ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    1/13

    On the Position of Maimon's PhilosophyAuthor(s): Nathan RotenstreichSource: The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 21, No. 3 (Mar., 1968), pp. 534-545Published by: Philosophy Education Society Inc.Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20124632.

    Accessed: 22/12/2014 19:42

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Philosophy Education Society Inc.is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The

    Review of Metaphysics.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=peshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20124632?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20124632?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=pes
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    2/13

    EXPLORATION

    ON

    THE

    POSITIONOF

    MAIMONA

    PHILOSOPHY

    NATHAN

    RUTENSTREICH

    I

    Interwoven

    in the complex texture

    of Solomon Maim?n

    's

    (1752-1800)

    system

    are

    strands

    of

    thought originating

    in

    the

    theories

    of his

    avowed

    creditors. Maim?n is

    one

    of the

    first

    modern

    philosophers

    who

    acknowledges

    his

    debt to

    diverse

    philo

    sophical

    trends

    and

    traditions.

    Among

    his

    major

    creditors,

    Maim?n

    includes Maimonides

    and

    Spinoza.1

    The

    present

    analysis,

    however,

    will

    be restricted

    to

    an

    exploration

    of

    his

    debt

    to

    Leibniz,

    Hume,

    and

    Kant.

    In interweaving aspects of thought from Leibniz and Hume,

    Maim?n

    takes

    his

    departure

    from

    the

    earlier

    synthesis

    of their

    posi

    tions,

    wrorked

    out

    by

    Kant

    in

    the

    Critique

    of

    Pure Reason.

    But

    Maim?n

    goes

    beyond

    Kant,

    by

    interlacing

    theories of

    the

    critical

    philosophy

    itself,

    with

    the web

    Kant

    had

    woven

    of

    strands

    from

    Leibniz

    and Hume. What

    permitted

    Maim?n

    to

    link

    the

    seemingly

    incompatible

    systems

    of the

    rationalist and the

    sceptic?

    In

    the

    first

    place,

    both

    thinkers

    sought

    to

    establish the

    validity

    of

    the

    relation

    between

    the

    two

    pillars

    of

    knowledge,

    concepts

    and

    sense

    data.

    Secondly,

    both

    philosophers

    believed

    that the

    way

    to

    ac

    complish

    their

    aim

    was

    to

    derive

    one

    component

    of

    knowledge

    from

    the other.

    According

    to

    Leibniz,

    the

    empirical

    factor

    can

    be

    derived

    from the

    conceptual;

    while,

    according

    to

    Hume,

    ideas

    can

    be derived

    from

    impressions.

    But

    the

    difference

    in

    direction

    does

    not

    alter the

    fact that

    both

    Leibniz

    and Hume

    posit

    a

    genetic

    relation

    between the

    two

    factors

    :

    according

    to

    both,

    concepts

    are

    applicable

    to

    sense-data

    because

    one

    factor

    grows

    out

    of the other.

    Hume

    maintains

    that

    concepts

    1

    On Maimon's relation

    to

    Spinoza

    see

    S.

    H.

    Bergman,

    The

    Philosophy

    of

    Solomon

    Maim?n

    (Jerusalem,

    1967),

    pp.

    216

    ff.

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    3/13

    ON THE POSITIONOFMAIMON'S PHILOSOPHY 535

    are

    valid

    because

    they

    are

    copies

    of

    impressions;

    Leibniz maintains

    that

    the

    empirical

    factor

    can

    be

    explained

    hecause it constitutes

    a

    stage

    in

    a

    continuous

    context

    originating

    in the monad.

    Both

    Leibniz

    and

    Hume,

    then,

    sought?albeit

    in

    opposite

    directions?a

    continuous

    transition

    between

    the

    heterogeneous

    component

    fac

    tors

    of

    human

    knowledge.

    Kant

    rejects

    this

    method

    of

    coping

    with

    the

    problem

    of

    valid

    ity.

    Taking

    his

    departure

    from

    the

    assumption

    that

    there

    can

    be

    no continuous transition between

    concepts

    and sense

    impressions,

    Kant

    sought

    another

    way

    of

    establishing

    the

    validity

    of

    concepts,

    or

    alternately,

    a

    different tnethod

    of

    justifying

    their

    application

    to

    sense-data.

    According

    to

    Kant,

    the

    relation between

    the

    two

    fac

    tors

    is

    not

    genetic

    but

    functional.2

    Unlike

    Leibniz

    and

    Hume,

    who

    abolish

    duality,

    Kant

    sustains

    it.

    Whereas

    Leibniz and

    Hume

    represent

    duality

    as

    the

    crux

    and

    source

    of

    their

    problem,

    Kant

    represents

    it

    as

    the

    framework and foundation for

    his

    solution.

    Arguing

    that the

    function of

    relating

    and

    ordering

    pertains

    to

    the

    very nature of concepts, and that only by being incorporated into

    a

    conceptually

    determined structure

    does the datum

    occupy

    a

    log

    ical

    position.

    Kant establishes the

    interrelatedness

    of

    the

    two

    fac

    tors,

    without

    assuming

    that

    one

    can

    be derived

    from

    the

    other.

    Unlike

    Leibniz,

    who

    posits

    a

    genetic

    relation

    in

    which

    intelligible

    truths find

    empirical

    realization

    and unlike

    Hume,

    who

    posits

    a

    genetic

    relation

    in

    which

    sense

    impressions

    find their

    conceptual

    copies,

    Kant

    posits

    a

    relation based

    upon

    the

    synthetic

    nature

    of

    knowledge,

    i.e.,

    a

    relation

    subsisting

    between

    heterogeneous

    factors.

    Both

    Leibniz

    and Hume furnish

    Maim?n

    with

    criteria for

    measuring

    Kant's

    solution

    to

    the

    problem

    of

    validity.

    On

    the

    one

    hand,

    Maim?n

    applies

    the

    Leibnizian

    criterion

    which?by

    repre

    senting

    the

    empirical

    factor

    as

    a

    realization of the

    rational

    factor?

    robs

    the

    former of its

    independence.

    On

    the other

    hand,

    he

    applies

    Hume's

    criterion

    according

    to

    which

    the

    empirical

    factor

    can

    be

    neither abolished

    nor

    reduced

    to

    another factor.

    It

    is

    not

    only

    against

    Kant,

    but

    also

    against

    Leibniz

    that Maim?n

    raises

    his

    2

    See

    my

    Experience

    and its

    Systemalization,

    Studies in

    Kant

    (The

    Hague,

    1965).

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    4/13

    536 NATHAN ROTENSTR?ICH

    objections.

    For the burden

    of

    Maim?n

    's

    objection

    is

    this:

    to

    translate

    intelligible

    truths

    into

    empirical

    truths

    is

    impossible

    owing

    to

    the

    irreducible

    residuum

    of

    experience

    established

    by

    Hume.

    If the

    heterogeneity

    of the

    factors

    is

    ultimate?so

    Maim?n

    's

    criticism runs?then

    Kant's

    solution is

    unsatisfactory.

    To

    repre

    sent

    duality

    as

    the

    foundation for

    one's

    solution,

    is

    merely

    to

    pretend

    that

    the

    question

    itself is

    an

    answer.

    But

    Maim?n

    uses

    Leibniz

    as a

    weapon

    rather

    than

    as

    a

    target

    for

    criticism.

    According

    to

    Maim?n,

    Leibniz

    provides

    the

    only

    possibility

    of

    solving

    the

    problem:

    a

    relation between

    empirical

    data and

    intelligible

    concepts

    can

    be

    established

    only

    by

    eliminating

    the

    former,

    that is

    to

    say,

    only by making

    the

    empirical

    factor

    thoroughly

    intelligible.

    In

    assuming

    a

    synthetic

    connection be

    tween the

    factors,

    Kant

    transfers

    the

    problem

    and

    its

    solution

    to

    a

    new

    sphere.

    But the

    heterogeneity

    of the factors is

    a

    problem

    posed

    by

    synthesis

    as

    well.

    Kant

    assumes

    that

    he has

    overcome

    the

    acute form

    of

    heterogeneity

    which

    might

    preclude

    the

    possi

    bility

    of a

    synthetic

    connection.

    This, however,

    is

    analogous

    to

    the

    assumption

    that

    by

    bringing

    one

    extreme

    in

    contact

    with

    the

    other,

    we

    cancel the

    polar opposition

    between them. Like

    Hume,

    whose

    spokesman

    he

    purports

    to

    be,

    Maim?n

    emphasizes

    the

    ir

    reducibility

    of

    the datum. But

    whereas Hume maintains the

    primacy

    of

    the

    datum,

    Maim?n maintains its

    independence

    vis-?-vis

    the

    concept.

    In this

    respect,

    Maim?n

    fights

    Kant with

    a

    Kantian

    weapon;

    for it

    was

    Kant

    who

    taught

    that

    the

    empirical-perceptual

    factor

    is

    no

    less

    independent

    than

    the

    conceptual

    factor.

    Accord

    ing to Maim?n, if the empirical factor is independent, then even

    synthesis

    is

    impossible.

    On the

    one

    hand, then,

    Maimon's

    position

    resembles

    Kant's

    in

    that

    it lies

    midway

    between Leibniz's

    and

    Hume's.

    On the

    other

    hand,

    however,

    Maim?n

    diverges

    from

    Kant

    in

    using

    Kant's

    system

    as

    evidence

    that

    the

    impossibility

    of

    solving

    the

    problem

    raised

    by

    Hume

    implies

    the

    impossibility

    of

    realizing

    the

    solution

    proposed by

    Leibniz.

    To

    put

    it

    another

    way,

    because

    he

    con

    sciously

    confines the

    solution

    he

    proposes

    within the limits

    of

    finite understanding, Kant draws a distinction between archetypal

    understanding

    and

    ectypal

    understanding.

    Maim?n

    apparently

    agrees

    with

    Kant that

    the solution

    is confined within the

    limits of

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    5/13

    ON

    THE

    POSITION

    OF MAIMON'S

    PHILOSOPHY

    537

    finite

    understanding.

    But

    he

    goes

    beyond

    Kant

    in

    two

    respects.

    For

    one

    thing,

    he

    stresses

    the

    limits

    of

    finite

    understanding by

    putting

    more

    pointedly

    the

    problem posed

    by

    Hume,

    i.e.,

    by

    pointing

    out

    what

    makes

    human

    understanding

    finite.

    For

    an

    other,

    he

    furnishes

    finite

    understanding

    with

    a

    criterion

    for

    measuring

    its

    own

    finitude

    by juxtaposing

    it

    with

    the infinite

    understanding

    posited

    by

    Leibniz.

    From

    Hume,

    Maim?n

    adopted

    the

    ultimate

    fact of sensation and

    the

    conclusion

    Hume

    based

    upon

    it,

    namely

    that the relations

    among

    concepts

    are

    purely

    psycholog

    ical. From

    Leibniz,

    Maim?n

    adopted

    the

    cognitive

    ideal

    by

    con

    trast with

    which

    the

    nature

    of

    empirical

    knowledge

    is

    illuminated.

    What

    conclusions

    can

    we

    draw

    from

    Maim?n's

    adaptation

    of

    elements

    from

    Leibniz,

    Hume and

    Kant? First

    of

    all,

    because

    Kant's

    system

    constitutes the

    background

    against

    which

    Maim?n

    develops

    his

    theory,

    we

    can

    increase

    our

    appreciation

    of

    Kant

    by

    studying

    Maim?n.

    Secondly,

    we

    may

    expect

    that

    one

    problem

    with

    which

    Maim?n

    will

    be

    preoccupied

    will

    be the

    nature

    of

    valid

    knowledge. Finally, we may assume that the other problem with

    which

    Maim?n

    will

    be

    preoccupied

    will

    be

    the

    nature of

    the factors

    which

    prevent

    the realization of

    valid

    knowledge.3

    II

    What

    are

    the

    distinguishing

    marks of valid

    knowledge?

    To

    answer

    this

    question

    it

    is

    necessary

    to

    recall that in

    classical

    philos

    ophy

    a

    distinction

    was

    drawn between the

    intelligible

    world

    on

    the

    one

    hand,

    and

    the

    empirical

    world

    on

    the other.

    The

    first

    step

    toward

    cancelling

    this

    distinction

    was

    taken

    by

    Kant.

    By

    substituting

    understanding

    and

    sensation

    for

    intelligible

    world

    and

    sensible

    world,

    Kant

    transformed

    what liad hitherto

    been

    a

    differ

    ence

    in

    the

    structure

    of the

    world,

    into

    a

    difference

    within

    the

    limits of

    knowledge.

    But

    despite

    the

    enclosure of

    the diverse

    factors

    within

    the realm of

    knowledge,

    their

    duality

    remained

    intact. The

    cognitive

    significance

    which

    Kant

    assigns

    to

    the

    differ

    3

    See

    the

    most

    recent

    comprehensive

    study

    :

    Samuel

    Atlas,

    From

    Critical

    to

    Speculative

    Idealism:

    The

    Philosophy of

    Solomon Maim?n

    (The

    Hague,

    1964).

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    6/13

    538

    NATHAN

    ROTENSTREICH

    ence

    between

    understanding

    and

    sensation?as

    distinguished

    from

    the

    ontological

    validity

    it had been

    assigned

    in

    classical

    philosophy

    ?can,

    perhaps,

    be

    said

    to

    constitute

    the

    logical

    condition of

    Kant's

    idea

    of

    synthesis.

    Maim?n

    goes

    beyond

    Kant

    by

    asking:

    if

    under

    standing

    and

    sensation

    are

    indeed elements

    of

    knowledge,

    then

    why

    must

    their

    duality

    be maintained? If

    understanding

    and

    sensation

    are

    indeed constituents of

    knowledge,

    then

    they

    ought

    to

    be understood

    as

    elements

    of

    a

    single

    system,

    rather than

    as

    two

    systems,

    one of which is based

    upon

    the other.

    In

    abolishing

    the

    ontological

    difference,

    and

    in

    substituting

    a

    difference between

    two

    sources

    of

    knowledge,

    Kant

    took the first

    step

    toward

    rationalization.

    The

    second

    step

    toward

    rationaliza

    tion is

    taken

    by

    Maim?n,

    who

    abolishes

    the difference

    between the

    two

    sources

    of

    knowledge

    and

    substitutes

    a

    duality

    immanent

    in

    the

    sphere

    of

    knowledge;

    a

    duality

    immanent

    in

    the

    process

    of

    rationalization

    which

    perpetually

    and

    progressively

    overcomes

    the

    irrational

    factor,

    i.e.,

    the datum.

    By

    being

    absorbed

    into

    the

    process

    of

    rationalization,

    the irrational factor is robbed of its

    irreducibility

    which would otherwise

    arrogate

    a

    stable

    status.

    Integration

    into the continuous

    process

    of

    rationalization

    is

    substituted for

    the

    fixed

    status

    of

    the

    components

    of

    knowledge.

    The

    change

    undergone

    by

    the

    datum entails

    a

    new

    view

    both

    of

    concepts

    and

    of

    the

    syntheses

    connected

    with

    them. From

    Kant's

    well-known observation

    that

    concepts

    without

    intuitions

    are

    empty,

    and

    intuitions without

    concepts

    are

    blind,

    it follows that

    contents

    are

    created

    through

    synthesis.

    It

    is

    the

    content

    which

    constitutes the encounter between the different elements. Abolish

    ing

    the difference between

    the

    elements entails

    the

    absorption

    of

    the

    content

    into

    the

    concept

    itself,

    i.e.,

    into

    the

    concept

    as

    endowed

    with

    the

    power

    of

    explication.

    As endowed

    with

    the

    power

    of

    explication,

    the

    concept

    itself

    is the

    content.

    Synthesis

    no

    longer

    denotes

    the

    self-transcendence

    of

    concepts

    and their

    application

    to

    intuitions. The

    fullness

    furnished

    by

    intuition is

    implicit,

    to

    begin

    with,

    in the

    concept;

    and

    synthesis

    is but

    the fullness

    of

    the

    con

    cept. Being

    full

    to

    begin

    with,

    not

    depending

    upon

    intuition

    for

    its fullness, the concept can serve as a starting point for an

    explicative

    process,

    i.e.,

    for

    a

    genetic

    process

    in

    which the

    problem

    of

    validity

    finds

    its

    solution.

    It

    may

    accordingly

    be said that

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    7/13

    ON

    THE

    POSITION

    OFMAIMON'S PHILOSOPHY

    539

    Maim?n

    goes

    beyond

    Leibniz,

    Hume,

    and

    Kant

    by developing

    the

    central

    tenet

    of

    each:

    with the

    help

    of

    Kant's

    concept

    of

    synthesis,

    Maim?n undertakes

    to

    demonstrate the

    possibility

    of

    a

    transition

    from

    understanding

    to

    experience,

    which

    was

    maintained

    by

    Leibniz and

    denied

    by

    Hume.

    But

    by

    so

    doing,

    he

    assigned

    a new

    meaning

    to

    Kant's

    conception

    of

    synthesis;

    whereas

    Kant

    defined

    concepts

    as

    functions which

    order

    the

    datum,

    Maim?n defines them

    as

    the

    content

    of

    the universe.

    Ill

    Maim?n 's

    new

    interpretation

    of

    synthesis

    leads

    him

    to

    a new

    conception

    of

    the

    rationality

    of the universe.

    Rationality,

    Maim?n

    maintains,

    consists

    in

    the

    creation of

    the

    datum

    out

    of the

    concept,

    not in

    the

    explanation

    of the

    datum

    by

    means

    of the

    concept.

    Rationality

    is realized in the

    generation

    of

    the datum.

    Maim?n

    sought

    concrete

    expression

    for

    this

    concept

    of

    rationality

    in

    the

    following

    facets of his

    system

    :

    (A)

    Conspicuous

    in

    its absence from

    the

    epistemological

    sphere

    is the

    noncognitive

    factor

    posited

    by

    Kant,

    namely

    the

    thing-in-itself.4

    In

    Kant's

    system,

    the

    thing-in-itself

    fulfills

    the

    twofold

    function of

    (a)

    supplying

    knowledge

    with

    the

    datum;

    and

    (b)

    guaranteeing

    that

    the datum will

    not be eliminated

    from

    knowledge.

    Kant's

    thing-in-itself

    frustrates,

    as

    it

    were,

    the

    ten

    dency

    of

    the

    concept

    to

    produce

    the datum

    out

    of

    itself

    by

    way

    of

    a

    continuous

    transition.

    If,

    however,

    by

    concept

    we

    mean

    the

    element of

    fullness,

    then there

    is

    neither

    room

    nor

    reason

    for

    limiting

    its

    fullness

    by

    assigning

    a

    cognitive

    function

    to

    the

    thing

    in-itself;

    there

    is

    neither

    room

    nor

    reason

    for

    allotting

    a

    cognitive

    function

    to

    a

    factor

    which

    subsists

    beyond

    the

    sphere

    of

    knowl

    edge.

    Anticipating

    Hermann

    Cohen

    and

    his

    followers,

    Maim?n

    argues

    that the

    thing-in-itself

    cannot

    bear

    the

    brunt of criticism

    based

    upon

    an

    analysis

    of the

    nature

    and constituent elements

    of

    knowledge.

    4

    See

    Bergman,

    op.

    cit.,

    pp.

    7

    ff.,

    and

    Atlas,

    op.

    cit.,

    pp.

    20

    ff.

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    8/13

    540

    NATHAN

    ROTENSTREICH

    (B)

    Elimination

    of

    the

    thing-in-itself

    is

    entailed

    by

    the

    assumption

    concerning

    the

    synthetic

    character of

    concepts

    ;

    but

    no

    positive

    characteristic

    of

    synthesis

    is

    illuminated

    by

    its

    elimination.

    The

    synthetic

    character

    of

    concepts

    finds

    positive expression

    in

    the

    apparent pivot

    of

    Maimon's

    system,

    the

    law of

    determinability

    (Satz

    der

    Bestimmbarkeit).

    How

    is it

    possible,

    Maim?n

    asks,

    to

    link

    a

    particular

    predicate

    with

    a

    particular subject?

    Predication,

    a

    fundamental

    function

    of

    all

    knowledge,

    is

    not

    an

    arbitrary

    act of

    formal assertion. This function must

    necessarily

    be anchored in

    the

    meaning

    and

    structure

    of the

    concepts

    it

    combines;

    it

    is

    not

    only

    from the

    perspective

    of the

    assertion,

    but also from the

    per

    spective

    of

    content,

    that

    a

    particular

    term

    must

    constitute

    a

    pred

    icate

    of

    a

    particular subject.

    Or,

    as

    Maim?n

    puts

    it,

    the content

    must

    be

    the

    measure

    of

    whether the

    subject

    is determined

    by

    the

    predicate,

    and whether

    the

    predicate

    is the

    determination. The

    combination

    in

    the assertion

    is

    accordingly

    based

    upon

    the

    clarity

    of the

    known

    content;

    and the known

    content

    guides

    the

    combina

    tion in the assertion. Not the formal facets of the proposi

    tional

    structure,

    but the known

    contents

    permit

    us

    to

    say

    This is

    a

    right-angled triangle,

    and

    prevent

    us

    from

    saying

    This

    is

    a

    right-angled

    truth.

    Whereas,

    according

    to

    the realistic

    solution,

    knowledge

    is valid

    because it

    copies

    the clear

    structure

    of the

    world,

    according

    to

    Maim?n,

    knowledge

    is valid

    when it

    is

    formulated

    in

    assertions which

    reflect

    its

    own

    clear

    structure,

    i.e.,

    the

    structure

    of

    a

    determinable

    subject

    and its determinations.

    Maim?n

    also

    maintains

    that

    the

    concept

    is

    not

    merely

    an

    ordering

    function

    but

    also

    a

    fullness of

    content,

    because

    its

    very

    nature

    leads

    us

    to

    bring

    forth from

    potentiality

    into

    actuality

    its

    implicit

    deter

    minations.

    Here

    Maim?n

    seems

    to

    interweave

    two

    strands

    of

    Aristotle's

    philosophy:

    the

    element

    of

    emergence

    from

    potentiality

    into

    actuality

    as a

    law

    of the

    universe,

    and the

    element of

    related

    ness

    between

    subject

    and

    predicate

    as

    the

    structure

    of

    propositions.

    As

    represented

    by

    Maim?n,

    the

    passage

    from

    potentiality

    into

    actuality

    is

    implicit

    in

    the

    relation

    between

    subject

    and

    predicate;

    the

    structure

    of the universe is

    implicit

    in

    the

    structure

    of

    proposi

    tions.

    The

    encounter

    between

    metaphysical

    and

    logical

    structure

    occurs neither on the plane of the universe, nor on the plane of

    formal

    logic,

    but

    on

    the

    plane

    of

    knowledge

    saturated with

    con

    ceptual

    content.

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    9/13

    ON

    THE

    POSITION

    OF

    MAIMON'S PHILOSOPHY

    541

    (C)

    The

    pivotal

    notion

    of Maim?n's

    system

    is

    not

    exhausted

    in the

    observation that

    it combines

    an

    element

    of

    Aristotelian

    logic

    with

    an

    element of

    Aristotelian

    metaphysics,

    the

    subject-predicate

    structure

    of

    propositions

    with the

    dynamic

    structure

    of the uni

    verse.

    For

    Maim?n also

    adapts

    for

    his

    purposes

    the

    element of

    substance

    and

    accident.

    Maim?n

    explicitly

    represents

    the

    relation

    between

    substance

    and

    accident

    as

    displaying

    a

    structure

    which

    has

    been transferred

    to

    the

    logical

    sphere

    :

    he

    correlates

    the

    determined

    subject with substance as being independent of its determination;

    and

    he

    correlates

    the determination with the

    accident

    as

    being

    dependent

    upon

    the determined

    subject.

    Maim?n

    's

    transfer of

    ontological

    categories

    to

    the

    logical-conceptual

    sphere

    clearly

    reflects

    his

    tendency

    to

    abolish

    the

    duality

    of

    the

    spheres.

    Also

    reflected

    in

    this

    transfer is

    Maimon's

    closely

    related

    argument

    that

    the

    structure

    of substances

    cannot

    be

    transparent

    or

    rational,

    unless

    it

    is

    at

    the

    same

    time the

    structure

    of

    concepts.

    To

    understand

    why

    Maim?n transfers the

    structure

    of

    sub

    stance and accident to the

    conceptual

    sphere,

    is at the same time

    to

    understand

    why

    he criticizes the

    notion

    that the

    category

    of

    causality

    constitutes the

    supreme

    principle

    of

    knowledge.

    Were

    we

    to

    represent

    as

    a

    central

    metaphysical

    motif

    the

    conflict between

    the

    principle

    of

    substance

    and

    the

    principle

    of

    causality,

    we

    would

    have

    to

    include Maim?n

    among

    the

    leading proponents

    of the

    former:

    measuring

    the

    principle

    of

    causality

    by

    his

    standard

    of

    rationality,

    Maim?n

    argues

    that

    the

    relation

    between

    cause

    and

    effect

    is

    not

    meaningful,

    because?being

    a

    relation of

    implication

    rather than explication?it is not based upon the inner content of

    the

    related

    terms.

    The assertion and

    determination which

    many

    thinkers

    represent

    as

    the

    strength

    of

    the

    causality principle

    are

    represented by

    Maim?n

    as

    its

    weakness.

    A connection of this

    kind,

    Maim?n

    argues,

    is external and

    meaningless.

    Maimon's

    cognitive

    ideal,

    then,

    is

    to

    find

    an

    immanent-meaningful

    founda

    tion

    for the

    interconnectedness

    of

    elements,

    even

    when

    their

    con

    nection

    occurs

    merely

    in

    time.

    This

    ideal

    cannot

    be satisfied

    by

    the

    merely

    temporal

    relation

    of succession. Maim?n

    consequently

    tries to correlate the principle of causality with

    a

    type of continuous

    transition

    based

    upon

    the

    content

    of the

    phases

    which follow

    one

    another,

    not

    upon

    their

    position

    in

    a

    temporal

    sequence.

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    10/13

    542 NATHAN ROTENSTREICH

    (D)

    The

    very

    terminology employed

    by

    Maim?n

    reflects

    the

    rationalization

    predominant

    in

    his

    teaching.

    Particularly

    per

    tinent,

    in

    this

    respect,

    is

    the

    term

    differential,

    which

    Maim?n

    uses

    to

    denote the

    process

    of

    creating

    the datum

    out

    of the

    con

    cept,

    the

    perceptions

    being

    integrals

    of

    the

    conceptual

    elements.

    As

    S.

    H.

    Bergman

    has

    shown,3

    the

    position

    occupied

    by

    the

    concept

    of

    differential

    in

    Maimon's

    system

    is

    parallel

    to

    the

    position

    occupied

    by

    the

    concept

    of

    schematism

    in

    Kant's

    system.

    Yet

    this

    aspect

    of Maimon's

    concept

    need not detain us, since it

    pertains

    to

    the technical

    machinery

    of

    his

    system,

    rather than

    to

    its

    main

    trend

    toward

    rationalization.

    To

    throw further

    light

    on

    that

    trend,

    it

    might

    be

    worthwhile

    to

    examine the

    relations

    between

    Formal

    Logic,

    which

    pertains

    to

    the

    structure

    of

    judgments,

    and

    Transcendental

    Logic,

    which

    per

    tains

    to

    objects.

    Maim?n

    was

    among

    the

    first

    philosophers

    to

    take issue

    with

    Kant

    on

    this

    central

    matter.

    Unlike

    Kant,

    Maim?n

    maintains the

    primacy

    of

    Transcendental

    Logic

    and its inde

    pendence of Formal Logic. In thus diverging from Kant, Maim?n

    sought,

    first of

    all,

    to

    invest

    thought

    with

    content

    and,

    secondly,

    to

    make

    Formal

    Logic?which

    deliberately

    disregards

    and abstracts

    from

    content?merely

    an

    abstraction of

    the

    full,

    and

    consequently

    creative,

    concept.

    Once

    we

    admit that

    the

    concept

    is

    dynamic,

    that

    it is

    the

    precondition

    of rationalization

    through generation

    of

    the

    datum

    out

    of

    a

    concept,

    then

    we

    are

    driven

    to

    regard

    content

    saturated

    thought

    as

    primary,

    and formal

    thought

    as

    secondary.6

    IV

    If

    Maimon's

    system appears

    Janus-faced,

    it

    is

    because

    the

    trend

    toward

    rationalization

    is

    accompanied

    by

    an

    awareness

    that

    ration

    ality

    cannot be

    realized

    within

    the

    limits

    of finite

    understanding.

    Rationalization

    is

    obstructed

    by

    the

    factual difference

    between the

    component

    elements

    of

    knowledge,

    i.e.,

    by

    the

    dual

    structure

    de

    scribed

    in

    Kant's

    critical

    system.

    Maimon's

    factual

    scepticism

    is

    5

    See

    Bergman,

    op.

    cit.,

    pp.

    65

    ff.; Atlas,

    op. cit.,

    pp.

    109

    ff.

    6

    See

    Rotenstreich,

    Experience

    and

    its

    Systematization,

    Studies

    in

    Kant, pp.

    14

    ff.

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    11/13

    ON

    THE POSITION

    OF MAIMON'S

    PHILOSOPHY

    543

    based

    upon

    two

    different

    uses

    of Kant's

    system:

    on

    the

    one

    hand,

    he

    measures

    Kant's

    system by

    the

    standard

    of

    rationalization,

    and

    finds it

    wanting;

    on

    the

    other

    hand,

    he

    measures

    rationalization

    by

    Kant's

    system,

    and

    finds

    that

    it

    cannot

    be

    realized.

    Thus

    Maim?n

    seems

    to

    accept

    the

    Kantian

    system

    de

    facto,

    even

    though

    he

    denies that

    it

    constitutes

    a

    solution

    to

    the

    problem

    it

    was

    designed

    to

    solve.

    Maimon's

    system

    may

    accordingly

    be described

    as

    a

    combination

    of

    fundamental

    rationalism

    and factual

    scepticism.

    What other reason is there for Maimon's factual scepticism?

    It

    will be

    recalled

    that

    there

    is

    an

    element

    of

    ambiguity

    in

    Kant's

    concept

    of

    experience.

    Experience

    connotes the domain

    of

    sensuous

    encounter with data.

    It is

    in

    this

    sense

    that

    Kant

    says

    Everything

    else

    has

    to

    be

    left

    to

    experience.

    7

    Yet

    when

    he

    says

    that

    he

    deals

    with

    experience

    as

    grounded

    both

    in

    perception

    and

    in

    understanding,8

    he refers

    to

    experience

    as

    a

    synthesis

    and

    not

    as

    a

    mere

    encounter.

    In

    any

    case

    Kant does

    not

    offer

    an

    exhaustive

    explanation

    of

    the

    relation

    between

    the

    two

    meanings

    of

    expe

    rience. Maim?n

    seems

    to

    have been

    more

    precise

    in

    this

    matter;

    using

    Kantian

    terms,

    he

    maintained

    that

    a

    particular

    sense-impres

    sion

    is

    an

    actual

    experience,

    while

    the total

    system

    of

    knowledge

    represents

    possible

    experience.

    This

    implies

    that

    concepts

    are

    applicable

    to

    knowledge

    in

    general

    qua

    possible

    experience,

    and

    that

    they

    are

    not

    applicable

    to

    actual

    experience

    qua

    this

    or

    that

    particular impression.

    There

    is

    no

    internal connection

    between

    this

    particular

    impression

    in its

    ultimate

    factuality

    and

    the

    system

    of

    knowledge.

    Hence

    the

    applicability

    of

    the

    system

    to

    the

    impres

    sion

    is

    not

    demonstrated

    by

    Kant.

    The

    question

    quid

    facti

    remains

    unsolved;

    rationalization

    through

    generation

    of

    the datum

    from

    the

    concept

    remains

    unattainable

    within

    the

    limits

    of

    finite

    under

    standing.

    In

    the

    history

    of

    sceptical

    ideas,

    Maimon's

    factual

    scepticism

    occupies

    a

    special

    position

    His

    scepticism

    is

    aware

    of,

    and

    mea

    sures

    itself

    by,

    a

    criterion of

    knowledge

    immune

    against

    scepticism.

    Both

    scepticism

    and

    relativism

    are

    generally

    challenged

    on

    the

    7

    Kritik

    der reinen

    Vernunft,

    B,

    p.

    218. In trans,

    by

    Kemp

    Smith

    (London,

    1950),

    p.

    208.

    8

    Prolegomena

    zu

    einer

    jeden k?nftigen

    Metaphysik,

    etc.

    S

    20,

    trans,

    by

    Peter and

    Lucas

    (Manchester,

    1953).

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    12/13

    544

    NATHAN

    ROTENSTREICH

    grounds

    that

    they

    presuppose

    what

    they

    negate.

    More

    specifically,

    it

    is

    objected,

    first

    of

    all,

    that

    the

    sceptic

    assertion

    there

    is

    no

    certain

    judgment

    is

    itself

    a

    certain

    judgment.

    Secondly,

    it is

    objected

    that

    scepticism

    is

    possible

    only

    by

    comparison

    with

    some

    thing

    which

    is

    beyond

    doubt. Neither of

    these

    objections

    seems

    pertinent

    to

    Maimon's

    scepticism.

    Maim?n

    explicitly

    restricts

    doubt within

    the

    limits of

    empirical knowledge.

    Doubt,

    as

    he

    puts

    it,

    applies

    to

    the existence of

    thought

    concerning objects

    in

    conformity

    to the a

    priori

    conditions of

    knowledge.

    Such doubt

    does

    not

    cancel

    itself

    because

    it

    applies

    only

    to

    knowledge

    of

    objects,

    not to

    knowledge

    of the

    structure

    of

    knowledge.

    Further

    more,

    such

    scepticism

    is

    explicitly

    formulated

    by

    reference

    to

    a

    definite, crystallized,

    cognitive

    ideal. Such

    scepticism accordingly

    implies

    the

    nonrealization of

    the

    ideal,

    not

    the

    self-contradiction

    or

    self-destruction

    of

    knowledge.

    V

    The

    Janus-faced

    character

    of

    Maimon's

    system

    carries decisive

    weight

    from the

    viewpoint

    of the

    development

    of

    philosophy.

    We

    may

    venture

    to

    say

    that

    Maim?n

    formulated the

    program

    of nine

    teenth

    century

    idealism,

    fully

    aware

    that

    the

    program

    could

    not

    be

    carried out.

    Nineteenth

    century

    idealism

    may

    be described

    as a

    philosophical

    movement

    which

    endeavors,

    or

    dares,

    to

    undertake

    the

    execution

    of

    Maimon's

    program.

    Idealism

    tries

    to

    abolish the

    sceptical boundary set by Maim?n; it attempts to abolish the differ

    ence

    between

    finite

    consciousness

    and infinite-divine consciousness.

    It is

    not

    by

    chance

    that

    Hegel's system

    is described

    by

    Whitehead

    as a

    philosophic

    attitude

    of

    a

    God.9

    Hegel's

    design

    was

    to

    abolish

    the

    inner

    opposition

    between

    our

    minds and

    objects,

    and

    to

    repre

    sent

    objects

    or

    objectivity

    as

    objectified

    mind.

    Why

    do

    we

    describe

    this

    realization

    of

    Maimon's

    program

    as

    daring?

    Unlike

    Maim?n,

    Hegel

    does

    not

    represent

    finite

    mind

    as

    a

    limitation

    of

    infinite

    mind;

    he

    represents

    infinite

    mind

    as

    an

    immanent

    explication

    of

    9

    Analysis

    of

    Meaning,

    in

    Essays

    in Science

    and

    Philosophy

    (London,

    1948),

    p.

    99.

    This content downloaded from 190.216.144.250 on Mon, 22 Dec 2014 19:42:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 ON THE POSITION OF MAIMONA PHILOSOPHY

    13/13

    ON

    THE

    POSITION

    OF

    MAIMON'S PHILOSOPHY

    45

    finite mind.

    This

    is

    why

    Hegel

    assigns

    a

    central

    position

    in

    his

    system

    to

    the

    Phenomenology of

    Spirit;

    for

    it

    is

    here

    that

    he

    justifies

    his

    daring

    venture.

    Here

    he undertakes

    to

    demonstrate

    not

    only

    that

    Maimon's

    program

    can

    be

    realized

    as

    a

    matter

    of

    principle,

    but

    also that

    it is

    actually

    realized,

    and

    realized

    precisely

    by

    that

    finite

    mind

    which

    Maim?n

    represented

    as

    incapable

    of

    realizing

    rationalization.

    What

    Maim?n

    represents

    as

    frustrating

    the

    trend

    toward

    realization,

    Hegel represents

    as

    sustaining

    it.

    The

    Hebrew

    University

    of

    Jerusalem.