

    stationary

    body

    in a

    [period

    of]

    time: for if the

    latter

    were

    the

    case [i.e.

    if

    a

    body had a determinate

    position

    for

    some temporal

    interval,

    however

    small],

    then a

    moving body

    would be

    at rest (239

    B

    1-4).

    Here at last we do

    get

    the denial of H we

    have been

    looking

    for:

    It

    is implied

    in

    (2) that the antecedent of H is

    true

    (the arrowwould

    not

    be moving

    in the

    "now")

    and

    in

    (1)

    that its

    consequent is false

    (the

    arrow would not be at rest

    in

    the

    "now").

    But this

    comes only

    at the

    high point of

    an

    intensive

    exploration

    of

    temporal concepts,

    begun in the Academy,31and continued with rare diligence and

    penetration

    in

    the Physics. And even

    so,

    for all the

    brilliantadvance in

    insight this treatise

    represents, it

    does not take

    Aristotle far enough to

    enable him to understand

    clearly

    the

    fact that the

    antecedent

    of H,

    though certainly true,

    is

    true not for

    physical, but

    semantic, reasons 32

    The sense in which the arrow is not

    moving

    in

    any instant is

    vastly

    different from that in which the Rock of

    Gibraltar s

    not moving in

    any

    day, hour,

    or second. To

    say

    that

    the

    Rock is

    moving

    in

    some

    period

    would

    be

    merely

    false.

    To

    say

    that the arrow is

    moving in any

    instant

    80

    A

    perfectly good

    sense

    may

    nonetheless be

    given

    to

    'instantaneous

    rest' as a

    limit: cf. the

    explanation

    of 'instantaneous

    velocity'

    in

    Section

    III

    below.

    31

    Cf. Owen

    2,

    92ff.

    32

    Some readers

    may

    think

    I

    am

    underestimating

    Aristotle's

    insight

    at this

    point.

    They

    may

    retort that since Aristotle

    has come to

    see

    that a

    body is

    neither

    moving

    nor

    resting

    in

    an instant

    (while

    knowing

    all too well

    that

    a

    body must be

    either

    moving

    or

    resting

    during

    an

    interval),

    he

    must have

    grasped

    the

    semantic

    difference

    in the two

    types

    of assertions. I am

    not

    questioning

    that

    Aristotle

    has

    some

    understanding

    of the difference. All I

    am

    claiming is that it is not

    extensive

    enough

    to enable him to

    (i)

    state

    formally

    the

    crucial

    point (in

    some

    such way as I proceed to do above or in some logically equivalent way) and,

    therefore

    (ii)

    see its full

    implications

    for

    questions

    of

    immediate

    concern to him.

    The second

    deficiency

    will be

    apparent

    in

    n.

    35

    below.

    13

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    13/17

    would be

    (strictly

    speaking)

    senseless:33 t is

    non-moving

    and non-

    resting in the same way in which e.g. a point is non-straightand non-

    curved,

    non-convex

    and

    non-concave

    -

    the

    predicatesare

    not

    falsely

    applicable, but

    inapplicable.

    If

    this is

    not

    understood,

    the

    antecedent

    of

    H

    will

    itself

    seem

    fully as

    paradoxical

    as

    its

    consequent, and

    will

    provoke

    the

    question,

    'But

    if

    the

    arrow is

    not

    moving in

    any

    given

    instant of its

    flight,

    when

    and how

    does it

    manage to

    move?' To

    answer

    this

    questionone

    must

    expose

    the confusion

    lurking behind

    the

    expec-

    tation that,

    if the arrow

    is to

    move at

    all,

    it

    must move in

    the

    instant.

    One

    must point out that to

    ask,

    'How

    can

    the

    arrow

    be

    moving

    during

    an interval when it is non-moving in every instant contained by that

    interval?'

    would

    be

    like

    asking,

    'How

    can

    the

    arc

    be

    curved

    when

    none

    of its points are

    curved?':

    motion

    (or

    rest)

    apply

    to

    what

    happens

    not

    in individual

    instants

    but

    in

    intervals

    (or

    ordered

    sets

    of

    instants),

    as curvature

    is

    a

    property

    not

    of

    individual

    points

    but of lines

    and

    surfaces

    (or

    orderedsets of

    points).

    Only

    when

    this

    has

    been

    understood

    will

    one be

    in

    a

    position

    to see that

    the

    arrow's

    non-moving

    in

    any

    given instant

    is

    absolutely

    irrelevant to

    its

    moving

    or

    resting

    during

    some

    interval

    containing

    the

    given

    instant,34

    and

    that

    conversely

    the

    arrow'smoving (orresting) duringa given interval allows no inference

    whatever that

    it is

    moving

    (or

    resting)

    in

    any

    instant

    contained

    by

    that

    interval.35

    0

    88

    As much so as would the

    -

    result for v in the formula above,

    and for parallel

    reasons.

    84 And, therefore,

    that the disjunction in [2a]

    is

    not exhaustive:

    it stops short of

    a third possibility

    which (stated with pedantic

    completeness)

    would run:

    "or [C] from

    the place,

    Po,

    in

    which it

    is

    at a given instant,

    io,

    to

    a place,

    Pi,

    in

    whicb

    it

    is not

    at

    io,

    during an interval which contains both

    io

    and the later

    instant, il, at which it is at

    pl."

    a6 While certainly

    allowing the

    inference

    that

    it

    is moving (or

    resting)

    at

    any

    instant contained

    by that interval. This

    -

    and the implied distinction

    between

    motion (or rest)

    in (or, for) an

    instant

    (which

    is

    senseless,

    as

    has just been

    explained) and

    motion (or rest)

    at

    an

    instant

    (to

    which

    sense

    can

    and must be

    given: cf. Section

    III below)

    -

    Aristotle totally failed to grasp.

    For positive

    evidence of this failure

    see

    Phys.

    236

    A

    15ff.,

    where

    he

    is

    dealing

    with a

    period

    of rest, CA,

    immediately

    followed

    by

    a

    period

    of

    change, AD,

    with

    A

    as

    the

    boundary

    instant

    common to

    the two

    periods.

    He remarks

    that

    if

    something

    were

    at rest throughout CA,

    it would

    follow

    that xxl

    &v r& A

    ipeLe,

    line 18. This

    inference is,

    of course, correct.

    But it

    appears

    to be

    in

    flagrant

    contradiction

    with Aristotle's formal doctrine that

    'pcrLeZv

    is

    impossible &v

    C

    vwov

    234 A 32-34;

    and

    cf. the

    citation

    from 239B

    in

    the

    text above).

    To

    get

    around

    the

    apparent

    inconsistency

    Aristotle

    would

    have

    to understand

    how

    vastly

    different is the

    14

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    14/17

    We

    may

    now

    return

    to Zeno. It

    should now be clear that to see

    the

    falsehoodof H, or even to suspectit, he would have neededto possess a

    clear-cut

    understanding

    of

    the

    instant/interval

    distinction and to

    bring

    this

    to

    bear

    on H

    in

    spite

    of the

    fact that it does

    not mention

    "in-

    stants"),

    thereby

    realizing that

    its

    evident truth

    for

    intervals

    is

    not

    the

    slightest reason

    why

    it

    should

    be

    true

    for

    instants.

    Zeno's

    ability

    to

    meet this

    condition

    may

    be

    gauged

    from

    the

    fact

    that,

    in all

    pro-

    bability, he did not

    even have a term

    for "instant"

    and

    could

    only get

    at this

    concept

    indirectly by

    thinking

    of

    what

    would

    happen

    to

    the

    time

    of

    the

    flight

    "when" the arrow was

    "at a

    place equal

    to

    itself,"

    i.e. by thinking of durationcut to zero as the distance traversed was

    cut

    to

    zero.

    Is

    it

    surprisingif in

    such

    circumstances he should

    have

    thought

    of the arrow's

    being

    at

    rest

    in

    such

    a

    time as

    being

    no

    more

    than

    verbally different

    from

    its

    not

    moving

    in

    it,

    and

    thereforefelt

    as

    certain

    of the former

    as

    he

    was

    entitled

    to

    feel of

    the

    latter?36

    III

    We

    saw

    above

    what

    William

    James made

    of

    the Arrow.

    Here is

    one

    of

    Bertrand Russell's glosses on it:

    Philosophers often tell us

    that

    when

    a

    body is in

    motion, it

    changes

    its

    position

    within

    the

    instant. To

    this view

    Zeno long

    ago made

    the fatal

    retort

    that

    every

    body

    always

    is

    where

    it is;

    but

    a

    retort so

    simple and so

    brief

    was not of

    the

    kind to which

    philosophers are

    accustomed to

    give

    weight,

    and

    they

    have

    continued

    down to

    our

    own day to

    repeat the

    same

    phrases

    which roused

    the Eleatic's

    destructive

    ardour. It was

    only recently

    that

    it

    became

    possible

    to explain

    motion

    in detail

    in

    accordance with

    Zeno's

    platitude,

    and in

    opposition to the

    philosophers'

    paradox. 2,

    1582.

    Here

    Zeno

    is

    given

    credit

    for

    having

    grasped the

    following

    truth:

    If

    time-specifications

    are

    made

    not in

    terms of

    temporal

    intervals,

    but

    in

    terms

    of

    instants, then

    it

    is possible

    to say

    that a moving

    body

    sense of

    iv in

    236A18

    (where

    Av

    -T&

    A

    =

    "at

    instant A")

    from

    e.g.

    Iv

    'r

    v5v

    Ogv

    7ri9oxe...

    QpqLiv,

    234A34

    (where

    &v

    =

    "in" or

    "within"

    [i.e.

    for] a

    given

    instant.)

    86

    It should be

    evident on

    inspection

    that

    in the

    Zenonian

    argument

    as

    recon-

    structed above

    (end of

    Section

    I)

    "not

    moving" and

    "resting"

    are

    being

    used as

    logically

    equivalent

    expressions:

    so e.g.

    at

    the

    third step

    where the

    arguer

    says

    "cannot move"

    though

    his

    inference,

    if

    valid, would have

    entitled

    him

    to

    say

    "must be at rest." But I am not entering this as evidence for the above con-

    clusion,

    since the

    extent

    to

    which the

    relevant

    texts

    have

    preserved Zeno's

    original

    wording

    is

    unknown.

    15

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    15/17

    is

    at one and

    only one place at any given instant just as unambigu-

    ously as we can say this of a body which is at rest. This insight liberates

    the philosopher from the idea of an instantaneous

    state of motion37

    an

    idea

    which, though (strictly) nonsense, is not

    obvious nonsense.

    For

    we do

    say such things as 'the ship is now moving

    at the rate of

    ten miles per hour,' meaning by "now" 'at

    this instant,' and our

    dynamics

    cannot

    dispense with the notion of "instantaneous

    velocity."

    How so,

    if the instantaneous state of

    motion

    makes no

    sense? How

    could motion at an instant

    make

    sense,

    if motion

    in

    (orfor)an instant

    does

    not?

    It was

    only

    with the

    greatest

    labour

    and

    after

    many false

    moves that it was found possibleto give a satisfactory answerto this

    question

    -

    "to

    explain motion in detail in accordance with Zeno's

    platitude"

    -

    by showing

    that

    'velocity

    at

    instant,

    i'

    can be understood

    to

    mean

    no

    more

    than

    the

    limit

    of

    average

    velocities

    over

    intervals

    approaching

    zero

    and

    always containing i,

    where "approaching

    zero"

    can

    be defined

    without covert

    appeal

    to an instantaneous state

    of

    change (or

    to

    its

    mathematical

    twin,

    the

    infinitesimal) by employing

    only

    variables

    quantified

    over intervals of finite

    length:

    the set of

    inter-

    vals

    containing

    i

    approaches

    zero

    if,

    and

    only if,

    for

    any preassigned,

    arbitrarily small, interval e, there is always a memberof the set such

    that

    the

    differencebetween

    its

    length

    and

    zero

    is less

    than

    e.

    We

    may

    be

    grateful

    to Russell

    for

    helping

    us see

    how

    important

    and

    87

    I.e. of a

    motion

    which

    is accomplished

    in,

    or within,

    an instant

    (cf.

    the first

    sentence

    in

    the

    citation from

    Russell).

    38

    Russell's

    most

    frequently

    cited

    gloss on

    Zeno

    -

    1, 347

    ff.: the historical

    fable

    and

    further leg-pulling

    of the "philosophers"

    - is a

    brilliant

    piece

    of

    writing

    and

    would

    be wholly

    delightful

    if it

    were not

    confusing for

    those

    who are not fully

    up

    to Russell's

    tricks (see

    e.g. what

    poor James

    made of it,

    186, n. 1). Here

    Russell

    tells us that Zeno (and Weierstrass following unknowingly in Zeno's footsteps)

    have proved

    "that

    we live

    in an unchanging

    world

    and that the

    arrow, at

    every

    moment [

    =

    instant]

    of its

    flight, is truly

    at rest"

    -

    this

    on the strength

    of

    the

    fact

    that

    Zeno is supposed

    to have

    proved that

    there is

    no instaneous

    state

    of change

    (= "Zeno's

    platitude"

    above),

    as

    though this

    entailed

    the

    vastly

    different

    propositions

    that

    there are

    instantaneous

    states

    of rest and

    that the

    moving

    arrow is always

    in one of these

    For still

    another

    Russellian

    analysis

    of the

    Arrow

    see 4, 805:

    here

    Zeno's denial

    of motion

    (suppressed

    in the citation

    from 2,

    1582

    in the text

    above) is

    acknowledged

    and pegged

    on

    Zeno's

    assumption

    that

    there

    can be

    no motion unless

    there

    are

    instantaneous

    states

    of motion.

    Another

    assumption

    is imputed

    to Zeno

    in

    the

    still different analysis

    of the

    Arrow in

    3,

    179: "the plausibility of the argument seems to depend upon supposing that

    there

    are

    consecutive

    instants."

    There

    seem to

    be almost as many

    Zenos

    in

    Russell

    as

    there are Russells.

    16

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    16/17

    how true is that

    insight

    he has

    called,

    with

    pugnacious

    understatement,

    "Zeno's platitude." With our own analysis of the texts behind us,

    we need not be disturbed

    by

    the

    accompanying

    historical

    fable.38

    If the foregoing

    interpretation is correct,

    Zeno has

    indeed seen

    that

    the arrow does not move in a

    given instant. But he could

    only

    have had

    a

    faint

    glimmering of what this

    means, else

    he

    would not have

    jumped

    to

    the

    conclusion

    that it must be

    resting

    at that

    instant

    and

    during

    all

    intervals

    containing that

    instant and that all bodies

    must be

    resting

    during

    all intervals

    containing

    all

    instants.

    Recognizing

    Zeno's

    mistake,

    we need not

    belittle

    his

    achievement.

    Zeno's

    paradox is not a

    bad

    first

    move in the direction of "Zeno'splatitude."39

    Princeton University

    89

    I

    am

    deeply

    indebted to

    Professor Carl B.

    Boyer,

    of

    the

    department of

    mathematics of

    Brooklyn

    College,

    for

    a

    criticism which has

    prompted

    some

    revisions in the

    penultimate

    paragraph

    of Section II

    and

    in

    note 35. I

    am also

    indebted

    to Professor Gunther

    Patzig

    for some useful

    suggestions.

    Bibliography

    Black, M. Problems of Analysis (Ithaca, 1954).

    Booth,

    N.B.

    "Were

    Zeno's

    arguments

    directed against the

    Pythagoreans?",

    Phronesis 2

    (1957), 90-103.

    Burkert,

    W. Weisheit

    und Wissenschaft

    (Nuirnberg,

    1962).

    Calogero,

    G. Studi Sull' Eleatismo

    (Rome,

    1932).

    Chappell, V. C.,

    "Time

    and Zeno's

    Arrow,"

    Journal

    of

    Philosophy 59

    (1962), 197ff.

    Diels, H. and

    Kranz, W.

    Fragmente

    der

    Vorsokratiker,6th

    edition, Berlin,

    1952.

    Frankel,

    H.

    "

    Zeno of Elea's

    Attacks

    on

    Plurality,"

    American

    Journal

    of

    Philology

    63

    (1942),

    1ff.

    and 193ff.

    (Transinto German

    in

    Wege

    und Former

    Fruh-

    griechischen

    Denkens

    [Munich, 1955],

    198ff.)

    Heidel, W.A.

    "The Pythagoreans

    and

    Greek

    Mathematics,"

    American Journal

    of Philology 61 (1940), 1ff.

    James,

    William,

    Some

    Problems of

    Philosophy (New

    York,

    1911).

    Lee, H.

    D.P.

    Zeno

    of Elea

    (Cambridge

    1936).

    Owen,

    G.E.L. (1) "Zeno

    and

    the

    Mathematicians,"

    Proc.

    Arist.

    Society 58

    (1957-58),

    199-222.

    Owen, G.E.L.

    (2) "TtO6vmL8

    Lptv6.Levx",

    Aristote et les

    ProblUmesde

    Mdthode

    (papers

    presented at the

    Symposium

    Aristotelicum held at

    Louvain

    in

    1960)

    (Louvain,

    1961), 83-103.

    Tannery, P. Pour l'Histoire de la Science

    Hellgne (Paris,

    1877).

    Ross, W. D.

    Aristotle's

    Physics

    (Oxford, 1936).

    Russell, B. (1)

    Principles of

    Mathematics

    (London, 1903).

    - (2) "Mathematics and the Metaphysicians," in The World of Mathematics,

    ed.

    by J.

    R.

    Newman

    (New

    York,

    1956):

    the date of

    Russell's essay

    not

    given.

    17

    This content downloaded from 170.140.26.180 on Thu, 15 Aug 2013 19:30:15 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Phronesis Volume 11 Issue 1 1966 [Doi 10.2307%2F4181773] Gregory Vlastos -- A Note on Zeno's Arrow

    17/17

    -

    (3)

    Our

    Knowledge

    of the External

    World (London,

    1914).

    -

    (4) History

    of

    Western Philosophy

    (New

    York,

    1945).

    Untersteiner,

    M. Zenone: testimonianze

    e

    frammenti

    (Florence,

    1963).

    van der

    Waerden,

    B. L. "Zenon

    und die Grundlagenkrise

    der griechischen

    Mathematik,"

    Mathematische

    Annalen 1172 (1940),

    141 ff.

    18