138
ON SOUND AND VOICE (c) 2013 Bart A. Mazzetti § 1

On Sound and Voice

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 1/138

ON SOUND AND VOICE

(c) 2013 Bart A. Mazzetti

§

1

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 2/138

TABLE OF CONTENTS

I. According to Plato.

II. According to Aristotle.

III. On phone (‘voice’) and psophos (‘sound’) in sum.

IV. On language as a systematic means of human communication.

V. On articulation.

VI. On speech as a species of discrete quantity.

VII. On elementary speech sounds.

VIII. On the motion of the voice.

IX. On the strings of a musical instrument.

X. On the overtone series.

XI. On tonality as consisting in hierarchy.

XII. Definitions of harmony.

XIII. On the principal meanings of harmonia.

XIV. On composition.

§

2

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 3/138

I. ACCORDING TO PLATO.

Plato, Philebus 17b-e (ed. Perseus; tr. Peter Kalkavage; rev. B.A.M.).

Sôkratês: phônê men hêmin esti pou mia dia

tou stomatos iousa, kai apeiros au plêthei,

 pantôn te kai hekastou.

Prôtarchos: ti mên;

Sôkratês: kai ouden heterôi ge toutôn esmen pôsophoi, oute hoti to apeiron autês ismen outh’

hoti to hen: all’ hoti posa t’ esti kai hopoia,

touto esti to grammatikon hekaston poioun

hêmôn.

Prôtarchos: alêthestata.

Sôkratês: kai mên kai to mousikon ho

tunchanei poioun, tout’ esti tauton.

Prôtarchos: pôs;

But voice, which passes through the mouth of 

each and all of us, is one; and yet again it is in-

definite in manyness.

Yes, to be sure.

And we aren’t ever wise, one man more thananother, either because we know its indefin-

iteness or because we know its unity, but be-

cause we know they are so many and what sort

 —this is what makes each of us grammatical

Very true.

Also this same thing makes each of us turn out

to be musical.

How is that?

Sôkratês: [17c] phônê men pou kai to kat’ekeinên tên technên esti mia en autêi.

Prôtarchos: pôs d’ ou;

Sôkratês: duo de thômen baru kai oxu, kai

triton homotonon. ê pôs;

Prôtarchos: houtôs.

Sôkratês: all’ oupô sophos an eiês tên

mousikên eidôs tauta mona,

mê de eidôs hôs g’ epos eipein eis tauta oudenos

axios esêi.

Prôtarchos: ou gar oun.

Voice according to this art is also one in it.

How could it not be!

And we set down two sounds—the low and the

high—and a third which is between them. Or 

how did we do it?

Just as you said.

But if you knew these things alone, you would

not yet be wise with respect to music.

Though if you didn’t know them, you would be,

as the saying goes, worth nothing in these

things.

Certainly.

Sôkratês: all’, ô phile, epeidan labêis ta

diastêmata

But, my friend, when you take hold of the

intervals— 

3

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 4/138

hoposa esti ton arithmon tês phônês oxutêtos te

 peri kai barutêtos, [17d] kai hopoia, kai tous

horous tôn diastêmatôn, kai ta ek toutôn hosa

sustêmata gegonen— 

ha katidontes hoi prosthen paredosan hêmin tois

hepomenois ekeinois kalein auta harmonias,

en te tais kinêsesin au tou sômatos hetera toiautaenonta pathê gignomena, ha dê di’ arithmôn

metrêthenta dein au phasi rhuthmous kai metra

eponomazein,

kai hama ennoein hôs houtô dei peri pantos

henos kai pollôn skopein— 

how many of them there are and the number 

concerning high and low voices, and of what

sort, and the boundaries of the intervals, and

whatever systems result from these— 

which those before us investigated and handed

down to us who follow them, and which men

call harmonies— 

and again the corresponding effects that comeabout in the motions of the body, which they

say must be measured by numbers and are

called rhythms and meters— 

and at the same time that it is necessary to think 

in this way and to look at every one and many— 

hotan gar auta [17e] te labêis houtô, tote egenou

sophos, hotan te allo tôn hen hotioun tautêi

skopoumenos helêis, houtôs emphrôn peri toutogegonas:

to d’ apeiron se hekastôn kai en hekastois

 plêthos apeiron hekastote poiei tou phronein kai

ouk ellogimon oud’ enarithmon, hat’ ouk eis

arithmon oudena en oudeni pôpote apidonta.

when you take hold of these things in this way,

then you have become wise, and whatever be

the unity you have looked to, that is the way to become thoughtful about it:

But this indefinite manyness in things collec-

tively and individually makes you in each case

indefinite in thinking and worthy neither of 

 being held in account nor arithmetical, inas-

much as not once did you look away towards

any number.

Plato, Philebus 17c-d, e (ed. Perseus; tr. Peter Kalkavage; rev. B.A.M.).

But, my friend, when you take hold of the intervals—how many of them there areand the number concerning high and low voices, and of what sort, and the boundaries of 

the intervals, and whatever systems result from these—which those before us investigated

and handed down to us who follow them, and which men call harmonies— 1 ...when [e] youtake hold of these things in this way, then you have become wise, and whatever be the

unity you have looked to, that is the way to become thoughtful about it....

1. Plato’s teaching on harmonics in sum.

Subject genus:  phone, ‘voice’2

Division of ‘voice’ into three: the high, the low, and the intermediate

1 hoposa esti ton arithmon tês phônês oxutêtos te peri kai barutêtos, [17d] kai hopoia, kai tous horous tôn

diastêmatôn, kai ta ek toutôn hosa sustêmata gegonen—ha katidontes hoi prosthen paredosan hêmin tois

hepomenois ekeinois kalein auta harmonias....2 N.B. ‘Voice’ is ‘indefinite’ when taken as the matter of speech or song, being understood on the analogy of 

first matter, which is one insofar as it is considered apart from every determination of form.

4

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 5/138

Division of the subject (its partsand passions): the number of intervals

their number with respect to high and low

‘voices’ (= ‘notes’ or ‘tones’)of what sort they are

the boundaries of intervals

the systems which result from the intervals(= the harmoniai)

Their corresponding effects ( pathe) in

the motions of the body, which mustbe measured by number: rhythms and meters

2. Note on Plato’s accounts of harmonia.

As one may gather from the text of the Philebus (17c-d), Plato understands the har-

moniai to be the systemata which result from intervals, which latter consist in high and low

‘voices’ or ‘notes’. But the text from the  Laws (665a) defines harmonia as the name for 

order in the voice, the simultaneous mixture of the high with the low.

Plato, Rep. 601 A (tr. B.A.M.).

 Melos is composed of three things: speech, as well as harmony and rhythm. 3

Plato, Laws II (664 E—665 A) (ed. Perseus; tr. B.A.M.).

The name for order in movement is rhythm; but the name placed on [the order] in

the voice (the simultaneous mixture of the high with the low), is harmony;4 but both to-

gether are called the choral art.5

Plato, Laws II (672 E—673 A) (ed. Perseus; tr. R. B. Bury).

o(/lh me/n pou xorei/a o(/lh pai/deusij h)=n h(mi=n, tou/tou d’ au)= to\ me\n r(uqmoi/ te kai\a(rmoni/ai, to\ kata\ th\n fwnh/n . . . to\ de/ ge kata\ th\n tou= sw/matoj ki/nhsin r(uqmo\n me\nkoino\n th=? th=j fwnh=j ei)=xe kinh/sei, sxh=ma de\ i)/dion. e)kei= de\ me/loj h( th=j fwnh=jki/nhsij.

Athenian

In our view, choristry as a whole is identical with education as a whole; and the part of thisconcerned with the voice consists of rhythms and harmonies.

3 to\ me/loj e)k triw=n e)sti sugkei/menon, lo/gou te kai\ a(rmoniaj kai\ r(uqmou=.4 “The movement of the voice…in the order of its high and low sounds”—that is to say, “the order of high

and low sounds in the movement of the voice”, which is virtually Aristotle’s definition of  melos: t$= tw=n

fqo/ggwn ta/cei tw=n o)ce/wn kai\ bare/wn, “the order of its high and low sounds” ( Probl . XIX. 27, 919b 34,

tr. B.A.M.).5  th=? dh\ th=j kinh/sewj [665a] ta/cei r(uqmo\j o)/noma ei)/h, th=? de\ au)= th=j fwnh=j, tou= te o)ce/oja(/ma kai\ bare/oj sugkerannume/nwn, a(rmoni/a o)/noma prosagoreu/oito, xorei/a de\ to\ sunamfo/teronklhqei.

5

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 6/138

Clinias

Yes.

Athenian

And the part concerned with bodily motion possesses, in common with vocal motion,rhythm; besides which it possesses gesture as its own peculiar attribute, just as tune is the

 peculiar attribute of vocal [673a] motion.

Plato, Laws II (655a-b) (ed. and tr. R. G. Bury).

Athênaios: all’ en gar mousikêi kai schêmata

men kai melê enestin, peri rhuthmon kai

harmonian ousês tês mousikês,

hôste euruthmon men kai euarmoston, euchrôn

de melos ê schêma ouk estin apeikasanta,

hôsper hoi chorodidaskaloi apeikazousin, orthôs

 phthengesthai:

to de tou deilou te kai andreiou schêma ê melosestin te, kai [655b] orthôs prosagoreuein echeita men tôn andreiôn kala, ta tôn deilôn de

aischra.

kai hina dê mê makrologia pollê tis gignêtai peri

tauth’ hêmin hapanta, haplôs estô ta men aretês

echomena psuchês ê sômatos,

eite autês eite tinos eikonos,

sumpanta schêmata te kai melê kala, ta de

kakias au, tounantion hapan.

But though there are figures and tunes in music,

as its subject matter is rhythm and melody,

and we may accordingly speak of a tune or 

 posture as rhythmical or melodious, we cannot

 properly use the metaphorical expression of the

chorus trainers, ‘brilliantly colored’, of either.

But the coward and brave man have their characteristic postures and strains, and it is very proper to call those of brave men good, those of 

cowards bad.

In fact, to spare ourselves a great deal of verbal

repetition in our treatment of the whole subject,

we may take it, once and for all, that universally

all postures and melodies connected with

goodness of soul or body— 

whether with such goodness itself or with some

image of it— 

are good, and those connected with badness

universally the reverse.

N.B. Order is in the before and after of things; but the before and after in movementgives rise to a number; hence, in bodily movement, rhythm is number; not just any

number, but some ratio.

Plato, Laws II (655a-b) (ed. Perseus; tr. Thomas Pangle).

It should be noted, though, that music includes postures and tunes, since music

involves rhythm and harmony; now one can speak of “good rhythm” and “good harmony,” but one cannot correctly apply to either tune or posture and image “good color”—as the

chorus teachers, speaking in images, do. On the other hand, with regard to the posture or tune of the coward and the courageous man, it is correct to call what pertains to cowards

“ugly.” To avoid our getting involved in a very lengthy discussion of all these things, let’s

simply let all the postures and tunes that belong to virtue of the soul or of the body

(whether they belong to virtue itself or to an image of it) be beautiful, and those belongingto vice be entirely the opposite.

6

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 7/138

3. A description of the Pythagorean conception of melody.

Iamblichus, Vita Pythagorica Liber .

 From Ch. 15. How Pythagoras Cured By Music

(tr. Thomas Taylor)

This melody also was the result of dissimilar 

and variously differing sounds, celerities,

magnitudes and intervals, arranged with

reference to each other in a certain most musical

ratio6 and thus producing a most gentle and, atthe same time, variously beautiful motion and

convolution.

(tr. Kenneth Sylvan Guthrie)

This melody was also the result of dissimilar 

and varying sounds, speeds, magnitudes and

intervals arranged with reference to each other 

in a certain musical ratio, producing a

convoluted motion most musical and gentle.

§

6 The arrangement of the sounds etc. = melopoiia or its work.

7

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 8/138

4. On the composition of vocal sound.

Plato, Philebus (add) (tr. B. Jowett).

Soc. Some god or divine man, who in the Egyptian legend is said to have been Theuth,observing that the human voice was infinite, first distinguished in this infinity a certain

number of vowels, and then other letters which had sound, but were not pure vowels

(i.e., the semivowels); these too exist in a definite number; and lastly, he distinguisheda third class of letters which we now call mutes, without voice and without sound, and

divided these, and likewise the two other classes of vowels and semivowels, into the

individual sounds, told the number of them, and gave to each and all of them thename of letters; and observing that none of us could learn any one of them and not

learn them all, and in consideration of this common bond which in a manner united

them, he assigned to them all a single art, and this he called the art of grammar or

letters.

Plato, Cratylus 424 b – 425 b (tr. B. Jowett).

Soc. So I should expect. But how shall we further analyse them, and where does the

imitator begin?

Imitation of the essence is made by syllables and letters; ought we not, therefore, first toseparate the letters, just as those who are beginning rhythm [c] first distinguish the powers

of elementary, and then of compound sounds, and when they have done so, but notbefore, they proceed to the consideration of rhythms?

Her. Yes.

Soc. Must we not begin in the same way with letters; first separating the vowels, and

then the consonants and mutes, into classes, according to the received distinctions of 

the learned; also the semivowels, which are neither vowels, nor yet mutes; anddistinguishing into classes the vowels themselves?

And when we have perfected [d] the classification of things, we shall give their names,and see whether, as in the case of letters, there are any classes to which they may be

all referred; hence we shall see their natures, and see, too, whether they have in them

classes as there are in the letters; and when we have well considered all this, we shall

know how to apply them to what they resemble- whether one letter is used to denote onething, or whether there is to be an admixture of several of them;

 just, as in painting, the painter who wants to depict anything sometimes uses purple only,or any other colour, and sometimes mixes up several [e] colours, as his method is when he

has to paint flesh colour or anything of that kind- he uses his colours as his figures appear 

to require them; and so, too, we shall apply letters to the expression of objects, either single

letters when required, or several letters; and so we shall form syllables, as they are called,and from syllables make nouns and verbs; and thus, at last, from the combinations of nouns

and verbs arrive at [425] language, large and fair and whole; and as the painter made a

figure, even so shall we make speech by the art of the namer or the rhetorician, or by someother art.

8

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 9/138

 Not that I am literally speaking of ourselves, but I was carried away—meaning to say that

this was the way in which (not we but) the ancients formed language, and what they puttogether we must take to pieces in like manner, if we are to attain a scientific view of the

whole subject, and we must see whether the [b] primary, and also whether the secondary

elements are rightly given or not, for if they are not, the composition of them, my dear Hermogenes, will be a sorry piece of work, and in the wrong direction.

Her. That, Socrates, I can quite believe.

Plato, Theaetetus 202 e – 204 b (tr. B. Jowett).

And yet there is one point in what has been said which does not quite satisfy me.

Theaet. What was it?

Soc. What might seem to be the most ingenious notion of all: That the elements or letters

are unknown, but the combination or syllables known. [e]

Theaet. And was that wrong?

Soc. We shall soon know; for we have as hostages the instances which the author of the

argument himself used.

Theaet. What hostages?

Soc. The letters, which are the elements; and the syllables, which are the combinations;-he

reasoned, did he not, from the letters of the alphabet?

Theaet. Yes; he did. [203]

Soc. Let us take them and put them to the test, or rather, test ourselves: What was the way

in which we learned letters? and, first of all, are we right in saying that syllables have adefinition, but that letters have no definition?

Theaet. I think so. [b]

Soc. I think so too; for, suppose that some one asks you to spell the first syllable of my

name: Theaetetus, he says, what is SO?

Theaet. I should reply S and O.

Soc. That is the definition which you would give of the syllable?

Theaet. I should.

Soc. I wish that you would give me a similar definition of the S.

Theaet. But how can any one, Socrates, tell the elements of an element? I can only

reply, that S is a consonant, a mere noise, as of the tongue hissing; B, and most other

9

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 10/138

letters, again, are neither vowel-sounds nor noises. Thus letters may be most trulysaid to be undefined; for even the most distinct of them, which are the seven vowels,

have a sound only, but no definition at all.

Soc. Then, I suppose, my friend, that we have been so far right in our idea aboutknowledge?

Theaet. Yes; I think that we have. [c]

Soc. Well, but have we been right in maintaining that the syllables can be known, but not

the letters?

Theaet. I think so.

Soc. And do we mean by a syllable two letters, or if there are more, all of them, or a singleidea which arises out of the combination of them?

Theaet. I should say that we mean all the letters.

Soc. Take the case of the two letters S and O, which form the first syllable of my own

name; must not he who knows the syllable, know both of them? [d]

Theaet. Certainly.

Soc. He knows, that is, the S and O?

Theaet. Yes.

Soc. But can he be ignorant of either singly and yet know both together?

Theaet. Such a supposition, Socrates, is monstrous and unmeaning.

Soc. But if he cannot know both without knowing each, then if he is ever to know the

syllable, he must know the letters first; and thus the fine theory has again taken wings and

departed.

Theaet. Yes, with wonderful celerity. [e]

Soc. Yes, we did not keep watch properly. Perhaps we ought to have maintained that a

syllable is not the letters, but rather one single idea framed out of them, having a separate

form distinct from them.

Theaet. Very true; and a more likely notion than the other.

Soc. Take care; let us not be cowards and betray a great and imposing theory.

Theaet. No, indeed.

10

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 11/138

Soc. Let us assume then, as we now say, that the syllable is a simple form arising out of the

several combinations of harmonious elements—of letters or of any other elements. [204]

Theaet. Very good.

Soc. And it must have no parts.

Theaet. Why?

Soc. Because that which has parts must be a whole of all the parts. Or would you say that a

whole, although formed out of the parts, is a single notion different from all the parts?

Theaet. I should.

Soc. And would you say that all and the whole are the same, or different?

Theaet. I am not certain; but, as you like me to answer at once, I shall hazard the reply, that

they are different. [b]

Plato. Sophist (253 a) (tr. B. Jowett).

Stranger: This communion of some with some may be illustrated by the case of letters; for 

some letters do not fit each other, while others do.

Theaetetus: Of course.

Stranger: And the vowels, especially, are a sort of bond which pervades all the otherletters, so that without a vowel one consonant cannot be joined to another.

Theaetetus: True.

Stranger: But does every one know what letters will unite with what? Or is art required in

order to do so?

Theaetetus: Art is required.

Stranger: What art?

Theaetetus: The art of grammar.

Stranger: And is not this also true of sounds high and low? —Is not he who has the art to

know what sounds mingle, a musician, and he who is ignorant, not a musician?

Theaetetus: Yes.

Stranger: And we shall find this to be generally true of art or the absence of art.

Theaetetus: Of course.

11

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 12/138

Stranger: And as classes are admitted by us in like manner to be some of them capable and

others incapable of intermixture, must not he who would rightly show what kinds willunite and what will not, proceed by the help of science in the path of argument? And will

he not ask if the connecting links are universal, and so capable of intermixture with all

things; and again, in divisions, whether there are not other universal classes, which makethem possible?

Theaetetus: To be sure he will require science, and, if I am not mistaken, the very greatestof all sciences.

Stranger: How are we to call it? By Zeus, have we not lighted unwittingly upon our free

and noble science, and in looking for the Sophist have we not entertained the philosopher unawares?

5. The primary division of vocal sounds according to Dionysius of Halicarnassus:

Dionysius of Halicarnassus,  De Comp. verborum 14 [In:  Dionysius of Halicarnassus.

Critical Essays II . On Literary Composition. With an English Translation by StephenUsher), pp. 91-105, with omissions].

[14] Now in the articulate speech of human beings there are prime units admitting nofurther division, which we call “elements” and “letters”: “letters” (gra/mmata),

because they are signified by certain [91-92] 

2 Underlying the following discussion is the theory, which probably originated with the Sophists of 

the fifth century, and was later adopted by the Stoic grammarians, that the letters or elements of 

speech bore a natural relationship, through the words formed from them, to the objects which thosewords described; and that hence letters might be thought to possess innately pleasant or unpleasant

characteristics through such associations. Plato examines this theory in the Cratylus 424 A ff.

lines (grammai/),1 and “elements”, because every vocal sound originates in these inthe first place,2 and is ultimately resolved into them. The elements and letters are not allof the same nature. The first of the differences between them, as the musical theorist

Aristoxenus3 indicates, is that some represent vocal sounds, and others noise: theformer being those which are called “vowels”,4 the latter being all the other letters. A

second difference is that some of the non-vowels by their own nature produce some

kind of sound—a whirring, a hissing, a murmur, or suggestions of other sounds of 

these kinds;5 while others are devoid of any voice or sound and cannot be sounded bythemselves. Consequently some theorists have called the latter “voiceless” and the

others “semi-voiced”. Those who divide the primary and the elementary powers of 

the voice into three give the name “vowels” to all the letters which can be made to

produce sound on their own or together with others, and are self-sufficient;“semivowels” to all which are pronounced more effectively in combination with

vowels, worse and imperfectly on their own; “voiceless”6 to all which have no soundon their own, whether perfect or imperfect, but are pronounced in combination with

others.

It is not easy to say precisely what the number of these letters is, for the subject has

caused our pre- [93-94] 

12

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 13/138

1 Cf. Dionysius Thrax, Ars Grammatica 6 (p. 9 Uhlig).2 Cf. Aristotle, Poetics 20; Plato, Theaetetus 202E-203C.3 Of Tarentum. See Demosthenes 48. Cf. Aristotele, De Anima 2. 8.4 The seven referred to below (p. 95, n. 2) correspond with those in Plato, Theaetetus 203B. Cf.

Cratylus 424C; Aristotele, Historia Animalium 4. 9. 1.5 This intermediate class of semivowels was recognised by the earliest known grammarian, the

Egyptian Theuth, according to Plato, Philebus 18B.6 Or “mute”.

decessors much perplexity. Some have thought that there are only thirteen “elements” of 

speech altogether and that the other letters are formed from these; while others have

thought that there are more even than the twenty-four which we employ today. Now the

discussion of these matters belongs more properly to grammar and prosody, or even, if youlike, to philosophy. It is enough for us to assume that there are neither more nor less than

twenty-four elements of sound,1 and to describe the properties of each, beginning with thevowels.

These are seven in number2: two are short, e and o; two long, h and w; and

three common, a, i, and u. These latter can be pronounced either long or short, and

some call them common, as I have done, others “variable”. All these sounds are produced

from the windpipe, which resounds to the breath, while the mouth is formed in a simpleshape, the tongue not being busy but remaining at rest.3 But the long vowels, and thosecommon vowels that are pronounced long, take an extended and continuous column of 

 breath, while the short vowels and those which are pronounced short are uttered abruptly,

with one burst of breath and only a brief movement of the windpipe. Now the most

 powerful of these, and those which produce the most attractive sound, are the long vowels,and those common ones which are lengthened in utterance, and this is because they are

sounded for a long time, and do not arrest the strong [95-96] 

1 So Dionysius Thrax, Ars Grammatica 6 (p. 9 Uhlig).2 See note 4, p. 93.3

For a rather different account of the part played by the tongue, see W.S. Allen, Vox Graeca, p. 3.A.J. Ellis, in his book  English, Dionysian and Hellenic Pronunciation of Greek , goes some way

towards reconciling the two points of view by observing that ou)de\n pragmateuomenhj may

mean that the tongue “does not move about, though it directs the breath.”

flow of the breath.

The short vowels, or those which are pronounced short, are inferior, because they lack volume and restrict the sound.

Again, of the long vowels, the one with the best sound is a, when lengthened,1 for 

it is pronounced with the mouth open to the fullest extent and the breath forced upwards to

the palate.2 Second comes h, because it presses the sound down around the base of thetongue and not upwards, and the mouth is only moderately open.3 In the third place is w,

for in pronouncing it the mouth is rounded, the lips are contracted and the breath makes itsimpact on the edge of the lips.4 Still lower on the scale is u, for here, since a considerable

contraction takes place around the lips themselves, the sound is choked and comes out

thin.5 Last of all comes i: with this the impact of the breath is on the teeth, while the mouth

is slightly open and the lips do not amplify the sound. 6 

13

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 14/138

Of the short vowels neither is beautiful, but o is less ugly that e: for the former causes the

mouth to open wider than the latter, and receives the impact more in the region of the

windpipe.Such, then, is the nature of the vowels. The semivowels are as follows. They are

eight in number, five being simple, l, m, n, r, j, and s, and three double, z, c and y.

They are called double either [97-98] 

1

The danger of applying such rigid aesthetic values to letters is nowhere better illustrated that inthe case of vowels. For example, a is used in tragedy to depict pain (e.g. in Sophocles,  Philoctetes

732, 739).2 Cf. Allen, op cit . pp. 59-60; Dionysius Thrax, p. 10 Uhlig.3 Cf. Allen, op cit . pp. 66-7; Dionysius Thrax, ibid .4 Cf. Allen, op cit . pp. 71-5; Dionysius Thrax, ibid .5 Cf. Allen, op cit . pp. 62-6; Dionysius Thrax, ibid ; Aristophanes,  Plutus 895 and Rogers note ad 

loc.6 Cf. Allen, op cit . pp. 61-2; Dionysius Thrax, ibid .

 because they are composite, receiving their individual sound through the amalgamation of 

s and d into z,1 of k and s into c, and of p and s into y; or because they each occupy the

space of two letters in the syllables where they occur.2

Of these semivowels the double aresuperior o the simple because they are ampler than the others and seem nearer to perfectletters.3 The simpler letters are inferior because their sounds are confined within a narrower 

compass. They are severally pronounced somewhat in the following manner....

The sound [99-100] 

1 Not ds, and hence the reverse of the English z .2 Thus rendering them metrically long.3 This judgement is difficult to reconcile with the unfavorable verdict on s below. By “perfect”

letters (te//leia gra/mmata) Dionysius seems to mean combinations of consonants closing a

syllable, and lengthening it. See Ch. 20, and Roberts’s note on p. 205.

assumed by the three remaining semivowels is of a mixed character, being formed fromone of the semi-voiced letters, s, and three voiceless letters, d, k and p.

...Of the letters that are called “voiceless”, of which there are nine, three are

smooth, three rough,1 and three intermediate. The smooth letters are k, p and t, the rough

q, f , and x2; the intermediate b, g, and d.3 

1 The metaphor, as before, is derived from the different kinds of animal skin: “hairy” and “smooth”.

See Dionysius Thrax, p. 12.2 On the aspirated plosives, see Allen, pp. 16-23.3 On the intermediates, or voiced plosives, see Allen, pp. 15-23; Dionysius Thrax, pp. 12-3.

<> [104-105] 

It is from this number of letters, with the properties described, that areformed what we call syllables. Of these the ones which are made from long vowels, or 

from variable vowels when pronounced long, are long, as are those which end in a long

letter or a letter pronounced long,3 or in one of the semivowels and on the voiceless letters.4

Those which are made from a short vowel, or from one taken as short, are short. There is

14

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 15/138

more than one kind of length and shortness of syllables; some are actually longer than the

long and some shorter than the short.

3 “Long letters” would include double consonants, z, c, y. The existence in metrical practice, if not

in theory, of a provision that any letter might be “pronounced long” would account for the licence

that is apparent in Homeric verse, and which reflects an oral tradition. The rules of quantity were

much more strictly observed in drama.

Consonant (Wikipedia).

Origin of the term

The word consonant  comes from Latin cōnsonantem, accusative of  cōnsonāns (littera)

“sounding-together (letter)”, a loan translation of Greek σύμφωνον  sýmphōnon.[1]  As

originally conceived by Plato,[2]  sýmphōna were specifically the stop consonants,

described as “not being pronounceable without an adjacent vowel sound”. [3] Thus the

term did not cover continuant consonants, which occur without vowels in a large minorityof languages, for example at the ends of the English words bott le and butt on. (The final

vowel letters e and o in these words are only a product of orthography; Plato was

concerned with pronunciation.) However, even Plato’s original conception of consonant isinadequate for the universal description of human language, since in some languages, such

as the Salishan languages, stop consonants may also occur without vowels (see Nuxálk),

and the modern conception of consonant does not require cooccurrence with vowels.

References

1 Robert K. Barnhart, ed., Chambers Dictionary of Etymology, Previously published as The

 Barnhart Dictionary of Etymology, originally ©1988 The H.W. Wilson Company; Edinburgh,

reprinted 2001: Chambers Harrap Publishers Ltd., p. 210.2 Plato, Cratylus 424 C; Theaetetus 203 B.3

R.H. Robins,  A Short History of Linguistics, 2nd Ed.; ©1967 R.H. Robins, ©1979 LongmanGroup Ltd.; paper edition, 5th printing 1985, p. 23.

<...>

Consonants and vowels

Consonants and vowels correspond to distinct parts of a syllable: The most sonorous part of the syllable (that is, the part that is easiest to sing), called the  syllabic peak  or 

nucleus , is typically a vowel, while the less sonorous margins (called the onset  and coda)

are typically consonants. Such syllables may be abbreviated CV, V, and CVC, where Cstands for consonant and V stands for vowel. This can be argued to be the only pattern

found in most of the world’s languages, and perhaps the primary pattern in all of them.

However, the distinction between consonant and vowel is not always clear cut: there aresyllabic consonants and non-syllabic vowels in many of the world’s languages.

One blurry area is in segments variously called semivowels , semiconsonants, or glides.

On the one side, there are vowel-like segments which are not in themselves syllabic, but

which form diphthongs as part of the syllable nucleus, as the i in English boil  [ bˈ ɔɪl̯]. On

the other, there are approximants which behave like consonants in forming onsets, but arearticulated very much like vowels, as the y in English yes [ jˈ ɛs]. Some phonologists model

15

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 16/138

these as both being the vowel /i/, so that the English word bit would phonemically be /bit/,beet  would be /biit̯/, and  yield  would be phonemically /ii̯il̯d/. Similarly,  foot would be

/fut/,  food  would be /fuu̯d/, wood  would be /u̯ud/, and wooed  would be /u̯uu̯d/.However, there is a (perhaps allophonic) difference in articulation between these segments,

with the [j] in [ jˈ ɛs]  yes and [ jiˈ  ʲld]  yield  and the [w] of  [ wuˈ ʷd]  wooed  having more

constriction and a more definite place of articulation than the [ɪ] in [ bˈ ɔɪl̯] boil or [ bˈ ɪt] bit 

or the [ʊ] of [ f ˈ ʊt].

The other problematic area is that of  syllabic consonants, that is, segments which arearticulated as consonants but which occupy the nucleus of a syllable. This may be the case

for words such as church in rhotic dialects of English, although phoneticians differ in

whether they consider this to be a syllabic consonant, / tˈ ʃɹt̩ ʃ/, or a rhotic vowel, / tˈ ʃɝt ʃ/:Some distinguish an approximant /ɹ/ that corresponds to a vowel /ɝ/, for rural as /ˈɹɝl/ or 

[ˈɹʷɝːl ]̩; others see these as the a single phoneme, /ˈɹɹl̩/.

Other languages utilize fricative and often trilled segments as syllabic nuclei, as in Czech 

and several languages in Congo and China, including Mandarin Chinese. In Mandarin,

they are historically allophones of  /i/, and spelled that way in Pinyin. Ladefoged and

Maddieson[4]

call these “fricative vowels” and say that “they can usually be thought of assyllabic fricatives that are allophones of vowels.” That is, phonetically they are consonants, but phonemically they behave as vowels.

Many Slavic languages allow the trill [r]̩ and the lateral [l]̩ as syllabic nuclei (see Words 

without vowels), and in languages like Nuxalk, it is difficult to know what the nucleus of asyllable is (it may be that not all syllables have nuclei), though if the concept of ‘syllable’

applies, there are syllabic consonants in words like /sx̩s/ ‘seal fat’.

§

16

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 17/138

II. ACCORDING TO ARISTOTLE.

Aristotle, De Anima ii. 8 (419b 4—421a 6) (tr. J. A. Smith).

 Now let us, to begin with, make certain distinctions about sound and hearing.[5] Sound may mean either of two things (a) actual, and (b) potential, sound. There

are certain things which, as we say, ‘have no sound’, e.g. sponges or wool, others which

have, e.g. bronze and in general all things which are smooth and solid – the latter are saidto have a sound because they can make a sound, i.e. can generate actual sound betweenthemselves and the organ of hearing.

Actual sound requires for its occurrence (i, ii) two such bodies and [10] (iii) a space

 between them; for it is generated by an impact. Hence it is impossible for one body only togenerate a sound – there must be a body impinging and a body impinged upon; what

sounds does so by striking against something else, and this is impossible without a

movement from place to place.As we have said, not all bodies can by impact on one another produce sound;

impact on wool makes no sound, while the impact on [15] bronze or any body which is

smooth and hollow does. Bronze gives out a sound when struck because it is smooth; bodies which are hollow owing to reflection repeat the original impact over and over again,

the body originally set in movement being unable to escape from the concavity.

Further, we must remark that sound is heard both in air and in water, though less

distinctly in the latter. Yet neither air nor water [20] is the principal cause of sound. Whatis required for the production of sound is an impact of two solids against one another and

against the air. The latter condition is satisfied when the air impinged upon does not retreat

 before the blow, i.e. is not dissipated by it. That is why it must be struck with a suddensharp blow, if it is to sound – the movement of the whip must outrun the dispersion of the

air, just as one might get in a stroke at a heap or whirl of sand as it was traveling rapidly

 past.[25] An echo occurs, when, a mass of air having been unified, bounded, and

 prevented from dissipation by the containing walls of a vessel, the air originally struck by

the impinging body and set in movement by it rebounds from this mass of air like a ball

from a wall. It is probable that in all generation of sound echo takes place, though it isfrequently only indistinctly heard. What happens here must be analogous to what happens

in the case of light; light is always reflected – otherwise it would not be diffused and

outside what was [30] directly illuminated by the sun there would be blank darkness; butthis reflected light is not always strong enough, as it is when it is reflected from water,

 bronze, and other smooth bodies, to cast a shadow, which is the distinguishing mark by

which we recognize light.It is rightly said that an empty space plays the chief part in the production of 

hearing, for what people mean by ‘the vacuum’ is the air, which is what causes hearing,

when that air is set in movement as one continuous mass; but owing to its friability it emitsno [35] sound, being dissipated by impinging upon any surface which is not smooth.

[420a] When the surface on which it impinges is quite smooth, what is produced by the

original impact is a united mass, a result due to the smoothness of the surface with which

the air is in contact at the other end.What has the power of producing sound is what has the power of setting in

movement a single mass of air which is continuous from the impinging body up to the

organ of hearing. The organ of hearing is physically united with air,34 and because it is inair, the air inside is moved concurrently with the air outside.

17

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 18/138

Hence animals do not hear [5] with all parts of their bodies, nor do all parts admit of the

entrance of air; for even the part which can be moved and can sound has not air everywhere in it. Air in itself is, owing to its friability, quite soundless; only when its

dissipation is prevented is its movement sound. The air in the ear is built into a chamber 

 just to prevent this dissipating movement, in order that the animal may accurately [10]apprehend all varieties of the movements of the air outside. That is why we hear also in

water, viz. because the water cannot get into the air chamber or even, owing to the spirals,

into the outer ear. If this does happen, hearing ceases, as it also does if the tympanicmembrane is damaged, just as sight ceases if the membrane covering the pupil is damaged.It is also a test of deafness whether the [15] ear does or does not reverberate like a horn;

the air inside the ear has always a movement of its own, but the sound we hear is always

the sounding of something else, not of the organ itself. That is why we say that we hear with what is empty and echoes, viz. because what we hear with is a chamber which

contains a bounded mass of air.

Which is it that ‘sounds’, the striking body or the struck? Is not the answer ‘it is both, but each in a different way’? Sound is a [20]

34 i.e. it has air incorporated in its structure.

movement of what can rebound from a smooth surface when struck against it. As we have

explained35 not everything sounds when it strikes or is struck, e.g. if one needle is struck against another, [25] neither emits any sound. In order, therefore, that sound may be

generated, what is struck must be smooth, to enable the air to rebound and be shaken off 

from it in one piece.

The distinctions between different sounding bodies show themselves only in actualsound;36 as without the help of light colours remain invisible, so without the help of actual

sound the distinctions between acute and grave sounds remain inaudible. Acute and grave

are here metaphors, transferred from their proper sphere, viz. that of [30] touch, where theymean respectively (a) what moves the sense much in a short time, (b) what moves the

sense little in a long time. Not that what is sharp really moves fast, and what is grave,

slowly, but that the difference in the qualities of the one and the other movement [420b] isdue to their respective speeds. There seems to be a sort of parallelism between what is

acute or grave to hearing and what is sharp or blunt to touch; what is sharp as it were stabs,

while what is blunt pushes, the one producing its effect in a short, the other in a long time,

so that the one is quick, the other slow.

[5] Let the foregoing suffice as an analysis of sound. Voice is a kind of sound

characteristic of what has soul in it; nothing that is without soul utters voice, it being only by a metaphor that we speak of the voice of the flute or the lyre or generally of what (being

without soul) possesses the power of producing a succession of notes which differ in

length and pitch and timbre. The metaphor is based on the fact that all these differences are

found also in voice. Many animals are voiceless, e.g. all non-sanguineous animals andamong [10] sanguineous animals fish. This is just what we should expect, since voice is a

certain movement of air. The fish, like those in the Achelous, which are said to have voice,really make the sounds with their gills or some similar organ. Voice is the sound made by

an animal, and that with a special organ. As we saw, everything that makes a sound does so

 by the impact of something (a) against something else, (b) [15] across a space, (c) filled

with air; hence it is only to be expected that no animals utter voice except those which takein air.

18

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 19/138

Once air is inbreathed, Nature uses it for two different purposes, as the tongue is used both

for tasting and for articulating; in that case of the two functions tasting is necessary for theanimal’s existence (hence it is found more widely distributed), while articulate speech is a

luxury

35 419b 6, 13.36 i.e. when these bodies, e.g. the strings of a lyre, are actually sounding.

subserving its possessor’s well-being; similarly in the former case [20] Nature employs the breath both as an indispensable means to the regulation of the inner temperature of the

living body and also as the matter of articulate voice, in the interests of its possessor’s

well-being. Why its former use is indispensable must be discussed elsewhere.37

The organ of respiration is the windpipe, and the organ to which this is related as

means to end is the lungs. The latter is the part of the body by which the temperature of land animals is raised above that of all others. But what primarily requires the air drawn in

 by [25] respiration is not only this but the region surrounding the heart. That is why when

animals breathe the air must penetrate inwards.

Voice then is the impact of the inbreathed air against the ‘windpipe’, and the agent

that produces the impact is the soul resident in these parts of the body. Not every sound, as

we said, made by an [30] animal is voice (even with the tongue we may merely make asound which is not voice, or without the tongue as in coughing); what produces the impact

must have soul in it and must be accompanied by an act of imagination, for voice is a

sound with a meaning , and is not merely the result of any impact of the breath as incoughing; in voice the breath in the windpipe is used as an instrument to knock with

against the walls of the windpipe. This is confirmed by our [421a] inability to speak when

we are breathing either out or in – we can only do so by holding our breath; we make themovements with the breath so checked. It is clear also why fish are voiceless; they have no

windpipe. And they have no windpipe because they do not breathe [5] or take in air. Why

they do not is a question belonging to another inquiry.38

37  De Resp.478a 28; P.A. 642a 31—b4.38 Cf. De Resp. 474b 25-9, 476a 6-15; P.A. 669a 2-5.

Aristotle, On the Generation of Animals, IV. 7 (786b 8—788b1) (tr. Arthur Platt).

As to the voice, it is deep in some animals, high in others, in others again well-pitched andin due proportion between both extremes. Again, in some it is loud, in others small, and it

differs in smoothness and roughness, flexibility and inflexibility. We must inquire then

into the causes of each of these distinctions.

We must suppose then that the same cause is responsible for high and deep voicesas for the change which they undergo in passing from youth to age. The voice is higher in

all other animals when younger, but in cattle that of calves is deeper. We find the same

thing also in the male and female sexes; in the other kinds of animals the voice of thefemale is higher than that of the male (this being especially plain in man, for Nature has

given this faculty to him in the highest degree because he alone of animals makes use of 

speech and the voice is the material of speech), but in cattle the opposite obtains, for thevoice of cows is deeper than that of bulls.

19

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 20/138

 Now the purpose for which animals have a voice, and what is meant by “voice” and

 by “sound” generally, has been stated partly in the treatise on sensation, partly in that onthe soul. But since lowness of voice depends on the movement of the air being slow and its

highness on its being quick, there is a difficulty in knowing whether it is that which moves

or that which is moved that is the cause of the slowness or quickness. For some say thatwhat is much is moved slowly, what is little quickly, and that the quantity of the air is the

cause of some animals having a deep and others a high voice. Up to a certain point this is

well said (for it seems to be rightly said in a general way that the depth depends on acertain amount of the air put in motion), but not altogether, for if this were true it wouldnot be easy to speak both soft and deep at once, nor again both loud and high. Again, the

depth seems to belong to the nobler nature, and in songs the deep note is better than the

high-pitched ones, the better lying in superiority, and depth of tone being a sort of superiority. But then depth and height in the voice are different from loudness and

softness, and some high-voiced animals are loud-voiced, and in like manner some soft-

voiced ones are deep-voiced, and the same applies to the tones lying between theseextremes. And by what else can we define these (I mean loudness and softness of voice)

except by the large and small amount of the air put in motion? If then height and depth are

to be decided in accordance with the distinction postulated, the result will be that the sameanimals will be deep-and loud-voiced, and the same will be high-and not loud-voiced; but

this is false.

The reason of the difficulty is that the words “great” and “small”, “much” and

“little” are used sometimes absolutely, sometimes relatively to one another. Whether ananimal has a great (or loud) voice depends on the air which is moved being much

absolutely, whether it has a small voice depends on its being little absolutely; but whether 

they have a deep or high voice depends on their being thus differentiated in relation to oneanother. For if that which is moved surpass the strength of that which moves it, the air that

is sent forth must go slowly; if the opposite, quickly. The strong, then, on account of their 

strength, sometimes move much air and make the movement slow, sometimes, havingcomplete command over it, make the movement swift. On the same principle the weak 

either move too much air for their strength and so make the movement slow, or if they

make it swift move but little because of their weakness.

These, then, are the reasons of these contrarieties, that neither are all young animalshigh-voiced nor all deep-voiced, nor are all the older, nor yet are the two sexes thus

opposed, and again that not only the sick speak in a high voice but also those in good

 bodily condition, and, further, that as men verge on old age they become higher-voiced,though this age is opposite to that of youth.

Most young animals, then, and most females set but little air in motion because of 

their want of power, and are consequently high-voiced, for a little air is carried alongquickly, and in the voice what is quick is high. But in calves and cows, in the one case

 because of their age, in the other because of their female nature, the part by which they set

the air in motion is not strong; at the same time they set a great quantity in motion and soare deep-voiced; for that which is borne along slowly is heavy, and much air is borne along

slowly. And these animals set much in movement whereas the others set but little, because

the vessel through which the breath is first borne has in them a large opening and

necessarily sets much air in motion, whereas in the rest the air is better dispensed. As their age advances this part which moves the air gains more strength in each animal, so that they

change into the opposite condition, the high-voiced becoming deeper-voiced than they

were, and the deep-voiced higher-voiced, which is why bulls have a higher voice thancalves and cows. Now the strength of all animals is in their sinews, and so those in the

20

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 21/138

 prime of life are stronger, the young being weaker in the joints and sinews; moreover, in

the young they are not yet tense, and in those now growing old the tension relaxes,wherefore both these ages are weak and powerless for movement. And bulls are

 particularly sinewy, even their hearts, and therefore that part by which they set the air in

motion is in a tense state, like a sinewy string stretched tight. (That the heart of bulls is of such a nature is shown by the fact that a bone is actually found in some of them, and bones

are naturally connected with sinew.)

All animals when castrated change to the female character, and utter a voice likethat of the females because the sinewy strength in the principle of the voice is relaxed. Thisrelaxation is just as if one should stretch a string and make it taut by hanging some weight

on to it, as women do who weave at the loom, for they stretch the warp by attaching to it

what are called “laiai”. For in this way are the testes attached to the seminal passages, andthese again to the blood-vessel which takes its origin in the heart near the organ which sets

the voice in motion. Hence as the seminal passages change towards the age at which they

are now able to secrete the semen, this part also changes along with them. As this changes,the voice again changes, more indeed in males, but the same thing happens in females too,

only not so plainly, the result being what some call “bleating”“ when the voice is uneven.

After this it settles into the deep or high voice of the succeeding time of life. If the testesare removed the tension of the passages relaxes, as when the weight is taken off the string

or the warp; as this relaxes, the organ which moves the voice is loosened in the same

 proportion. This, then, is the reason why the voice and the form generally changes to the

female character in castrated animals; it is because the principle is relaxed upon whichdepends the tension of the body; not that, as some suppose, the testes are themselves a

ganglion of many principles, but small changes are the causes of great ones, not per se but

when it happens that a principle changes with them. For the principles, though small insize, are great in potency; this, indeed, is what is meant by a principle, that it is itself the

cause of many things without anything else being higher than it for it to depend upon.

The heat or cold also of their habitat contributes to make some animals of such acharacter as to be deep-voiced, and others high-voiced. For hot breath being thick causes

depth, cold breath being thin the opposite. This is clear also in pipe-playing, for if the

 breath of the performer is hotter, that is to say if it is expelled as by a groan, the note is

deeper.The cause of roughness and smoothness in the voice, and of all similar inequality,

is that the part or organ through which the voice is conveyed is rough or smooth or 

generally even or uneven. This is plain when there is any moisture about the trachea or when it is roughened by any affection, for then the voice also becomes uneven.

Flexibility depends on the softness or hardness of the organ, for what is soft can be

regulated and assume any form, while what is hard cannot; thus the soft organ can utter aloud or a small note, and accordingly a high or a deep one, since it easily regulates the

 breath, becoming itself easily great or small. But hardness cannot be regulated.

Let this be enough on all those points concerning the voice which have not been previously discussed in the treatise on sensation and in that on the soul.

Aristotle, Hist. Animal., IV. 9 (534b 29—535a 2) (tr. D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson).

Voice [fonh=] and sound [yofoj] are different from one another; and language

[dialektoj] differs from voice and sound. The fact is that no animal can give utterance to

voice except [30] by the action of the pharynx, and consequently such animals as aredevoid of lung have no voice; and language is the articulation of vocal sounds by the

21

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 22/138

tongue. Thus, the voice and larynx can emit vowel sounds; consonantal sounds are made

 by the tongue and the lips; and out of these language is composed.Consequently, animals that [535a] have no tongue at all or that have a tongue not

freely detached, have no language; although they may be enabled to make sounds by other 

organs than the tongue.

Aristotle, Hist. Animal., IV. 9 (536a 2-3) (tr. D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson).

For this creature [the dolphin] has a voice, for it is furnished with a lung and awindpipe; but its tongue is not loose, nor has it lips, so as to give utterance to an articulate

sound.

N.B. To say that the dolphin “has a voice” means that it can therefore utter vowel sounds,

“for it is furnished with a lung and a windpipe; but its tongue is not loose, nor has it lips, so

as to give utterance to an articulate sound”. But ‘an articulate sound” is a sound of voweland consonant in combination.

[Aristotle], Probl., X. 38 (895a 4-6) (ed. Loeb, tr. W. S. Hett).

Dia\ ti/ ma=llon a)/nqrwpoj polla\j fwna\ja)fi/hsin, ta\ de\ a)/lla mi/an, a)dia/forao)/nta t%= ei)/dei;

<h)\> kai\ tou= a)nqrw/pou mi/a fwnh/,a/)lla dia/lektoi pollai/;

Why does man show great variety of voice, but

other animals have only one, unless they are of 

different species?

Or has man only one voice, though many

varieties of speech?

[Aristotle], Probl., X. 39 (895a 7-14) (ed. Loeb, tr. W. S. Hett).

Dia\ ti/ de\ au(/th a)/llh, toi=j de\ a)/lloijou)/;

h)\ o(/ti oi( me\n a)/nqrwpoi gra/mmatapolla\ fqe/ggonta, tw=n de\ a)/llwn ta\me\n ou)de/n, e)/nia de\ du/o h)\ tri/atw=n [10] a)fw/nwn;

tau=ta de\ poiei= meta\ tw=n fwnhe/ntwnth\n dia/lekton.

e)/sti de\ o( lo/goj ou) to\ t$= fwn$=shmai/nein; a)lla) toi=j pa/qesin au)th=j,kai\ mh\ o(/ti a)lgei= h)\ xai/rei.

ta\ de\ gra/mmata pa/qh e)sti th=jfwnh=j.

o(moi/wj de\ o(/ te pai=dej kai\ ta\ qhri/adhlou=sin: ou) ga/r pw ou)de\ ta\ paidi/afqe/ggontai ta\ gra/mmata.

Why does this speech take different forms,

when it does not with other animals?

Is it because man can utter a number of letters,

 but of the other animals some utter none and

some only two or three consonants?

These consonants combined with vowels make

articulate speech.

 Now speech consists of conveying a meaning

not by the voice, but by certain affections of it,

and not only shows pain and pleasure.

 Now the letters are certain affections of thevoice.

Children and beasts show their meaning in the

same way, for children cannot yet pronounce

the letters.

Aristotle, De Part. Animal., II. 17 (660a 15-661a 30) (tr. William Ogle).

22

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 23/138

(Greek to be added) The tongue is placed under the vaulted roof of  

the mouth.

In land animals it presents but little diversity.

But in other animals it is variable, and this

whether we compare them as a class with such

as live on land, or compare their several specieswith each other.

It is in man that the tongue attains its greatest

degree of freedom, of softness, and of breadth;

the object of this being to render it (20) suitable

for its double function.

For its softness fits it for the perception of 

savours, a sense which is more delicate in man

than in any other animal, softness being most

impressionable by touch, of which sense taste is

 but a variety.

This same softness again, together with its

 breadth, adapts it for the articulation of letters

(= he ton grammaton diarthrosis) and for (25)

speech.

For these qualities, combined with its freedom

from attachment, are those which suit it best for 

advancing and retiring in every direction.

That this is so is plain, if we consider the case of 

those who are tongue-tied in however slight adegree.

For their speech is indistinct and lisping; that is

to say there are certain letters which they cannot

 pronounce.

In being broad is comprised the possibility of  becoming narrow; for in the great the small is

included, but not the great in the small.

What has been said explains why, among birds,

those that are most capable of pronouncingletters are such as have the broadest tongues;

and why the viviparous and sanguineous

quadrupeds, where the tongue is hard and thick 

and not free in its motions, have a very limited

vocal articulation.

Some birds have a considerable variety of notes.

23

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 24/138

These are the smaller kinds.

But it is the birds with talons that have the

 broader tongues.

All birds use their tongues to communicate with

each other.

But some do this in a greater degree than the

rest; so that in some cases it even seems asthough actual instruction were imparted from

one to another by its agency.

These, however, are matters which have already been discussed in the Researches concerning

Animals.

As to those oviparous and sanguineous animals

that live not in the air but on the earth, their 

tongue in most cases is tied down and hard, andis therefore useless for vocal purposes;

in the serpents, however, and in the lizards it is

long and forked, so as to be suited for the

 perception of savours.

So long indeed is this part in serpents, that

though small while in the mouth it can be protruded to a great distance.

In these animals it is forked and has a fine and

hair-like extremity, because of their great likingfor dainty food.

For by this arrangement they derive a twofold

 pleasure from savours, their gustatory sensation

 being as it were doubled.

Aristotle, De Gen. Animal., V. 7 (787b 10-788a 16) (ed. & tr. Loeb).

e)/sti me\n ou)=n pa=sin h( i)sxuj e)ntoi=j neu/roj, dio\ kai\ ta\ a)kma/zonta

i)sxu/ei ma=llon. a)/narqra ga\r ta\ ne/ama=llon kai\ a)/neura.

e)/ti de\ toi=j me\n ne/oij ou)/pwe)pite/tai, toi=j de\ geghrako/sin h)/dha)nei=ta h( suntoni/a. dio\ a)/mfwa)sqenh= kai\ a)du/nata pro\j th\nki/nhsin.

 Now the strength of all animals is in their sinews, and so those in the prime of life are

stronger, the young being weaker in the jointsand sinews;

moreover, in the young they are not yet tense,

and in those now growing old the tension

relaxes, wherefore both these ages are weak and

 powerless for movement.

24

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 25/138

ma/lista d) oi( tau=roi neurw/deij, kai\h( kardi/a. dio/per su/ntonon e)/xousitou=to to\ mo/rion %(= kinou=si to\pneu=ma, w(/sper xordh\n tetame/nhnneuri/nhn.

dhloi= de\ toiau/th th\n fu/sin ou)=sah( kardi/a tw=n bow=n t%= kai\ o)stou=ne)ggi/nesqai e)n e)ni/aij au)tw=n. ta\ d)

o)sta= zhtei= th\n tou= neu/rou fu/sin.

And bulls are particularly sinewy, even their 

hearts, and therefore that part by which they set

the air in motion is in a tense state, like a sinewy

string stretched tight.

(That the heart of bulls is of such a nature is

shown by the fact that a bone is actually found

in some of them, and bones are naturally

connected with sinew.)

)Ektemno/mena de\ pa/nta ei)j to\ qh=lumetaba/llei, kai\ dia\ to\ a)ni/esqai th\ni)sxu\n th\n neurw/dh e)n th= a)/rx$=o(moi/an a)fi/hsi fwmh\n toi=j qh/lesin.

h( d) a)/nesij paraplhsi/a gi/netai w(/spera)\n e)i/ tij xordh\n katatei/naj su/ntononpoi/h/seie t%= e)ca/yai ti bar/oj, oi(=ondh\ poiou=sin ai( tou\j i(stou\j u(fai/nousai.kai\ ga\r au(=tai to\n sth/monakatatei/nousi prosa/ptousai ta\j

kaloume/naj laia/j.

All animals when castrated change to the female

character, and utter a voice like that of the

females because the sinewy strength in the

 principle of the voice is relaxed.

This relaxation is just as if one should stretch a

string and make it taut by hanging some weight

onto it, as women do who weave at the loom,

for they stretch the warp by attaching to it what

are called ‘laiai’.

ou(/tw ga\r kai\ h( tw=n o)/rxewn fu/sijprosh/rthtai pro\j tou)j spermatikou\jpo/rouj, ou(=toi d) e)k th=j flebo/j h(=jh( a)rxh\ e)k th=j kardi/aj pro\j au)t%= t%= kinou=nti th\n fwnh/n.

dio/per kai\ tw=n spermatikw=n po/rwnmetaballo/ntwn pro\j th\n h(liki/an e)n $(=h)/dh du/nantai to\ spe/rma e)kkri/nein,summetaba/llei kai\ tou=to to\ mo/rion.

For in this way are the testes attached to the

seminal passages, and these again to the blood-

vessel which takes its origin in the heart near the

organ which sets the voice in motion.

Hence as the seminal passages change towards

the age at which they are now able to secrete the

semen, this part also changes along with them.

tou/to de\ metaba/llontoj kai\ h( fwnh\metaba/llei, ma=llon me\n toi=j a)/rresin,sumbai/nei de\ tau)to\ kai\ e)pi\ tw=nqhleiw=n, a)ll) a)dhlo/teron, kai\ gi/netaio(/ kalou=si/ tinej tragi/zein, o(/tana)nw/maloj $)= h( fwnh/.

meta\ de\ tau=ta kaqi/statai ei)j th\n th=je)piou/shj h(liki/aj baru/thta h)\o)cufwni/an.

a)fairoume/nwn de\ tw=n o)/rxewna)ni/etai h( ta/sij tw=n po/rwn, w(/spera)po\ th=j xordh=j kai\ tou= sth/monoja)fairoume/nou tou= ba/rouj. tou/tou d)a)nieme/nou kai\ h( a)rxh\ h( kinou=sath\n fwnh\n e)klu/etai kata\ t\n au)to\nlo/gon.

As this changes, the voice again changes, moreindeed in males, but the same thing happens in

females too, only not so plainly, the result being

what some call ‘bleating’ when the voice is

uneven.

After this it settles into the deep or high voice of 

the succeeding time of life.

If the testes are removed the tension of the

 passages relaxes, as when the weight is taken

off the string or the warp;

as this relaxes, the organ which moves the voice

is loosened in the same proportion.

dia\ me\n ou)=n tau/thn th\n ai)ti/an ta\e)ktemno/mena metaba/llei ei)j to\ qh=luth/n te fwnh\n kai\ th\n a)/llhn morfh/n,

This, then, is the reason why the voice and the

form generally changes to the female character 

in castrated animals;

25

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 26/138

dia\ to\ sumbai/nein a)ni/esqai th\na)rxh\n e)c h(=j u(pa/rxei t%= sw/matih( suntoni/a,

a)ll) ou)x w(/sper tine\j u(polama/nousinau)tou\j tou\j o)/rxeij ei)=nai su/nammapollw=n a)rxw=n. a)lla\ mikrai\metasta/seij mega/lwn ai)ti/ai gi/nontai,ou) di) au(ta/j, a)ll) o(/tan sumbai/n$

a)rxh\n summetaba/llein.

it is because the principle is relaxed upon which

depends the tension of the body;

not that, as some suppose, the testes are

themselves a ganglion of many principles, but

small changes are the causes of great ones, not

 per se but when it happens that a principle

changes with them.

ai( ga\r a)rxai\ mege/qei ou)=sai mikrai\t$= duna/mei megalai ei)si/n.

tou=to ga\r e)sti to\ a)rxh\n ei)=nai, to\au)th\n me\n ai)ti/an ei)=nai pollw=n,tau/thj d) a)/llo a)/nwqen mhqe/n.

For the principles, though small in size, are

great in potency;

this, indeed, is what is meant by a principle, that

it is itself the cause of many things without

anything else being higher than it for it to

depend upon.

§

26

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 27/138

1. On the division of voiced sound into elements and their composition into syllables.

Aristotle, Poetics ch. 20 (1456b 20-37) (Lat. William of Moerbeke; tr. B.A.M.).

Locutionis autem omnis hee sunt partes:

elementum, sillaba, coniunctio, nomen, verbum,

articulus, casus, oratio.

But of language as a whole these are the parts:

‘element’, ‘syllable’, ‘conjunction’, ‘name’,

‘verb’, ‘article’, ‘case’, ‘speech’.

 Elementum quidem igitur vox indivisibilis, non

omnis autem sed ex qua nata est fieri

intelligibilis vox

(et enim bestiarum sunt indivisibiles voces,

quarum nullam dico elementum),

huius autem partes vocalis et semivocalis et

muta.

An element , therefore, is an indivisible vocal

sound, but not every one from which an

intelligible vocal sound is naturally apt to result

(for there are indivisible vocal sounds belonging

to the beasts none of which I call an ‘element’),

 but the parts of these are vowel and semivowel

and mute [= ‘consonant’].

 Est autem vocalis quidem sine adiectione

habens vocem audibilem;

semivocalis autem cum adiectione habens

vocem audibilem, velut ‘s’ et ‘b’;

muta autem que cum adiectione secundum

quidem nullam habet vocem, cum habentibus

autem aliquam vocem facta audibilis, velut ‘g’

et ‘d’.

 Now a vowel  indeed is [an indivisible vocal

sound] having an audible sound without

application <, such as a and o>;

 but a  semi-vowel one having an audible sound

with closure, such as ‘s’ and [‘r’];

 but a mute is that which, even with application,

has of itself no sound, but is made audible

[when sounded together] with things having

sound [i.e. vowels], like ‘g’ and ‘d’.

 

Hec autem differunt figurisque oris et locis, et

asperitate et lenitate, et longitudine et brevitate,

adhuc autem acuitate et grauitate et medio;

quibus per singula in metricis congruitspeculari.

But these differ by both the shape and location

of the mouth, and by roughness or smoothness

[sc. of the breathing], and by length and

shortness, but besides by acuteness, lowness and[what is] intermediate [between these]; each of 

which it is appropriate for those learned in

metrics to consider.

Sillaba autem est vox non significativa

composita ex non vocali et vocem habente;

et enim ipsius ‘gr’ sine ipso ‘a’ sillaba et cum‘a’, puta ‘gra’.

Sed horum considerare differentias metrice est.

But a syllable is a non-significant vocal sound

composed from a non-vowel [i.e. a mute] and

[an element] having sound;

for ‘gr’ itself without ‘a’ itself <is not> asyllable, and (is a syllable) with ‘a’, for 

example, ‘gra’.7

But it pertains to the metrical art to consider the

differences of these things.

7 As I argue elsewhere, in order to avoid a manifest contradiction the text should be corrected to read, “For  g 

r without a is NOT itself is a syllable; but with a, as gra IT IS”.

27

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 28/138

2. The division of voiced sound: parallel translations.

(tr. Ingram Bywater)

A vowel is a Letter having an audible sound

without the addition of another Letter.

A semivowel, one having an audible sound by

the addition of another Letter; e.g. S and R.

A mute, one having no sound at all by itself, but becoming audible by an addition, that of one of 

the Letters which have a sound of some sort of 

their own; e.g. D and G.

(tr. S. H. Butcher)

A vowel is that which without impact of tongue

or lip has an audible sound.

A semivowel that which with such impact has

an audible sound, as S and R.

A mute, that which with such impact has byitself no sound, but joined to a vowel sound

 becomes audible, as G and D.

(tr. Theodore Buckley)

And a vowel, indeed, is that which has an

audible sound, without percussion; such as a

and o.

But a semivowel is that which has an audible

sound, with percussion; as s and r .

And a mute is that which, even with the

concurrence of the tongue, has of itself, indeed,

no sound, but becomes audible in conjunction

with the things which have a certain sound; as  g and d .

(tr. B.A.M.)

 Now a vowel  is [an indivisible vocal sound]

having an audible sound without application <,

such as a and o>;

 but a  semi-vowel one having an audible sound

with application, such as ‘s’ and ‘‘r’;

 but a mute is that which, even with application,

has of itself no sound, but is made audible

[when sounded together] with things having

sound [i.e. vowels], like ‘g’ and ‘d’.

Aristotle, Hist. Animal., IV. 9 (534b 29-33) (tr. D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson).

Voice [fonh=] and sound [yofoj] are different from one another; and language[dia/lektoj] differs from voice and sound. The fact is that no animal can give utterance to

voice except [30] by the action of the pharynx, and consequently such animals as are

devoid of lung have no voice; and language is the articulation of vocal sounds by thetongue. Thus, the voice and larynx can emit vowel sounds; consonantal sounds are made

 by the tongue and the lips; and out of these language is composed.

Aristotle, De Part. Animal., II. 16 (660a 3-10) (ed. Loeb, tr. A. L. Peck).

o( me\n ga\r lo/goj o( dia\ th=j fwnh=j e)k

tw=n gramma/twn su/gkeitai,

th=j de\ glw/tthj mh\ toiau/thj ou)/shj mhde\tw=n xeilw=n u(grw=n ou)k a)\n h)=nfqe/ggesqai ta\ plei=sta tw=n gramma/twn.

ta\ me\n ga\r th=j glw/tthj ei)si\ prosbolai/, ta\de\n sumbolai\ tw=n xeilw=n.

poi/aj de\ tau=ta kai\ po/saj kai\ ti/naj e)/xeidiafora/j, dei= punqa/nesqai para\ tw=n

 Now vocal speech consists of combinations of 

the various letters or sounds,

some of which are produced by an impact of the

tongue, others by closing the lips, and if the lips

were not supple,

or if the tongue were other than it is, the greater 

 part of these could not possibly be pronounced.

28

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 29/138

metrikw=n.

For further particulars about the various

differences between these sounds you must

consult the authorities on Metre.

3. Comparison of translations.

(tr. Perseus)

 Now speech through the voice is composed of letters,

and most of these letters would be impossible to

 pronounce were the lips not moist, nor the

tongue such as it is.

For some are formed by the closure of the lips

and others by applications of the tongue.

But of what sort and how many such differencesthese things have, must be sought from those

skilled in metrics.

(tr. A. L. Peck)

 Now vocal speech consists of combinations of the various letters or sounds,

some of which are produced by an impact of the

tongue, others by closing the lips, and if the lips

were not supple,

or if the tongue were other than it is, the greater 

 part of these could not possibly be pronounced.

For further particulars about the variousdifferences between these sounds you must

consult the authorities on Metre.

Aristotle, De Part. Animal., II. 16 (660a 3-10) (ed. Perseus; rev. B.A.M.).

o( me\n ga\r lo/goj o( dia\ th=j fwnh=j e)ktw=n gramma/twn su/gkeitai,

th=j de\ glw/tthj mh\ toiau/thj ou)/shj mhde\tw=n xeilw=n u(grw=n ou)k a)\n h)=nfqe/ggesqai ta\ plei=sta tw=n gramma/twn.

ta\ me\n ga\r th=j glw/tthj ei)si\ prosbolai/, ta\de\n sumbolai\ tw=n xeilw=n.

poi/aj de\ tau=ta kai\ po/saj kai\ ti/naj e)/xeidiafora/j,

dei= punqa/nesqai para\ tw=n metrikw=n.

 Now speech through the voice is composed of 

littera,

and most of these littera would be impossible to

 pronounce were the lips not moist, nor thetongue such as it is.

For some are formed |by applications of the

tongue,| |and others by the closure of the lips|.

But of what sort and how many such differences

these things have,

must be sought from those skilled in metrics.

Aristotle, De Part. Animal., II. 17 (660a 24-25) (tr. William Ogle).

(Greek to be added) This same softness again [sc. of the tongue],

together with its breadth, adapts it for the

articulation of letters [he ton grammaton

diarthrosis] and for (25) speech.

§

29

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 30/138

4. The division of voiced sound: an analysis.

Aristotle, Poetics ch. 20 (1456b 34-37) (tr. B.A.M.).

 e)/stin de\ tau=ta fwnh=en me\n <to\> a)/neuprosbolh=j e)/xon fwnh\n a)kousth/n,

h(mi/fwnon de\ to\ meta\ prosbolh=j e)/xon

fwnh\n a)kousth/n, oi(=on to\ S kai\ to\ R,

a)/fwnon de\ to\ meta\ prosbolh=j kaq’ au(to\me\n ou)demi/an e)/xon fwnh/n, meta\ de\ [30]tw=n e)xo/ntwn tina\ fwnh\n gino/menona)kousto/n, oi(=on to\ G kai\ to\ D.

 Now a vowel  indeed is [an indivisible vocal

sound] having an audible sound without

application8 <, such as a and o>;

 but a  semi-vowel one having an audible soundwith application, such as ‘s’ and ‘‘r’;

 but a mute is that which, even with application,

has of itself no sound, but is made audible

[when sounded together] with things having

sound [i.e. vowels], like ‘g’ and ‘d’.

an indivisible vocal sound either 

has an audible sound per se or not

involves prosbole (i.e. an ‘application’) or not

needs to be sounded with a vowel in order to be made audible or not

• has an audible sound per se without prosbole: the vowel

• has an audible sound with prosbole: the semi-vowel

• has no audible sound without  prosbole, but needs to be sounded with a vowel in

order to be made audible: the mute or consonant

Note. As we see from the  De Partibus Animalium text cited above, Aristotle understandsthe pronunciation of elementary speech sounds to involve the  prosbole or ‘application’ of 

the tongue, and the  sumbole or ‘closure’ of the lips. But from the  Poetics we see that he

draws distinctions between elements which have sound of themselves and those which do

not. But, as the reader will observe, in the following text the commentator Ingram Bywater mistakenly takes the words meta\ prosbolh=j to mean “with the addition of a vowel ”,

when the presence or absence of a vowel is manifestly an additional differentia:

Ingram Bywater,  Aristotle on the Art of Poetry, Commentary. 20. 1456b 26 a)/neu

prosbolh=j [= “without addition”], pp. 264-265.

…The general [264-265] sense, then, according to this view of  prosbolh/, will be

that the vowels are audible by themselves (a)/neu prosbolh=j); whereas the semivowels

and mutes (the consonants) require the support or addition of a vowel (meta\prosbolh=j) to make them audible.9 This was certainly the distinction in later grammar:

Dionysius Thrax p. 11 Uhlig su/mfwna de\ le/gontai o(/ti au)ta\ me\n kaq )e(auta\fwnh\n ou)k e)/xei, suntasso/mena de\ meta\ tw=n fwnhe/ntwn fwnh\na)potekei.= —Sextus Emp. Adv. math. 1. 102 a)/fwna de/ e)sti ta\ . . . meta\ tw=na)/llwn sunekfwnou/mena.—Diomedes 418 P. mutae dictae quod per se sine

adminculo vocalium non possunt enuntiari.

8 Sc. “of the tongue, and closure of the lips”; the additon of which words would bring the text into line with

Aristotle’s related observations, cited above.9 Note that Butcher correctly takes prosbolh to refer to the ‘application’ of the tongue.

30

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 31/138

Dionysius Thrax, Grammar of Dionysios Thrax (tr. Thomas Davidson), p. 328.

7. ...They are called vowels (fwnh/enta) because they form a complete sound (fwnh/) by

themselves.... They are called consonants because by themselves they have no sound, but

 produce a sound only when combined with vowels.

Priscian, Inst. gramm., xvi. 10-11 (pp. 114-115) (ed. Hertz, tr. B.A.M.).

Further, just as among the elements, some are vowels, which complete a vocalsound by themselves, but others consonants, which are unable to complete a vocal sound

without vowels, so also in words we advert to the fact that certain ones, like vowels, can be

spoken by themselves, as is especially the case with imperative verbs and nouns or  pronouns often with vocatives or adverbs, which are applied to antecedent actions or 

speeches, as when we cry “Good! Right! Well said!” to those who do or say something at

the right moment. But there are other words which, like consonants, cannot be uttered tocomplete the sense without the help of the other parts of speech (which imitate vowels in

this), like prepositions or conjunctions. For they always consignify—that is, they signify

when conjoined to the others—but by themselves they do not.10

St. Thomas Aquinas, In X Meta., lect. 3, n. 10 (tr. B.A.M.).

And likewise if all beings were tones, there would be a number of beings becauseof some subjects [there is] number itself, namely of the elements; that is, of the letters. And

consequently the vowel-letter [litera vocalis] which is first among litera, since without

them consonants could not give back a sound, would be one.11

Evidence for the pronunciation of Ancient Greek Β (beta) as [b] (from a website).12

Greek grammarians (e.g., Dionysius Thrax) divide consonants into two primary categories:

the aphona (beta, gamma, delta, kappa, pi, tau, theta, phi, and chi ), and the hemiphona

( zeta, ksi, psi, lambda, mu, nu, rho, sigma). In Aristotle’s  Poetics (1456b) the aphona (of 

which beta is a member) are described as “having contact” (= “meta prosboles”),13 but not being pronounceable without a vowel . In modern parlance we would say that aphona are

the plosives, pronounced instantaneously, while hemiphona are  fricatives, and those other 

consonants that can be pronounced continuously, without the need for a following vowel.If beta were fricative, it would be classified as one of the hemiphona.

10  Praeterea, quemadmodum elementorum alia sunt vocalia, quae per se voce perficiunt, alia consonantia,

quae sine vocalibus perficere vo- [10] cem nequent, sic etiam in dictionibus animadvertimus quasdam ad 

 similitudinem vocalium per se esse dicendas, ut in verbis maxime imperativis vel nominibus vel 

 pronominibus saepe vocativis vel adverbiis, quae adiciuntur antecedentibus actionibus vel orationibus, cum

clamamus ‘bene, recte, diserte’ ad illos, quo oportune aliquid agunt vel dicunt. aliae vero dictio- [15] nes sunt, quae ad similitudinem consonantium sine adiumento aliarum partium orationis, quae imitantur in hoc

vocales, proferri ad perfectionem sensus non possunt, ut praepositiones vel coniunctiones. eae etenim

 semper consignificant, id est coniunctae aliis significant, per se autem non.11

  et similiter si omnia entia essent toni, esset quidem numerus entium, quia aliquorum subiectorum ipsi

numero, scilicet elementorum, idest literarum. et per consequens litera vocalis quae est prima inter literas,

cum sine ea consonantes sonum reddere non possint, essent unum.12 (http://www.foundalis.com/lan/betapro.htm [11/23/07])13 It should be noted that, were the text to add sumbole to prosbole, its assigning the formation of consonants

to the ‘closure’ of the lips would be in perfect agreement with the modern view. See Buck below.

31

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 32/138

5. The division of consonants according to the foregoing:

• “consonants” properly so called: the aphona (beta, gamma, delta, kappa, pi, tau,

theta, phi, and chi): “having contact”: the plosives, which require a following

vowel

• “semi-vowels”: the hemiphona ( zeta, ksi, psi, lambda, mu, nu, rho, sigma): “not

having contact”: the fricatives, which do not require a following vowel

Carl Darling Buck, Comparative Greek and Latin Grammar . (Chicago: The University

of Chicago Press, 1933), n. 37, pp. 32-33.

SOME GENERAL FEATURES OF LINGUISTIC HISTORY

MECHANISM OF SPEECH AND CLASSIFICATION OF SPEECH SOUNDS

Of the consonants some are formed with complete closure, by which the stream of 

air is wholly blocked, followed by a sudden release of the breath, as, for example,  p withclosure of the lips. These are called “stops” (“explosives”, “mutes”). The nasal consonants

are stops, so far as concerns the passage of the breath [32-33] through the mouth (the

closure is the same for m as for  p), but the flow of breath through the nose is continuous.The release may be followed by an added puff of breath, as in uphill . Then we have

aspirated stops (aspirates). Our English initial stops in words like  pen are distinctly

aspirated by comparison with the French.Others are formed with close approximation (not complete closure) and resulting

friction, as  f  with friction between the lower lip and upper teeth. These are called

“fricatives” (“spirants”).

6. The division of consonants according to Buck:

• The “stops” or “explovises” or “mutes”: “Of the consonants some are formed

with complete closure, by which the stream of air is wholly blocked, followed by a

sudden release of the breath, as, for example,  p with closure of the lips. These are

called “stops” (“explosives”, “mutes”). The nasal consonants are stops, so far asconcerns the passage of the breath through the mouth (the closure is the same for m

as for  p), but the flow of breath through the nose is continuous.”

• The “fricatives” or “spirants”: “Others are formed with close approximation (not

complete closure) and resulting friction, as f with friction between the lower lip andupper teeth. These are called “fricatives” (“spirants”).”

§

See also:

Poetics Chapter 20: The Elements of Language (Papers In Poetics 9)

32

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 33/138

7. Supplement on the discovery of the consonant: “Roman Law, the Evolution of Ideas, and Writing Technologies.” Thomas Vesting, Frankfurt am Main, pp. 18-20.14

4. Writing technologies

(2) These are very intricate and highly contested questions in the specialized literature.

However, for various reasons which I try to explore more precisely in my book, I have a

lot of sympathy for a position mainly introduced by I. Gelb in his book “A Study of Writing”, first published in 1952 with the subtitle “The Foundations of Grammatology”.

(3) If we follow Gelb, the introduction of the Greek vocalic system can and should not be

regarded as a new and original creation. Its Semitic origin is beyond any doubt. Even anuninitiated epigrapher, Gelb stated, cannot fail to observe the identity or great similarity of 

form in the signs of the Greek alphabet and those of the Semitic writings.

(4) However, for Gelb the Greek alphabet makes a difference. Compared with its

forerunners, it represents an evolutionary jump in the history of writing. It is the first

writing system that really isolated and by that step generated the consonant as asingle sign of language. The word “sign” here is of great importance. Why? Because, the

consonants do not exist in oral speech.15 The consonants by strict definition are themselves

‘dumb’, ‘mute’, ‘unpronounceable’, aphona, aphtonga, as Plato sometimes said. Or, to put

it in another way: They are called “con-sonants’,  sum-phona, because they only sound incompany with. The consonant therefore has its identity only as a

19

visual sign. Or, to slightly modify an observation Gilbert Ryle made in 1960: While

phonemes like b and c are not phonetic atoms, characters like b and x are graphicatoms (57). That is, in a nutshell, why Gelb considers the Greek alphabet to be the

first true and full alphabet, while all other so-called alphabets for him actually

remained cases of syllabic writing. “If the alphabet is defined as a system of signs

expressing single sounds of speech, then the first alphabet which can justifiably be socalled is the Greek alphabet.” (I. Gelb, A Study of Writing, 1952/1965, p.166)

(5) Because of Gelb’s lucid reconstruction of the history of writing, many scholars like, for example, the classicist Eric Havelock, in dozens of publications traced the capacity for 

abstract analysis back to the emergence of the Greek alphabet. For Havelock, it was

exactly this difference between alphabetic writing and its forerunners that could help us tounderstand the emergence of epistemic knowledge in Greek philosophy and dialectics. And

for Havelock the linkage between the Greek alphabet and abstract thinking was exactly

that the writing technology confronted its observers to written abstractions and by that togo beyond the empiricism of orality. “The Greek system got beyond empiricism, by

abstracting the nonpronounceable, nonperceptible elements contained in the syllables.

14 (www.jura.uni-frankfurt.de/fb/fb01/ifoer1/vesting/Dokumente/online-pub/Roman_Law-Vortrag.

 pdf [2/5/08])15 That consonants are ‘mute’ follows from the fact that they cannot be pronounced without a following

vowel sound, just as one cannot make a ‘b’ sound without saying ‘buh’ or some such thing, a state of affairs

 presumably underlyying the claim that they “do not exist in oral speech”—that is, in isolation.

33

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 34/138

We now style these elements’”con-sonants’ ( sum-phona, …). Their creation separated out

an unpronounceable component of linguistic sound and gave it a visual entity.” 11

(6) As I said, I have a lot of sympathy with this standpoint, but I have not fully made up

my mind yet. Nevertheless, for me one thing seems to be clear: Gelb’s and Havelock’stheory have very strong force, not at least because they have been and still are proven

again and again tenable (for instance, in a newer linguistic publication by Ch. Stetter).

These publications especially confirm that alphabetic-writing cannot fully be understood ina concept of representation: The mere consonant, the phoneme as such, is a discovery of script. It does not represent an entity of oral language.

11 E. Havelock, The muse learns to write, 1986, p. 60. [N.B. For the complete excerpt, see below.]

20

(7) If we thus take this path of reconstruction for granted, then it becomes very clear

why in Plato’s late dialogues considerations about diaeresis are so often connected

with considerations about the division and recombination of letters and syllables,nouns and verbs; and why in Plato considerations about divisions are also connected

with that entity Plato calls “something great and fair and complete”: the proposition(Cratylus, 425 c). The paradigm for epistemic knowledge is the study of grammar(téchne grammatiké ), but the study of grammar would have never been likely to

emerge without the invention of Greek alphabetic writing. So with the adaptation of 

epistemic knowledge, Roman jurisprudence, for the first time, made sense of a new type of 

knowledge in the field of law that was invented in Greece. And with the import of epistemic knowledge Roman jurisprudence adapted a type of knowledge that’s emergence

was intrinsically tied together with the evolution of a new medium: Greek alphabetic

writing.

Eric Havelock, The Muse Learns to Write: Reflections on Orality and Literacy From

 Antiquity to the Present (Yale University Press: 1986), p. 60.

It is easy to see why pre-Greek systems never got further than the syllable. This

‘piece’ of linguistic sound is actually pronounceable and so empirically perceptible. The

consonants by strict definition are by themselves ‘dumb,’ ‘mute,’ ‘unpronounceable’

(aphona, aphthonga —Plato’s terms, borrowed he says from previous sources). The Greek system got beyond empiricism by abstracting the nonpronounceable, nonperceptible16 

elements contained in the syllables. We now style these elements ‘con-sonants’ ( sum-

 phona, the more accurate Greek term replacing aphona, because the are ‘sounded incompany with’). Their creation separated out an unpronounceable component of linguistic

sound and gave it visual identity. The Greeks did not ‘add vowels’ (a common

misconception: vowel signs had already shown up in Mesopotamian Cuneiform andLinear B) but invented the (pure) consonant. In so doing, they for the first time

supplied our species with a visual representation of linguistic noise that was both

economical and exhaustive: a table of atomic elements which by grouping themselves in

an inexhaustible variety of combinations can with reasonable accuracy represent any actuallinguistic noise. The invention also supplied the first and last instrument perfectly

constructed to reproduce the range of previous orality.

16 One may presume that a consonant is called ‘nonperceptible’ for the reasons adduced above.

34

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 35/138

8. On Gelb and the systems of writing.

Gelb, I J. A Study of Writing . 2nd Ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963.17

Gelb began a new phase in the study of writing systems by introducing “Grammatology”, ascientific approach to the study of writing which borrows methodology from linguistics

(for a good history of the study of writing systems, see Daniels, “The Study of Writing

Systems” in The World’s Writing Systems, ed Peter T Daniels and William Bright.(Oxford, 1996), 3-18). Gelb presents a basic view of the evolution of writing fromnarrative art to symbol to pictographic system. Next, the leap of phonetization allows the

correspondence of symbols with either words or sounds. From this developed syllabic

systems and finally the alphabet. Gelb has been criticized for over-systematizing in his principles of uniform development and economy (see Daniels, “Fundamentals of 

Grammatology”). The principle of uniform development states that writing always

develops from logographic to syllabic to alphabetic; thus Gelb argued that the earlyWest-Semitic scripts were not alphabetic but syllabic since the later Ethiopian syllabic

script could not have developed from a true alphabetic script. Just as certain cuneiform

signs can indicate a consonant plus the full range of vowels (e.g., wi, we, wa, wu), hemaintained that the West-Semitic letters actually indicated a consonant plus an unmarked

vowel. The matres lectionis then function as phonetic complements to mark the proper 

vowel. Only when the Greek system developed individual vowel letters was a true alphabet

created.

DANIELS Peter T. “Fundamentals of Grammatology”, JAOS 110/4, 727-731.

In this short article Daniels responds to his teacher IJ Gelb’s suggestion that the early

West-Semitic scripts are not alphabets but syllabaries similar to the Ethiopic script (see

Gelb,  A Study of Writing , 2nd Ed (1963)). He argues that Gelb’s “principal of unidirectional development” (i.e., scripts always progress from logographic to syllabic to

alphabetic) was an over-generalization. Instead, he suggests that the standard three-fold

typology of writing systems should be expanded to include the “abjad” and the “abugida”

which represent the Phoenician and Ethiopic scripts respectively. The “abjad” does notdenote syllables, but only the individual consonants, while the “abugida” uses a base

symbol to denote the consonant which is appended with a vowel mark. Daniels does notsee the great intellectual leap in script development as the creation of vowel letters,

but the isolation of the sound stream into phonological segments smaller than the

syllable.

Richard Sproat, Review of Daniels & Bright, The World’s Writing Systems.

LINGUIST List 7.400. Sat Mar 16 1996 (excerpt).18

The book is divided into thirteen main parts. In the first part, Daniels introduces the field

of grammatology, giving a brief history, and a broad typology of writing systems. The

typology includes some familiar terms:

17 (http://balshanut.wordpress.com/2007/08/05/gelb-ij-a-study-of-writing-2nd-ed-chicago-university-

of-chicago-press-1963/ [2/6/08])18

(http://www.linguistlist.org/issues/7/7-400.html [2/6/08])

35

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 36/138

“logosyllabary” for writing systems like Chinese where the individual characters of the

script simultaneously represent both morphemes and syllables; “syllabary”, where theindividual characters represent syllables (or at least CV morae, following on Poser’s 1993

LSA presentation, which is lamentably unavailable in written form); and “alphabet”,

where the individual characters represent phonemes. Less familiar terms are: “abjad”(“formed from the first letters of the most widespread example, the Arabic script, in their 

historic order”), where the basic characters of the script denote consonants (and only

 peripherally, vowels), typical examples being Semitic scripts as used for Semitic languages(adaptations of Semitic scripts to other languages such as Hebrew for Yiddish, Arabic for Uyghur or indeed Phoenician for Greek, often end up functioning as alphabets); and

“abugida” (derived from the first four vowels and first four consonants of the traditional

order of the Ethiopic script) where the characters denote consonants with a designatedinherent vowel, and other vowels are denoted by diacritics on the basic consonant symbols.

Examples of abugidas are Indian and Indian-derived scripts; and of course Ethiopic.

Finally there is a “featural” script, namely Korean Hankul, where “the shapes of thecharacters correlate with distinctive features of the segments of the language” (cf. Sampson

1985). It is actually not clear from the above definition in what sense Daniels means that

Hankul is featural, and thus constitutes a separate type of script. There is no question thatthat some of the basic Hankul symbols are derived graphically from aspects of vocal tract

shapes, and that they are combined to form the basic letters of the script in a somewhat

compositional way. On the other hand it is certainly not the case that Hankul represents

features in the same sense as a phonologist represents them in a distinctive feature matrix(DeFrancis 1989). Indeed, Koreans (at least non-linguistically informed Koreans) evidently

think of Hankul as being composed of segmental letters (again, DeFrancis 1989), so it may

 perhaps make the most sense to view Hankul as being an intelligently constructed alphabet. Note that Daniels’ terms “abjad” and “abugida” are only somewhat consistently used in

contributions to this volume: the term “alphasyllabary” (which is Bright’s preferred term)

is often used instead of “abugida”.

9. Supplement: On the origin of writing.

Carl Darling Buck, Comparative Greek and Latin Grammar . (Chicago: The University

of Chicago Press, 1933), n. 44, pp. 42-43.

WRITING AND ITS RELATION TO SPEECH

44. Writing has its ultimate origin in art, in the crude pictures which spring fromthe impulse to artistic expression in prehistoric man.19  The use of pictures to convey

messages or record events was adventitious, and picture writing arose independently in

different parts of the earth. It was extensively employed by the American Indians and was

understood by those of different tribes, being quite independent of the spoken language.

For in pure picture writing the picture stands for an object or idea, not the word forit in any particular language. So long as the relation holds, whether or not thepictorial form remains obvious, it is an ideogram. But the sign may come to be felt as

representing the familiar word for the idea, and the ideogram becomes a phonogram.

Thus a crude picture of the sun in the heavens will convey the same idea, no matter 

whether one’s own word for is  sun,  sol ,, h(/lioj, or what not. It may be conventionalized

19 To this remark one should compare Aristotle’s remarks in the Poetics on the causes of imitation.

36

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 37/138

and lose all resemblance to the object, and still remain an ideogram for the sun. When it

comes to be felt as representing the group of sounds making up the word for it in a givenlanguage, namely, if we take the English word for illustration, [svn], it is now a

 phonogram. But as a pure phonogram for [svn] it is ambiguous, as it may represent

sun or son. To determine which, one must combine with the phonogram a determinativeor classifier, [42-43] for example a “heavenly body” determinative for  sun or a “human

 being” determinative for  son.20 Such a combination of phonograms and determinatives is

characteristic of Egyptian hieroglyphics, Assyrian cuneiform, and Chinese writing.The evolution of the phonogram from the ideogram is the most significant step inthe history of writing, the one which first brings writing into relation to speech. The

syllabary and alphabet are successive simplifications of the phonogram (but the imaginary

illustration of a phonogram chosen above, [svn] would be already adapted to a syllabarysystem). The simplified syllabaries like the Cyprian with signs for the single

consonant plus vowel, and eventually the alphabets, developed mostly according to

the acrophonic principle, as if the phonogram for [svn] became the sign for [sv] andthen for [s].

The distinction between ideogram and phonogram, syllabary or alphabet, must not

 be confused with that of the external form of the writing, namely pictorial or linear (inwhich the pictorial origin is no longer obvious). The Egyptian hieroglyphics continued

 pictorial in form, but certain of the pictures constituted an alphabet of 24 letters, which was

employed as early as 3000 B.C. Conversely Assyrian and Chinese writing are linear in

form, but not alphabetic.

§

20On this matter, compare the following: Porphyry, Commentary on the Categories (In:  Porphyry: On

 Aristotle’s Categories. Translated by Steven K. Strange (Ithaca, New York, 1992), pp. 39-40: “Q. Why does

he begin with homonyms {= equivocals}, not with synonyms {= univocals}, if synonyms {univocals} are

things that share both the same name and the same account, and something sharing both its account and its

name would be a clearer case than something that has only [39-40] its name in common with something else?

A. I claim that Aristotle discusses homonyms {equivocals} first because he holds that being is a homonym{equivocal} and because predications (kategoriai) are homonymously {equivocally} said to be predications

of that of which they are predicated.Q. Why does he not discuss homonymy {equivocity} before discussing homonyms {equivocals}, given

that ‘homonymy’{equivocity} is a word, whereas homonyms {equivocals} are things, and you claim that he

is primarily concerned in this treatise with words, not with things?

A. Because what produces homonymy {equivocity} in words is not the character of the expression itself,

 but rather things are found to be different and in no way have anything in common yet acquire one and the

same expression as their name. Until it is recognised that a word applies to a number of things that do not

share the same account, there cannot be homonymy {equivocity}”.

37

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 38/138

III. ON PHONE (‘VOICE’) AND PSOPHOS (‘SOUND’) IN SUM.

Aristotle, De Anima II. 8 (420a 19-27) (tr. J. A. Smith).

Which is it that ‘sounds’, the striking body or the struck? Is not the answer ‘it is both, but each in a different way’? Sound is a [20] movement of what can rebound from a

smooth surface when struck against it. As we have explained35 not everything sounds when

it strikes or is struck, e.g. if one needle is struck against another, [25] neither emits anysound. In order, therefore, that sound may be generated, what is struck must be smooth, toenable the air to rebound and be shaken off from it in one piece.

 Aristotle, De Anima II. 8 (420b 5—421a 5) (tr. J. A. Smith).

[5] Let the foregoing suffice as an analysis of sound. Voice is a kind of soundcharacteristic of what has soul in it; nothing that is without soul utters voice, it being only

 by a metaphor that we speak of the voice of the flute or the lyre or generally of what (being

without soul) possesses the power of producing a succession of notes which differ inlength and pitch and timbre. The metaphor is based on the fact that all these differences are

found also in voice. Many animals are voiceless, e.g. all non-sanguineous animals and

among [10] sanguineous animals fish. This is just what we should expect, since voice is a

certain movement of air. The fish, like those in the Achelous, which are said to have voice,really make the sounds with their gills or some similar organ. Voice is the sound made by

an animal, and that with a special organ. As we saw, everything that makes a sound does so

 by the impact of something (a) against something else, (b) [15] across a space, (c) filledwith air; hence it is only to be expected that no animals utter voice except those which take

in air. Once air is inbreathed, Nature uses it for two different purposes, as the tongue is

used both for tasting and for articulating; in that case of the two functions tasting isnecessary for the animal’s existence (hence it is found more widely distributed), while

articulate speech is a luxury

35 419b 6, 13.36 i.e. when these bodies, e.g. the strings of a lyre, are actually sounding.

subserving its possessor’s well-being; similarly in the former case [20] Nature employs the breath both as an indispensable means to the regulation of the inner temperature of the

living body and also as the matter of articulate voice, in the interests of its possessor’s

well-being. Why its former use is indispensable must be discussed elsewhere.37

37  De Resp.478a 28; P.A. 642a 31—b4.

The organ of respiration is the windpipe, and the organ to which this is related asmeans to end is the lungs. The latter is the part of the body by which the temperature of 

land animals is raised above that of all others. But what primarily requires the air drawn in

 by [25] respiration is not only this but the region surrounding the heart. That is why whenanimals breathe the air must penetrate inwards.

Voice then is the impact of the inbreathed air against the ‘windpipe’, and the agentthat produces the impact is the soul resident in these parts of the body.

38

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 39/138

 Not every sound, as we said, made by an [30] animal is voice (even with the tongue we

may merely make a sound which is not voice, or without the tongue as in coughing); what produces the impact must have soul in it and must be accompanied by an act of 

imagination, for voice is a sound with a meaning , and is not merely the result of any impact

of the breath as in coughing; in voice the breath in the windpipe is used as an instrument toknock with against the walls of the windpipe. This is confirmed by our [421a] inability to

speak when we are breathing either out or in – we can only do so by holding our breath; we

make the movements with the breath so checked. It is clear also why fish are voiceless;they have no windpipe. And they have no windpipe because they do not breathe [5] or takein air. Why they do not is a question belonging to another inquiry.38

38 Cf. De Resp. 474b 25-9, 476a 6-15; P.A. 669a 2-5.

Aristotle, Hist. Animal., IV. 9 (534b 29-33) (tr. D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson).

Voice [fonh=] and sound [yofoj] are different from one another; and language

[dia/lektoj] differs from voice and sound. The fact is that no animal can give utterance to

voice except [30] by the action of the pharynx, and consequently such animals as aredevoid of lung have no voice; and language is the articulation of vocal sounds by the

tongue. Thus, the voice and larynx can emit vowel sounds; consonantal sounds are made

 by the tongue and the lips; and out of these language is composed.

1. The difference between logos and lexis.

Diogenes Laertius,  Lives of the Eminent Philosophers 7.57 (tr. A. A. Long & D. N.

Sedley; rev. B.A.M.; Gr. added from ed. R. D. Hicks).

Vocal sound [fwnh\] and language [le/cij] differ, because vocal sound [fwnh\]

may be merely noise [h)=xo/j], but only language is articulate [e)/narqron mo/non].And language is different from speech, because speech is always significant, but languagecan lack significance [a)/shmoj], such as blituri, whereas speech is not so at all.

Furthermore, saying [le/gein] is different from uttering [or ‘pronouncing’, profe/resqai].For vocal sounds are uttered [or ‘pronounced’], but it is things [ pra/gmata] which aresaid [le/getai] – they, after all, are actually sayables [lekta\].

The  Suda, Lambda 658, s.v.  Logos [‘speech’] (ed. The Suda On Line; tr. B.A.M.,

based on Marcelo Boeri).

Speech [lo/goj] is significative vocal sound [fwnh\ shmantikh/], derived fromthought [a)po dianoi/aj e)kpempome/nh]. It has two hundred meanings. But language

[le/cij] differs from speech. For language can be meaningless, such as ‘blituri’, while

speech cannot in any way be meaningless. Saying [le/gein], too, differs from uttering [or ‘pronouncing’, profe/resqai]; for vocal sounds are uttered, but things [pra/gmata],

which are sayable [lekta\], are spoken [le/getai].

39

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 40/138

2. Some dictionary definitions taken from Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott,  A

Greek-English Lexicon.

psoph-os , ho,

A.  noise (prop. of one thing striking against another, Arist.de An.420a21; or of 

insects, which produce a sound, but not by the larynx, Id. HA535a28; opp. phônê,Id.de An.420b29,  HA535b31, al.; psophos monon [to sigma] Pl. Tht.203b, cf.

 Lg. 669d , Aristox. ap. D.H.Comp.14); first in h.Merc. 285 , ater psophou; glôssês ps.

E.  HF 229; philêmatôn S.  Fr.537 ; psophoi anemôn Pl.  R.397a; of rolling stones,X.  An.4.2.4; of footsteps, psophôi tôi ek tou prosienai autous antipatagountos touanemou  Th.3.22, cf.  Hdt.7.218; of  knocking  at a door, Ar.  Ra.604 (lyr.),

Pl. Smp.212c; cf. psopheô 11; crash of a falling building, Th.4.115; also of musical

instruments, lôtou, kitharas, E.  Ba.687, Cyc. 443 ; of a trumpet, Paus.2.21.3.2. mere sound, noise, tou sou ps. ouk an strapheiên your  noise will

never turn me, S.  Aj.1116; kenos ps. E.  Rh.565 ; eudoxia psophos esti

mainomenôn anthrôpôn Diog. ap.Arr. Epict.1.24.6; psophoi mere sounds, of high-sounding words or names, ho mê phronôn . .

 psophois halisketai Men.737 , cf. Alciphr.2.3, Luc.  DMeretr.15.3,

Arr. Epict.2.6.19; psophou pleôs, of Aeschylus, Ar.  Nu. 1367; ho ps.tôn rhêmatôn, of his language, Id.  Ra.492.

phôn-ê , hê,A.  sound, tone, prop., the sound of the voice, whether of men or animals with lungs

and throat (hê phônê psophos tis estin empsukhou Arist.de An.420b5 , cf. 29,

 HA535a27, PA664b1); opp. phthongos (v. phthongos 11):I. mostly of human beings,  speech, voice, utterance, ph. arrêktos Il.2.490;

ateirea ph. 17.555; ph. de hoi aither’ hikanen, of  Ajax‘ battle-cry, 15.686; of 

the battle-cry of an army, Trôôn kai Akhaiôn . . ph. deinon aüsantôn 14.400: pl., of the cries of market-people, X. Cyr.1.2.3; ho tonos tês ph. Id. Cyn.6.20,

D.18.280,  Aeschin.3.209; oxeia, barutera, leia, trakheia ph., Pl. Ti.67b; ph.

malakê Ar.  Nu.979 (anap.); miara, anaidês, Id.  Eq.218,638: with Verbs,

 phônên rhêxai Hdt.1.85,  Ar.  Nu.357 (anap.); ph. hienai Hdt.2.2, 4.23,Pl.  Phdr.259d, etc.; ph. hêsei  E.  HF 1295; proïesthai Aeschin.2.23; arthroun

X.  Mem.1.4.12; diarthrôsasthai Pl.  Prt.322a; enteinasthai  Aeschin.2.157; ph.

eparei D.19.336; phônêi with his voice, aloud, Il.3.161 , Pi.  P.9.29; eipe têi phônêi ta aporrêta Lys.6.51; dia zôsês phônês Anon.Geog . Epit .1p.488M.;

miai ph. with one voice, Luc.  Nigr.14; apo phônês, c. gen., dictated by . . ,

Choerob.in Thd.1.103 tit., Marin. in Euc.Dat. p.234 M., Olymp. in Grg. p.1 N., Pall. in Hp.2.1 D.: pl., hai ph. the notes of the voice,  Pl. Grg.474e; 

skhêmasi kai phônais  Arist.  Rh.1306a32: prov., phônêi horan, of a blind

man, S. OC 138 (anap.); pasan, to legomenon, ph. hienta, i.e. using everyeffort, Pl.  Lg.890d, cf.  Euthd. 293a ; pasas aphienai phônas Id.  R.475a,

D.18.195; phônas aprepeis proïento PTeb. 802.15  (ii B. C.).

2. the cry of animals, as of swine, dogs, oxen, Od.10.239, 12.86,396; 

of asses,  Hdt.4.129; of the nightingale,  song, Od.19.521; anthrôpos pollas phônas aphiêsi, ta de alla mian Arist. Pr.895a4 .

3.  any articulate sound, opp. inarticulate noise ( [psophos] ), ph.

kôkumatôn S.  Ant.1206 ; hôsper phônês ousês kata ton aera pollakiskai logou en têi phônêi Plot.6.4.12: stoikheion esti ph. adiairetos

40

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 41/138

Arist.  Po.1456b22; also esp. of  vowel sound, opp. to that of 

consonants,  Pl. Tht.203b, Arist. HA535a32; in literary criticism, of  sound, opp. meaning, Phld. Po.5.20 (pl.), [p. 1968] 21.

4. of  sounds made by inanimate objects, mostly Poet., kerkidos ph.

S.  Fr.595; suringôn E. Tr.127 (lyr.); aulôn Mnesim.4.56 (anap.); rarein early Prose, organôn phônai Pl.  R.397a ; freq. in LXX, hê ph. tês

salpingos LXX  Ex.20.18 ; ph. brontês ib.  Ps. 103(104).7 ; hê ph.

autou hôs ph. hudatôn pollôn Apoc. 1.15  .5. generally,  sound, defined as aêr peplêgmenos, plêgê aeros, Zeno Stoic.1.21, Chrysipp.ib.2.43.

II.  faculty of speech, discourse, ei phônên laboi S.  El.548 ; pareskhe phônên

tois aphônêtois tina Id. OC 1283 .2.  language, hdt.4.114, 117; ph. anthrôpêïê Id.2.55 ; agnôta ph.

 barbaron A.  Ag.1051 ; phônên hêsomen Parnêsida Id. Ch.563 , cf.

E. Or.1397 (lyr.), Th.6.5, 7.57, X. Cyn.2.3,  Pl.  Ap.17d, etc.; tôn barbarôn prin mathein tên ph. Id. Tht.163b; kata tên Attikên tên

 palaian ph. Id. Cra. 398d , cf. 409e.

III.  phrase, saying, tên Simônidou ph. Id.  Prt. 341b ; hê tou Sôkratous ph.Plu.2.106b, cf. 330f, etc.; of   formulae, stoikheiômata kai ph.

Epicur. Ep.1p.4U., cf. Sent.Vat.41 (= Metrod.  Fr.59); hai skeptikai ph.

S.E. P.1.14 , cf. Jul.Or.5.162b, etc.IV. report, rumour, LXXGe.45.16.

b. message, Sammelb.7252.21 (iii/iv A. D.).

V. loud talk, bragging, Epicur.Sent.Vat. 45.

phthong-os , ho (both Poet. and Prose),

A.  any clear, distinct sound, esp. voice of men,  Il.5.234, etc.; of the Sirens,Od.12.41,159; phthongôi eperkhomenai 18.199 ; ph. araion oikois A.  Ag.237 (lyr.);

goôn ouk asêmones ph. S. OC 1669 ; ph. oikeiou kakou voice, telling  of . . ,

Id.  Ant.1187; ton Haimonos ph. ib.1218, cf. 1214; of birds, alektruonôn ph.

Thgn.864 ; agnôta . . ph. ornithôn S.  Ant.1001 , cf.  424; phthongos out’ ornithônoute thalassês E.  IA9 (anap.); kunôn kai probatôn kai orneôn Pl.  R.397a .

2.  speech, Hellados phthongon kheousan A. Th.73; ph. emmetros,

opp. peza, poetical  speech, Phld. D.3.13; utterance, saying,Trag.Adesp.417.

II. generally,  sound, anemôn Simon.37.11; daimonos pedarsiou . . pterôtos

 ph. Ar.  Av.1198 (= Trag.Adesp.47); phônês men ou, phthongou demetekhonta tinos, of semi-vowels, Pl.  Phlb. 18c, cf. Arist. Aud.801b2, 804b9;

aneu phthongou kai êkhês Pl. Ti.37b , cf. Epicur. Ep.1p.32U.; eis tous ph. kai

tas sullabas Pl. Cra.389d , cf. Plu. Alex.27, Gal.15.6.2. of musical  sounds, lôtos phthongon keladei E.  El.716 (lyr.); luras

Pl.  Lg.812d, etc., cf. phthongous alurous thrênoumen Alex. 162.6

(anap.).b. pl., notes on a musical instrument;  strings of lyre,D.Chr.10.19; stops of flute, Philostr.VA5.21; cf. Corn. ND14.

dialekt-os , hê,

41

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 42/138

A.  discourse, conversation, Hp. Art.30; theois pros anthrôpous Pl. Smp.203a;

discussion, debate, argument, Id. Tht.146b; opp. eris, Id.  R.454a.2. common language, talk, d. hê pros allêlous Arist.  Po.1449a26; hê

eiôthuia d. Id.  Rh. 1404b24 .

II.  speech, language, Ar. Fr.685; kainên d. lalôn Antiph. 171; d. amniou,opp. ta endon drakontos, Hermipp.3; articulate speech, language, opp.

 phônê, Arist. HA535a28; tou anthrôpou mia phônê, alla dialektoi pollai

Id. Pr.895a6 ; but also, spoken, opp. written language, D.H.Comp.11.2.  the language of a country, Plb.1.80.6, D.S.5.6, etc.: esp. dialect,as Ionic, Attic, etc., Diog.Bab.Stoic.3.213, D.H.Comp.3, S.E. M.1.59,

Hdn.Gr.2.932; also, local word or expression, Plu. Alex.31.III. way of speaking, accent, D.37.55.

2. pl., modes of expression, Epicur. Ep.1p.24U.

IV.  style, panêgurikê, poiêtikê d., D.H.Comp.23,21: esp.  poetical diction,

Phld. Po. 2 Fr.33, al.V. of musical instruments, quality, ‘idiom’, Arist. de An.420b8.

dialekt-ikos , ê, on,

A. conversational, khoros Demetr. Eloc.167 .

2. d. organa organs of articulate speech, opp. phônêtika, Gal.16.204.II.   skilled in dialectic, ho erôtan kai apokrinesthai epistamenosPl. Cra.390c ; ê kai d. kaleis ton logon hekastou lambanonta tês ousias;

Id.  R.534b ; dialectical,  Arist.  Metaph.995b23; d. sullogismos

Id.Top.100a22 ; pros tous d., title of work by Metrodorus, D.L.10.24, cf.Phld. Rh.1.279 S., al.

III. hê dialektikê (sc. tekhnê) dialectic, discussion by question and answer,

invented by Zeno of  Elea, Arist. Fr.65;  philosophical method, hôsper thrinkos tois mathêmasin hê d. epanô keitai Pl.  R.534e: to -kon Id. Sph. 253e; 

 peri -kês, title of work by Cleanthes, D.L.7.174.

2. the logic of probabilities, hê d. peirastikê peri hôn hê philosophia

gnôristikê Arist.  Metaph.1004b25, cf. Rh. 1354a1 .IV. Adv. -kôs dialectically, Pl.  Phlb.17a, etc.; for the sake of argument, opp.

kat’ alêtheian, Arist. Top.105b31, cf. de An.403a2; by argument on general 

 principles, opp. scientifically, Phld. Rh.2.134 S.,  Mus. p.89 K.: Comp.-ôteron Pl.  Men. 75d ; more logically, Dam. Pr.97.

This text is based on the following book(s):

Henry George Liddell. Robert Scott. A Greek-English Lexicon. revised and augmented

throughout by. Sir Henry Stuart Jones. with the assistance of. Roderick McKenzie. Oxford.Clarendon Press. 1940.

ISBN: 0198642261

§

42

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 43/138

3. Supplement: Aristotle’s teaching on sound and voice according to John Philoponus,as excerpted by the Suda.

(a) The Suda, s.v. Phônê [‘voice’; ‘vocal sound’] Adler number: phi,653 (In. The Suda

Online, tr. Marcelo Boeri; slightly rev. B.A.M.).

Phônê: hoti eidos hê phônê tou psophou.

esti de phônê plêxis aeros, ê aêr peplêgmenos.

ou gar pas psophos phônê, hôsper oude ho ek 

tôn apsuchôn hoion kumatôn ê anemôn

ginomenos:

all’ empsuchou tinos psophos estin hê phônê. ou

mên de pas psophos empsuchou phônê:

oude ho dia cheirôn krotos oude to

chrempsasthai oude to bêxai:

 phônê gar estin empsuchou psophos, dia tôn

 phônêtikôn ginomenos moriôn, hoion

 pneumonos te kai tôn anapneustikôn moriôn, kai

tês tracheias artêrias kai tês pharungos.

kai oude dia toutôn hopôsoun tou psophou

ginomenou,

dioper oude ho bêttôn legetai phônein:

all’ hotan meta phantasias sômatikês tauta

kinêthêi, tote ho ginomenos hupo toutôn

 psophos phônê kaleitai.

tria de tauta theôreitai peri tên tou anthrôpou

 phônên, rhuthmos, harmonia, lexis.

echei de ho men rhuthmos peri ton chronon tês

ekphônêseôs ton makron kai ton brachun:

dio kai tôn phônêentôn ta men en pleionichronôi ekphônoumena makra ônomasan, ta de

en elattoni brachea.

ek de tês toutôn pros allêla suntheseôs to

euruthmon tôn epôn ginetai.

[Voice:] Voice [is] a form of sound.

Voice is a stroke of air or air stricken.

For not every sound is voice, such as it is not

voice a sound coming from unanimated things,

either; for instance, waves or winds.[1]

By contrast, voice is a sound of something

animated, even though not every sound of 

something animated is voice.

 Neither the noise produced through the hands

nor clearing one’s throat or coughing are voice.

For voice is a sound of something animated

coming through parts endowed with voiced

speech,[2] such as the sounds coming through

 parts of lung as well as parts designed for respiration: a rough artery and windpipe.[3]

But voice does not come through any of these

things when a sound is produced.

That is why it is said that the one who is

coughing does not give voice.

However, when these things are set in motion

accompanied by a bodily impression,[4] then,

the sound produced by these is named voice.

The following three things are taken into

account with regard to human voice: (i) rhythm,

(ii) harmony, (iii) language.

(i) Rhythm is concerned with time (long or 

short) of pronunciation.[5]

For this reason, among uttered things, those thatare voiced in much time are also denominated

long, while those that are voiced in less time are

called short.

And the appropriate rhythm of words arises

from the mutual composition of these things.

43

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 44/138

hê de harmonia peri tên tou oxeos kai bareos

summetrian echei,

hê de lexis peri tên diatupôsin tôn sullabôn, ex

hês hê tôn legomenôn sêmainetai ennoia.

epei oun tauta men echei kuriôs hê tou

anthrôpou phônê, mimountai de pôs tauta kai tamousika organa, dia touto kat’ analogian

legontai kai auta phônein.

hoti diakrinousi tên phônên apo tou psophoudichôs, ek te tou tropou tês geneseôs kai ek tou

telous.

ek men oun tou tropou tês geneseôs, hoti hê

 phônê ginetai tou eispneusthentos aeros

ekthlibomenou têi sustolêi tou thôrakos kata tênenuparchousan autôi psuchikên dunamin kai

 prospiptontos têi tracheiai artêriai kai tôi

enapeilêmmenôi en autêi aeri,

hos têi athroai plêgêi athruptos apopallomenos

aei tuptei ton prosechê aera heôs tês akoês.

esti gar to men achanes tou stomatos to mechri

tês rhizês tês glôttês pharunx:

ekeithen duo angeia pherontai, to men epi tonthôraka, kai kaleitai artêria, to de heteron pros

tôi tenonti, kai kaleitai oisophagos.

ginetai de dia tês tracheias artêrias hê parodos

tou pneumatos, hê te kata tên eispompên kai tên

ekpompên, hoper tôi eirêmenôi tropôi

ekpneomenon poiei psophon, hos kaleitai

 phônê, hotan meta tinos sêmantikês phantasias

ginêtai.

ek men oun tou tropou tês geneseôs tautêi

diapherei hê phônê tôn psophôn.

ek de tou telous, hoti hê phônê kath’ hormên

tina tou zôiou ginetai kai prossêmainei ti:

(ii) Harmony is concerned with the due

disposition of the acute and the grave.

(iii) language is concerned with the perfect

formation of the syllables, from which the

concept of the spoken things is meant [or ‘by

which the thought of the things said is signified’

(B.A.M.)].

 Now since the human voice is strictly these

things, and such things in a certain sense alsoimitate the musical instruments, because of this

it is said by analogy that they also utter.[6]

They distinguish voice from sound in twomanners: by the mode of its generation and by

the mode of its end.

 Now by the mode of its generation because

voice arises when the inhaled air is squeezed out

 by a contraction of the chest according to the psychic power inherent in it; and when the air 

falls upon a rough artery, is reduced in such an

artery by the air [itself].

Such air, in rebounding a stroke at once and in

 being unbroken, is beating the proximate air all

the time up the hearing.

For the empty of the mouth up to the root of the

tongue is the windpipe.

From that place two cavities are set in motion:the one, which is also called artery, toward the

chest; the other in the sinew, which is called

gullet, as well.

And the breath’s passing occurs through the

rough artery, and such a passing happens both in

inhaling and exhalation, which produces,

according to the already mentioned mode, a

 breathed out sound that is called voice when

such a sound arises accompanied by a

significant impression.

Thus by the mode of its generation voice differs

from sounds in this fashion.

By the mode of its end [voice differs from

sound] because voice arises and connotes

something in accordance with a certain impulseof the animal.

44

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 45/138

dio kai meta phantasias.

dio kai hoi tôn alogôn psophoi phônai.

kai gar ho kuôn, hopênika phantasian echei tou

allotriou, hulaktei: hotan de tou oikeiou, sainei.

kai epi tôn allôn zôiôn hôsautôs sêmantikai eisinhai phônai tôn psuchikôn dunameôn kai

diatheseôn.

kai gar trophês oregomena ê allou tinoskechrêtai phônêi.

For that reason such a voice is accompanied by

an impression as well.

Therefore, the sounds of the irrational animals

are also voices.

For a dog, when it has an impression of 

someone alien to it, barks, and when it has an

impression of someone familiar to it, fawns.

In the other animals voices of the psychicfaculties and dispositions are also meaningful in

the same way.

For while desiring food or any other thing, theymake use of voice.

Notes.

Source (with slight changes): John Philoponus, Commentary on Aristotle‘s de anima

375.9-376.1 and 378.29-379.15.

[1] The distinction between utterance or voice ( phone) and sound ( psophos) is extremely subtle and

was widely discussed by different philosophers. We find a similar discrimination in the Stoic

sources where utterance is said to be different from “expression” or “speech” ( le/cij) on the groundthat a vocal sound is also an utterance but only articulated speech ( to\ e)/narqron) is an

expression (le/cij; see Diogenes Laertius 7.57). The more or less systematic study of  fwnh/ in

Stoic philosophy was considered under dialectic and le/cij was regarded as a kind of  fwnh/

(Diogenes Laertius 7.44). According to the Stoic Posidonius, a poi/hma is a le/cij in metre or 

rhythm, i.e. a le/cij going outside of prose in its structure (Diogenes Laertius 7.60). Diogenes of 

Babylon, for example, took the human fwnh/ to be all articulate and sent forth in a deliberate way

(DL 7.55). But this specific passage belongs to Philoponus‘ Commentary on Aristotle‘s de an.

(420b5ff.), where Aristotle, after having explained some issues concerning sound and hearing,starts distinguishing utterance from sound. In Aristotle‘s view, utterance is a type of sound proper 

to what is animated or has soul in it (e)/myuxon). So for him a name is an utterance (or voice)

significant by convention but without time (Int. 16a19-20). With the expression ‘by convention’

Aristotle refers to the fact that, in his view, no name is a name naturally but only when it has

 become a symbol (Int. 16, 27-28).

[2] That is to say, phonetic parts. All animals endowed with such phonetic parts are able to produce

some utterance or voice, but human beings are the only ones capable of producing articulated

discourse. For, as Aristotle observes, inarticulate noises of beasts reveal something but they don’t

qualify as names and thereby as a significant utterance (see again Int. 16a28-29).

[3] Or fa/rugx which, according to Aristotle, is the organ of respiration (de An. 420b22-23).[4] This assertion is clarified by Aristotle himself: what causes the impact must be also animated

(following the MSS that give e)/myuxon)) and must be accompanied by a certain impression (or representative image; phantasia), for utterance is indeed a significant sound (de An. 420b31-33).

[5] The Greek is e)kfw/nhsij, a cognate of  fwnh/, and its meaning is almost the same: uttered

sound, pronunciation.

[6] What now follows here is a quotation of Philoponus 378.29-379.15.*

*N.B. Note that Philoponus’ remark is based on De Anima; cf. II. 8, 420b 6-8 (tr. B.A.M.):

45

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 46/138

h( de\ fonh\ yo/foj ti/j e)stin e)my/xou.

tw=n ga\r a)yu/xwn ou)qe\n fwnei=,

a)lla\ kaq) o(moio/thta le/getai fwnei=n,

oi(=on au)lo\j kai\ lu/ra kai\ o(/sa a)/llatw=n a)yu/xwn a)po/tasin e)/xei kai\

me/loj kai\ dia/lekton.

But voice is the sound belonging to a thing with

soul.

For no inanimate thing has a voice,

though they are said to give voice by a likeness,

as the aulos, the lyre, and other inanimate things

that have prolongation, melody, and idiom.

(b) According to Boethius:

Boethius,  In Librum Aristotelis De Interpretatione Libri Sex Editio Secunda, Seu

 Majora Commentaria (ed. Migne, PL, tr. B.A.M.).

Prius ergo quid vox sit diffiniendum est.

Hoc enim perspicuo et manifesto omnis libri

hujus patefiet intentio.

Vox est aeris per linguam percussio, quae per 

quasdam gutturis partes, quae arteriae vocantur,

ab animali profertur.

Sunt enim quidam alii soni qui eodem

 perficiuntur flatu, quos lingua non percutit, ut

est tussis.

Haec enim flatu fit quodam per arterias

egrediente, sed nulla linguae impressione

formatur, atque ideo nec illis subjacet elementis,scribi enim nullo modo potest.

Quocirca vox haec non dicitur, sed tantum

sonus.

Illa quoque potest esse diffinitio vocis, ut eam

dicamus sonum esse cum quadam imaginatione

significandi.

Vox namque cum emittitur, significationis

alicujus causa profertur.

Tussus vero cum sonus sit, nullius significati-

onis causa, surrepit potius quam profertur.

Quare quoniam flatus noster ita sese habet, ut si

ita percutiatur atque formetur, ut eum lingua

 percutiat, vox sit.

First of all then, what voice is must be defined.

For when this is made clear, the intention of the

whole of this book will be evident.

Voice is a percussion of the air by the tongue,

which is uttered by an animal through certain

 parts of the throat called arteries [i.e. the

windpipe].

There are also certain other sounds which are

 produced by the same breath which the tongue

does not strike, such as a cough.

For this results from a breath coming out of the

windpipe, but is formed by no impression of the

tongue, and therefore neither is placed under theelements, for in no way can it be written.

Therefore this is not called ‘voice’, but only

sound.

And so let us say that the definition of voice can

 be that it is a sound accompanied by a certain

imagination of signifying.

For when the voice is emitted, it is uttered for 

the sake of some signification [or ‘meaning’].

But a cough, though it is a sound, (is not

emitted) for the sake of any signification; it just

comes out rather than is uttered.

So when our breath so has itself that if it is

struck and formed in such a way that the tongue

strikes it, it is voice [or ‘vocal sound’].

46

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 47/138

Si enim lingua ita percutiat, ut terminato

quodam et circumscriptio sono vox exeat,

locutio fit quae Graece dicitur le/xij.

Locutio enim est articulata vox, neque enim

hunc sermonem, id est le/xin, dictionem

dicemus, idcirco quid fa/sin dictionem

interpretamur, le/xin, locutionem.

Cujus locutionis partes sunt litterae, quae cumconjunctae fuerint, unam efficiunt vocem

conjunctam compositamque, quae locutio

 praedicatur.

For if the tongue so strikes it that the voice

comes forth in a certain finite and distinct

sound, it becomes ‘locution’ [or ‘an utterance’],

which is called le/xij in Greek.

For locution is articulate vocal sound; for we do

not call this word le/xij a dictio [‘word’],

 because we translate fa/sin by dictio, but le/xij

 by locutio.

The parts of locution are the ‘letters’* which,when they have been conjoined, effect one

conjoint and composite vocal sound, which is

called ‘locution’.

* I.e. indivisible vocal sounds, nowadays called phonemes.

Sive autem aliquid quaecunque vox significet,

ut est hic sermo, homo, sive omnino nihil, sive

 positum alicui nomen significare possit, ut est

 blictiri; haec enim vox cum per se nihil

significet, posita tamen ut alicui nomen sit,significabit,

sive per se quidem nihil significet, cum aliis

vero juncta designet, ut sunt, conjunctiones,

haec omnia locutiones vocantur, ut si propria

locutionis forma vox composita quae litteris

describatur.

Ut igitur sit locutio, voce opus est, id est eo

sono quem percutit lingua, et ut vox ipsa sit per 

linguam determinata in eum sonum qui inscribilitteris possit, similiter opus est eo sono quem

 percutit lingua.

Sed ut haec locutio significativa sit, illud

quoque addi oportet ut sit aliqua significandi

imaginatio, per quam id quod in voce vel in

locutione est proferatur.

Aut certe ita dicendum est si in hoc flatu quem

 per arterias emittimus, sit linguae sola percussio, vox est.

Si vero talis percussio sit, ut in litteras redigat

sonum, locutio est.

Quod si vis quoque quaedam imaginationis

 Now whether a vocal sound signify something,

as this word ‘man’, or nothing at all, or can

signify if given as a name to something, as does

‘blictiri’—for this vocal sound, although it does

not signify anything by itself, given as a nameto something, will signify— 

or whether it signify nothing by itself, but might

designate [something] when joined with other 

[words], like conjunctions, they are all called

‘locutions’, as if the proper form of locution

[were to be] composite vocal sound which can

be written out in letters.

In order for there to be locution, therefore, there

is need for a vocal sound; that is, that sound

which the tongue strikes, and that the vocalsound itself be determined by the tongue into

the kind of sound which can be written in

letters, likewise there is need for the sound

which the tongue strikes.

But in order for a locution to be significative, it

is necessary to add that there be a certain

imagination of signifying by which what is in

the voice or in the locution is uttered.

And so it can certainly be said that if in the

 breath we emit through the windpipe there beonly a percussion of the tongue, it is vocal

sound.

But if the percussion is such that the sound can

 be rendered in letters, it is locution.

But if a certain power of imagination be added,

47

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 48/138

addatur, illa significativa vox redditur.

Concurrentibus igitur his tribus, linguae

 percussione, articulato vocis sonitu,

imaginatione aliqua proferendi, fit interpretatio.

Interpretatio namque est vox articulata per 

seipsam signifcans.

Quocirca non omnis vox interpretatio est, suntenim caeterorum animalium voces, quae

interpretationis vocabulo non tenentur.

 Nec omnis locutio interpretatio est, idcirco quia

(ut dictum est) sunt locutiones quaedam, quae

significatione carent et cum per se quaedam non

significent, juncta tamen cum aliis significant,

ut conjunctiones.

Interpretatio autem in solis per se significativis

et articulatis vocibus permanent (?).

Quare convertitur, ut quidquid sit intepretatio,

illud significet. Et quidquid significat,

interpretationis vocabulo nuncupetur.

that vocal sound is rendered significative.

And so when these three things come together,

the percussion of the tongue, the articulate

sound of voice, and the uttering of it with a

certain imagination, interpretation results.

For interpretation is articulate vocal sound

signifying by itself.

But not every vocal sound is ‘interpretation’, for there are vocal sounds belonging to the rest of 

the animals which are not included under the

word ‘interpretation’.

 Neither is every locution interpretation because,

as has been said, there are certain utterances

which lack meaning and although they do not

signify anything by themselves, nevertheless

when they are joined with other [words] do

signify, like conjunctions.

Interpretation, however, consists solely in

articulate vocal sounds signifying by

themselves.

Wherefore the following conversion of 

statements holds good, that whatever is an

interpretation, that signifies—and whatever signifies is named by the word ‘interpretation’.

Unde etiam ipse quoque Aristoteles in libris

quos de Arte poetica scripsit, locutionis partesesse syllabas et conjunctiones etiam tradit,

quarum syllabae, in eo quod sunt syllabae, nihil

omnino significant.

Conjunctiones vero consignificare quidem

 possunt, per se vero nihil designant.

That is why Aristotle in the books which he

wrote about the poetic art [cf.  Poetics ch. 20,1456b 20ff.] also taught that syllables and

conjunctions are parts of locution, of which the

syllables as syllables signify nothing at all.

But conjunctions in fact can consignify, but

designate nothing by themselves.

Interpretationis vero partes hoc libro constituit

nomen et verbum, quae scilicet per seipsa

significant.

 Nihilominus quoque orationem interpretationemesse constat, quae et ipsa cum vox sit et

significativis partibus juncta, significatione non

caret.

In this book, however, he has established the

name and verb as parts of an interpretation,

which, of course, signify by themselves.

And nevertheless it cannot be denied that speechis interpretation which, since it is vocal sound

 joined from parts which are significative, does

not lack signification.

48

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 49/138

Quare quoniam non de oratione sola, sed etiam

de nomine et verbo, nec vero de sola locutione,

sed etiam de significativa locutione, quae est

interpretatio, in hoc libro ab Aristotele tractatur,

idcirco quoniam verbis atque nominibus, et

significativis locutionibus nomen interpre-

tationis aptatur, a communi nomine eorum dequibus in hoc libro tractatur, id est

interpretatione, ipse quoque de Interpretationeliber inscriptus est….

Wherefore not of speech alone, but also of the

name and the verb, and not of locution alone,

 but also of significative locution, which is

interpretation, are treated by Aristotle in this

 book,

and as the name ‘interpretation’ designates

verbs, names, and significative utterances as

well, this book is entitled On Interpretationfrom the common name of the things which are

treated in this book; that is, interpretation….

Boethius, Commentarium In Librum Aristotelis Perihermeneias Primae Editionis . Liber

Primus. [Introductio] (ed. Migne, PL 64, tr. B.A.M.).

49

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 50/138

/3l/ ...Et prius quae sit huius operis intentio

 breuiter demonstrandum est. Inscribitur etenim

liber Graece  PERIHERMENEIAS  quod Latine

“De interpretatione” significat.

Quid ergo sit interpretatio paucis absoluam.

Interpretatio est uox significatiua per se ipsamaliquid significans.

Siue enim nomen sit, quod per se significat, ut

est “homo”; siue uerbum, ut est “curro”;

siue quod grammatici participium uocant, siue

 pronomen est,

siue ex his iuncta oratio, ut est “Homo currit”,

siue quolibet alio modo uel nomen uel uerbum

uel ex his oratio iuncta per se aliquid significet,

interpretatio nominatur.

Quare cum sint quaedam in orationis partibus

quae per se nihil significant, aliis tamen iunctadesignant, ut sunt coniunctiones uel

 praepositiones, haec interpretationes esse non

dicimus.

Interpretatio enim siue simplex est, ut nomen et

uerbum, siue composita, ut ex his iuncta

copulataque oratio, uel per se ipsam significare

debet, si simplex est, uel ex his quae per se

significant iuncta esse, si composita est.

Quare interpretatio est uox aliquid per se ipsam

significans.

Sed quoniam uerba nominaque interpretationes /33/ sunt, oratio quoque omnis quae ex

significantibus per se praedicamentis iungitur interpretatio nuncupatur,

et sunt plurimae interpretationes, inter quas illa

quoque est oratio, in qua uerum falsumue

But the intention of the work we have before us

must be briefly explained: for in Greek the book 

is entitled PERHERMENEIAS, which in Latin

means “On Interpretation”.

What “interpretation” is must therefore be

cleared up.

‘Interpretation’ is significative vocal soundsignifying something by itself.

For whether it be a name, which signifies by

itself, as is ‘man’—or whether a verb, as is ‘[I]

run’— 

or whether what the grammarians call the

 participle [,as is ‘running’]—or whether it is a

 pronoun [,as is ‘I’] — 

or whether [it is] speech conjoined from these,

as is ‘Man runs’— 

or whether in any other way either a name or a

verb or speech conjoined from these might

signify something by itself, it is named

interpretation.

Wherefore, since among the parts of speech21 

there are certain ones which signify nothing bythemselves, yet do convey a meaning when

 joined to the others, as do conjunctions or 

 prepositions, these things we do not call

‘interpretations’.

For interpretation is either  simple, like the name

and verb, or complex, like speech conjoined and

coupled from these, or  should signify by itself,

if it is simple, or being conjoined from these

[words] which signify by themselves, if it is

composed.

Wherefore ‘interpretation’ is vocal sound

signifying something by itself.

But since verbs and names are interpretations,so also every [instance of] speech joined from

things signifying predicaments by themselves isnamed ‘interpretation’,22

and there are many interpretations, among

which are those speeches in which the true and

21 Notice how Boethius speaks of “parts of speech” rather than of “language” in this earlier commentary.22 That is, the sort of terms logicians call categorematic are called ‘interpretations’.

50

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 51/138

inueniri potest, id est enuntiatiua, de qua hoc

libro tractandum est: idcirco igitur Aristoteles

de communi nomine et continenti libro titulum

scripsit.

the false may be found, that is, the enunciative,

which is to be treated in this book: for that

reason Aristotle entitled the book under the

common and comprehensive name.

(c) According to St. Thomas Aquinas:

St. Thomas Aquinas, In I Peri Herm., lect. 4, n. 3 (tr. B.A.M.).

et ideo quinque ponit in definitione nominis.

 primo, ponitur vox per modum generis, per 

quod distinguitur nomen ab omnibus sonis, qui

non sunt voces.

nam vox est sonus ab ore animalis prolatus, cumimaginatione quadam, ut dicitur in ii de anima.

additur autem prima differentia, scilicet

significativa, ad differentiam quarumcumque

vocum non significantium, sive sit vox litterata

et articulata, sicut biltris, sive non litterata et

non articulata, sicut sibilus pro nihilo factus.

et quia de significatione vocum in superioribus

actum est, ideo ex praemissis concludit quod

nomen est vox significativa.

And so he puts down five things in the

definition of a name.

First, ‘vocal sound’ [or ‘voice’] is put down by

way of a genus, by which the name is

distinguished from other sounds which are not

voices.

For  ‘voice’ is a sound uttered by the mouth of an animal , as is said in the second book of the

 De Anima (ch. 8, 420b 6ff.).

But the first difference, namely, ‘significative’,

is added to differentiate it from whatever vocal

sounds are not significant, whether the voice be

formed in letters and articulate, like ‘biltris’,23 or 

not formed in letters and not articulate, like a

hiss made for no reason.

And because the signification of vocal sounds

was treated above, he therefore concludes from

the things premised that a name is a

significative vocal sound.

23 Cf. Boethius’ In Librum Aristotelis De Interpretatione, Editio Secunda seu Majora Commentaria, ed. J. P.

Migne, Patrologia Latina, vol. LXIV, p. 13, col. b.

51

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 52/138

IV. ON LANGUAGE AS A SYSTEMATIC MEANS OF HUMAN COMMUNI-CATION.

1. Some definitions of language.24

Human speech; the expression of ideas by words or significant articulate sounds, for the

communication of thoughts.  Noah Webster, An American Dictionary of the English

 Language (New York, 1828), “Language”

Language is the expression of ideas by means of speech-sounds combined into words.

Words are combined into sentences, this combination answering to that of ideas into

thoughts. Henry Sweet 

Language is a purely human and non-instinctive method of communicating ideas, emotions

and desires by means of voluntarily produced symbols. Edward Sapir 

Language is most often defined as an organized system of speech that allows humans to

communicate with each other. Encyclozine.com

The institution whereby humans communicate and interact with each other by means of 

habitually used oral-auditory arbitrary symbols. R. A. Hall 

A language is a system of arbitrary vocal symbols by means of which a social group

cooperates. Bernard Bloch and George L. Trager 

language, a system of conventional spoken or written symbols by means of which human

 beings, as members of a social group and participants in its culture, communicate.

 Encyclopaedia Britannica

A system of vocal sounds and combinations of such sounds to which meaning is attributed,

used for the expression or communication of thoughts and feelings. Webster’s New World 

 Dictionary (Third College Edition)

The systematic, conventional use of sounds, signs, or written symbols in a human society

for communication and self-expression. David Crystal 

William Wallace, O.P., The Elements of Philosophy, Ch. 9: Philosophy of the

Humanities. Sec. 75. Philosophy of Language, p. 179 (cf. The New Catholic

 Encyclopedia, s.v. ‘Language’).

1.  Language (8:365c) is a systematic means of human communication, particularly byarrangement of vocal sounds conventionally representing concepts, feelings, objects, etc.

Like eating and sleeping it is common to all mankind; unlike them it is not instinctive but

must be learned by every individual from other members of the social group to which he

 belongs. It is a kind of behavior that is man’s alone, that he shares with no other livingcreature. Without it, man’s uniquely complex knowledge and control of his environment

would be inconceivable.

24 Excerpted from a Web Site.

52

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 53/138

2. Some characteristics of language.

Francis P. Dineen, S.J.  An Introduction to General Linguistics. Ch. 1. Linguistics as a

Scientific Study of Language. Some Characteristics of Language (New York, 1967), p.

10. (bold by B.A.M.)

Linguists have found by experience that there are several characteristics of 

language that provide a basis for accurate description. The first is that all languages aresound and, as a consequence, can be represented as linear.25 Second, all languages aresystematic, both in the permissible combinations of language sounds26 and in the

combination of meaningful elements of the language.27 Third, language is meaningful,

since the sounds speakers make are connected with factors other than language itself.When the relation between the sounds the speakers make and their meanings is

investigated we find that the relation is both arbitrary and conventional.

Ibid., p. 11.

The units and relations that the linguist discusses when describing a language aregenerally selected as a consequence of the nature of spoken language. Since language is

sound, all the units will be stated basically in terms of sounds or sound differences. Since

language is meaningful, all the units will be established according to the meanings or 

meaning differences that they signal. Since language is arbitrary, the connection betweensounds and meanings will always be indirect. All sounds will, therefore, at least make a

difference in meaning, and some sounds and sound sequences will have a constant,

conventional connection with some feature of the nonlinguistic environment. Since the primary focus of the description is on the patterns of sounds and sound sequences of a

language, the description is called formal; since another primary focus of the description is

on the contrasts among units and patterns of units, the description is called structural. In brief, each linguistic unit will be definable in terms of its characteristic composition,

distribution, and function.

Ibid., p. 12.

The units of which a language is composed can also be defined in terms of their 

function—that is, in terms of what they do or in terms of the use made of them. It is theover-all function of language to communicate meanings, and this is done through sounds

and sound differences. Every unit of language will, therefore, have at least a differential

function. It will distinguish one message from another, even though it does not have ameaning itself. This is the usual function of the individual sounds. Other units of language,

in addition to their differential function, will have a referential function. That is, there

will be a conventional connection between the unit and some aspect of the nonlinguisticenvironment. An obvious example of this would be the name for anything, which can be

said to have a referential function when it is used to point to some subject of discussion

and a differential function, because it makes clear that we are discussing what it name and

not something else.

25 Cf. speech considered as a species of discrete quantity.26 Cf. the discussion of dialektos as meaning ‘idiom’ below.27 I discuss this matter in my paper “ Poetics Chapter 20”.

53

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 54/138

Francis P. Dineen, S.J.  An Introduction to General Linguistics. Ch. 2. The Study of Language As Sound. (New York, 1967), p. 20.

One aspect of both traditional grammar and linguistics is talking about language,

and any efficient system of communication requires shared experience as its basis. Themost universal experience all of us have of language is speaking it and hearing it. We have

already seen that most writing systems do not conform exactly to the sounds people make

in speaking, so that it is easy to appreciate the need for some accurate method of transcribing the sounds of languages. Phonetics provides us with an accurate means of describing language sounds, and phonemics with an efficient system of writing the sounds.

Since the linguist takes sound to be the basic manifestation of language, it will be useful to

give a brief sketch of how the sounds of English can be described phonetically and phonemically. We will then be able to appreciate the shortcomings of earlier work and the

 progress that has been made in language study in recent years.

The sounds of a language can be described in three principal ways: according to (1)

their composition, (2) their distribution, and (3) their function. Phonetics is primarily

concerned with the composition of sounds, while phonemics treats the distribution andfunction of sounds.

Ibid., pp. 20-21.

The sounds of a language can be studied in terms of the articulatory movements

required to produce them or as disturbances in the air in the form of sound waves or according to the manner in which they strike [20-21] our ears. Articulatory phonetics is

concerned with the first sort of study while acoustic phonetics deals with the second. The

third type of investigation is often called impressionistic phonetics.

Ibid., p. 22.

Sounds in languages are generally produced when air which has been taken into the

lungs is expelled through the two exits open to it, the mouth, the nose, or both. In Figure 1

[not reproduced here] it can be seen that the air from the lungs passes through the trachea.The air in normal breathing takes the same route, but since breathing is a constant factor 

and is not generally used for conventional language functions, its audible sound and its

wave form are usually ignored in phonetics.

Francis P. Dineen, S.J.  An Introduction to General Linguistics. Ch. 2. The Study of Language As Sound. The Production of Language Sounds (New York, 1967), pp. 22-

23.

In the channel above the trachea is the larynx, a cartilaginous enclosure in whichare contained the vocal chords. From the outside the larynx is called the Adam’s apple. If 

we look down into the throat with a laryngoscope or a mirror properly placed, we can see

that the vocal cords resemble two lips hinged together at the front. When they arecompletely closed air cannot pass through them from the lungs.

54

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 55/138

The liplike closure is called the glottis, and the stoppage it effects is called a glottal stop.

In normal breathing the lips are spread open, resembling the sides of a printed capital  A; inwhispering the cords close down to about the middle of the  A opening. When engaged in

the production of the [22-23] vowels, the vocal cords open and close at very high rates of 

speed, often hundreds of times per second. The vibration causes the air stream comingfrom the lungs through the trachea and the vocal cords to pulsate in the typical fashion

called voice, and a sound produced in such a manner is called voiced sound. The vibration

of the larynx can be readily felt by putting a finger on or near the Adam’s apple andhumming; it is also noticeable when holding the hand on the top of the head.

The wave form of the air after passing through the vocal cords can be differentiated

in many ways, depending on the shape of the cavities through which it passes (for example, the pharyngeal, oral, and nasal cavities) or on an overlay of friction imparted to

it by narrowing the passage of exit. If the velum is lowered, there is no velic closure of the

nasal cavity and the voiced sounds passing through the nasal cavity acquire a quality callednasality. Many other important modifications can be introduced, depending on the

contacts made by the various movable and immovable parts of the mouth.

V. ON ARTICULATION.

Francis P. Dineen, S.J.  An Introduction to General Linguistics. Ch. 2. The Study of 

Language As Sound. The Points of Articulation in English (New York, 1967), p. 23.

To articulate something is to break it down into segments, links, or joints.Language sounds are said to be articulated with respect to each other through interruption

or change of quality. While “change of quality” is not an articulatory description, it is

 possible to detect the correspondence between the organic adjustments that give rise toqualitative differences and the wave forms caused by such sounds by means of electronic

analysis. Devices such as the sound spectrograph show that speech is generally a

continuous passage from one type of articulation to another, but the ear appears to

discriminate centers or peaks in this continuous flow. It is these centers that the phonetician principally attempts to describe and symbolize. Transitions from one such state

of the articulatory organs to the next are often difficult to analyze and describe.

Francis P. Dineen, S.J.  An Introduction to General Linguistics. Ch. 2. The Study of 

Language As Sound. Manners of Articulation: Consonants (New York, 1967), p. 24.

Because it is fairly easy to feel the approach of a movable organ to an immovable

one, or their contact, consonantal articulations are easier to describe than vocalic. If wedefine a vowel as a sound resulting from the unrestricted passage of the air stream

through the mouth or nasal cavity without audible friction or stoppage, we can define

a consonant as the opposite—a sound that involves stoppage, preventing the airstream from escaping through the mouth, or a constriction of the air stream that

results in audible friction. Since no stream of air through the passages is wholly without

friction, this is a relative matter. While vowel sounds are generally voiced, they need not

 be, as whispering shows. Some languages regularly employ both voiced and whisperedvowels.

55

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 56/138

James Craig La Drière, “Prosody” (from Preminger, ed. Encyclopedia of Poetry and 

 Poetics, bold added by B.A.M.).

Vocal sound is the result of vibration produced by constriction of the current of air 

 projected from the lungs (by movements of the diaphragm and other muscles of abdomenand chest) through the larynx, throat, and mouth, with resonance in chest and head and

modification of the current and vibrations by varying articulation of the parts of organs in

these passages, especially in the mouth.

Continuity and interruption or remission of sound depend upon and correspond to the

muscular actions and pressures of expiration (during which normal speech-sound occurs)

and inspiration of air and the pauses between them (which though considerable in breathing at rest are neither frequent nor lengthy in continuous speech, in which inspiration

normally follows expiration with no interval of rest); it is therefore primarily to the

mechanisms of respiratory pressure that most of the massing and grouping of sounds, andin general their quantitative acoustic effects (especially of intensity and duration, but also

largely of pitch) are due.

Larger and intermediate groupings are determined by action of the diaphragm supported by

the muscles of the abdominal and thoracic walls; the smallest aggregatory (and rhythmic)

unit, the syllable, as it occurs in polysyllabic utterance in most languages, appears to be the

 product of a single pressure (“chest-pulse”) of the smaller intercostal muscles. (Uttered inisolation the syllable, like all whole-utterance units, is produced by pressure from the

abdomen. In polysyllabic utterances it is a slighter pulsation within a larger stretch of 

sound produced by sustained abdominal pressure. This is the physiological foundation of the “rhythmic group,” for which see below).

Obstruction of the current of air and articulatory modification of vibration andresonance produce qualitative differentiation of sounds, upon which phonemic

discrimination of segments of sound is based.

Qualitative differences among sounds are usually described and classified interms of the articulations involved in their production; but the foundation of phonemic

distinctions is a generalizing discrimination of acoustic differences which corresponds at

times only loosely to articulatory, or to very sensitive auditory, differentiation. (Thephonemes of a language are roughly represented by the letters of an alphabet; hence the

name alliteration for repetitive figuration of qualitative similarities in sounds).

Quality in vocal sound may be generally described as the acoustic effect of articulatory

action, broadly including all varieties of constriction and obstruction (vocalic,

consonantal, liquid, etc.) or of vibration and resonance (voiced, voiceless; oral, nasal,etc.) as well as distinction of organ, part, or place (glottal, palatal, dental, labial, etc.;

dorsal, lateral, apical, etc.; front, back, high, low, etc.) or mode (open, closed,

rounded, unrounded; plosive, spirant, affricate, etc.) of articulation. Each vowel or 

consonant is a composite “bundle” of several such qualitative properties or (sub- phonemic) component “features” (now being systematically classified by Jakobson and

others), and the relations upon which qualitative structure of sounds depends are relations

among these properties or features rather than among the composite sounds or segments(phonemes) as such.

56

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 57/138

Some qualitative differences, e.g., that between voiced and unvoiced sounds, involve

accompanying difference in quantity. But qualitative differentiation of sounds, though itsfiguration (alliteration, assonance, rhyme) may be combined with and even assimilated to

rhythmic structure, is never directly a factor in the production of rhythm, since rhythm is a

structure of quantitative relations. The properties of sound directly relevant to rhythmicstructure are the quantitative or quantifiable properties of  intensity, duration, and pitch.

Intensity (loudness or volume) and duration are obviously quantitative in perceptual effect

as well as physically measurable. Pitch (corresponding roughly to frequency of vibrationand thus easily quantified, though not subject to extensive or intensive measurement) hasan ambiguous perceptual effect, in part quantitative, in part qualitative. As it is used in

language, variation of pitch is normally associated with other variation that is quantitative

and, whether independently or because pitch is easily conflated in perception withassociated features, its effect is quantitative, increasing the prominence of the sound altered

 by its variation. The quantitative or prosodic properties of sound are used in language not

for their absolute or “inherent” characters (as pitch is used in music) but, in contrasting juxtaposition with other variants of the same property in adjacent sounds within an

utterance, to provide “relational” oppositions which have semantic effects or syntactic

functions. The prosodic features are therefore often distinguished as “relational” from the“inherent” features by which segmental phonemes are characterized, because the

 phonologically functional characteristics of the individual phonemic segments are

discernible in isolated utterance of single phonemes, whereas it is only in continuous

successive utterance of sounds that prosodic contrasts can be observed. A similar distinction now in common use opposes prosodic features as “suprasegmental” to the

(qualitative) features of the phonemic “segments” of sound upon which they are imposed;

 phonologically regulated occurrences of prosodic entities (“prosodic phonemes”) maythen be called “suprasegmental phonemes,” patterns of these called “superfixes,” and

 prosodic superfixes called “suprasegmental morphemes” when they have a fixed

“morphological” function in the syntax of a language. (British linguists who follow J.R.Firth make different distinctions, otherwise grounded, among prosodic and “phonematic”

entities: cf. R. H. Robins, “Aspects of prosodic analysis,” Univ. of Durham Philosophical

Society, Proc. I, ser. B, no. 1, 1957).

The various contrasts provided by the prosodic features are used in some

languages for lexical distinctions, between words or functional classes of words (e.g.,English contrast , n. = ó o, vb. = o ó), but their most general linguistic use is that of 

ordering and grouping sounds to produce phonological units that function

syntactically. The mechanisms of this ordering and aggregation of sounds are those of 

“accent” (of intensity, “dynamic”; or of pitch, “tonic”), of  “intonation” (systematicsuccessive arrangement of pitch-values) and of “pause” and “timing” (dilation or holding,

contraction, and interruption of sound; transition with “juncture” of various degrees of 

“openness” between sounds); these mechanisms and their effects (fusion, reduction or  promotion, elision of sounds) may involve accompanying qualitative changes. One of their 

effects is the production of what is usually called (rhythmic) “cadence,” i.e., pattern of 

successive or positional relation of prominent (“strong” or “emphatic”) elements to less

 prominent (“weak” or “unemphatic”) elements. The prominence and weakness relevant for cadence may be of intensity, of duration, or of pitch; these factors may operate singly and

distinctly or in combinations; and the phonological patterns of a single language (e.g.,

ancient Gr. and L., modern Czech, Chinese) may produce distinct “natural” cadences of more than one kind. [= dialektos]

57

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 58/138

Cadence involves the two aspects of “span” (the number of elements over which a

unitary pattern extends) and “direction”(the positional or successional order of theelements).

Direction is usually classified as “rising” (o ó, o o ó), “falling” (ó o, ó o o), “mixed” or “undulating” or “rocking” (o ó o, ó o ó), and “level” or “even” (ó ó, o o); these last and

other cadence-units (as ó) exhibiting neither “rise” nor “fall,” and often the undulating

cadences which include both, are also called “neutral”; cadence is called “alternating”when “emphatic” and “unemphatic” elements of equal span succeed each other in a series(especially when the series begins and ends with the same value) and more loosely when

equivalence of span is only approximated.

James Craig La Drière, “Prosody” (from Preminger, ed. Encyclopedia of Poetry and 

 Poetics, emphasis added by B.A.M.

Sounds are differentiated in quality (discriminable character or kind) and in

quantity (measurable degree or amount of sonority or of general or specific acousticmagnitude, including that of duration in time; temporal duration is the only common

 property of sound and silence, and the only positive attribute of silence, which is thus

essentially quantitative).

Carl Darling Buck, Comparative Greek and Latin Grammar . (Chicago: The Universityof Chicago Press, 1933), nn. 36-37, pp. 31-35.

SOME GENERAL FEATURES OF LINGUISTIC HISTORY

MECHANISM OF SPEECH AND CLASSIFICATION OF SPEECH SOUNDS

36. Speech sounds (hereafter called simply “sounds”) are vibrations of air produced bythe organs of speech (their genetic aspect) and perceived by the organs of hearing (their 

acoustic aspect). The production and perception are co-ordinated through the motor and

auditory centers in the brain, and it is this combined mental image which is the element of continuity in the history of a sound. For the sound once uttered vanishes. When we speak 

of the change of a given sound, as of  a _ to o _, as if it had an independent life of its own,

we are merely employing a convenient figure of speech.It is the genetic aspect that is the main basis of the classification of sounds and will

 be considered in the following.

The number of distinct sounds that can be produced by the organs of speech is

infinite, and those actually employed in language would run to many hundreds. But in any

one language there is only a limited number, usually between the limits of thirty and sixty.These are the pattern sounds or “phonemes” of the particular language.

  37. The lungs, controlled by the chest and abdominal muscles, act like bellows and

furnish the stream of air. This passes up through the windpipe to the chamber at the top,

the larynx, in which are situated the vocal cords, and hence to the mouth and nose, whichact as resonance chambers of variable shape.

58

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 59/138

The vocal cords are not like violin strings, but are the edges of two folds of 

membrane, more like the edges of flaps of rubber. They may be drawn together and madetense by muscular action, so that they are set in vibration. In breathing they are left open,

and in the production of some sounds they are equally inactive, while in others they

vibrate. According as there is or is not vibration of the vocal cords, sounds are classified as“voiced” (“sonant”) or “voiceless” (“breathed”, “surd”). The vowels are voiced, and so

usually the liquids and nasals. The stops and fricatives (cf. below), including the sibilants,

occur in pairs, voiceless (also with stronger aspiration) and voiced (also with [31-32] weaker aspiration), as English  p:b, t:d, f:v, s:z , etc. The vibration can be felt by putting one’sfinger on the “Adam’s apple”, or more clearly through the skull when the ears are covered

tight by the hands. Contrast the  s of  sin with the  z  of  zero, each pronounced by itself 

without [the] following vowel.The vocal cords are also subject to alterations in length and tensity, with

consequent variation in the frequency of vibrations. These constitute differences in pitch

(tone, intonation), which in our own current speech (as distinguished from song) areobserved mainly in sentence modulation, as in the rising tone of interrogation, but in some

languages as ancient Greek and Sanskrit are the dominant elements of word-accent.

Apart from the action of the vocal cords, the distinguishing characteristics of our 

sounds are the result of overtones produced in the resonance chambers of the mouth or 

nose. Of these two the less important and the simpler is the nose. This functions only in the

nasal sounds produced when the nasal passage is left open. If the stream of air is cut off inthe mouth and issues only through the nose and mouth we have nasal vowels as in French.

The nose is a rigid chamber, not subject to alteration in shape, and the difference between

the various nasal sounds is caused by different mouth positions.In distinction from the nasals, all other vowel sounds are “oral”. The nasal passage,

open in breathing, is cut off by raising the velum or soft palate, and the mouth alone acts as

the resonance chamber. Owing to the mobility of the jaws, lips, and especially the tongue,the chamber of the mouth may assume a great variety of shapes, resulting in as many

different sounds.

Of the consonants some are formed with complete closure, by which the stream of 

air is wholly blocked, followed by a sudden release of the breath, as, for example,  p withclosure of the lips. These are called “stops” (“explosives”, “mutes”). The nasal consonants

are stops, so far as concerns the passage of the breath [32-33] through the mouth (the

closure is the same for m as for  p), but the flow of breath through the nose is continuous.The release may be followed by an added puff of breath, as in uphill . Then we have

aspirated stops (aspirates). Our English initial stops in words like  pen are distinctly

aspirated by comparison with the French.Others are formed with close approximation (not complete closure) and resulting

friction, as  f  with friction between the lower lip and upper teeth. These are called

“fricatives” (“spirants”).The distinctions so far made, as stop, fricative, nasal, voiceless, or voiced, may be

conventionally called “orders”, as contrasted with the “series” (or “classes”) depending

upon the position where the closure or friction takes place.

Between lips and throat there is a continuous range of possible points of contact. Arough division of this into three main areas and the recognition of three series, labial,

dental, and guttural (palatal), is the general basis of classification, and sufficient for some

languages. But labials include bilabials, as  p, b, m, and labiodentals, as  f, v. The dentalstops, t, d, differ considerably in different languages, as the French, which are pure dentals,

59

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 60/138

from the English in which the tongue touches the gums back of the teeth; and sometimes

there are two distinct series in the same language, as in Sanskrit. The area back of thedental is the most extensive, and “guttural”, used here as the general term, covers the

greatest diversity. There is some difference between the gutturals of English card and kin,

much more between those of German kann and Kind or doch and ich, and frequently onemust recognize two distinct guttural series, a front (“palatal”, “prae-palatal”) and back 

(“velar”).

The series represented in English are then:

   Labials.—The bilabial stops, voiceless  p, voiced b; the labio-dental fricatives, voiceless

 f , voiced v; the nasal m.   Dentals.—The stops, voiceless t , voiced d ; the (interdental) fricatives, written th,

voiceless in thin, voiced in then; the nasal n.

  Gutturals.—The stops, voiceless k , c (as in cat ), voiced g , (as in [33-34]  get ); the gutturalnasal [ŋ],1 as in ink  [iŋk],1  finger  [fiŋgɘ(r)], ring  [riŋ]. There is no guttural fricative, of 

which German ch is an example.

The “sibilants” from a special class of fricatives and are so named from their 

acoustic character, rather than from the manner of production. In the voiceless  s of  sin and

the voiced z of  zero (often written s as in rose) the tongue forms a narrow channel through

which the breath is projected onto the teeth, with a resulting hissing sound. In the voiceless[š] of  shake, sure and the voiced [Z] of azure, the channel is broader and the stream of air 

more spread out.

The “liquids”, as the term is now applied (it has no precise descriptive value), are l and r . The l is produced by touching the tip of the tongue to the palate, leaving openings at

the sides through which the breath passes. For the r  the sides of the tongue form the

contact, leaving a channel down the middle through which the breath passes over the tip of the tongue. But in both there are several variable factors, and there is the greatest variety

among the l- and r- sounds of different languages.

The vowels are produced without closure or friction. Their differences depend upon

the various shapes of the resonance chamber caused by the position of the lips and tongue.The lips may be rounded or unrounded. The tongue may be raised high in the front of the

mouth or in the back, or it may lie flat; its position may be intermediate. Hence vowels are

distinguished as rounded or unrounded, and by extremes as front or back and as close(high) and open (low). Thus the u of  pull is a close (high) back rounded vowel, while the i

of  pit is a close (high) front unrounded vowel. The French u and the German U are front

rounded vowels, Open and close are relative terms and one speaks of an open or close o or an open or close e. [34-35]

1 Here and in the following square brackets are sometimes used to enclose phonetic transcriptions

(in accordance with a current practice), but the brackets are omitted where there seems to be nodanger of ambiguity. [remainder of note omitted]

The semivowels, w of  wet  and  y of  yet , are produced with virtually the same

 position as the vowels u and i, but with a rapid glide to the following vowel, so that theyhave the function of consonants.

The h is merely a strong breathing. There is no independent mouth position, which

is that of the coming vowel.

60

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 61/138

1. On what ‘speech’ consists in.

[Aristotle], Probl. X. 39 (tr. B.A.M.)

 Now speech28 consists in conveying a meaning not by the voice [=  phone], but bycertain affections of it [=  pathesin],29 and not only shows pain and pleasure. But the

letters30 are certain affections of the voice.

James Mark Baldwin, Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, s.v. Articulation.

Articulation (vocal) [Lat. articulatio, a joining together]: Ger.  Artikulirung ; Fr.

articulation; Ital. articolazione. The act of co-operation among the organs of speech inlarynx and mouth, whereby, through modification or check of the breath-current, distinct

speech-sounds are produced. The character of speech-sounds is determined by the noises

generated as the breath-current passes the articulated organs, or by the resonancedependent on the form of the resonance cavity in mouth and nose created in the

articulation, or by both. See Vietor,  Elemente d .  Phonetik , 2nd ed., §§ 1 ff. Whitney’s

definition ( Proc. Amer . Philol . Assoc., 1881, 22) is: ‘Articulation is virtually syllabication —a breaking of the stream of utterance into joints, by the intervention of closer utterances

or consonants between the opener utterances or vowels.’ This does not represent with any

exactness the present scientific use of the term, though it may be etymologically more

correct.

2. On the universal elements in grammar.

R. H. Robins, “Noun and Verb in Universal Grammar” (In:  Diversions of 

 Bloomsbury: Selected Writings on Linguistics. Amsterdam, 1970, pp. 295-296) (First

Published in: Language 28 [1952] 289-298).

In the article by Burt and Ethel Aginsky referred to at the outset, the universal

elements of grammar are given as segments, morphemes, and significant sequences of 

morphemes.40 These, and some other terms employed in grammatical analysis—word(minimal free form), suffix, prefix, juncture, aggluti- [295-296]

40 Word 4.168.72 (1948). [= Burt W. and Ethel G. Aginsky, Word 4.168-72 (1948)]

nation, inflection, and so on—can be claimed by us as universally applicable, because, for 

us, all language consists of events in one dimension, time. In employing such terms we aredoing no more than segmenting the unidimensional stream of speech into various

meaningful pieces more or less independent; we are not attributing to the language itself 

or to its component parts any categories of meaning, however, abstract, that are found in

the semantics of our own language. These categories are, therefore, of an altogether different order from word-classes (nouns, verbs, and the rest) and the secondary categories

associated with them.§

28 = logos, a species of which is dialektos, = phone enarthros, ‘articulate vocal sound’.29 Cf. Poet . 25 on the ‘passions’ of the voice.30 = grammata, = stoicheia, ‘elementary speech sounds’, = ‘phonemes’.

61

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 62/138

VI. ON SPEECH AS A SPECIES OF DISCRETE QUANTITY.

Aristotle, Cat . 6 (4b 20 ff.) (Lat. tr. Boethius; Eng tr. B.A.M.).

Quantitas autem, aliud quidem est discretum,

aliud autem continuum;

et aliud quidem ex habentibus positionem ad se

invicem suis partibus constat, aliud autem exnon habentibus positionem.

Est autem discreta quantitas, ut numerus et

oratio.

Continua vero, ut linea, superficies, corpus.

Amplius autem et praeter haec est tempus et

locus….

Similiter autem et oratio discretorum est.

Quod autem oratio quantitas sit manifestum est;

mensuratur enim syllaba brevi et longa.

Dico autem oratio cum voce factam, ad nullam

enim communem terminum particulae ejus

copulentur.

 Non enim est communis terminus ad quem

syllabae copulenter, sed unaquaeque divisa est,

ispa secundum seipsam.

But some quantity is discrete and some is

continuous;

and some quantity consists of parts having

 position with respect to each other, someconsists of parts not having position.

A discrete quantity is such as number and

speech.

A continuous quantity is such as line, surface, or 

 body,

and besides these there is time and place….

Likewise speech is also among the discrete.

But that speech is a quantity is obvious, for it is

measured by the short and long syllable.

And I mean speech made with the voice; for its

 parts are joined at no common boundary,

for there is not a common boundary at which the

syllables are joined, but each is divided and by

itself.

tr. Glen Coughlin:

In the case of number, though, one could not see how the parts have a certain position withregard to each other or lie somewhere, or which of the parts conjoin with others. Nor those

of time. For not one of those parts of time endure; but what is not enduring, how would

that have a certain position?

But you would say rather that there is a certain order, by there being a before and an after 

of time. And so too in the case of number, by one being counted before two, and two

 before three. And thus there could be a certain order, though you certainly could not find position.

And so too speech. For none of its parts endure, but it is spoken and one can no longer findit, whence, its parts could not have position, if indeed none endures.

Therefore, some are constituted from parts having position, some not from ones having position.

62

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 63/138

1. According to the Summa Totius Logicae Aristotelis.

Ignotus Auctor, Summa Totius Logicae Aristotelis, tract. III, cap. iii (tr. B.A.M.).

TR3 CP02

oratio est vox aggregata ex distinctis syllabis

eam mensurantibus, et in partibus suis non

habens permanentiam.

ad intelligendum autem praedictam definiti-onem, sciendum quod vox non ponitur hic pro

qualitate: est enim vox in tertia specie qualitatis,

ut infra patebit; sed pro aliquo quod fuit in voce:

quia in tali voce sunt multae dictiones et sylla- bae, quae licet indivisibiles sint, tamen sunt

successivae:

nam una succedit alteri.

unde in talibus syllabis est duo considerare:

scilicet indivisibilitatem earum, et successi-

onem.

talis autem indivisibilitas non est indivisibilitas

unitatis, alioquin oratio esset numerus:

sed est indivisibilitas mensurans durationem,

secundum quod tales plures syllabae indivisi-

 biles plus durant quam una.

unde si in oratione consideramus indivisibilita-

tem syllabarum, per hoc convenit cum numero.

si vero ibi consideratur mensura durabilitatis,

quae tamen non est semper stans, sed est suc-cessiva;

in hoc convenit cum tempore, quod est mensura<successiva et>** successivorum, ut infra

 patebit.

** The Latin words added to the text are taken

from the Marietti edition.

Speech is vocal sound [or voice] composed 

 from distinct syllables measuring it, and not 

having permanence in its parts.

In order to understand the aforesaid definition itmust be borne in mind that voice is not put

down here for a quality—for vocal sound is in

the third species of quality, as will be clear 

 below—but for something that flows* in the

voice,

* Reading  fluit with the Marietti edition of the

text.

since in such vocal sound there are many wordsand syllables which, although they are indivisi-

 ble, nevertheless are successive:

for one succeeds another.

Whence in such syllables there are two things to

consider: their indivisibility and succession.

 Now such indivisibility is not the indivisibility

of a unit, otherwise speech would be number:

 but it is an indivisibility measuring duration, in-

sofar as many such indivisible syllables endure

longer than one does.

Whence if in speech we consider the indivisi-

 bility of the syllables, in this respect it agrees

with num ber.

But if the measure of the endurance (of the

syllables) be considered there, which neverthe-

less is not always standing still, but is success-

sive— 

in this regard it agrees with time, which is a

<successive> measure <and (a measure)> of 

successive things, as will be clear below.

63

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 64/138

non tamen oratio est numerus simpliciter, sed

est numerus pertinens ad mensuram durationis:

nec est tempus continuum, quod nihil aliud est

quam successio continuata semper divisibilis;

sed est successio aliquorum indivisibilium, puta

syllabarum.

sciendum est autem, quod philosophus libro

 praedicamentorum dicit, quod oratio mensuratur syllaba brevi et longa.

alius textus habet quod syllaba brevis et longamensuratur oratione.

mensuratur autem oratio syllaba eo modo, sicut

dictum est, quod numerus mensuratur unitate

quae indivisibilis est, in quantum hujusmodi:

similiter etiam oratio mensuratur syllaba, quae

ut dictum est, indivisibilis est.

in hoc autem quod dicitur, talis syllaba brevis

est vel longa, non est intelligendum quod talis

 brevitas vel longitudo pertinet ad tempus

continuum, ita videlicet quod oratio sitaggregata ex multis temporibus continuis:

alioquin non esset alia species a tempore:

 partes enim temporis non faciunt aliam speciema tempore.

sed indivisibili durationi syllabae aliquando

coexistit tempus continuum, seu simul cum eo

existit:

quod tempus aliquando est breve, et aliquando

longum: unde tempus continuum est mensura

successivorum quae sunt in motu.

syllabae vero existunt in quodam indivisibili, et

sine motu, licet sint cum mutatione et success-sione, sub aliqua tamen mensura, ut dictum est.

unde mensura quae est tempus, et mensura quae

est ipsius syllabae, licet sint diversae mensurae

durationum seu durabilium, tamen possuntsimul existere.

 Nevertheless, speech is not number simply, but

is number pertaining to the measure of duration:

nor is it continuous time, which is nothing other 

than an always divisible continued succession— 

 but it is a succession of indivisibles, for ex-

ample, of syllables.

But it must be borne in mind that in the book of 

the  Predicaments the Philosopher says thatspeech is measured by the short and long sylla-

 ble.

Another text has that the long and short syllableis measured by speech.

But, as has been stated, speech is measured by

the syllable in the way that number is measured

 by a unit, which is indivisible insofar as it is of 

this sort:

likewise speech is also measured by the syllable

which, as has been stated, is indivisible.

 Now in saying this, ‘by such a short or long

syllable’, it is not to be understood that such

shortness or length pertains to continuous time

in such a way that speech is composed frommany continuous times—otherwise it would not

 be a species other than time— 

for the parts of time do not make a species other than time.

But continuous time sometimes31 coexists with

the indivisible duration of the syllables, or exists

with it at the same time:

 but the time sometimes is short and sometimes

long: whence continuous time is a measure of 

successive things which are in motion.

But the syllables consist in something indivi-

sible and without motion, although they involvechange and succession, yet under a certain

measure, as has been stated.

Whence the measure which is time, and the

measure which is the very syllables, although

they are diverse measures of duration or endurance, nevertheless can exist at the same

31 Should one read aliqualis rather than aliquando here?

64

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 65/138

et sic syllaba dicetur brevis vel longa, non ex

longitudine vel brevitate continua quae sit in ea,

cum ipsa sit indivisibilis;

sed ex longitudine et brevitate temporis con-

tinui, quod ei coexistit.

aliqui tamen dicunt, quod licet syllabae non sint

motus, tamen fiunt per motum.

cum autem omnis motus mensuretur tempore

continuo, propter hoc syllabae dicuntur longaevel breves, ex longitudine vel brevitate temporis

continui mensurantis motus per quos syllabae

fiunt.

alii dicunt aliter de oratione.

secundum enim eos cum numerus causetur ex

divisione continui, et nihil addat supra con-

tinuum nisi divisionem in qua quodlibet est in-

divisum, et tamen est alia species quantitatis

quam continua;

ita accidit de oratione respectu temporis: nam

oratio est multa tempora divisa, quorum quod-libet est indivisum; et tamen est alia species a

tempore.

et sic patet de quantitate discreta etc..

time.

And in this way a syllable will be called short or 

long not from the continuous length or shortness

which is in it, since it is indivisible— 

 but from the length or shortness of the con-

tinuous time which coexists with it.

 Nevertheless, some say that although the syl-

lables are not motion, they still come to bethrough motion.

But since every motion will be measured by

continuous time, for this reason the syllables arecalled long or short from the length or shortness

of the continuous time measuring the motion

through which the syllables come to be.

But others speak of speech otherwise.

For according to them since number is caused

 by the division of the continuum and adds

nothing to the continuum except the division in

which anything is undivided, and yet it is a

species of quantity other than the continuous— 

in this way it happens with respect to time, for 

speech is many divided times, any one of whichis undivided, and yet it is a species other than

time.

And thus it is clear about discrete quantity, etc.

Duane Berquist, Commentary on the Categories. 6/21/96

 Now what’s the next thing he does when he goes towards speech? What’s the first

thing he says?

Likewise, speech is of discrete. That speech is a how much is clear.

But he does try to manifest that speech is a quantity. I think everybody who meets

speech is a little bit puzzled by that. So Aristotle stops and gives a reason why this is in fact aquantity. And notice he uses the word measure there, which is a kind of confirmation of what

I was quoting from Thomas in the  Metaphysics, that Aristotle is distinguishing the species of 

quantity by diverse measures. You have the exact word there. It reminds me of Thomas’s point when Aristotle distinguishes the four kinds of causes in the  Physics, and the last and

least known, of course, is the end. When he gets to the end he shows that it is a cause. He

doesn’t do that with the other three causes. Thomas says he does that because it’s not as wellknown. Speech is measured by the long and the short syllable. We would measure by the

65

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 66/138

accented and unaccented syllable. He’s talking about the  phone, the vocal sound. But notice

there’s a different measure, there, in the case of speech and in the case of number. Number ismeasured by the one. This is measured by the long and short syllable. There’s a different kind

of measure, therefore etc. But do the parts meet at a common boundary in the case of the

syllables? No. If you have the word “animal”, where do the syllables meet? They don’t. Now would one say that a syllable is measured by time? Later on, Aristotle is going to

talk about the accidental quantities. There’s some question about speech. One might wonder 

whether speech is an accidental quantity, as white is said to be large because it is spread over a large surface, so it is not the white as such but the surface over which it is spread, and wespeak of an action or motion as being long because it took a long time. Someone might say

we call the syllable long because it takes a long time, and the other short because it takes a

short time. If that were all there was to it, then you would have to put speech with theaccidental quantities. You would say there’s not in reality a different kind of quantity than

you have with time and the rest. On the other hand, you might say we are not concerned, here,

with things as things in this book. What we are concerned with in the category of quantity isdistinguishing them by a diverse kind of measure. You use something different to measure

with. We don’t simply measure speech by time, but by the long and the short syllable. We’d

say Shakespeare writes in iambic pentameter. Is it the amount of time the line takes that weare talking about? No. How do you get this 5? Because we’re measuring by the unaccented

and the accented syllable. You have five iambs, what you’re measuring, your unit you might

say, is four unaccented syllables and one accented syllable. Then you go to another meter, and

you have three syllables, and your unit is two accented, one unaccented syllable. You seem tohave a different kind of measure, and therefore a different kind of measured, and therefore a

different species of quantity as far as the Categories is concerned. When you look at quantity

in the  Metaphysics, and you’re more interested in real diversity, maybe you won’t have asmany.

2. Some further observations on the syllable.

Aristotle, Metaph., XIV. 5 (1092a 22-28) (ed. & tr. W. D. Ross).

e)/dei de\ tou\j le/gontaj e)k stoixei/wn ei)=naita\ o)/nta kai\ tw=n o)/ntwn ta\ prw=ta tou\ja)riqmou/j, dielome/nouj pw=j a)/llo e)c a)/lloue)sti/n, ou(/tw le/gein ti/na tro/pon o( a)riqmo/je)stin e)k tw=n a)rxw=n.

po/teron mi/cei;

a)ll’ ou)/te pa=n [25] mikto/n,

to/ te gigno/menon e(/teron,

ou)k e)/stai te xwristo\n to\ e(\n ou)d’ e(te/rafu/sij: oi( de\ bou/lontai.

Those who say that existing things come from

elements and that the first of existing things are

the numbers, should have first distinguished the

senses in which one thing comes from another,

and then said in which sense number comes

from its first principles.

By intermixture? [= ‘mixture’]

But (1) not everything is capable of 

intermixture,

and [25] (2) that which is produced by it is

different from its elements,

and on this view the one will not remain

separate or a distinct entity; but they want it to be so.

66

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 67/138

a)lla\ sunqe/sei, w(/sper sullabh/;

a)lla\ qe/sin te a)na/gkh u(pa/rxein,

kai\ xwri\j o( now=n noh/sei to\ e(\n kai\ to\plh=qoj.

tou=t’ ou)=n e)/stai o( a)riqmo/j, mona\j kai\plh=qoj, h)\ to\ e(\n kai\ a)/nison.

By juxtaposition [= ‘composition’], like a

syllable?

But then (1) the elements must have position;

and (2) he who thinks of number will be able to

think of the unity and the plurality apart;

number then will be this—a unit and plurality,or the one and the unequal.

3. Note.

A syllable comes from its elements by ‘composition’, not by ‘mixture’, for which

reason the elements must have position (which is a before and after or order in the

elements according to place). Note that ‘having position’ distinguishes the parts making upa composition from the parts making up a mixture. (In a mixture, the parts exist virtually,

rather then potentially or actually, and hence cannot have position.)

Aristotle, On the Generation of Animals, I ch. 18 (add) (tr. Arthur Platt).

We may also ask whether the semen comes from each of the homogeneous partsonly, such as flesh and bone and sinew, or also from the heterogeneous, such as face and

hands. For if from the former only, we object that resemblance exists rather in the

heterogeneous parts, such as face and hands and feet; if then it is not because of the semencoming from all parts that children resemble their parents in these, what is there to stop the

homogeneous parts also from being like for some other reason than this? If the semen

comes from the heterogeneous alone, then it does not come from all parts; but it is morefitting that it should come from the homogeneous parts, for they are prior to the

heterogeneous which are composed of them; and as children are born like their parents inface and hands, so they are, necessarily, in flesh and nails. If the semen comes from both,what would be the manner of generation? For the heterogeneous parts are composed of the

homogeneous, so that to come from the former would be to come from the latter and from

their composition. To make this clearer by an illustration, take a written name; if anything came from the whole of it, it would be from each of the syllables, and if from

these, from the letters and their composition.

So that if really flesh and bones are composed of fire and the like elements, the semenwould come rather from the elements than anything else, for how can it come from their 

composition? Yet without this composition there would be no resemblance. If again

something creates this composition later, it would be this that would be the cause of theresemblance, not the coming of the semen from every part of the body.

§

67

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 68/138

VII. ON ELEMENTARY SPEECH SOUNDS.

1. ‘Element’ as entering into speech according to Aristotle and St. Thomas Aquinas.

In ordering the principal meanings of ‘element’ in the  Metaphysics, Aristotle begins by stating that by an ‘element’ he understands

(1) the first constituent of which a thing is composed and which is indivisible in kind into

other kinds; for example, the elements of speech are those of which speech is composed and

into which it is ultimately divisible, while they can no longer be divided into other parts of 

speech distinct in kind from them. And even if they are divisible, but the parts are of the

same kind, they are called ‘elements’; for example, a part of water is water, while a part of a

syllable is not a syllable.32

St. Thomas comments on this passage as follows:

 Now he manifests this definition in four things in which we use the name ‘element’. For we

say the ‘letters’ themselves are the elements of vocal sound because every vocal sound is

composed of them, and first; which is clear from this, that all vocal sounds are resolved into

‘letters’ as into a last thing. For what is last in resolution must be the first in composition. Now the ‘letters’ are not ultimately resolved into other vocal sounds different in species. But

if they are divided in any way, the parts into which they are divided would be “of the same

form”, i.e. of one species, just as all the parts of water are water. Now a ‘letter’ is divided

according to the time of its pronunciation, inasmuch as a long ‘letter’ is said to have two

times, but a short [‘letter’], one [time]. Yet, neither are the parts into which the ‘letters’ are

thus divided different according to different species of vocal sound. For it is thus concerning

the syllable: for its parts are diverse according to species: for the sound is other according to

species which makes the vowel and the consonant, from which syllables are composed.33

Man’s speech, then, understood as articulate vocal sound , has as its basis the

syllable as composed of elementary speech sounds, the vowels and consonants; a vowel or 

consonant, inasmuch as it can be written, being known as a litera or ‘letter’ (cf. Boethiusabove, as well as St. Augustine, De Dialectica, ch. 5).

 Now it is clear from the foregoing passages that, whereas the ‘letter’ (which is

clearly a litera vocalis, or vowel sound) is divided into the long and the short, which is a

quantitative division, the syllable is divided into the vowel and the consonant, which is aqualitative division. But it must also be noted that St. Thomas’ account assumes without

remark the fact that vowels and consonants can only be divided out of  syllables, the reason

 being that only certain combinations of elementary vocal sounds are possible, and so arefound only in syllables, a point which I treat next.

32 Aristotle, Metaph. V, 3 (1014a 26-35) (tr. H. G. Apostle).33

St. Thomas Aquinas, In V Meta., lect. 4, n. 5 (tr. B.A.M.): hanc autem definitionem manifestat in quatuor,in quibus utimur nomine elementi. dicimus enim ipsas literas esse elementa vocis, quia ex eis omnis vox

componitur, et primo. quod ex hoc patet, quia omnes voces in literas resolvuntur, sicut in ultima. quod est enim ultimum in resolutione, oportet esse primum in compositione. literae autem non resolvuntur ulterius in

alias voces specie diversas. sed, si aliquo modo dividantur, particulae in quas fit divisio, erunt conformes,

idest unius speciei, sicut omnes particulae aquae sunt aqua. dividitur autem litera secundum tempora

 prolationis, prout litera longa dicitur habere duo tempora, brevis vero unum. nec tamen partes, in quas sic

dividuntur literae, sunt diversae secundum speciem vocis. non est autem ita de syllaba: nam eius partes sunt 

diversae secundum speciem: alius enim sonus est secundum speciem, quem facit vocalis et consonans, ex

quibus syllaba componitur .

68

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 69/138

In sum, in one way vocal sound is divided into literae; but literae are divided

quantitatively into the long and the short, a long being said to have two ‘times’ (=chronoi), a short, only one. But the syllable itself can only be divided qualitatively into the

vowel and the consonant (and the subdivisions of the consonant).

2. ‘Element’ as said of both the written and the spoken litera.

St. Thomas Aquinas, In I Peri Herm., lect. 2, n. 7 (tr. B.A.M.).

Second, when he says Those which are written, etc. he treats the signification of writing.

And according to Alexander, he introduced this in order to make clear the precedingthought by way of a likeness, as though the sense were: those in vocal sound are signs of 

the passions of the soul in the same way as letters are signs of vocal sounds.

He also makes this clear by what follows, when he says  And in a way neither letters, etc. introducing this as a sign of the preceding. For that letters signify vocal sounds

is signified by this, that, just as vocal sounds are different among different people, so also

the letters are different. And according to this explanation he does not therefore say and 

letters of those which are in vocal sound, but those which are written: the reason being that

they are called ‘letters’ both in utterance and in writing, although more properly, according

as they are in writing, they are called ‘letters’; but according as they are in an utterance, the

are called ‘elements’ of vocal sound. But because Aristotle does not say, and just as thosewhich are written, but makes a continuous narrative, it is better to say, as Porphyry

explained, that Aristotle proceeds in the last place to complete the order of signification.

For after he had said that names and verbs, which are in vocal sound, are signs of thosewhich are in the soul, he adds by way of continuation that names and verbs which are

written are signs of the names and verbs of those which are in vocal sound.34

3. On the collocation of elementary speech sounds.

The next point to consider is that, as Aristotle understands it, language arises fromthe various compositions or collocations of syllables, giving rise to the several ‘dialects’ or 

‘tongues’ spoken by the various ethnic groups, a collocation which, in any tongue or 

language, as we have observed, happens only in a limited number of ways. To see how thisis so, it will be helpful here to review Aristotle’s teaching on the voice in relation to

language, already met with above:

34  secundo, cum dicit: et ea quae scribuntur etc., agit de significatione scripturae: et secundum alexandrum

hoc inducit ad manifestandum praecedentem sententiam per modum similitudinis, ut sit sensus: ita ea quae

 sunt in voce sunt signa passionum animae, sicut et litterae sunt signa vocum. quod etiam manifestat per 

 sequentia, cum dicit: et quemadmodum nec litterae etc.; inducens hoc quasi signum praecedentis. quod enimlitterae significent voces, significatur per hoc, quod, sicut sunt diversae voces apud diversos, ita et diversae

litterae. et secundum hanc expositionem, ideo non dixit, et litterae eorum quae sunt in voce, sed ea quae scribuntur: quia dicuntur litterae etiam in prolatione et scriptura, quamvis magis proprie, secundum quod 

 sunt in scriptura, dicantur litterae; secundum autem quod sunt in prolatione, dicantur elementa vocis. sed 

quia aristoteles non dicit, sicut et ea quae scribuntur, sed continuam narrationem facit, melius est ut dicatur,

 sicut porphyrius exposuit, quod aristoteles procedit ulterius ad complendum ordinem significationis.

 postquam enim dixerat quod nomina et verba, quae sunt in voce, sunt signa eorum quae sunt in anima,

continuatim subdit quod nomina et verba quae scribuntur, signa sunt eorum nominum et verborum quae sunt 

in voce.

69

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 70/138

Vocal sounds and modes of language differ according to locality. Vocal sounds are

characterized chiefly by their pitch, whether high or low, and the kinds of sound capable of 

 being produced are identical within the limits of one and the same species; but articulate

[vocal] sound, that one might reasonably designate ‘language’ [dialektoj], differs both in

various animals, and also in the same species according to diversity of locality…. Men have

the same voice or vocal sounds, but they differ from one another in speech or language.35

Voice [fonh=] and sound [yofoj] are different from one another; and language [dialektoj]

differs from voice and sound. The fact is that no animal can give utterance to voice except[30] by the action of the pharynx, and consequently such animals as are devoid of lung have

no voice; and language is the articulation of vocal sounds by the tongue. Thus, the voice and

larynx can emit vowel sounds; consonantal sounds are made by the tongue and the lips; and

out of these language is composed. Consequently, animals that [535a] have no tongue at all

or that have a tongue not freely detached, have no language; although they may be enabled

to make sounds by other organs than the tongue.36

For this creature [the dolphin] has a voice, for it is furnished with a lung and a windpipe; but

its tongue is not loose, nor has it lips, so as to give utterance to an articulate sound.37

 Now speech through the voice is composed of letters, and most of these letters would be

impossible to pronounce were the lips not moist, nor the tongue such as it is. For some areformed by the closure of the lips and others by applications of the tongue. But of what sortand how many such differences these things have, must be sought from those skilled in

metrics.38

Why does this speech take different forms, when it does not with other animals? Is it because

man can utter a number of letters, but of the other animals some utter none and some only

two or three consonants? These consonants combined with vowels make articulate speech

[dialektoj]. Now speech consists in conveying a meaning not by the voice [ fonh=], but by

certain affections [or ‘passions’, paqesin] of it, and not only shows pain and pleasure. But

the letters are certain affections of the voice.39

But voice is the sound belonging to a thing with soul. For no inanimate thing has a voice,though they are said to give voice by a likeness, as the aulos, the lyre, and other inanimate

things that have prolongation, melody, and idiom [dialektoj].40

 Notice that in this final text dialektos refers to a musical quality of the voice. In order tounderstand this usage, we must turn to further witnesses. Let us begin with the following

 passage from the Peripatetic Adrastus as reported by Theon of Smyrna:41

(tr. R & D. Lawlor)

VI. Adrastus, the student of Aristotle, in his

(tr. Andrew Barker)

(49.6) Adrastus the Peripatetic, who discusses

35 Aristotle, Hist. Animal. IV, 9 (536b 9-14, 19-20) (tr. D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson).36 Ibid. IV. 9 (534b 29—535a 2).37 Ibid. IV. 9 (536a 2-3).38 Aristotle, De Part. Animal., II. 16 (tr. W. Ogle) (660a 3-10).39 [Aristotle], Probl. X. 39 (895a 7-14) (tr. W. S. Hett; rev. B.A.M.).40 Aristotle,  De An. II. 8, 420b 6-8: h( de\ fonh\ yo/foj ti/j e)stin e)my/xou. tw=n ga\r a)yu/xwnou)qe\n fwnei=, a)lla\ kaq) o(moio/thta le/getai fwnei=n, oi(=on au)lo\j kai\ lu/ra kai\ o(/sa a)/lla

tw=n a)yu/xwn a)po/tasin e)/xei kai\ me/loj kai\ dia/lekton .41 Theon of Smyrna, Mathematics Useful for the Understanding of Plato, Book II: Music. On Consonances

(49.6-21) (tr. Andrew Barker, Gk ed. Hiller added by B.A.M.).

70

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 71/138

well known treatise On Harmony and 

Consonance, says:

Likewise, in discourse, whether written or 

spoken, verbs and nouns are the most important

 parts;

the essential parts of verbs and nouns are the

syllables composed of letters;

and letters are the primary signs of language,

 being elementary, indivisible and the shortest

element,

since discourse is composed of letters and, in

the end, resolves into letters.

In the same way, that which makes up the principal part of sound and of all melody are the

systems called tetrachords, pentachords and

octachords, which are composed of intervals

which are themselves composed of sounds,

these sounds being the primary and indivisible

elements of which all melody is composed, and

into which it definitively resolves itself….

The sounds differ from each other throughtensions, some being higher, others lower.

These tensions are defined in different manners.

harmonia and concordance more intelligibly

[than Thrasymachus], speaks as follows.

Just as the wholes [holoscherê] constituting the

 primary parts [ prôta merê] of written sound [en-

 grammtou phônês] and of all speech [ pantos tou

logou] are the verbs and nouns [rhêmata kai

onomata],

(10) and their parts are the syllables, which

themselves arise from letters,

while the letters are the primary sounds, ele-

mentary, indivisible and smallest

(for speech is put together out of letters as its

first constituents and is resolved into them as its

last),

so also the wholes that are parts of melodic andattuned sound [tês emmelous kai

hermosomenês phonês] and of all melody

[ pantos tou melous] are what are called

 systemata (tetrachords, pen-tachords and

octachords): they arise out of intervals [ta

diastemata], and the intervals out of notes [ex

 phthongôn],which once again are primary and

indivisible and elementary (20) sounds, out of which, as its first constituents, all melody is put

together, and into which, as its last, it is

resolved.1

(50) The notes differ from one another in their 

 pitches [tais tasesin], since some of them are

higher and some lower; and their pitches [taseis]

are determined according to certain ratios.

Analogies between analyses of speech and of melody became common: they seem to have their 

origins in Plato Philebus 174ff…and 7 Aristox. El. Harm. 27.18ff. With this description of notes as‘indivisible’ compare the definition of ‘note’ mentioned in n. 29 to 10 Nicomachus  Enchiridion.

(Barker’s note) [N.B. For these and other related texts, see further below.]

 Note that the foregoing passage presupposes an understanding of the meaning of  melos.

For a Peripatetic definition of the term, cf. the following excerpt from the Aristotelian Pro-blemata:42

Why is it that among the sensibles the audible [or ‘what is heard’, akouston] alone has

character [êthos]? For even without speech melos nevertheless has character, but neither a

color, a smell, nor a taste has it. Is it because [the audible] alone has movement [kinêsis]?

42 [Aristotle], Probl . XIX. 27 (919b 26-30, 33-34) (Greek ed. Loeb; tr. W. S. Hett; rev. B.A.M.).

71

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 72/138

Though not the movement that sound produces in us, for movement of this sort exists in

other sensibles as well…. This [movement] has a likeness [sc. of ‘character’] both in its

rhythms and in the order of its high and low sounds [ en te tois rhutmos kai en te ton

 phthongon taxei ton oxeon kai bareon (= melos)],43  but not in their mixture [en te mixei].

As for the question we are investigating, the necessity of putting together theelements in a certain way, it is well explained in the following passage from Theon:44

(tr. R. & D. Lawlor)

VI. This series of modulations is not situated bychance, nor without art and according to a single

mode, but following certain determined modes

which must be observed in different types of 

melody.

For in the same way that in discourse, whether 

spoken or written, not just any letter combined

with any other letter produces a syllable or aword,

likewise in melody; it is not the combination of 

 just any sounds that produces the well orderedsound, or which, in its turn, produces the

interval appropriate to modulation;

 but it is necessary that this combination take

 place, as we have just said, following the law of 

defined modes.

(tr. Andrew Barker)

The process of advancing in a continuous seriesand in a melodic way, however, does not occur 

either randomly or in just one unique manner,

 but according to certain determinate methods

[tinas tropous], in accordance with which the

differences between what are called the ‘genera’

of melody [ genôn tês melôidias] are understood.

For as in speech and in written sound not every

letter when joined to just any other (20)

 produces a syllable or a word,

so also in melody, in respect of attuned sound

[kata tên hêrmosmenên], not every note placedafter just any other within the range of attuned

sound makes a melodic interval [emmeles poiei

diastêma],

 but only, as we have said, when placed

according to determinate methods.45

The following passages from Aristotle’s student, Aristoxenus of Tarentum,46 providefurther evidence of the Peripatetic provenance of this doctrine:

The nature of continuity in melody seems to be similar to that which in speech relates to the

 putting together of letters. For in speaking it is natural for the voice, in each syllable, to place

some one of the letters first, others second, third and fourth, and so on for the other numbers.It does not place just any letter after any other: rather, there is a kind of natural growth in the

 process of putting together.47

43 “The movement of the voice [= kinesis tes phones]…in the order of its high and low sounds [en te ton

 phthongon taxei ton oxeon kai bareon]”—that is to say, “the order of high and low sounds in the movement

of the voice”—is, of course, the definition of melos.44 Ibid., Book II: Music. On Consonances (52.13-22) (Gk ed. Hiller added by B.A.M.).45 Cf. 7 Aristox. El. Harm. 28.18ff. (Barker’s note)46 Readers familiar with Aristoxenus will recall that in many matters pertaining to harmonics he departed

from his master’s teaching, but in the doctrinal point at issue here he appears to be a faithful disciple of 

Aristotle.47 fai/neti de\ toiau/th tij fu/sij ei)=nai tou= sunexou=j e)n t$= mel%di/# oi(/a kai\ e)n t$= le/cei

peri\ th\n tw=n gramma/twn su/nqesin: kai\ ga\r e)n t%= diale/gesqai fu/sei h( fwnh\ kaq )e(ka/sthn tw=n sullabw=n prw=to/n ti kai\ deu/teron tw=n gramma/twn ti/qhsi kai\ tri/ton kai\te/tarton kai\ kata\ tou\j loipou\j a)riqmou\j w(sau/twj, ou) pa=n meta\ pa=n, a)ll ) e)/sti toiau/th

72

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 73/138

In singing, similarly, when the voice places intervals and notes in succession, it appears to

maintain a natural principle of combination, and not to sing every interval after every other,

either when the intervals are equal or when they are unequal.48

Cf. also the following:

And yet the order which relates to the melodic and unmelodic is similar to that concerned

with the combination of letters in speech: from a given set of letters a syllable is not

generated in just any way, but in some ways and not in others.49

Cf. Richard Janko, Philodemus, On Poems, Introduction, Ch. 5: Philodemus’s Sources and

Opponents, p. 172:

Sounds have a natural sequence, as the rules of Greek syllabification prove; combinations of sounds which are natural, i.e. syllables ending in vowels, are easy to pronounce, whereas

those which are against nature, i.e. those ending in continuants or obstruents, are less

attractive (120).50  pla- and kla- are pleasant, whereas iota is not (122 I-123 16). Of non-

nasal stops, voiceless are better than voiced; the aspirated ones are worst, as they have

unpleasant associations (122-4).

Cf. ibid., footnote 3, p. 259.

Pausimachus considered speech to be a continuous stream of sound, which the ancient reader 

(lacking spaces between the words) had to divide into segments by merismo/j: see 92. This

notion goes back at least to Aristoxenus El. Harm. 1. 27, 2. 37 (cited in Introd., p. 170, n. 3);

cf. D.H. Dem. 40. 5 (of h)=xoi), 43. 4 (of a(rmoni/a), Comp. 22. 39.

§

tij fusikh\ au)/chsij th=j sunqe/sewj.48 Aristoxenus of Tarentum, Elementa Harmonica I. 27 (ed. Da Rios; tr. Andrew Barker, p. 145) (remaining

Greek to be added). On the kind of whole at issue here, cf. Aristotle,  Meta., V, 25-26 (1023b 25ff., where thePhilosopher explains that this is the sort of whole which “so contains the things it contains that they form a

unity” (tr. W. D. Ross). In this sense, as he goes on to state, “...the continuous and limited is a whole, when itis a unity consisting of several parts”. But such parts cannot be put together in just any way, as he also

explains. An easily-understood sensible example is a jigsaw puzzle, which must be composed of certain parts

 put together in a certain way in order for the whole to exist as a unity.49 Ibid. II. 37 (ed. Da Rios; tr. Andrew Barker, p. 153): e)/sti de\ toiau/th tij h( peri\ to\ e)mmele/j tekai\ e)kmele\j ta/cij oi(/a kai\ h( peri\ <th\n> tw=n gramma/twn su/qesin e)n t%= diale/gesqai:ou) ga\r pa/nta tro/pon e)k tw=n au)tw=n gramma/twn suntiqeme/nh cullabh\ gignetai, a)lla\

pw\j me/n, pw\j d ) ou)/.50 Cf. Aristoxenus’ view that sounds have a natural sequence ( El. Harm. 1. 27, 2. 37, cited above, p. 170, n.

3), and D. H. Comp. 15. 4 (see n. on 120). (Janko’s note)

73

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 74/138

4. That one harmonia of the same notes differs from another if at one time it is in theDorian mode and at another in the Phrygian, which pertains to dialektos or ‘idiom’.

Aristotle, Pol. III. 10 (1276b 6-10) (tr. Antiquior & B.A.M.).

An homines quidem dicendum esse eosdem

 propter talem causam, civitatem autem

alteram?

siquidem est communicatio quaedam civitas,

est autem communicatio civium politica;

facta altera specie et differente politica,

necessarium esse videbitur et civitatem esse

non eamdem,

sicut et chorum quandoque quidem comicum,

quandoque autem tragicum alterum essedicimus eisdem saepe hominibus existentibus.

Similiter autem, et omnem aliamcommunionem et compositionem alteram, si

species altera compositionis sit,

velut harmoniam eorumdem sonorum alteram

esse dicemus, si quandoque quidem sit Doria,

quandoque autem Phrygia.

Sit itaque hunc habet modum, manifestum,

quod maxime dicendum eamdem civitatem ad

 politiam rescpicientes:

nomine autem vocare altero, vel eodem utique,et eisdem habitantibus ipsam, et omnino alteris

hominibus.

Si autem iustum dissolvere vel non dissolvere,

quando ad alteram politiam transmutantur 

civitas, ratio altera.

But should the men be called the same for such

a reason, but the city different?

if indeed, the city is a certain community, but

the community is the polity of the citizens;

the polity having been made other in species

and different, it will seem to be necessary that

the city not be the same,

 just as a chorus, often existing with the same

men, we say is different [if] at one time [it is]comic but at another tragic.

And similarly, [we call] every other communityand composition different if the species of its

composition is different,

 just as we say a harmony consisting of the

same sounds [notes] is different if at one time it

is Dorian and at another Phrygian.

If, then, these have the same mode, it is

obvious that the city ought to be called the

same looking chiefly to the polity:

 but one may or may not call it by another name, the inhabitants being the same and the

men wholly different.

But if it is just to dissolve or not to dissolve

[their agreements], when the city has been

transformed to another polity, is another story.

Aristotle, Pol. III. 10 (1276b 6-10)

o(moi/wj de\ kai\ pa=san a)/llhnkoinwni/an kai\ su/nqesin e(te/ran, a)\nei)=doj e(/teron h)=? th=j sunqe/sewj,

a(rmoni/an tw=n au)tw=n fqo/ggwne(te(ran ei)=nai le/gomen, a)\n o(te\ me\n

$)= Fw/rioj o(te\ de\ Fru/gioj.

And similarly, every other community and

composition (we say is) different if the species

of its composition is different,

 just as we will call a harmony of the same notes

different if at one time it is in the Dorian mode

and at another in the Phrygian.

74

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 75/138

St. Thomas Aquinas, In III Politic, lect. 2, n. 8 (tr. B.A.M.).

LB3 LC-2N.-8

deinde cum dicit aut homines quidem etc.,

solvens hanc dubitationem ostendit veram

rationem unitatis civitatis.

et dicit quod propter praedictam successionemhominum unius generis potest aliqualiter dici

eadem multitudo hominum;

non tamen potest dici eadem civitas, si mutetur 

ordo politiae.

cum enim communicatio civium, quae politia

dicitur, sit de ratione civitatis, manifestum est

quod mutata politia non remanet eadem civitas,

sicut videmus in illis qui dicunt cantiones inchoreis quod non est idem chorus si quandoque

sit comicus, idest dicens cantiones comediales

de factis infimarum personarum, quandoque

autem tragicus, idest dicens tragicas cantiones

de bellis principum:

et ita etiam videmus in omnibus aliis quae

consistunt in quadam compositione velcommunione, quod quandocumque fit alia

species compositionis non remanet identitas:

sicut non est eadem harmonia, si quandoque sit

dorica, idest septimi vel octavi toni, quandoque

autem phrygia idest tertii vel quarti.

cum igitur omnia talia habeant hunc modum,

manifestum est quod civitas est dicenda eadem

respiciendo ad ordinem politiae; ita quod

mutato ordine politiae, licet remaneat idem

locus et iidem homines, non est eadem civitas,

quamvis materialiter sit eadem.

 potest autem civitas sic mutata vocari, veleodem vel altero nomine, sive sint iidem, sive

alii:

sed si est idem nomen, erit aequivoce dictum.

Then when he says, Whether men indeed  etc.,

solving this difficulty he shows the true notion

of the unity of the city.

And he says that on account of the aforesaidsuccession of men of one race the multitude of 

men can in some way be called the same;

 but still the city cannot be called the same if the

order of the polity be changed.

For, since the community of the citizens which

is called the polity belongs to the notion of the

city, it is obvious that when the polity is

changed the city does not remain the same,

 just as we see in those who sing songs inchoruses that the chorus is not the same if at

one time it is comic, i.e. singing comedic songs

about the deeds of lowly persons, but at another 

tragic, i.e. singing tragic songs about the

 beginning of wars.

and in this way we also see that in all things

which consist in a certain composition or community, that whenever another species of 

composition comes about an identity does not

remain:

 just as the harmony is not the same if 

sometimes it is Dorian, i.e. of the seventh or 

eighth tones, but at other times Phrygian, i.e. of 

the third or the fourth (tones).

Since, then, all such things would have this

mode, it is obvious that the city should be

called the same looking to the order of the

 polity, so that the order of the polity being

changed, although the place remain the same

and the men the same, the city is not the same,

although it is the same materially.

 Now the city changed in this way can be calledeither by the same or by another name, whether 

they are the same or different.

But if the name is the same, it will be said

equivocally.

75

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 76/138

utrum autem propter hoc quod non remanet

eadem civitas facta transmutatione politiae, sit

iustum, quod conventiones prioris politiae

adimpleantur, vel non, pertinet ad aliam

considerationem, quod quidem in sequentibus

determinabitur.

But whether, on account of the fact that the city

does not remain the same when a

transformation of the polity has been made, it is

 just that the agreements of the earlier polities

 be performed or not, pertains to another 

consideration, which will be determined in

what follows.

Aristotle, Pol. III. 10 (1276b 6-10).

(tr. Antiquior)

Similiter autem, et omnem aliam communionem

et compositionem alteram, si species altera

compositionis sit,

velut harmoniam eorumdem sonorum alteram

esse dicemus, si quandoque quidem sit Doria,quandoque autem Phrygia.

(tr. B.A.M.)

And similarly, every other community and

composition (we say is) different if the species

of its composition is different,

 just as we say a harmony consisting of the same

sounds is different if at one time it is Dorian andat another Phrygian.

Aristotle, Pol. III. 10 (1276b 6-10).

(tr. H. G. Apostle)

In a similar manner, we speak of any other kindof association as being different whenever the

composition of its members differs,

as in the case of a scale whose mode is at one

time Dorian and at another Phrygian even if the

notes are the same.

(tr. H. Rackham)

And similarly with any other common whole or composite structure we say it is different if the

form of its composition is different— 

for instance a harmony consisting of the same

notes we call different if at one time it is

Dorian and at another Phrygian.

Note.

One harmony consisting of the same notes differs from another when the steps

 between the notes differ, just as our C-Major scale differs from the C-Minor. It is clear 

from this description that a harmony is a kind of disposition—that is, an order of parts in athing having parts, but according to form or species.

Aristotle, Pol. III. 10 (1277a 1-12 (tr. ed. Csapo & Slater).

There would not be a single virtue for the citizen and the good man. For the virtue

of a proper citizen must be common to all (it is necessarily in this way that the state is

 best), but the virtue of the good man cannot be, unless all citizens must necessarily be goodin a proper state.

Further, the state is composed of unlike elements, just as an animal is composed of soul and body, and soul, of reason and appetite, and a household out of a man and woman,

and a property of master and slave; and since in the same way a state is composed of all

these and other unlike elements besides, there is necessarily no single virtue common to all

citizens, just as among choreuts there is no single virtue for the koryphaios and the manstanding beside him ( parastates).

76

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 77/138

5. Supplement: Dionysius of Halicarnassus on the voice.

Dionysius of Halicarnassus, On Literary Composition, Ch. 11 (tr. Stephen Usher), pp.

77-80.

To prove the point, I refer to the case of instrumental music [tês organikês mousês],

whether it accompanies song or dancing [kai tês en ôidêi kai tês en orchêsei charitos ]: if it

achieves charm in everything it aims to do, but it fails to introduce variety at the right timeor strays from propriety, we feel the weight of satiety and have an unpleasant impression of disharmony with the subject. In oratory, as in music, the phrases possess melody, rhythm,

variety and appropriateness; so that here too the ear delights in the melodies, is stirred by

the rhythms, welcomes the variations, and all the time desires what is appropriate to theoccasion. The distinction is simply one of degree.

 Now the melody of spoken language [dialektou men oun melos] is measured by a

single interval, which is very close to that which is called a  fifth. When the voice risestowards the acute, it does not rise more than three tones and a semitone; and when it falls

towards the grave, it does not fall from this position by than this interval. However, the

whole utterance during one word is not delivered at the same pitch throughout, but one partof it is at the acute pitch, another is at [77-78] the grave, another is at both. Of the words

which have both pitches, some have the grave fused with the acute on the same syllable,

and we call these “circumflexed”; others have them falling on separate syllables, and each

retains its own quality. Now in words of two syllables there is no interval intermediate between low and high pitch; while in polysyllabic words, however long, only one syllable

carries the acute accent among the many others in low pitch.1 But music, both instrumental

and vocal, uses a considerable number of intervals, not the fifth only. Beginning with thewhole octave, it also uses in its melodies the fourth, the third, the tone, the semitone, and

even the quarter-tone quite distinguishably, according to some. Music requires that the

words should be subordinate to the melody, [79-80] 

1 [note omitted]

and not the melody to the words. Many lines of verse illustrate this, but none better than the lyric

which Euripides makes Electra address to the Chorus in the Orestes:

Be silent! Silent! Let the sandal’s tread

Be light, no jarring sound.

Depart ye hence afar, and from this bed withdraw.

Dionysius of Halicarnassus, On Literary Composition, Ch. 11 (tr. Stephen Usher), pp.

81-82.

The same thing happens with regard to rhythm. For the diction of prose does not

violate or even alter the quantities in any noun or verb, but keeps the syllables long or short

as it has received them from nature. However, the arts of music and rhythm change them by shortening or lengthening them, so that they often pass into their opposites: the time-

length is not regulated by the quantity of the [81-82] syllables, but the quantity of the

syllables by the time-length.1

77

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 78/138

 Now that the difference between music and speech has been shown, a few

remaining points may be made. If the intonation of the voice [ phônês melos]—not in song but in ordinary conversation [ou tês ôidikês alla tês psilês]—has a pleasant effect upon the

ear, it will be called “song-like” rather than “singing” [eumeles legoit an, all ouk emmeles,

lit. ‘melodic rather than in melody’]. So too the measured arrangement of the wordsaccording to their quantity [he d en tois chronois tôn moriôn summetria, lit. ‘the symmetry

of the durations of the parts’], when it preserves the lyrical form [ sôizousa to melikon

 schêma], is rhythmical rather than in rhythm [eurhuthmos, all ouk enrhuthmos].

2

I shallspeak at the proper time of the precise nature of this distinction.

1 Dionysius is here referring especially to the metrical devices of correption, synizesis, and perhaps

syncopation. (See Raven Greek Metre, pp. 24, 37-9)2 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric 3. 8. 1-3; Demosthenes 50 (Vol. I, p. 431).

§

78

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 79/138

6. On the three things in which a musical instrument resembles the voice, illustratingthe collocation of elementary speech sounds.

Aristotle, De Anima II. 8 (420b 6-9) (tr. J. A. Smith).

Voice is a kind of sound characteristic of what has soul in it; nothing that is without

soul utters voice, it being only by a metaphor that we speak of the voice of the flute [ aulos]

or the lyre [kithara] or generally of what (being without soul) possesses the power of  producing a succession of notes which differ in length and pitch and timbre. The metaphor is based on the fact that all these differences are found also in voice.

St. Thomas Aquinas, In II De Anima, lect. 18, nn. 2-3 (tr. B.A.M.).

LB2 LC18N.-2

nullum autem inanimatum habet vocem.

et si aliquando aliquod eorum dicatur habere

vocem, hoc est secundum similitudinem, sicut

tibia et lyra et huiusmodi instrumenta dicuntur habere vocem.

habent enim tria, eorum soni, in quibus

assimilantur voci.

quorum primum est extensio.

manifestum est enim quod in corporibusinanimatis ex simplici percussione causatur 

sonus:

unde, cum percussio statim transeat, sonusetiam cito transit et non continuatur.

sed vox causatur ex percussione aeris ad

vocalem arteriam, ut post dicetur:

quae quidem percussio continuatur secundum

appetitum animae, et ideo vox extendi potest et

continuari.

illa igitur instrumenta, de quibus dictum est, exhoc ipso quod habent quamdam continuitatem

in suo sono, habent similitudinem vocis.

But no inanimate thing has a voice.

And if sometimes some one of them is said to

have a voice, this is according to a likeness, as

the aulos and the lyre and other instruments of the sort are said to have a voice.

For their sounds have three things in which they

are likened to the voice.

The first is prolongation.

For it is obvious that in inanimate bodies soundis caused by a simple percussion [‘stroke’,

‘blow’]:

and so, since the percussion passes away atonce, the sound also passes quickly and is not

continued.

But voice is caused by a percussion of air 

against the vocal artery [= ‘windpipe’], as will

 be stated hereafter— 

a percussion which is continued according to a

desire of the soul—and so the voice can be

 prolonged and continued.

The instruments mentioned, then, because theyhave a certain continuity in their sound, have a

likeness to the voice.

LB2 LC18N.-3

secundum autem, in quo assimilantur voci, est

melos, idest consonantia.

But the second thing in which they are likened

to the voice is melos —that is, consonance.

79

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 80/138

sonus enim corporis inanimati, cum ex simplici

 percussione proveniat, uniformis est, non

habens in se diversitatem gravis et acuti:

unde in eo non est consonantia, quae ex eorum

 proportione causatur.

sed vox diversificatur secundum grave et

acutum, eo quod percussio, quae causat vocem,diversimode fit secundum appetitum animalis

vocem emittentis.

unde, cum in praedictis instrumentis distinctio

sit gravis et acuti in sono, eorum sonus est cumquadam melodia ad similitudinem vocis.

For the sound of an inanimate body, since it

comes from a simple percussion, is uniform, not

having in itself the diversity of low and high.

And so there is no consonance in it, which is

caused by their proportion [i.e. ‘ratio’].

But the voice is diversified according to the low

and high by the fact that a percussion whichcauses the voice is produced in diverse ways

according to the desire of the animal uttering thevoice.

And so, since in the instruments mentioned

there is a distinction of the low and the high insound, their sound has a certain ‘melody’

similar to the voice.

LB2 LC18N.-3

tertium, in quo sonus horum instrumentorumhabet similitudinem vocis, est locutio, idest

interpretatio sonorum ad similitudinem

locutionis.

manifestum est enim, quod humana locutio non

est continua;

unde et in libro praedicamentorum, oratio, quaein voce profertur ponitur species quantitatis

discretae.

distinguitur enim oratio per dictiones, et dictio

 per syllabas; et hoc accidit propter diversas

 percussiones aeris ab anima.

et similiter sonus praedictorum instrumentorum

distinguitur secundum diversas percussiones,

utpote diversarum chordarum, vel diversorum

flatuum, aut aliquorum huiusmodi.

The third thing in which the sound of theseinstruments has a likeness to the voice is

locution —that is, an interpretation of sounds

similar to locution.

For it is obvious that human locution is not

continuous;

and so, in the book of the  Predicaments, [cf.

Cat., 6, 4b 20] the speech which is brought forth

in the voice is placed in the species of discrete

quantity.

For speech is distinguished by words, and a

word by syllables; and this happens on account

of diverse percussions of the air by the soul.

And likewise the sound of the aforesaid

instruments is distinguished according to

different percussions, for example, of different

strings, or of different breaths, or of other things

80

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 81/138

of the sort.

N.B. Following Moerbeke’s translation, which reads locutio, St. Thomas understands the

third point of likeness to consist in the power to bring forth the voice discontinuously, the

syllables distinguishing it being either long or short, themselves arising from “diverse persussions of the air by the soul; but as we shall explain below, the reading dialektos (=

idioma) of our MSS leads to a quite different exegesis.

7. Note on lexis, dialektos, and the three points of resemblance.

As have seen, in Aristotle’s view ‘speech’ is not merely ‘articulate vocal sound’,

 but such sound insofar is it is ‘significative’ or ‘has meaning’. Now as one may gather from his several accounts excerpted above, in Aristotle’s usage the terms lexis and

dialektos, though they name the same thing in subject, namely articulate vocal sound ,

nevertheless differ in account; the name dialektos being used by him to designatearticulate vocal sound according as it arises from a combination of vocal sounds (vowel,

 semi-vowel, and mute); but lexis is the term he uses when considering the same thing

according as it is measured by the long and short syllable, and hence prescinding from its

qualitative composition out of vocal sounds. As an example of the former usage, cf. Historia Animalium, IV. 9 (535a 29-30), where the Philosopher defines ‘language’ [=

dialektos] as “the articulation of vocal sounds by the instrumentality of the tongue”; but in

what immediately follows (at 535a 30) he goes on to explain ‘articulation’ as meaning “asound of vowel and consonant in combination”, in which usage the name is manifestly

taken qualitatively. As an example of the latter, consider, for instance,  Rhetoric, III. 1

(1430b 30-31), where he says, “As for the arrangement [ schema] of the language [= lexis],number is rhythm, of which metres [or ‘verses’] are a part. Thus, speech [= logos] should

have rhythm, but not metre. For then it will be poetry [=  poiêma]” (tr. B.A.M.). Taking the

foregoing passage together with the passage from the Categories referenced above, thereader will observe that Aristotle uses lexis to designate articulate vocal sound

quantitatively, according as it is measured by long and short syllables, themselves being

caused by “different percussions of the air by the soul”, as we have seen. Now as many of the witnesses cited note, there is an analogy between speech and

musical sound: for, just as in the notes produced by a musical instrument certain

elementary tones are naturally apt to be composed in certain ways so as to form intervals,

as the tones themselves are composed of certain ‘harmonics’ or partial tones in ‘voices’,so, too, elementary vocal sounds are composed in certain ways to form syllables.51 

Consequently, just as a distinctive way of composing elementary musical tones into

intervals and intervals into ‘systems’ produces the ‘idiom’ characteristic of a harmonicgenus, or the timbre characteristic of a musical instrument, so also a distinctive way of 

composing elementary speech sounds, vowels, semi-vowels, and consonants, into

syllables, and the syllables into words, produces a unique ‘tongue’ or ‘idiom’.

51 For, as Richard Janko notes (op. cit., p. 172), certain combinations are natural and hence pleasing to the

ear : “Sounds have a natural sequence, as the rules of Greek syllabification prove; combinations of soundswhich are natural, i.e. syllables ending in vowels, are easy to pronounce, whereas those which are against

nature, i.e. those ending in continuants or obstruents, are less attractive”. Likewise, there is a natural

combination of musical sounds constituting a distinct ‘idiom’ or  harmonia, as a whole tone combined with

another whole tone and a semi-tone compose a tetrachord of the diatonic genus, according to which

combination it differs from a tetrachord arranged in the enharmonic genus. Similarly, the tones produced by a

lyre differ in the composition of ‘harmonics’ or partial tones from that of a wind instrument, like the aulos,

giving the instrument its characteristic timbre, as will be explained below on the overtone series.

81

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 82/138

 Now it is evident that the difference between lexis and dialektos necessarily

impacts the correctness of St. Thomas’ interpretation,52 since the third point of likeness sounderstood, namely, as the production of the voice discontinuously, necessarily reduces to

the first point, which is  prolongation,53 and thus omits the point of resemblance produced

 by the collocation of elementary sounds producing an ‘idiom’, or ‘dialect’, or ‘timbre’.

(a) The three points of likeness:

(a) ‘prolongation’ (the producing and sustaining of the voice on a single pitch)(b) ‘consonance’ (its movement as by ‘steps’ from one tone to another)

(c) ‘idiom’ (the subsequent collocation of tones, as in small whole number ratios)

(b) The three cases to be considered in explaining the analogy:

(1) the speaking voice (itself including two cases)(2) the singing voice

(3) the voice of a musical instrument

(c) prolongation: the producing (and sustaining) of the ‘voice’ at a single pitch (cf. the

definition of ‘note’ as the incidence or sustaining of the voice on a single pitch):

(1) in the speaking voice:(a) the production of a vowel sound

(b) the production of the other kinds of littera: a semi-vowel or a mute

(2) in the singing voice: the production of a note(3) in the voice of a musical instrument: the production of a note

(d) consonance: having produced some first pitch, the producing (and sustaining) of the ‘voice’ at a subsequent pitch standing in a certain relation to the first pitch

produced:

(1) in the speaking voice:(a) the movement of the voice from a single pitch to another, not by steps,

constituting the intonation of the speaking voice

(b) such a movement constituting an interval according to a simple whole number ratio, such as 2:1, producing an octave, or 3:2, a fifth, etc., constituting a ‘harmony’ or 

consonance of the voice by steps (cp. the ‘root’ and ‘partials’ of an overtone series)

(2) in the singing voice: the same as (1)(b)(3) in the voice of a musical instrument: the same as (1)(b)

(e) idiom: the collocation of vocal sounds so produced:

(1) in the speaking voice: the collocation of vowels, semi-vowels, and/or consonants in

a determinate manner, as with the dialect or idiom spoken by a group or people

52 And note that the whole problem arises from St. Thomas’ text reading locutio instead of idioma here.53 For just as the power to sit is not other than the power to stand , so, too, the power to discontinue the voice

is not other than the power to sustain it on a single pitch , and so cannot constitute a  separate point of 

likeness.

82

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 83/138

dwelling in a certain place: Dorian, Phrygian, Lydian as dialects or idioms (=

‘tongues’ spoken by a people)(2) in the singing voice: the collocation of intervals of notes or tones: the dialect or 

idiom spoken by the singing voice: Dorian, Phrygian, Lydian, etc. as harmoniai or 

‘modes’(3) in the voice of a musical instrument: the collocation of intervals of notes or tones:

the dialect or idiom spoken by an aulos or kythera: Dorian, Phrygian, Lydian, etc.

as harmoniai or ‘modes’

54

8. The analogy between speech, poetry, and music.

To better understand the foregoing considerations, it will be helpful to see how the

analogy as spelled out above by Adrastus has its basis in Aristotle.

Cf. Rhet., III. 1 (1430b 30-31) (tr. B.A.M.):

As for the arrangement [or ‘configuration’;  schema] of the language [lexis], number is

rhythm, of which metres [or ‘verses’] are a part. Thus, speech [ logos] should have rhythm,

 but not metre. For then it will be poetry [ poiêma].55

Cf. also Poetics ch. 6 (1449b 35) (tr. B.A.M.):

[35] But by ‘language’ [lexis] I mean the composition itself of the metres [or ‘verses’, ten

ton metron sunthesin]….

Cf. also Poetics ch. 6 (1450b 12-15) (tr. B.A.M.):

But fourth is the language consisting in speech [ ton men logon he lexis]: but I mean (as was

said before), language is that interpretation which is by naming [ lexin einaiten dia tes

onomasias hermeneian], which has the same power in metres [or ‘verses’] as in speech.

In the first text, Aristotle says that speech will be ‘poetry’ ( poiêma) when thelanguage in which it consists is so configured as to have metre, a configuration, as isexplained elsewhere, resulting from a certain ordering of long and short syllables. And

note here that the definition is through  genus, ‘configuration’, and difference, ‘language’.

In the second, Aristotle gives another definition of  poiêma, although he does not there use

the name; the definition being given through form (‘composition’), and matter (‘metres’).In the third, the definition is from the end and the means for attaining it. By way of 

comparison, just as lexis understood as  poiêma —that is, ‘language’ understood as

‘poetry’—consists in a ‘composition of metres’ ( Rhet . III. 1, 1430b 30-31),56 so, too,melopoiia would consist in a composition of melodic phrases (mele)—a melos being the

order of high and low sounds in the movement of the voice (cf. [Arist.],  Probl . XIX. 27,

919b 26-30, 33-34). Likewise, in calling lexis a composition of metres, Aristotle is taking54 Note that the analogy regards the singing voice and the ‘voice’ of a musical instrument; but the explanationof dialektos requires the consideration of the speaking voice; there being a counterpart to each element.55 Note that Aristotle defines  poiêma as speech having metre. It will be recalled that the Sophist Gorgias in

his Encomium of Helen defined poiêsis in this way, whereas Aristotle understands the latter term as meaning

“plot construction”; cf. Poet . ch. 1.56 To take some examples: epic poetry consists in a hexameter line of verse composed with another and

another, etc., but elegiac poetry, in such a line composed with a line of pentameter verse forming a couplet,

which in turn is composed with other such couplets, etc.

83

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 84/138

the line of verse as the immediate constituent of poetry, where it is understood that such a

line is itself composed of ‘feet’, and ‘feet’ of ‘times’. Similarly, mele or melopoiia mustconsist of a  sustema or ‘arrangement’ like the tetrachord, which in turn is composed of a

lesser unit, namely,  phthongoi or ‘notes’. (And note also that the phrase “melodic and

attuned sound” in Adrastus is virtually a definition of  melopoiia, although he does notthere use the name.)57

9. Definitions applicable to articulate vocal sound in sum:

(a) poiêma

•  by causal predication: that arrangement58 of language which is effected by its

 possession of metre (worded by B.A.M.)

•  by genus and difference: language (lexis) in the form of speech (logos) so arranged

or configured as to have metre (cf. Rhet., III. 1, 1430b 30-31)59

(b) lexis

•  by form and matter: “the composition itself of the metres (or ‘verses’)” ( Poet . ch. 6,

1449b 35)

•  by that for the sake of which and the means thereto [looking to the signification]:

“that interpretation which is by naming” [or ‘which takes place through naming’;

lexin einaiten dia tes onomasias hermeneian], when, e.g., the names are disposed in

metre ( Poet . 6, 1450b 12-15)

(c) dialektos

•  by that for the sake of which and the means thereto [looking to the signifier]: “…

and language is the articulation of vocal sounds by the instrumentality of thetongue” ( Hist. Animal., IV. 9, 535a 29-30)

10. Correspondences (going from the ultimate parts, or ‘elements’, up to the wholes

which they compose).

In lexis (= ‘language’)

1. ‘letters’ (vowels & con-

sonants)

In metris (= ‘metre’, ‘verse’)

1. ‘times’ (long or short)

In melos (= ‘melody’)

1. ‘notes’ (high or low)

57 In a separate discussion, I endeavor to show that melopoeia may also be defined as ‘melodic composition’itself, or ‘sounds in melodic combination’—that is, a disposition (diathesis) consisting in an order of notes

( phthongoi) according to form or species (eidos) (such a form or species constituting the harmoniai).58 And note that ‘arrangement’ or  schema here means an order of parts in a thing having parts according to

the figure and species of the whole, which is the third meaning of  diathesis or ‘disposition’ Aristotle lays

down in the Metaphysics (cf. V. 19, 1022 b 1-2).59 Note that in the Poetics Aristotle never uses the word in this sense: rather, in every occurrence it names the

result of the activity of the poetic art, as in the ‘poems’ of Homer.

84

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 85/138

2. syllables

3. verbs & names (words)

4. speech (phrase; sentence) (=

logos)

2. feet

3. metres or lines of verse

(dactylic hexameter; trochaic

tetrameter, etc.)

4. verse (metrical composition)

(= poiêma)

2. intervals

3. systems (or arrangements) of 

intervals (Dorian, Phrygian,

Lydian, etc.)

4. melopoeia (‘melodic and

attuned sound’; ‘melodic com-

 position’ or ‘tune’) (=melopoiia)

11. Correspondences (going from the whole to the parts).

Speech is composed of verbs and names (which we call ‘words’); but words are composedof syllables; and syllables are composed of ‘letters’, understood as vowels and consonants

(the latter being divided into semi-vowels and mutes).

Verse is composed of metres; but metres are composed of feet; and feet are composed of 

‘times’, understood (in Greek and Latin) as the long and the short in duration.

 Melopoeia is composed of  systemata (that is, ‘systems’, or ‘arrangements’, ‘of intervals’), but systems or arrangements of intervals, or  harmoniai, are composed of  diastemata

(‘intervals’); and intervals are composed of  phthongoi (‘notes’), understood as the high and

low in pitch.

Gathering up the foregoing observations on ‘speech’, we arrive at the following

formulations:

• ‘speech’ (logos as oratio), understood as something brought forth in the voice;

• ‘speech’, understood as ‘thought’ (to dianoeisthai) or the unuttered conversation of 

the soul with herself ;

• ‘locution’ (lexis; locutio), understood as articulate vocal sound according as it includes speech, insofar as the latter is itself understood as being composed of long 

and short syllables;

• ‘language’ (dialektos), understood as articulate vocal sound according as it is

composed of the several species of vocal sound, the vowel, the semi-vowel, and the

mute (or ‘consonant’), as Aristotle divides them (cf.  Poet., ch. 20, 1456b 20ff.);

and finally,

• ‘speech’ (logos; oratio) considered as significative vocal sound.60

§

60 Considered thus, it is understood to be composed of the name and the verb.

85

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 86/138

12. Compendium of definitions.

 LOGOS  (‘SPEECH’, ‘DISCOURSE’). (1) Speech is significative vocal sound,

deriving from thought61  (The Suda, Lambda 658, tr. Marcelo Boeri; rev. B.A.M.); (2)

according to Plato,62 the result of the intertwining [ sumploke] of a verb [rhema] with aname [onoma], where the former is understood as that which discloses being [ousia] in the

form of  praxis or ‘action’ (cf. Sophist  262a), the latter as a significant sound of voice

unveiling being in the form of the one doing the action ( ibid.), with the intertwining or combination being such that there is the expression of action or inaction or of existence or non-existence (ibid. 262c); or otherwise as “giving an intimation about something which

is, or is becoming, or has become, or will be” (ibid.); (3) according to Aristotle,

“significative vocal sound, some parts of which are significative separately[kechorismenon;  separatim], that is, as an expression [or ‘thing said’,  phasis; dictio], but

not as an affirmation” ( De Int . I. 4, 16b 27-28);63 or again, according to Aristotle, (4)

“composite significative vocal sound some of whose parts signify something bythemselves [kath auto; secundum se]” ( Poet. 20, 1457a 24).64

 LEXIS (‘LANGUAGE’, ‘LOCUTION’; ‘DICTION’; ‘VERBAL EXPRESSION’).(1) Articulate vocal sound understood quantitatively, according as it is measured by long

and short syllables (B.A.M., after Aristotle); that is, (ii) “the distinguishing of speech by

words and a word by syllables by means of diverse percussions of the air by (= at the

command of) the soul” (St. Thomas Aquinas,  In II De Anima, lect. 18, n. 4); (2) in thesense of  poiêma or ‘poetry’, “the composition itself of the metres” (Aristotle,  Poet . 6,

1449b 35, tr. B.A.M.); or again (ii), “that interpretation which is through naming” (ibid.,

1450b 14).

61 lo/goj e)sti fwnh\ shmantikh/ a)po dianoi/aj e)kpempome/nh.62 Cf. Sophist 262 c-e (tr. B. Jowett): “Str. When anyone says ‘A man learns,’ should you not call this the

simplest and least of sentences [logoi]? Theaet. Yes. [d] Str. Yes, for he now arrives at the point of giving an

intimation about something which is, or is becoming, or has become, or will be. And he not only names, but

he does something, by connecting verbs with nouns; and therefore we say that he discourses, and to thisconnection of words [e] we give the name of discourse [logos]”.63 “For”, as Aristotle goes on to say, “not every speech is composed from verbs and names, ...but there is

speech which happens to be without verbs, ||for example, the definition of man|; yet a part will always have a

certain significance, for example, in ‘Cleon walks’, ‘Cleon’” (ed. rev. & tr. B.A.M.). Hence, unlike Plato,

Aristotle does not require the presence of “intertwining” for composite vocal sound significative by human

agreement to be ‘speech’. But as we shall see from a passage cited from the Theaetetus below, Plato himself 

allowed definitions to be instances of logos. This apparent divergence may be reconciled by recognizing thatwhile Aristotle’s definition is proper to logic, Plato’s understanding of  logos here, while also primarily that

of the dialectician, is nevertheless open to the formulation proper to the grammarian, as may be seen by

considering the following definitions: Dionysius Thrax, Techne Grammatike: logo/j e)sti le/cewj sun/qesij

dia/noian dhlou=sa; “Speech is a composition of words expressing a thought” (tr. B.A.M.); cf. also

Priscian, Inst. gramm. ii. 4. 14: Oratio est ordinatio dictionum congrua, sententiam perfectam demonstrans;

“Speech is a fitting ordering of words, expressing a complete thought” (tr. B.A.M.). Cf. also St. ThomasAquinas,  In I Peri Herm., lect. 7, n. 4, where he defines oratio perfecta, ‘perfect speech’, as that which

“completes a thought” [ perfectae orationis, quae complet sententiam], and “make[s] perfect sense in the soulof the hearer [(facit) perfectum sensum in animo audientis]”. Hence Plato’s account is to be understood of 

 perfect speech, rather than of speech simply.64 The parts which signify separately are, or course, the name or noun and the verb, the former being defined

as “vocal sound significative by human agreement, without time, no part of which is significant separately”,

the latter, as vocal sound signifying with time, “and a sign of something said of something else” ( De interp..,

16a 19; 16b 5), it being proper to “substance considered in itself” to be signified by a noun or a pronoun, as

St. Thomas notes (op. cit., lect. 4, n. 7), whereas “the verb signifies action or passion” (ibid., lect. 5, n. 5).

86

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 87/138

 DIALEKTOS  (‘DIALECT’; ‘IDIOM’; ‘LANGUAGE’). Articulate vocal sound

understood qualitatively, according as it is composed of vowels and consonants—that is,“the articulation of vowel sounds by means of the tongue and of non-vowels or consonants

 by means of the tongue and the lips” (cf. Aristotle, Hist. Animal ., IV, 9, 535b 29—535a 3).

IDIOM. In language, (1) that quality of a composite vocal sound which results from

the collocation of vowels and consonants in a certain way (worded by B.A.M.); in music,

(2) that quality of a composite vocal sound which results from the collocation of intervalsin a certain way; that is, the quality of a composite vocal sound which results from the presence of overtones (idem); syn. timbre.

13. On rhythm and metre.

[Aristotle], Probl., XIX. 38 (add).

We delight in rhythm because it has a recognizable and regular number, and makes

us move in an ordered fashion.

St. Thomas Aquinas, In X Meta., lect. 2, n. 15 (tr. B.A.M.).

Likewise also the vocal sounds by which we measure are many. For the quantities

of one metre or of one foot are measured by different syllables, of which some are short

and others long. Likewise also there is the diameter of the circle and also the side of thesquare: and any other magnitude measured by two things: for an unknown quantity is not

found except through two known quantities.65

14. On the definitions of rhythm and metre.

Order is in the before and after of things; but the before and after in movement

gives rise to a number; hence in bodily movement rhythm is the number of bodily motion

according to a before and after; not just any number, but some ratio. A definition of rhythm

can be induced according to an analogy with the definition of consonance given by St.Thomas, commenting on Aristotle ( In II Post. Anal ., lect. 1, n. 8): “Consonance is a ratio,

i.e. a proportion in numbers of the high and low”.66  Now since harmony is a consonance of 

sounds, it follows that harmony is the ratio or proportion in numbers of the high and low insound. But rhythm in speech is constituted by a number of long and short syllables in its

 pronunciation or expression, as is clear from the following text of St. Thomas ( In V Meta.,

lect. 4, n. 5): “Now a ‘letter’ is divided according to the time of its pronunciation,inasmuch as a long ‘letter’ is said to have two times, but a short (letter), one (time).”67

65  similiter etiam voces quibus etiam mensuramus, plures sunt. quantitas enim unius metri vel unius pedis,

mensuratur ex diversis syllabis, quarum aliae sunt breves, et aliae longae. similiter etiam est diameter 

circuli vel quadrati, et etiam latus quadrati: et quaelibet magnitudo mensuratur duobus: non enim invenitur 

quantitas ignota nisi per duas quantitates notas.66 Consonantia est ratio, idest proportio in numerum secundum acutum et grave.67  Dividitur autem litera secundum tempora prolationis, prout litera longa dicitur habere duo tempora,

brevis vero unum.

87

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 88/138

Again, at  In X Meta. V, lect. 2, n. 15, St. Thomas says: “For the quantities of one

metre or of one foot are measured by different syllables, of which some are short andothers long.”68 This understanding is also evident in the account Aristotle gives of the

several kinds of rhythm: “The paean is a third kind of rhythm, related to those under 

discussion. For it has the ratio of three to two [i.e. three short syllables and one long, thelatter equal in time to two beats], whereas the others are one to one [i.e. the heroic, with

one long syllable and two shorts], or two to one [i.e. iambic, a long and a short; and

trochaic, a short and a long]. And one-and-one half [i.e. the ratio of three to two] is themean ratio, and this is the paean.” ( Rhetoric, III. 8, 1409a 3-6, tr. W Rhys Roberts) Hence,rhythm may be defined as a ratio in numbers of the long and short in syllables; or more

simply as the ratio in syllables of the long and short . Now a given metre is a species of 

rhythm differing from it by the regularity of the recurrence of its characteristic foot,creating in the listener an expectation of its immediate return. So, then, metre can be

defined as a rhythm the regularity of the recurrence of whose characteristic foot creates in

the listener an expectation of its immediate return.

15. Definitions.

 RHUTHMOS  (‘RHYTHM’). According to its first imposition, (1) numbered

number (common doctrine); properly speaking, (2) the number of the configuration of the

language (cf. Aristotle,  Rhet., III. 1, 1430b 30-31); (3) by analogy with Aristotle’s

definition of harmonia, the ratio in numbers of the long and short in durations (sc. of thesyllables)—that is, the configuration of the words according to the long and short in

durations; or more simply, (ii) the ratio in durations of the long and short; also, (4) a

system of durations (‘times’ or chronoi) arranged in ‘feet’; hence, (5) the recurrence of a“recognizable and regular number” ( gnorimon kai tetagmenon aruthmon, [Aristotle],

 Probl., XIX. 38, 920b 34-5); or otherwise, (6) an order which follows the melos of the

harmonia (The Suda, s.v. “rhuthmos”).

§

68 quantitas enim unius metri vel unius pedis, mensuratur ex diversis syllabis, quarum aliae sunt breves, et 

aliae longae.

88

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 89/138

VIII. ON THE MOTION OF THE VOICE.

1. According to Boethius and Vitruvius.

Boethius, De Institutione Musica, Liber I (Source: Boethii De institutione musica libriquinque, ed. Godofredus Friedlein; tr. Calvin M. Bower).

[-199-] De divisione vocum earumque

explanatione.

XII. Sed de his hactenus. Nunc vocum

differentias colligamus.

Omnis vox aut suneches est, quae continua, autdiastematike, quae dicitur cum intervallo

suspensa.

Et continua quidem est, qua loquentes vel

 prosam orationem legentes verba percurrimus.

Festinat enim tunc vox non haerere in acutis et

gravibus sonis, sed quam velocissime verba

 percurrere, expediendisque sensibus

exprimendisque sermonibus continuae vocis

impetus operatur.

Diastematike autem est ea, quam canendo

suspendimus, in qua non potius sermonibus sedmodulis inservimus,

estque vox ipsa tardior et per modulandas

varietates quoddam faciens intervallum, nontaciturnitatis sed suspensae ac tardae potius

cantilenae.

His, ut Albinus autumat, additur tertia

differentia, quae medias voces possit includere,

cum scilicet heroum poema legimus neque

continuo cursu, ut prosam, neque suspenso

segniorique modo vocis, ut canticum.

12. Concerning the classification of voices and 

the explanation thereof 

Enough concerning these things. Now we

should consider the different kinds of voices.

Every voice is either  sunexh/j, which iscontinuous, or  diastematixh/, which it is

named when it is sustained by means of interval.

A voice is continuous when, as in speaking or 

reciting a prose oration, we hurry over words:

the voice hastens not to get caught up in high

and low sounds, but to run through the words

very quickly, and the impulse of continuous

voice is occupied with pronouncing and giving

meanings to the words.

Diastematixh/, on the other hand, is that voice

which we sustain in singing, wherein we submitless to words than to a sequence of intervals

forming a tune.

This particular voice is more deliberate, and by

measuring out differences of pitch it produces acertain interval, not of silence, but of sustained

and drawn out song.

To these, as Albinus asserts, is added a third,

different kind, which can incorporate

intermediate voices, such as when we recite

heroic poems not in continuous flow as is prose

or in a sustained and slower moving manner as

in song.

Vitruvius Pollo, The Ten Books on Architecture, (ed. Morris Hicky Morgan) Book V.Chapter IV: Harmonics.

[2] Vox enim mutationibus cum flectitur, alias

fiat acuta, alias gravis; duobusque modismovetur, e quibus unus effectus habet

continuatos, alter distantis.

[2] 2. The voice, in its changes of position when

shifting pitch, becomes sometimes high,sometimes low, and its movements are of two

kinds, in one of which its progress is

continuous, in the other by intervals.

89

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 90/138

Continuata vox neque in finitionibus consistit

neque in loco ullo, effiicitque terminationes non

apparentes,

intervalla autem media parentia, uti sermone

cum dicamus: sol lux flos vox.

 Nunc enim nec unde incipit nec ubi desinit,

intellegitur;

sed quod ex acuta facta est gravis et ex gravi

acuta, apparet auribus.

Per distantiam autem e contrario.

 Namque cum flectitur inmutatione vox statuit se

in alicuius sonitus finitionem, deinde in alterius,

et id ultro citro crebre faciendo constans apparetsensibus, uti in cantionibus cum flectentes

vocem varietatem facimus.

Modulationis itaque intervallis ea cum versatur,

et unde initium fecit et ubi desiit, apparet in

sonorum patentibus finitionibus, mediana autem patentia intervallis obscurantur.

The continuous voice does not become

stationary at the “boundaries” or at any definite

 place, and so the extremities of its progress are

not apparent,

 but the fact that there are differences of pitch is

apparent, as in our ordinary speech in  sol , lux,

 flos, vox;

for in these cases we cannot tell at what pitch

the voice begins, nor at what pitch it leaves off,

 but the fact that it becomes low from high and

high from low is apparent to the ear.

In its progress by intervals the opposite is the

case.

For here, when the pitch shifts, the voice, by

change of position, stations itself on one pitch,

then on another, and, as it frequently repeats thisalternating process, it appears to the senses to

 become stationary, as happens in singing when

we produce a variation of the mode by changing

the pitch of the voice.

And so, since it moves by intervals, the points at

which it begins and where it leaves off are

obviously apparent in the boundaries of thenotes, but the intermediate points escape notice

and are obscure, owing to the intervals.

2. The motion of the voice in relation to pitch and the overtone series.

Dr. Charles W. L. Johnson, “The Motion of the Voice, h( th=j fwnh=j ki/nesij, in

the Theory of Ancient Music” (TAPhA 30, 1899, 42-55), pp. 42-43.

 Many of the Greek treatises on music begin the development of the subject proper 

 by describing and analyzing the changes in pitch which take place in the course of human

utterance. The term applied to these changes was h( th=j fwnh=j ki/nesij. I propose inthis paper to consider the nature of this ‘motion,’ the merits and defects of the ancient

analysis, and the object of introducing the subject in treatises on musical theory, and then

to show what light is thereby thrown for us upon the nature of ancient Greek music.

In almost every sound there is present to a sensible degree the property or quality of musical pitch. Pitch, regarded as a physical phenomenon, may be defined as regularity or 

 periodicity in the vibrations of some suitable medium, such as air or water. Every set of 

regular or periodic vibrations constitutes what is technically called a simple sound, and thedegree of pitch of this sound depends upon the rapidity of the vibrations. A simple sound

of this nature will seldom, if ever, occur in the ordinary course of events. Those sounds

which appear to our senses the purest and simplest are in reality compound sounds inalmost every instance.

90

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 91/138

The material objects which generate the vibrations in the air are usually of such a nature

that not one set of vibrations only, but a number of sets at various rates is produced at oneand the same time. Now the effect upon the ear of such a compound sound depends upon

the interrelationship of the constituent pitches. If these pitches are not related to one

another on certain numerical principles, the sound is a noise. If, on the other hand, a certainrelationship exists between them, the sound is a musical sound. For a musical sound is a

complex, formed by a series of simple sounds. Of these the lowest in pitch is generally the

loudest. Superimposed upon this lowest pitch there will be found a group of fainter pitches,standing at certain definite distances from one another. These are the so-called overtones,and it is their presence which determines the ‘quality’ of the sound as a whole. Simple

though the sound may seem to the ear, it is, in reality, as it were, a chord, in which all but

one of the notes are faint. It is easy to see what a large number of combinations can beformed by varying the intensity of the several overtones, by omitting some and

strengthening others. In this way physicists account for the great variety of quality

observable in the tones of instruments and voices.

In a musical sound, then, of the constituent related pitches one is predominant. 69 

This gives the note its name and position. But in a noise, instead of order among the pitches we have confusion, instead of one predominant pitch, many pitches of considerable

intensity.

W.K.C. Guthrie,  A History of Greek Philosophy. I. The Earlier Presocratics and the

Pythagoreans. Ch. IV: Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans, p. 228.

 Additional Note: ‘Speed’ and pitch

The passage from Archytas himself suggests that he was also not very clear in his ownmind about any distinction between ‘speed’ and ‘violence’ of movement. Adrastus (second

century A.D. quoted by Theon, p. 50 H.), in a very lucid account of the Pythagorean

theory, clears up this latter obscurity, which may have been only due to carelessness of expression:

‘The Pythagoreans give the following account. Every melody and every note are sounds,and a sound is a blow inflicted on air which is prevented from dispersing. Therefore there

can be no sound, and hence no note, where the air is undisturbed. But when a blow and a

movement occur in the air, then if it is swift the note produced is high, if slow it is low; if 

violent the noise is loud, if gentle, soft. The speed and violence of the motions may or maynot stand in a relationship of rational proportion to one another. If they do not, the sounds

are disproportionate and discordant, not to be called notes but mere noises, whereas

motions that stand in a simple numerical relationship, or such that one is a multiple of the

other or superparticular to it [i.e. containing the whole plus a fraction with 1 for itsnumerator], produce genuine and mutually compatible notes. Some deserve to be called

only this, but those constructed according to the primary, commonly recognized and mostfundamental ratios are actually called concordant.’

69 I.e. the “root” or fundament of an overtone series. See further below.

91

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 92/138

3. Sound and pitch according to modern experimental science.

Frank Lamonica. Lesson Supplement: The Acoustics of Music. The Basics: Sound,

Vibration, Frequency, Pitch, and Amplitude.70

Sound is created by the vibration of some physical object. That object may be a

solid, liquid, or even a gas. All physical objects have a property called elasticity that comes

into play to create vibrations. Elasticity determines how an object that is deformed by someforce will tend to restore itself to its original position. A diving board is a good example of an object that is deformed by the diver and which restores itself to its original form after 

the diver leaves the board. The movement of the board from its rest position to the

maximum deformation and then back to the rest position is called a half cycle. Theelasticity of the object again comes into play as the inertia of the moving object actually

causes it to move past its rest position and to deform itself again in the opposite direction

of the initial force. The motion from the original position to the maximum deformation inthe opposite direction and then back to the original position is another half cycle. This back 

and forth vibration occurs at a rate that depends on the physical makeup of the object being

vibrated. A complete vibration occurs when an object completes two half cycles.

The rate of motion of the object is measured in cycles per second, which is the

definition of frequency—the number of cycles per second at which an object is vibrating.

The pitch of a sound is determined solely by the frequency at which the object is vibrating.This is a very important point—the pitch does NOT depend on the force used to set the

object into motion. The amount of force used controls the amplitude, or loudness, of the

sound, not the pitch. The pitches we use in our musical culture have evolved from years of experimentation and argument. It was not until a conference was held in London in 1939

with the blessing of the International Standards Association that the pitch of the note “A”

which is used today was fixed at 440 cycles per second. This replaced the prior internationally agreed upon “A” of 435 cycles per second which had been in place since

1859. The methods of computing the pitches in our 12 tone musical scale have a complex

 but interesting history which I’ll explain after we talk about harmonics, overtones, and

intervals. [end excerpt]

3. On pitch, tone, timbre, and related matters.

PITCH. In music, the position of a tone in the musical scale, today designated by a letter 

name and determined by the frequency of vibration of the source of the tone. Aninternational conference held in 1939 set a standard for A above middle C of 440 cycles

 per second. (Encyclopedia.com, sv. “Pitch”)

TONE. In music, a tone is distinguished from noise by its definite PITCH, caused by the

regularity of the vibrations that produce it. Any tone possesses the attributes of pitch,

intensity, and quality. Pitch is determined by the frequency of the vibration, measured by

cycles per second. Intensity, or loudness, is determined by the amplitude, measured indecibels.

70 (www.classic-guitar.com/less5sup.html [1/15/05])

92

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 93/138

Quality is determined by the overtones (subsidiary tones), the distinctive timbre of any

instrument being the result of the number and relative prominence of the over tones it produces. (Encyclopedia.com, s.v. “Tone”)

That quality of a musical sound which depends upon the comparative rapidity of thevibrations producing it; degree of acuteness or graveness of tone (sometimes also in

reference to the tone of voice in speaking). Also a particular standard of pitch for voices

and instruments, a concert pitch, etc. (Oxford English Dictionary, s.v. “Pitch”)

Pitch is something we subjectively perceive and it is directly related to the relative spacing

of the harmonics in a sound. (Stephen M. Sprenger, Re: Time domain pitch shifting)

In music, (the) position of a single sound in the complete range of sound. Sounds are

higher or lower in pitch according to the frequency of vibration of the sound waves

 producing them. A high frequency (e.g., 880 hertz [cycles per second]) is perceived as ahigh pitch; a low frequency (e.g., 55 Hz) as a low pitch. In Western music, standard pitches

have long been used to facilitate tuning. Usually a ′ above middle C (c′) is taken as a

referent pitch. The current standard pitch of a′ = 440 Hz was adopted in 1939. For some

eighty years previous, a′ had been set at 435 Hz. A confusing variety of pitches prevaileduntil the 19th century, when the continual rise in pitch made some international agreement

a matter of practical necessity. (Encyclopedia Britannica. s.v. “Pitch”)

Alistair Disley, Human Perception of Sound . Assignment 2: Human Pitch Perception.

Pitch.

To consider human pitch perception, we need a definition of pitch. The American National Standards Institute (1960) defines pitch as “that attribute of auditory sensation in

terms of which sounds may be ordered on a scale extending from low to high ”. Another 

simpler definition is “our perception of the frequency of sound ”. Pitch is, therefore, one of 

the essential percepts of sound. A more complex definition of pitch [is the following:]Pitch (psychoacoustics/music) The subjective impression of frequency, in the same sense

that loudness is the subjective sense of the intensity or amplitude of a sound. As such, pitchis a psychoacoustic variable, and the degree of sensitivity shown to it varies widely with

 people. Some individuals have a sense of remembered pitch; that is, a pitch once heard can

 be remembered and compared to others for some length of time; others have a sense of 

absolute pitch called perfect pitch. The pitch of a tone or note allows it to be placed in amusical scale; thus notes of a scale are often called pitches, and given names (A, B, C, C#,

do, re, mi, etc.).

Dr. Charles W. L. Johnson, “The Motion of the Voice, h( th=j fwnh=j ki/nesij, in

the Theory of Ancient Music” (TAPhA 30, 1899, 42-55), p. 43.

Pitch, regarded as a physical phenomenon, may be defined as regularity or 

 periodicity in the vibrations of some suitable medium, such as air or water.

Every set of regular or periodic vibrations constitutes what is technically called asimple sound, and the degree of pitch of this sound depends upon the rapidity of the

vibrations.

93

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 94/138

4. On frequency.

Sound is composed of three basic elements:  frequency, amplitude, and timbre. These are

all different characteristics of the sound wave itself, which is essentially a vibration in the

air that eventually reaches our ears.  Frequency is the number of cycles per second (cps or Hertz, Hz). In music, we call this  pitch. This is the relative highness or lowness that we

hear in a sound. The highest pitch produced by a piano has a frequency of 4,186 Hz, the

lowest 27 Hz. The range of human hearing varies from individual to individual, butnormally falls between 20 Hz and 20,000 Hz. Here are a few examples of pitches atdifferent frequencies:  Amplitude is a measure of how big/strong a wave is, and therefore

how loud a sound is perceived to be. In music, we refer to different levels of loudness as

dynamics. (http://www.nightcourses.com/articles/melodymaker.html [2/4/01])

Frequency refers to the number of vibrations per second made by the sonorous body; it

also indicates the number of oscillations per second occurring in the transmitting medium.(Charles A. Culver , Musical Acoustics. Chapter 7: Pitch, p. 83)

That quality of a musical sound determined by the number of vibrations per second made by a sounding body; that is to say, that attribute of a tone produced by the frequency of the

sounding body’s vibration, measured in cycles per second. (B.A.M.)

5. On the ‘high’ or acute and the ‘low’ or grave.

The ‘high’ or acute is that which is naturally apt to move the sense in a short time. (adaptedfrom St. Thomas Aquinas, In II Post. An., lect. 1, n. 9)

The ‘low’ or grave is that which is naturally apt to move the sense in a long time. (adaptedfrom St. Thomas Aquinas, In II Post. An., lect. 1, n. 9)

The ‘high’ or acute is that which is naturally apt to impact the sense more frequently (that

is, to strike it a greater number of times in a given period). (B.A.M.)

The ‘low’ or grave is that which is naturally apt to impact the sense less frequently (that is,

to strike it a lesser number of times in a given period). (B.A.M.)

§

94

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 95/138

IX. ON THE STRINGS OF A MUSICAL INSTRUMENT.

1. That in the strings of a musical instrument  one is called ‘prior’ to another insofar

as there is one determinate string (namely, the mese) relative to which the others are

placed at intervals according to a determinate rationale (such a ‘priority’ comprisingan order according to discrete quantity).

Aristotle, Metaph. V. 11 (1018b 25-29).

(tr. W. D. Ross)

Others are prior in arrangement;

these are the things that are placed at intervals in

reference to some one definite thing according

to some rule,

e.g. in the chorus the second man is prior to the

third,

and in the lyre the second lowest string is prior 

to the lowest;

for in the one case the leader and in the other the

middle string is the beginning.

(tr. H. G. Apostle)

With respect to order,

when there is some definite thing relative to

which other things are arranged at intervals

according to some formula, that which is nearer 

to that thing is called “prior”.

For example, in the chorus the second man is

 prior to the third,

and the next to the lowest string is prior to the

lowest;

in the first case, the principle is the leader, in the

second, it is the middle string.

St. Thomas Aquinas, In V Meta., lect. 13, n. 9 (tr. B.A.M.).

LB5LC13N.-9

deinde cum dicit alia secundum ordinem ponitmodum secundum ordinem in rebus discretis;

dicens, quod alia dicuntur priora secundum

ordinem, qui invenitur in aliquibus rebus

tantummodo quodam ordine associatis sibi, non

 per continuitatem, ut in praecedentibus

accidebat.

huiusmodi autem sunt, quae distant ab aliquo

uno determinato secundum aliquam rationem

determinatam, ut parastata, tritostata.

 parastata est prius tritostata.

Then when he says Others according to anorder he gives the mode according to an order in discrete things,

saying that other things are called ‘prior’

according to an order, which is found in some

things in no other way than by some order of the

things associated with one another, not by

continuity, as happened in the preceding case.

 Now there are things of this sort which stand at

intervals from some one determinate thing

according to a determinate rationale, as the parastat , the tristostat .

[Meaning ‘the one who stands second’ and ‘the

one who stands third’, namely, from the chorus-

leader.]

The  parastat is prior to the tritostat .

95

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 96/138

 parastata dicitur ille, qui stat iuxta aliquem, puta

regem.

tritostata autem ille, qui stat tertius ab eo.

unde alia litera habet, praestans, tertio stante

 prius est.

 patet autem, quod alia ratio distantiae est distareut secundum, vel tertium.

et similiter paranitae sunt priores nitis.

in chordis enim hypatae dicuntur quae sunt

graves, nitae vero acutae dicuntur, mediocresautem vocantur mesae.

 paranitae autem dicuntur quae sunt iuxta nitas

mesis propinquiores.

For he is called the  parastat which stands next

to someone, for instance, a king.

But tritotstat one who stands third from him.

And so another text has the preeminent person

is prior to the one standing third .

But it is clear that to stand second or thirdinvolves another rationale of distance.

And likewise the paranete are prior to the nete.

For in strings those are called hypate which are

low, but those are called nete which are high, but the ones in between are called mese.

But those are called  paranete which are next to

the nete (and so) nearer to the mese.

LB5LC13N.10

 patet etiam, quod hic dicitur etiam esse aliquid

 prius per propinquitatem ad aliquod principium.

sed differenter in utroque praedictorum

exemplorum:

quia in illis, scilicet parastata et tritostata,

accipitur principium id quod est verum initium

et extremum,

scilicet ille, qui est summus inter alios vel

vertex aliorum, ut rex vel aliquis alius talis.

sed in chordis accipitur ut principium, medium,

et media chorda quae dicitur mesa,

cui propinquiores dicuntur paranitae, et per hoc

 priores dicuntur nitis.

ista ergo dicuntur priora per hunc modum,

scilicet per ordinem quantitatis vel continuae vel

discretae.

It is also clear that in the present case something

is also said to be ‘prior’ by a nearness to some

 principle (or ‘beginning’).

But differently in both of the examples

mentioned:

the reason being that in the former case, namely,

the  parastat  and the tritostat , that which is a

true beginning and extreme is taken as the

 principle (or ‘beginning’),

the one, namely, who is highest among them, or 

uppermost among the others, as a king or some

other such person.

But in strings is taken as the principle (or 

‘beginning’) the middle one— 

that is the middle string called mese — 

the nearer to which are called  paranete, and by

this are called ‘prior’ to nete.

These, then, are called ‘prior’ in this way,

namely, by an order of quantity, whether 

continuous or discrete.

§

96

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 97/138

2. That the strings of a musical instrument are distinguished according to the high,low, and middle found in ‘sounds’ understood as ‘notes’.

Aristotle, Metaph. X. 7 (1057a 18-29)

(tr. W. D. Ross)

Since contraries admit of an intermediate and in

some cases have it, intermediates must be com-

 posed of the contraries.

For (1) all (1057a 20) intermediates are in the

same genus as the things between which they

stand.

For we call those things intermediates, into

which that which changes must change first;

e.g. if we were to pass from the highest string to

the lowest by the smallest intervals, we shouldcome sooner to the intermediate notes, and in

colours if we were to pass from white (1057a

25) to black, we should come sooner to crimson

and grey than to black; and similarly in all other 

cases.

But to change from one genus to another genus

is not possible except in an incidental way, as

from colour to figure.

Intermediates, then, must be in the same genus

 both as one another and as the things they stand between.

(tr. H. G. Apostle)

Since there may be an intermediate between

contraries, and in some cases there is, inter-

mediates must consist of contraries.

 Now all intermediates are in the same genus as

the contraries between which they are.

For we call “intermediates” those into which

that which changes into something must change

 before.

For example, if one were to pass from the

highest string to the lowest by the smallest inter-vals, he would come to the intermediate tones

 before; and if in colors he were to pass from

white to black, he would come to crimson and

grey before coming to black; and similarly with

the others.

But it is not possible to change from one genus

to another except accidentally, as from color to

shape, for example.

All intermediates, then, as well as the things

 between which they are, must be in the samegenus.

St. Thomas Aquinas, In V Meta. lect. 9, n. 1 (tr. B.A.M.).

LB10LC-9N.-1

 postquam philosophus determinavit de con-

trariis, hic determinat de mediis contrariorum; et

circa hoc duo facit.

 primo proponit de quo est intentio; dicens: quia

contrariorum contingit aliquid esse medium, ut

supra dictum est, et quaedam contrariorum

medium habent, ostendendum est quod necesse

est media esse ex contrariis.

After the Philosopher determined about con-

traries, here he determines about the inter-

mediates between contraries. And with respect

to this he does two things.

First, he lays down a proposition about what his

intention is, saying that because there can be an

intermediate between contraries, as has been

said above, and certain contraries have an inter-

mediate, it must be shown that inter-mediatesmust be (composed) of contraries.

97

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 98/138

non autem hoc solum ostendit, sed etiam

quaedam alia quae ad huius probationem sunt

necessaria.

LB10LC-9N.-2

deinde cum dicit omnia namque prosequitur 

suam intentionem;

et circa hoc tria facit.

 primo ostendit, quod media sunt in eodem

genere cum contrariis.

secundo ostendit, quod media sunt inter con-traria tantum, ibi, at vero media etc..

tertio vero ostendit, quod media componuntur 

ex contrariis, quod est principaliter intentum,

ibi, si vero sunt in eodem genere.

dicit ergo primo, quod omnia media sunt in

eodem genere cum his quorum sunt media.

quod sic probat.

quia haec est diffinitio mediorum, quod mediasunt inter quae prius venit illud quod mutatur de

uno extremorum, quam in alterum extremum.

 Not only does he show this, but also certain

other things which are necessary for proving

this point.

Then when he says  For all these, he carries out

his intention.

And with respect to this he does two things.

First, he shows that intermediates are in the

same genus with the contraries.

Second, he shows that intermediates are only between contraries, at But all intermediates etc.

Third, he shows that intermediates are com-

 posed of contraries, which is his principal inten-

tion, at  Now if intermediates are in the same

 genus.

He says, therefore, first, that all intermediates

are in the same genus with those things of which

they are the intermediates,

which he proves as follows,

(saying) that this is the definition of inter-mediates, that intermediates are those things

among which that which changes from one ex-

treme to another extreme first comes.71

LB10LC-9N.-3

et hoc manifestat per duo exempla.

 primo quidem in sonis.

sunt enim quidam soni graves, et quidam acuti,

et quidam medii.

et secundum hanc distinctionem sonorum, dis-

tinguuntur chordae in musicis instrumentis.

illae enim chordae, quae reddunt graves sonos,dicuntur hypatae, quia principales.

And he makes this clear by two examples.

The first in sounds [= ‘notes’].

For some sounds [or ‘notes’] are low, some are

high, and some intermediate [in the middle].

And in accordance with this distinction of 

sounds [or ‘notes’] the strings of a musical in-

strument are distinguished.

For the strings which give back low sounds [or ‘notes’] are called hypate because they are the

 principal ones.

71 That is, if there is a change from one extreme to another, the first things ‘among which’—that is, ‘into

which’—the one extreme must ‘come’ (or ‘change’, according to the Greek implied by the translations cited),

are called ‘intermediates’.

98

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 99/138

illae veroquae reddunt acutos sonos, dicuntur 

netae.

si igitur musicus paulatim a gravibus ad acutos

descendere velit, quod est transire per mediam

rationem, necesse est quod prius veniat ad sonos

medios.

But the ones which give back high sounds [or 

‘notes’] are called nete.

If, then, a musician wishes to descend by small

steps [= ‘gradually’ or ‘without leaps’] from the

highs to the lows, which is to pass through an

intermediate range, he must first come to inter-

mediate sounds [or ‘notes’].

LB10LC-9N.-4

sic igitur patet quod de mediis fit transmutatio

ad extrema, et e converso.

sed in his quae sunt in diversis generibus, non

fit transmutatio in invicem nisi per accidens,

sicut patet in colore et figura.

non enim mutatur aliquid de colore in figuram

aut e converso; sed de colore in colorem, et defigura in figuram.

unde necesse est quod media et extrema sint in

eodem genere.

In this way, then, it is clear that a change is

made from intermediates to extremes, and

conversely.

But in those things which are in different genera

a change between them is not possible except

accidentally, as is clear in color and shape.

For something does not change from a color to a

shape or conversely; but from a color to a color,and from a shape to a shape.

And so it is necessary that the intermediates and

the extremes be in the same genus.

3. That in the strings of a musical instrument one is called ‘successive’ to another (as

the  paramese with respect to the mese) when it comes after a beginning in positionaccording to a determinate rationale, and when it has nothing of the same genus

between it and that to which it is in succession.

Aristotle, Phys. V. 3 (226b34-227a 7).

(tr. Thomas Heath; rev. B.A.M.)

I call “successive” that which, coming after the

 beginning, and having been marked off either in

 position or in form or in some other respect, has

nothing of the same [genus] between it and that

to which it is successive.

Examples are a line or lines in succession to a

line, a unit or units to a unit, or a house to a

house.

There is nothing to prevent something of a

different kind coming between.

What is successive is successive to somethingand is something posterior to it;

(tr. R. Glen Coughlin)

“In succession” is that which, being after the

 beginning either by position or in species or in

something else thus determined, has nothing

among things in the same genus between itself 

and that to which it is in succession.

I mean , e.g., a line [is in succession] to a line or 

lines, or a unit to units, or a house to a house.

But nothing prevents something from being

 between.

For what is “in succession” is in succession to acertain thing and is after a certain thing.

99

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 100/138

thus one is not successive to two, nor the first

day of the month to the second day, but the

other way about.

For one is not in succession to two, nor the first

day of the month to the second, but the latter to

the former.

Aristotle, Phys. V. 3 (226b34-227a 7).

(tr. Hardie & Gaye)

A thing is ‘in succession’ when it is after the

 beginning in position or in form or in someother respect in which it is definitely so

regarded, and when further there is nothing of 

the same kind as itself between it and that to

which it is in succession, e.g. a line or lines if itis a line, a unit or units if it is a unit, a house if it

is a house

(there is nothing to prevent something of a

different kind being between).

For that which is in succession is in succession

to a particular thing, and is something posterior:

for one is not ‘in succession’ to two, nor is the

first day of the month to be second: in each case

the latter is ‘in succession’ to the former.

(example furnished by B.A.M.)

E.g. a string of a musical instrument, such as the

 paramese, is ‘in succession’ to another when itcomes ‘after the beginning’, which is the mese,

‘in position’, doing so according to a deter-

minate rationale, and when it has nothing of the

same genus between it and that to which it is insuccession.

St. Thomas Aquinas, In V Physic. lect. 5, n. 6 (tr. B.A.M.).

LB5 LC-5N.-6

deinde cum dicit: consequenter autem est etc.,definit hoc quod est consequenter, et quandam

speciem eius, scilicet habitum.

et dicit quod ad hoc quod aliquid dicatur esse

consequenter ad alterum, duo requiruntur.

quorum unum est, quod sit post aliquod

 principium quodam ordine;

vel secundum positionem, sicut in iis quaehabent ordinem in loco;

vel secundum speciem, sicut dualitas est post

unitatem;

vel quocumque alio modo aliqua determinate

ordinentur, sicut secundum virtutem, secundum

dignitatem, secundum cognitionem, et

huiusmodi.

100

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 101/138

aliud quod requiritur est, quod inter id quod est

consequenter, et id cui est consequenter, non sit

aliquod medium de numero eorum quae sunt in

eodem genere:

sicut linea consequenter se habet ad lineam, si

nulla linea sit in medio;

et similiter est de unitate ad unitatem, et dedomo ad domum.

sed nihil prohibet, ad hoc quod aliquid sit alteri

consequenter, quin aliquid sit medium inter ea

alterius generis; sicut si aliquod animal sit

medium inter duas domus.

quare autem dixerit et cuius est consequenter, et

quod est post principium, manifestat subdens,

quod omne quod dicitur consequenter, est

consequenter respectu alicuius, et non tanquam

 prius, sed tanquam posterius.

non enim dicitur quod unum sit consequenter 

duobus, neque nova luna secundae, sed e

converso.

deinde definit quandam speciem eius quod est

consequenter, quae dicitur habitum.

et dicit quod non omne quod est consequenter,

est habitum;

sed quando sic est consequenter, quod tangit; itaquod nihil sit medium, non solum eiusdem

generis, sed nec alterius.

4. An example showing that the strings of a musical instrument are successive.

To see that the strings of a musical instrument are successive, consider the

following example.

The Diatonic genus is illustrated by this tetrachord:

A mese

/ > tone = ‘major 2nd’

/ G lichanos3:4 > tone = ‘major 2nd’

\ F  parhypate

\ > semitone = ‘minor 2nd’

\ E hypate

101

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 102/138

The lichanos is ‘successive’ in comparison to the mese because nothing of the same

genus comes between them; likewise the parhypate in comparison to the lichanos, and thehypate in comparison to the parhypate. Hence, the strings of a lyre (or the notes they

 produce) are ‘successive’ insofar as they can admit nothing the same in genus between

them.

5. That in a musical harmony the parts composing it are dissimilar, have a

determinate position, and are not continuous.

Aristotle, Metaph. V. 27 (1024a 11-28).

(tr. W. D. Ross)

It is not any chance quantitative thing that can be said to be ‘mutilated’; it must be a whole as

well as divisible.

For not only is two not ‘mutilated’ if one of the

two ones is taken away

(for the part removed by mutilation is never 

equal to the remainder), but in general no

number is thus mutilated;

for it is also necessary that the essence remain;

if a cup is mutilated, it must still be a cup; but(1024a 15) the number is no longer the same.

Further, even if things consist of unlike parts,

not even these things can all be said to bemutilated,

for in a sense a number has unlike parts (e.g.

two and three) as well as like;

 but in general of the things to which their 

 position makes no difference, e.g. water or fire,

none can be mutilated;

to be mutilated, things must be such as in virtue

of their essence have a certain position.

Again, they must be continuous; for a musicalscale consists of unlike parts (1024a 20) and has

 position, but cannot become mutilated.

(tr. H. G. Apostle)

It is not any chance quantity that is called“mutilated” but only the one which is divisible

into parts and is a whole.

For two is not called “mutilated” when one of 

the units is taken away

(for the part removed by mutilation is never 

equal to what is left), and in general no number 

is called “mutilated”,

for the substance of the thing must remain after 

mutilation.

If a cup is mutilated, it must still be a cup; butthe number is no longer the same.

Further, even if a thing consists of unlike parts,

it is not always that it is said to be mutilated;

for, in a sense, even a number has unlike parts,

such as two and three.

And in general, things in which position makes

no difference, such as water and fire, are not

said to be mutilated;

 but in order to be mutilated, things must be such

that according to their substance position makes

a difference.

Besides, they must be continuous; for aharmony is composed of unlike parts which

have position, but it does not become mutilated.

102

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 103/138

Besides, not even the things that are wholes are

mutilated by the privation of any part.

For the parts removed must be neither those

which determine the essence nor any chance

 parts, irrespective of their position; e.g. a cup is

not mutilated if it is bored through, but only if the handle or a projecting part is (1024a 25)

removed,

and a man is mutilated not if the flesh or the

spleen is removed, but if an extremity is,

and that not every extremity but one which

when completely removed cannot grow again.

Therefore baldness is not a mutilation.

Further, even if the things are wholes, they do

not become mutilated by the privation of any

 part.

For the parts removed must neither be the main

 parts of the substance nor be in any chance

 place; for example, if a whole is made in a cup,

we do not have something mutilated, but we dohave a mutilated cup if the handle or some

 projecting part is removed.

And a man is mutilated not if the flesh or the

spleen is removed, but if an extremity is

removed,

not any extremity, but one which when

completely removed does not grow again.

Because of this, people with shaven heads are

not said to be mutilated.

St. Thomas Aquinas, In V Meta. lect. 21, n. 32 (tr. B.A.M.).

LB5LC21N.32

septimum est quod oportet esse continua coloba.

harmonia enim musicalis non potest dici coloba

voce vel chorda subtracta, licet sit dissimilium

 partium:

quia constituitur ex vocibus gravibus, et acutis;et licet partes eius habeant determinatam

 positionem:

non enim qualitercumque voces graves et acutae

ordinatae, talem constituunt harmoniam.

The seventh is that what is mutilated must be

continuous.

For a musical harmony cannot be called

‘mutilated’ when a ‘voice’ [that is—a ‘note’] or 

a string is taken away, even though it be of dissimilar parts:

the reason being that it is constituted from lowand high notes; and even though its parts have a

determinate position:72

for low and high notes ordered in any way

whatsoever do not constitute such a harmony.

6. The three attributes of a musical harmony.

According to the foregoing account, a musical harmony is

(1) made of dissimilar parts, such as the ‘high’ and ‘low’ in notes or strings,(2) having a determinate position, as a ‘high’ note is ‘above’ a ‘low’ one, and as one string

is before another, but is

72 I.e. they require a determinate order in their parts, just as does a house or a shoe. But should not the text

read: “must not only be continuous, but possessing a determinate order in its parts”?

103

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 104/138

(3) not continuous, notes or strings being divided off from one another 

7. Note.

The reason why a musical harmony cannot be (or be called) ‘mutilated’ or 

‘truncated’ is that what is colobon must continue to exist when a part is taken away—that

is, it must retain its species, as a man is still a man when a hand or foot is taken away, butnot when he is decapitated.73 Now a musical harmony is constituted from high and lownotes. For the harmony to exist, then, these notes must be put together in a certain way. But

when a chord or note is taken away, it no longer exists, and so cannot be continuous.74

8. On the mese as tonic or key-note.

[Aristotle], Probl ., XIX. 20 (643b 13-28) (tr. W. S. Hett; rev. B.A.M.).

Why is it that, if one shifts the mese after tuning the other strings, and then plays

the instrument, it is not only when the tune touches the sound of the mese that it is

unpleasant and seems out of tune, but also all the rest of the melody? If, on the other hand,one shifts the lichanos or any other note, then the difference is only apparent when one

employs this particular note. This is only natural, for all the best tunes make frequent use

of the [20] mese, and all good musicians employ it frequently, and quickly revert to it, if they leave it, but not to any other note to the same extent.

The same is true in speech; if certain connectives [ sundesmoi] are omitted, such aste and kai/ [oi(=on to\ te kai\ to\ kai/], the language ceases to be Greek; but the

omission of others gives no such offence, because there are some conjunctions which one

[25] must use often if there is to be sense, but with others it is not so. In the same way withsounds, the mese is a kind of conjunction, especially in good music, because its note most

often underlies the tune.

[Aristotle], Probl ., XIX.12 (tr. Andrew Barker).

Why does the lower of the notes always take the melody? 75 For if one omits

 paramese when one ought to have played it with mese, the melody is there none the less: but if one omits mese when both should have been played, it is not.76 Is it because what is

73

What is ‘necessary’ being “[t]hat without which, as a condition, a thing cannot live” ( Meta., V.5, 1015a 20)(tr. W. D. Ross).74 Note that a melos, something other than a harmony—can be continuous when there is frequent recourse tothe mese.75 See also 186  Probs. XIX.49. In the expression krousis hypo ten ouden, ‘playing under the song’, used for 

non-unison accompaniment at e.g. 183  Probs. XIX.39, 187 ps.-Plut. 1141 b, ‘under’ indicates subordination,

not lower pitch. (Barker’s note)76 The text here is corrupt and obscure: I have translated the emended version of Monro. But because of the

textual confusion, no conclusions about the details of performing practice can reliably be based on this

sentence. Paramese is a tone above mese. (Barker’s note)

104

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 105/138

low is large,77 and hence powerful? What is small is included in what is large: and in

division78 there are two netai in hypate.

77 The Greek word for ‘low’, here as usually, is bary, lit. ‘heavy’. Passages (particularly from  Probs.XI)

exploiting the theoretical consequences of this metaphor will be reviewed in Vol. 2. (Barker’s note)78 That is, when intervals are constructed by proportional division of a single string. See particularly Sect.

Can. 19-20, and cf. 175  Probs. XIX.23.  Nete is an octave above hypate: if a hypate string is divided by a

 bridge at the half-way point, each half sounds nete. (Barker’s note)

105

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 106/138

9. On the prelude in aulos-playing and its relation to the key-note.

Aristotle, Rhet., III. 14 (1414b 19-20).

(tr. J. C. Jebb)

The Proem is the beginning of the speech,— 

analogous to the Prologue in poetry and the

Prelude in flute-playing.

All these are beginnings, and pave the way, as itwere, for what follows.

The musical prelude is most like the Epideiktic

 proem.

Flute-players begin by playing anything that

they can execute brilliantly; and then knit this

on the key-note of their theme.79

The same kind of composition suits epideikticrhetoric.

The speaker should start by saying whatever his

fancy prompts—then strike his key-note, andknit his proem to his theme: and this is just what

they all do.

Take, for instance, the proem to the  Helen80  of Isokrates;— 

there is nothing common between the Eristics

and Helen.

And here, even if the speaker passes into a

foreign region, it is fitting, rather than that the

speech should be monotonous.

(tr. W. Rhys Roberts)

The Introduction is the beginning of a speech,

corresponding to the prologue in poetry and the

 prelude in flute-music;

they are all beginnings, paving the way, as itwere, for what is to follow.

The musical prelude resembles the introduction

to speeches of display;

as flute players play first some brilliant passage

they know well and then fit it on to the opening

notes of the piece itself,

so in speeches of display the writer should proceed in the same way;

he should begin with what best takes his fancy,

and then strike up his theme and lead into it;which is indeed what is always done.

(Take as an example the introduction to theHelen of Isocrates— 

there is nothing in common between the

‘eristics’ and Helen.)

And here, even if you travel far from your 

subject, it is fitting, rather than that there should

 be sameness in the entire speech.

10. On endosimos.

R. C. Jebb’s note regarding to\ e)ndosi/moj. (On Aristotle’s Rhetoric).

Footnote 4, p. 180: t%= e)ndosi/m%, ‘the actual opening, preliminary note, of thesubject, which gives the tone to the rest’ (Cope). to\ e)ndosi/mon  is defined by

Heschyius as to\ pro\ th=j %)dh=j kiqa/risma.81

79 t%= e)ndosi/m%, ‘the actual opening, preliminary note, of the subject, which gives the tone to the rest’

(Cope). to\ e)ndosi/mon is defined by Heschyius as to\ pro\ th=j %)dh=j kiqa/risma. (Jebb’s note)80 § 1-13. (Jebb’s note)81 = “that which gives the key to the tune”; cf. LSJ, which I give next.

106

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 107/138

Henry George Liddell. Robert Scott.  A Greek-English Lexicon. revised andaugmented throughout by. Sir Henry Stuart Jones. with the assistance of. Roderick 

McKenzie. Oxford. Clarendon Press. 1940.

e)ndo/simoj,  on,  serving as a prelude, a)=?sma Artem.2.66; yalmo\j e). th=?w)?dh=? , Suid.: but usu. neut. e)ndo/simon, to/ (to\ pro\ th=j w)?dh=jkiqa/risma , Hsch.); that which gives the key to the tune, in music, Aristot. Rh. 1414b24,

ti=Arist.  Mu.399a19, Hld.3.2, Ael. NA11.1, Poll.1.210: metaph., key-note of a speech,Aristot. Rh. 1415a7, ti=Aristot. Pol. 1339a13, cf. Max.Tyr.7.7, Jul. Ep. 186: generally,

 signal  for a race, Hld.4.3; [pro/bata ] pro\j ta\ e). th=j su/riggojpoimaino/mena IDEM=Hld.5.14: metaph., to\ tou= kairou= kai\ th=j w(/raje). IDEM=Hld.4.16; tou= filosofei=n e). e)/dwkan Phld. Acad.Ind. p.5M.; w(/spere). e(/cei pro/j ti Plu.2.73b; tou= logismou= to\ e). paresxhko/toj Porph. Sent.

32, cf. Luc. Symp.30 (also e). parasxe/sqai Dam. Pr.415); labei=n Luc.  Alex.19;

me/xrij a)\n to\ e). th=j dialu/sewj shmh/nh? M.Ant.11.20; e). toi=jstratiw/taij e)/rgw? didou/j Hdn.3.6.10 (so prob. as Adj., [siti/a ] e). th=? pe/yei giving the signal for digestion, Plu.2.131c).

The Suda Online.

Headword: Endosimon

Adler number: epsilon,1183Translated headword: signal, prelude

 

Translation:“The boatswains gave the signal to the oarsmen, but at the sign [the oarsmen] shouted all

together with their onslaught.”[1]

And in addition to this [the word] e)/ndosij [is used].[2]

[The word] e)ndo/simon [also means] a cause of motion and beginning.[3] The psalm [is]such as to be a prelude for the song.[4]

Greek Original: Endosimon: hoi de keleustai tois eretais to endosimon enedosan, hoi de epi têi endosei

athrooi tôi rhothiôi epêlalaxan. kai Endosis epi toutôi. Endosimon, kinêseôs kai archês

aition. ho de psalmos hoios endosimos einai têi ôidêi.

Notes:

[1] Arrian, Parthica fr.61; cf. kappa 1297 (1287 is a misprint in Adler’s apparatus).

[2] Translated ‘sign’ in the Arrian quotation (to which this comment perhaps refers).

[3] cf. Synesius, Epistle 4.162a.[4] cf. mu 1303.

Translated by: Catharine Roth on 3 April 2007@01:39:30.

Vetted by:  David Whitehead (tweaked tr; augmented notes and keywords) on 3 April

2007@03:09:57.

§

107

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 108/138

X. ON THE OVERTONE SERIES.

JT 2.2 - The Overtones Series.82

Many of the basic principles and harmonic developments of music originate fromthe acoustic makeup of a single tone. When a length of string (or column of air) is made to

vibrate, it produces the basic pitch of the string, called the Fundamental. Let us look at a

low C string (on a piano for example.)

The full wavelength produces a low C = the Fundamental Nr.1 Simultaneously this

same string also vibrates at a wavelength half of the fundamental wavelength.

Half the wavelength produces a low C, 1 octave higher = Overtone Nr.2

The string also vibrates at a third of the fundamental wavelength.

One third of the wavelength produces a G, a 5th higher = Overtone Nr.3

The same string also vibrates simultaneously at a quarter of the fundamental

wavelength.

One quarter of the wavelength produces a c, a 4th higher = Overtone Nr.4The same string also vibrates at wavelengths of :

a fifth of the Fundamental wavelength = Overtone Nr.5

a sixth of the Fundamental wavelength = Overtone Nr.6

a seventh of the Fundamental wavelength = Overtone Nr.7

an eighth of the Fundamental wavelength = Overtone Nr.8, and so on.

An infinite number of vibrations, dividing the fundamental string into an ever-

increasing number of equal wavelengths (are produced). Each of these vibrations produces

their own pitch. This composite of sounds accompanies the Fundamental tone and is calledthe Overtone Series.

JT 2.3 - Some Characteristics

Here are some useful characteristics of the Overtone Series you should know:

The intervals between successive Overtones gradually become smaller.

Chord voicings that simulate the structure of the overtone series, with larger 

intervals at the bottom and smaller intervals at the top, will have a clearer and moreresonant sound.

82 This excerpt comes from a Website, but unfortunately at the time I downloaded it I did not note its URL; it

having since disappeared from the Internet.

108

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 109/138

The Number of each Overtone expresses its wavelength as a fraction of the

fundamental wavelength:

Overtone Nr.3 = 1/3 of the Fundamental wavelength

Overtone Nr.5 = 1/5 of the Fundamental wavelengthOvertone Nr.16 = 1/16 of the Fundamental wavelength

Overtone Nr.89 = 1/89 of the Fundamental wavelength

Overtones are therefore also called partials.

The Fundamental tone is repeated each octave, and its Overtone Nr. increases each

time by a magnitude of 2.

For the overtones of C’ for example:

 Nr. 1 = C’ (the Fundamental)

 Nr. 2 = 2 x 1 = C

 Nr. 4 = 2 x 2 = c Nr. 8 = 2 x 4 = c’

 Nr.16 = 2 x 8 = c”

 Nr.32 = 2 x 16 = c”‘

 Nr.64 = 2 x 32 = c”“ etc.

The number of Overtones doubles within each successive octave.

JT 2.4 - What the Ear perceives

The human ear (or rather the human brain) consciously perceives in most casesonly the fundamental pitch of the tone. This is partly because all overtones have a nodal

 point (point of no vibration) at the nodal points of the fundamental and thus re-enforce the

fundamental tone. Another important reason why we only tend to distinguish the

fundamental tone is that three of the first four tones of the Overtone series represent thesame (fundamental) tone at successive octave levels.

The human brain recognises the composite of overtones as the characteristic soundand timbre of an instrument, for the vibration intensity of individual overtones varies

considerably for each type of instrument. This is largely how we recognise the difference

in sound between a piano, a flute, a guitar, a saxophone, and so on.

Life is Music.83

According to the familiar structure of the harmonic overtone series, the periodic

vibration of a medium produces a fundamental tone which contains within it an infinite

series of overtones. In addition, each overtone can itself be considered a fundamental tonewith an infinite overtone series of its own. The picture is one of an infinite matrix of 

harmonic vibration.

83(www.stokstad.com/cyberspacecafe/lifeismusic2.html [2/3/01])

109

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 110/138

The relationships between the overtones in the series described above are not

chaotic but are organized in a beautiful sequence of whole number ratios: 1:2, 2:3, 3:4.This is because the medium, for example, a piano string, is not only vibrating as a whole,

 but is also vibrating as if divided into halves, thirds, fourths, etc., on to infinity. If the

frequency of the fundamental tone (called “1” in the series) is vibrating at 100 cycles per second, then the frequency of the next overtone, “2”, would be 200cps, or twice that of the

fundamental; “3”= 300cps, “4”= 400cps, etc.

Frank Lamonica, Lesson Supplement: The Acoustics of Music.84

Harmonics and Overtones

When a string is set into motion, the frequency or “pitch” we usually hear is

referred to as the “fundamental” pitch. That pitch is also called the “first harmonic.” The

two points which attach the strings are the “nodes” of the fundamental vibration. What isnot obvious is that each string also vibrates simultaneously at many other frequencies, each

 progressively higher in pitch and lower in amplitude (volume). When the fundamental

 pitch is created by the vibration of a string of length x, additional frequencies, called“overtones” or “higher harmonics”, begin vibrating with effective lengths of x/2, x/3, x/4,

x/5, etc. Each of these additional frequencies vibrate between additional

imaginary nodes that are located exactly at the points on the string

which are integer divisibles of the string length.

The basic physical law which governs vibrating objects states that

the frequency of a vibrating string is inversely proportional to the

string length. What that means is if a string of length x vibrates at

frequency f, than that same string if cut to length x/2 will vibrate at

2f. Since strings vibrate simultaneously at all integer subdivisions of

the string length (effectively creating shorter and shorter string

lengths), the vibrating string will produce additional pitches, called

higher harmonics or overtones, at frequencies of 2f, 3f, 4f, 5f, and

higher. 

Pitch is paradoxical. Pitch is fundamental frequency.85

The pitch of a pure tone is simply its frequency. A harmonic tone consists of a sum

of pure tones (each one called a partial), whose frequencies are in integer ratios of 1, 2, 3, .

…, etc. Partials related in this way are called the harmonics of the tone. The frequency of the first harmonic is the fundamental frequency.

1. Definition.

THE OVERTONE SERIES. The set of vibrations produced by a body resonating as

a whole, in halves, in thirds, and so on ad infinitum, such that its resultant pitches arerelated to one another in the ratios of 2:1, of 3:2, of 4:3, etc., the frequency of the pitch

 being inversely proportional to the length of the vibrating body (e.g. given a string length

of 1, f = ½), with the lowest pitch, or ‘fundamental’, and the other pitches, called ‘over-tones’, ‘partials’, or ‘harmonics’, superimposed upon it giving the tone its timbre.

84 (www.classic-guitar.com/less5sup.html [2/3/01])85 (www.ihear.com/Pitch/paradoxical.html [2/3/01])

110

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 111/138

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 112/138

The seventh and fourteenth partials are the out-of-tune subtonic degrees

found in the third octave (7th partial) and fourth octave (14th partial) of agiven series. The upper partial is derived by doubling the lower. It may help

to think of the seventh partial as a simple interval to remember its scale

degree although it is actually a minor 21st from the fundamental.

The Fourth Octave Partials 

If the ninth through fourteenth partials are thought of as intervals and thenreduced to simple intervals, the scale degree numbers are produced. That is,

the ninth partial (9 - 7 = 2) is the supersonic; the tenth partial (10 - 7 = 3) is

the mediant; the eleventh partial (11 - 7 = 4) is the out-of-tune raised sub-dominant (the only time the subdominant occurs it is raised and out of 

tune); the twelfth partial (12 - 7 = 5) is the dominant; the thirteenth partial

(13 - 7 = 6) is the submediant (major); and the fourteenth partial (14 - 7 = 7)is the out-of-tune subtonic. The fifteenth partial is not carried through the

interval reduction process; it is considered the leading tone to the sixteenth

 partial (tonic). [end excerpt]

The overtone series is therefore seen to consist in something  principal and some-

thing subject to what is principal  —the ruler or ruling principle being the fundamental, or 

fundamental tone, and the subjects ruled by that principle the overtones or partials (or par-tial tones). In sum, the overtone series is an instance of a kind of  rule. On this matter, cf.

the following texts:

3. On what is principal and what is subject in a harmony of sounds: that in a

harmony of sounds, some one ‘voice’ (or ‘note’) predominates.

Aristotle, Pol., I. 5 (1254a 24-34) (ed. W. D. Ross; tr. B. Jowett).

kai\ ei)/dh polla\ kai\ a)rxo/ntwn

kai\ [25] a)rxome/nwn e)/stin kai\ a)ei\ belti/wnh( a)rxh\ h( tw=n beltio/nwn a)rxome/nwn,oi(=on a)nqrw/pou h)\ qhri/ou:

to\ ga\r a)potelou/menon u(po\ tw=nbeltio/nwn be/ltion e)/rgon: o(/pou de\ to\ me\na)/rxei to\ d’ a)/rxetai, e)/sti ti tou/twn e)/rgon:

And there are many kinds both of rulers and

subjects

(and that rule is the better which is exercised

over better subjects—for example, to rule over 

men is better than to rule over wild beasts;

for the work is better which is executed by

 better workmen, and where one man rules and

another is ruled, they may be said to have a

work);

o(/sa ga\r e)k pleio/nwn sune/sthke kai\gi/netai e(/n ti koino/n, ei)/te e)k sunexw=nei)/te e)k [30] dih?rhme/nwn, e)n a(/pasine)mfai/netai to\ a)/rxon kai\ to\ a)rxo/menon,

kai\ tou=to e)k th=j a(pa/shj fu/sewje)nupa/rxei toi=j e)myu/xoij:

for in all things which form a composite whole

and which are made up of parts, whether 

continuous or discrete, a distinction between the

ruling and the subject element comes to light.

Such a duality exists in living creatures, but not

in them only; it originates in the constitution of 

the universe;

112

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 113/138

kai\ ga\r e)n toi=j mh\ mete/xousi zwh=j e)/stitij a)rxh/, oi(=on a(rmoni/aj.

a)lla\ tau=ta me\n i)/swj e)cwterikwte/raj e)sti\ske/yewj:

even in things which have no life there is a

ruling principle, as in a musical mode.

But we are wandering from the subject.

St. Thomas Aquinas, In I Pol., lect. 3, nn. 5-8 (tr. B.A.M.).

LB1 LC-3N.-5

deinde cum dicit quaecumque enim ex pluribus

etc., ostendit propositum ex ratione.

et ponit rationem ad ostendendum quod aliqui

sunt naturaliter servi quibus expedit servire.

secundo ostendit qui sint tales, ibi, quicumque

quidem igitur etc..

circa primum ponit talem rationem.

quaecumque sunt ex pluribus constituta, in his

est aliquid principans et aliquid subiectum

naturaliter, et hoc expedit.

sed hominum multitudo est ex pluribus

constituta:

ergo naturale est et expediens quod unus

 principetur et alius subiiciatur.

huius autem rationis minor manifesta est ex

 praemissis: in quibus ostensum est quod homo

est naturaliter animal politicum, et ita naturaleest quod ex multis hominibus constituatur una

multitudo.

LB1 LC-3N.-6

unde, ea praetermissa, probat maiorem:

et sic in hac ratione tria facit.

Then when he says, Whatever things [are put 

together] from many things, etc. he shows what

he has proposed by argument.

And he gives an argument for showing that

some things are naturally servants for whom it

is expedient to serve.

Second, he shows who are such, at, Whoever 

therefore, etc.

With respect to the first, he gives the following

argument.

Whatever things are constituted from many

things, in these there is something ruling [or 

 principal] and something naturally subject, and

this is expedient.

But a multitude of men is constituted from

many things.

It is therefore natural and expedient that one be

made ruler, and the other made subject.

 Now the minor of this argument is clear from

the things premised, in which it has been shown

that man is naturally a political animal, and so itis natural that one multitude be constituted from

many men.

And so, having premised these things, he provesthe major,

and so in this argument he does three things.

113

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 114/138

 primo ponit maiorem.

secundo probat eam, ibi, et hoc ex omni natura

etc..

tertio infert conclusionem, ibi, eodem autem

modo etc..

dicit ergo primo, quod quaecumque sunt

constituta ex pluribus ita quod ex eis fiat unumcommune,

sive illa plura sint coniuncta, sicut membra

corporis coniunguntur ad constitutionem totius,sive sint divisa sicut ex multis militibus

constituitur unus exercitus,

in omnibus his invenitur esse principans et

subiectum:

et hoc est naturale et expediens, ut per singula

 patebit exempla.

First, he sets down the major.

Second, he proves it at And from this every

nature, etc.

Third, he draws the conclusion at  But in the

 same way, etc.

He says, therefore, first that whatever things are

constituted from many things such that onecommon thing result from them— 

whether the many be conjoined, as the limbs of 

the body are conjoined for the constitution of the whole, or whether they be divided, as from

many soldiers one army is constituted — 

in all these there is found a ruler (or ‘what is

 principal’) and a subject (or ‘what is subject’):

and this is natural and expedient, as will be clear 

 by taking individual cases.

LB1 LC-3N.-7

dicit ergo primo, quod veritas praemissae

 propositionis invenitur in rebus animatis:

non quasi sit eis proprium, sed ex eo quod est

commune toti naturae:

quia etiam in his quae non participant vita, est

aliquis principatus, puta harmoniae.

quod potest intelligi dupliciter.

uno modo de harmonia sonorum; quia semper in

vocibus quae consonant aliqua vox

 praedominatur, secundum quam tota harmonia

diiudicatur.

He says, therefore, first, that the truth of the

things premised in the proposition is found in

animate things:

not as if it were proper to them, but from the

fact that it is common to the whole of nature:

since even in what does not have a share in life

there is something made principal, as in the case

of harmony.

This can be understood in two ways.

In one way, of a harmony of sounds; the reason

 being that in ‘voices’ [or ‘notes’] which sound

concordantly, some one note predominates,

according to which the whole harmony is

 judged.

114

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 115/138

 potest etiam intelligi de harmonia elementorum

in corpore mixto, in quo semper unum

elementorum est praedominans.

sed huiusmodi pertransit, quia sunt extrinseca

ab hac consideratione.

It can also be understood of the harmony of 

elements in a mixed body, in which one of the

elements is always predominant.

But he passes over these sorts of things because

they are extrinsic to this consideration.

LB1 LC-3N.-8

deinde cum dicit animal autem primum etc.,ostendit propositum in partibus hominis,

et dicit quod prima compositio animalis est ex

anima et corpore.

quae quidem compositio dicitur prima, non

secundum ordinem generationis, sed secundum

 principalitatem, quia est ex partibus

 principalissimis:

harum autem partium una est naturaliter 

 principans, scilicet anima; alia vero subiecta,

scilicet corpus.

 posset autem aliquis dicere quod hoc non est

naturale, cum non inveniatur in omnibus;

et ideo ad hoc excludendum subdit quod adiudicandum quid sit naturale, oportet

considerare ea quae se habent secundum

naturam, non autem ea quae sunt corrupta, quia

huiusmodi deficiunt a natura.

et ideo ad iudicandum quae pars in homine

naturaliter principetur, oportet considerare

aliquem hominem qui sit bene dispositus et

secundum animam et secundum corpus in quo

est manifestum quod anima corpori dominatur.

Then when he says,  But an animal , etc. he

shows his intention in the parts of man,

and he says that the first composition is of the

soul and body,

which composition is called ‘first’ not

according to the order of generation, but

according to what is principal, because it

consists of the principal parts.

 Now of these parts one is naturally the ruling principle, as is the soul, but the others subject,

namely, the body.

 Now someone might say that this is not natural

 because it is not found in all things— 

and so in order to exclude this he adds that in

order to judge what is natural, one must

consider those things which have themselves

according to nature, not those which are

corrupted, since these fall short of nature.

And so in order to judge which part in man is

naturally subject to what is principal, one must

consider some man who is well disposed, both

with respect to the soul and with respect to the

 body, in which it is obvious that soul is

dominant with respect to the body.

4. In sum:

“[O]r in all things which form a composite whole and which are made up of parts,whether continuous or discrete, a distinction between the ruling and the subject element

comes to light. Such a duality exists in living creatures, but not in them only; it originates

in the constitution of the universe; even in things which have no life there is a ruling principle, as in a musical mode. But we are wandering from the subject.” (Aristotle Pol., I.

5, 1254a 29-34)

115

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 116/138

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 117/138

According to St. Thomas, a hierarchia, properly speaking, is a sacred ‘principate’

or ‘ruling body’; a principate being a multitude ordered in one way under one  princeps;that is, one multitude ordered in one way under the governance of one prince. But the name

is customarily used to name any ‘principate’, or what is analogous to such. Now as we

have seen, in every multitude there is something  principal and something  subject to what is principal , as in a political community there is a ruler or ruling principle and the subjects

ruled by that principle. But one must also note that, as St. Thomas goes on to explain in ar-

ticle 2 of the same question of the Summa, every multitude includes a diversity of orders,as in the state there is an order of magistracies, an order of soldiers, an order of farmers,etc. But all such orders can be reduced to three, inasmuch as every perfect multitude has a

 beginning, a middle, and an end.90 

In this respect, consider St. Augustine’s definition of ordo: Order is the disposition[or ‘arrangement’] of things equal and unequal in rank, assigning its proper place to each

one. (City of God , xix. 13.1) Hence the disparity, or difference in rank, found in the diverse

grades of such a multitude constitutes a hierarchy; such an ordination being one accordingto dignity.

Hence, inasmuch as it is a multitude ordered in one way under the governance of one ruling principle, the overtone series is a hierarchy and therefore a perfect multitude: As

such, it has a beginning, a middle, and an end: the beginning being the fundamental, which

is the ‘best’, and so holds the highest place; the middle being the lower partials, whose

relationship to the fundamental is perceptible, and so hold the middle place; and the end being the higher partials which are so distant from the fundamental that their relation to it

is not perceptible, and so hold the lowest place. Again, as we have noted above, there is a

diversity of orders found in the overtone series: tonic partials, dominant partials, as well asmediant (or major), subtonic, and fourth octave partials; such a diversity also being proper 

to a hierarchy.

§

90  sed quamvis multi sint unius civitatis ordines, omnes tamen ad tres possunt reduci, secundum quod 

quaelibet multitudo perfecta habet principium, medium et finem. “But although there are many orders

 belonging to one state, nevertheless they all can be reduced to three according as in any perfect multitude

there is a beginning, a middle, and an end”.

117

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 118/138

XI. ON TONALITY.

1. Tonality as consisting in a hierarchy.

Solomon’s Music Gallery. “What is Tonality?” (The Tonal Center).91

Tonality describes the relationships between the elements of melody and harmony

 —tones, intervals, chords, scales, and the chromatic gamut; but particularly those types of relationship that are characterised as hierarchical, such that one of the elements dominatesor attracts another. These relationships occur both within and between every type of 

element, making a complex weave between a tone and its melodic, harmonic, and

chromatic contexts. When this weave is coherent and stable we have a tonal system whichis coherent and stable.

The major and minor scale systems and the part that they play as members of the

chromatic gamut is one such system.In its most conventional sense, tonality refers to just the major and minor scale

types—scales whose elements are capable of maintaining a consistent set of functional

relationships. The most important functional relationship is that of the tonic note and the

tonic chord with the rest of the scale. The tonic is the element which tends to assert its

dominance and attraction over all others, and it functions as the ultimate point of attraction,

rest and resolution for the scale.

Solomon’s Music Gallery. “What is Tonality?” (The Tonal Center). Music Glossary.

tonality. a hierarchy (ranking) of pitch-class. Tonal is the adjective. If only one pitch-class

is stressed more than others in a piece of music, the music is said to be tonal. If all pitch-

class are treated as equally important, the music is said to be atonal , or  pantonal .tone. 1. a pitch and all of its overtones. 2. a whole-step, or whole-tone.

tonic. the predominant pitch-class. Tonic is not necessarily the first pitch-class of a scale;

i.e., a C major scale does not have to start or end on a tonic in a musical context, yet it is a

C major scale. The convention in writing scales out of context, however, is to begin andend on the tonic. A tonic is determined by its prominence in the music (by means of 

repetition, accents, and other means of emphasis). Thus, a tonic can only be determined in

a musical context, which is why a key signature cannot tell us what the key is. Syn., tonal center .

Encyclopedia.com

TONALITY. In music, a quality by which all tones of a composition are heard inrelation to a central tone called the keynote, or tonic. Some relationship to a tonic is

characteristic of all music except that in which it is deliberately avoided (see atonality and

twelve-tone music).

The term tonality is also used in contrast to modality (see mode).

91 (www.tonalcentre.org [2/3/01])

118

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 119/138

Sir James Jeans, Science and Music (Dover Books, 1968). From Chapter 5, p. 169.

A collection of notes played in succession does not of itself constitute a melody

which can awaken our musical imagination; to satisfy modern musical feeling, there must

 be a further element, which we describe as tonality. Our musical thought does not wish towander indifferently all over the scale; it remains associated always with one particular 

note, the tonic or key note, which we somehow think of as giving a fixed and central point.

Just as the traveller thinks of each point of his journey in terms of its distance from hishome, so we moderns think of each note of a melody in terms of its interval from the keynote.92 The skilful composer contrives to make us conscious of the key note from the very

 beginning of his music, and keeps our minds conscious of its position through all the notes

that are played. In general, for instance, we expect the music—or at least the bass of it—toend on the key note, just as the traveller expects his journey to end at his home; we refuse

to accept any other ending place as final. Even ancient Greek music had a sort of key note

 —the tone of the middle string of the lyre; Aristotle tells us that “All good melodies oftenemploy the tone of the middle string, and good composers often come upon it, and if they

leave it, recur to it again; but this is not the case with any other tone.”

Ernst Terhardt, Basse Fondamentale (Root-Relationship).93

Since hundreds of years, composers and theorists of music have been aware thateach individual sound of music, especially chords, bears a close relationship to a

fundamental note that characterizes and determines its harmony. In the 16th Century,

Generalbass notation occurred, i.e., a reduced notation system that takes advantage of thefact that the harmonic layout of a piece of tonal music can be prescribed by just denoting

the corresponding sequence of bass notes. Primarily, a bass note indicated a major triad of 

which that note was the “root”. Variants thereof, i.e., minor chords, sixths, diminishedchords, etc., were indicated by numbers added to the bass notes. Until present days, this

kind of simplified notation is widely in use, essentially in improvised music such as in

Jazz.

While in the Generalbass technique the performer’s task was to find appropriatechords to given bass notes, a crucial task of harmonic analysis of any given piece is to find

the fundamental notes of the prescribed sounds. Indeed, many relevant musical features of 

a given chord can be characterized by a single note, i.e., the chord’s root . There is a mutualrelationship between chords and fundamental notes, i.e., roots.

In many types of music the fundamental notes are not necessarily played on any

instrument. Rather, they are implied in both the “horizontal” (melodic) and “vertical”(harmonic) structure of the music. In this sense they are virtual . Countless sophisticated

examples of this phenomenon are included in J. S. Bach’s music.

92One should compare here Aristotle’s observation on the ‘free-running’ style of composition: “This style is

unsatisfying just because it goes on indefinitely—one always likes to sight a stopping-place in front of one: itis only at the goal that men in a race faint and collapse; while they see the end of the course before them, they

can keep on going” ( Rhet., III. 9 (1409a 31-34) (tr. W. Rhys Roberts). Much preferable is the ‘compact’ style

arising from the use of the  period , as he goes on to explain. Cf. the notion of  periodicity, which may be

defined as the property of being repeated at regular intervals. And cf. also our ‘Aristotetlian’ observation on

metre above: “Now a given metre is a species of rhythm differing from it by the regularity of the recurrence

of its characteristic foot, creating in the listener an expectation of its immediate return”.93 (www.mmk.ei.tum.de/persons/ter/top/basse.html [2/4/08])

119

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 120/138

Another, fairly simple example is the “Alberti” accompaniment of melodies that so

frequently was employed by W. A. Mozart, e.g., in his piano sonatas. Those “Alberti”notes are not to be regarded as bass notes (comparable to those of the baroque Generalbass

music) but as arpeggized chords that in turn represent virtual bass notes.

So it is more or less evident that, from the beginning of polyphony, tonal music has been based upon, and has taken advantage of, the mutual relationship that exists between

chords and fundamental notes—just as if that relationship were a basic auditory

 phenomenon such as the affinity of tones, in particular, octave equivalence.J.P. Rameau (1722, 1750) was the first who, in his Traite de l’Harmonie, explicitlytreated the fundamental notes as an auditory percept. He regarded the basse fondamentale

as an “implied” or “inferred” auditory feature of sound which nevertheless has

 psychological reality and is of crucial significance in tonal music.And this is exactly what the basse fondamentale actually is: An auditory percept,

though a virtual one. Any pitch corresponding to any fundamental note merely is a virtual

 pitch [22] , [30] , [34] , [35] , [53] , [56] , [59] , [63] , [72] , [76] , [104] p. 398, 404. So,the theory of virtual pitch can be employed as a universal tool to determine the roots of any

type of musical sound [53] (see topic harmony).

This implies that the root of musical chords is not merely a theoretical (thoughquite useful and smart) concept , but that it is an attribute of auditory sensation, i.e., virtual

 pitch. It may be true that in a typical musical context one is rarely, if ever, aware of 

 perceiving roots as definite pitches. This does not disprove, however, that those virtual

 pitches are perceived unconsciously, and that they may become conscious when attentionis properly guided. Apparently, Rameau was the first who became aware of those

“unconscious” pitches, and made them apparent in his concept of harmony.

In fact, even for ordinary listeners those pitches can be lifted into conscious perception. An efficient trick to accomplish this is designing a fairly rapid sequence of 

chords in random inversions, the roots of which define a melody. Provided that the chords

are designed such that this melody is not discernible from the tones of the chords, presentation of the sequence to listeners is a test of whether or not they can perceive the

virtual pitches of the roots. If they can recognize the melody “hidden” in the chord

sequence, one can conclude that they have perceived a corresponding sequence of virtual

 pitches [35], [104] p. 28 (cf. the CD attached to [104]). Through many years I have presented this demonstration to many audiences (The melody was the French tune “Sur le

 pont d’Avignon”); throughout, 80-90% of the listeners recognized the melody.

In 1976/77 we have carried out a formal test of auditory root recognition. Studentsof music (who already had taken some lessons on transcription of music) were asked to

transcribe the virtual pitches they heard in brief sequences of 5 sounds. These sounds were

either dyads or triads designed such that the pertinent root sequences were composed of thetones C, D, E, F, G. Both the composition of the dyads and triads, respectively, and the

order of the five root notes were randomized. In this test, three out of nine subjects

achieved 70%-83% correct recognition of root sequences. Another four subjects scored8%-20%, and two subjects scored just above the borderline of significance (Note that there

are 5! = 120 permutations of the above five root notes. So the chance for correct guessing

without recognizing anything was only 0.8 percent.) [34], [104] p. 400.

In summary, there can be hardly any doubt that Rameau’s basse fondamentale, i.e.,

the root of chords, has got its psychophysical explanation in the above findings.

Author: Ernst Terhardt [email protected] Feb 28, 2000

120

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 121/138

2. Tonality according to Molly Gustin:

Molly Gustin, Tonality (New York: Philosophical Library, 1969). Chapter One: The

 Perceived Sound , footnote, p. 10.

Whenever a musical tone is sounded, whether produced by a vibrating string or an

air column, what actually occurs is a whole set of vibrations which the ear synthesizes into

one sound. For the string vibrates simultaneously, or nearly, simultaneously, as a whole, inhalves, in thirds, etc. ad infinitum. Each of these vibrations produces a partial tone. If thefrequency produced by the string as a whole is 1, then the frequency produced by half the

string is 2, and by a third of the string is 3, and so on. This physical manifestation of the

natural numbers was discovered by the physicist Joseph Sauveur in the seventeenthcentury.

“I was made to observe that especially at night one may hear from long strings notonly the principal sound but also other small sounds…such that the number of vibrations is

a multiple of the number for the fundamental sounds…. I concluded that the string in

addition to the undulations it makes in its entire length so as to form the fundamentalsound may divide itself in two, in three, in four, etc. undulations….”

Joseph Sauveur, “System general des intervalles des sons, & son application à tous

les instrumens de musique,” Mém. acad. sci. Paris 1701.

Molly Gustin, Tonality. Chapter One: The Perceived Sound , footnote, p. 11.

The overtone series is relevant to music because musical tones, including those of 

the human voice, are produced by the impingement of a set of pulses in the air upon the

hearing organ of a person. A pulse is a periodic alternation between high and low air pres-sure. The wave lengths of a set of pulses or partial tones which constitute a single musical

tone are related to each other as are the positive integers, 1, 2, 3, … etc. Each musical tone

consists of a theoretically infinite quantity of these wave trains. Of course the set of pulses

which our instruments measure is always a finite set. How many partials are perceived de- pends upon the sensitivity of the instrument.

Molly Gustin, Tonality.

Music is tonal if the majority of its adjacent tones, whether simultaneous or consec-

utive, form single-rooted sets. Tonal music thus possesses one or more perceptible com-mon measures, or roots, among its tones. Some music is tonal and some music is not tonal.

Some music is more tonal than other music. (p. 78)

The measure of tonality is the following: The greater the quantity of simultaneous

common measures, or roots, to which the tones of a composition are related, the higher the

degree of tonality. (p. 78)

Music is tonal if, and only if, the majority of its adjacent tones, whether simul-

taneous or consecutive, form single-rooted sets. The greater the quantity of simultaneous

common measures to which the tones of a composition are related, the more tonal is thecomposition. p. 81)

121

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 122/138

The root of a set of tones (or that tone which appears to be most important) is the

tone of the set which is represented by the lowest power of 2, and is, therefore, either thefundamental of the set or an octave transposition of that fundamental. (p. 39)

By “set” I merely mean a group of tones whose frequencies are related to eachother as are the integers which represent them, quite apart from the temporal order of oc-

currence of the tones, whether simultaneous or successive. (p. 10)

The overtone series is relevant to music because musical tones, including those of the human voice, are produced by the impingement of a set of pulses in the air upon the

hearing organ of a person. (p. 11)

3. A composite definition of tonality derived from the foregoing:

Tonality may be defined as that quality music has when the majority of its adjacent

tones, whether simultaneous or consecutive, form single-rooted sets—that is, when it pos-

sesses one or more perceptible common measures, or roots, among its tones (the root of aset being that tone which is represented by the lowest power of 2, and is therefore either 

the fundamental of the set or an octave transposition of that fundamental); but a set is a

group of tones whose frequencies are related to each other as are the integers which re-

 present them, quite apart from the temporal order of occurrence of the tones, whether simultaneous or successive.

4. Notes on tonality.

• a compound or complex sound

• the interrelationship of pitches

• having a root

When the pitches are related to one another on certain numerical principles—thatis, when they embody, or at the least, approximate, the lower partials of the overtone

series, there is tonality. Again, there is tonality when the predominant pitch determines the

fundamental of an overtone series. Its genus is quality, coming under its first species,

habitus. Quality answers the question, of what sort is it? But in saying that a piece of musicis ‘tonal’ or ‘has tonality’, one is saying what sort it is. For this reason it is a disposition: in

a thing having parts, it is an order of parts according to form or species. It admits a vari-

ation of degree. Tonality is that quality which music has when the majority of its adjacenttones, whether simultaneous or consecutive, form single-rooted sets; that is, when it pos-

sesses one or more perceptible common measures, or roots, among its tones. The root of aset of tones being that tone which is represented by the lowest power of 2, and is, there-fore, either the fundamental of the set or an octave transposition of that fundamental.

§

122

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 123/138

XII. DEFINITIONS OF HARMONY.

§1. ACCORDING TO PHILOLAUS THE PYTHAGOREAN.

Philolaus, DK fr. 10 (tr. Andrew Barker).

 Harmonia comes to be in all respects out of opposites: for   Harmonia is a

unification of things mutually mixed, and an agreement of things that disagree.

Philolaus, DK fr. 6 (tr. Andrew Barker).

This is how it is with Nature and Harmony: the Being of things is eternal, and

 Nature itself requires divine and not human intelligence; moreover, it would be impossible

for any existing thing to be even recognised by us if there did not exist the basic Being of 

things from which the universe was composed, (namely) both the Limiting and the Non-Limited. But since these Elements exist as unlike and unrelated, it would clearly be

impossible for a universe to be created with them unless a harmony was added, in which

way this (harmony) did come into being.

 Now the things which were like and related needed no harmony; but the things which

were unlike and unrelated and unequally arranged are necessarily fastened together bysuch a harmony, through which they are destined to endure in the universe. (Philolaus,

DK fr. 6; tr. Kathleen A. Freeman)

The magnitude of harmonia is syllaba and di’oxeian.1 The di’oxeain is greater thanthe  syllaba in epogdoic ratio.2 From hypate to mese is a  syllaba, from mese to neate is a

di’oxeian, from neate to trite is a syllaba, and from trite to hypate is a di’oxeian.3

The interval between trite and mese is epogdoic, the  syllaba is epitiritic, the

di’oxeian hemiolic, and the dia pason is duple.4

Thus harmonia consists of five epigdoics and two dieses; di’oxeian is threeepogdoics and a diesis; and syllaba is two epogdoics and a diesis.5

Here harmonia acquires the sense ‘(attunement of) the octave’. Syllaba is the fourth and di’oxeian

the fifth. The terminology is explained in 10 Nicomachus  Ench. ch. 9, where this paragraph is

quoted. A somewhat different account is given by Aelianus ap. Porph. Comm. 96.21-3, 96.29-97.8;cf. also 12 Arist. Quint.  De Mus. 15.8-10. The use of harmonia to mean ‘octave’ is related to its

sense ‘system of attunement’ through the treatment of such systems as exemplifying species of the

octave: see, for example, 7 Aristox. El. Harm. 46.30-2, 12 Arist. Quint. De Mus. 15.9-20.It seems unlikely that Philolaus wrote this paragraph as the immediate successor of the one

 printed before it, though that is how Stobaeus quotes them. But their uses of the notion of 

harmonia must be related. In the musical case, notes and intervals are coordinated by taking their 

 place within the embracing framework of the octave, becoming articulations of its parts. Something

similar holds for the components of the universe and its all-inclusive harmonia. Then concordant

and melodic musical relations are not so in their own right, but only as entering into the octave

structure. Contrast the standpoint of the Pythagoreans discussed in 1.8 Porph. Comm. 107.15ff.

123

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 124/138

2 That is, the ratio 9:8, that of the tone. (The tone, whether conceived as a ratio or as an intervallic

distance, is standardly defined by Greek writers as the difference between the fourth and the fifth,

e.g., 7 Aristox. El. Harm. 21.22-3, 45.34-46.1; 8 Eucl. Sect. Can. proposition 13.)3 Here hypate is hypate meson, neate (a variant form of nete) is nete diezeugmenon. What Philolaus

calls trite corresponds to the position of the note which most writers call  paramese, trite

diezeugmenon being the name normally given to the note a semitone or  leimma above it (in the

diatonic genus).

  Standard Terminology

Nete (diezeugmenon)Paranete (diezeugmenon)

Trite (diezeugmenon)

Paramese

MeseLichanos (meson)

Parhypate (meson)

Hypate (meson)

  Philolaus

Neate

Trite

Mese

Hypate

The oddity of Philolaus’ terminology is important because trite means ‘third (note)’, and its use

here implies that only one note lay between it and neate. Then Philolaus’ octave system contained

at most seven notes. A persistent tradition held that early scale systems, whether they covered an

octave or not, had only seven notes (the lyra often had only seven strings, even in the fifth

century); an eighth was added later. See especially 4.27 ps.-Ar. Probs. XIX.47, cf. 7 and 32 (and

GMW vol. 1, p. 198, n. 62), 10 Nicomachus  Ench. chs. 5 and 9, ps.-Plut. De Mus. 1140f (and

GMW vol. 1, p. 233, n. 177), cf. 1137b-c. These sources do not tell a single, consistent story. Their 

confusions may be due in part to the existence of two different seven-note systems, one formed by

a conjunction of two tetrachords, spanning a seventh, the other a ‘gapped’ system, spanning an

octave, formed by two fourths disjoined by a tone, but lacking a note in the upper tetrachord. See

notes to the passages mentioned, and cf. Levin (1975), pp. 75-84, Burkert (1972), pp. 391-4, with

the additional references given there.4 These are the ratios standardly given for the tone and the concords, respectively 9:8, 4:3, 3:2, 2:1.

On the names of the ratios see 8 Eucl. Sec. Can. 149.14-24. Dia pason, literally, ‘through all (thestrings or notes)’, is the usual term for ‘octave’.5[Barker’s note omitted]

§2. ACCORDING TO PLATO.

Plato, Phaedo, 86b-c (adapted by B.A.M.).

(Understood of the soul) A mixture and a harmony of the hot and the cold, the wet

and the dry, and the like, when they are well and proportionately mixed. (In other words,

the soul understood as a harmony is a proportionate mixture of the hot and the cold, the

wet and the dry, and the like.)

Plato, Laws, 665a (adapted by B.A.M.).

The name for order in the voice (the simultaneous mixture of the high with the low)

is harmony.

124

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 125/138

Plat, Rep., III, 671b (adapted by B.A.M.).

That which is formed from all eight strings (sc. of the lyre).

Plato, Philebus, 17d (adapted by B.A.M.).

The systems which result from intervals of high and low ‘voices’ (= ‘notes’).

[Cf. also additional texts from Timaeus, Symposium, Laws, etc.]

§3. ACCORDING TO ARISTOTLE.

Aristotle, De Anima, I. 4 (407b 30-2).

For men say the soul is a certain harmony; for they say a harmony is a tempering

and composition of contraries, and the body is composed from contraries. For a harmony iseither a certain ratio of things which are mixed, or even a composition.

Adapted from Aristotle, Rhet., III. 1 (1403b 30).

Harmony pertains to the high, the low, and the intermediate in the use of the voice.

(syn. melos)

Aristotle, Pol., III. 3 (1276b 6-10).

And similarly, every other community and composition (we say is) different if thespecies of its composition is different, just as we will call a harmonia consisting of the

same notes different if at one time it is in the Dorian mode and at another in the Phrygian.

Aristotle, Pol., IV. 3 (1290a 14-29).

But (the forms of government) appear to be chiefly two, in the way in which it is

said of winds, some are ‘north’, some ‘south’, but the remaining ones of these aredeviations, in this way there are two governments, democracy and oligarchy. For they hold

aristocracy to be a form of oligarchy, as being a sort of oligarchy, and the one they call

‘government’, democracy, just as in winds (they hold) the west (to be a form of) the north,and the east (a form of) the south.

Likewise in the case of the harmoniai, as some men say, for here, too, some hold

that there are two forms, the Dorian and the Phrygian; but with respect to the other arrangements they call the ones ‘Dorian’, but the others ‘Phrygian’. In this way, then, men

are chiefly accustomed to think about governments.

But the way in which we divide them is truer and better, one or two being well

founded (i.e. aristocracy and ‘polity’), but the others deviations, the former, of well-tempered harmoniai, the latter, of the best governments; oligarchies being those which are

harsher and more despotic, but the democratic ones relaxed and moderate.

125

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 126/138

Aristotle, Pol., VIII, 7, 1342 b? (tr. B. Jowett).

All men agree that the Dorian music is the gravest and manliest. And whereas we

say that the extremes should be avoided and the mean followed, and whereas the Dorian is

a mean between the other modes, it is evident that our youth should be taught the Dorianmusic.

Aristotle, Pol., VIII, 7, 1342 a?-b? (tr. B. Jowett).

But since the spectators are of two kinds—the one free and educated, and the other 

a vulgar crowd composed of mechanics, laborers, and the like—there ought to be contestsand exhibitions instituted for the relaxation of the second class also. And the music will

correspond to their minds; for as their minds are perverted from the natural state, so there

are perverted modes and highly strung and unnaturally colored melodies. A man receives pleasure from what is natural to him, and therefore professional musicians may be allowed

to practice this lower sort of music before an audience of a lower type.

But, for the purposes of education, as I have already said, those modes andmelodies should be employed which are ethical, such as the Dorian, as we said before;

though we may include any others which are approved by philosophers who have had a

musical education. The Socrates of the  Republic is wrong in retaining only the Phrygian

mode along with the Dorian, and the more so because he rejects the flute; for the Phrygianis to the modes what the flute is to musical instruments—both of them are exciting and

emotional.

Poetry proves this, for Bacchic frenzy and all similar emotions are most suitablyexpressed by the flute, and are better set to the Phrygian than to any other mode. The

dithyramb, for example, is acknowledged to be Phrygian, a fact of which the connoisseurs

of music offer many proofs, saying, among other things, that Philoxenus, having attemptedto compose his Mysians as a dithyramb in the Dorian mode, found it impossible, and fell

 back by the very nature of things into the more appropriate Phrygian.

Aristotle, Pol., VIII, 5 (1340a 39—1340b 19) (tr. B Jowett).

On the other hand, even in mere melodies there is an imitation of character, for themusical modes differ essentially from one another, and those who hear them are differently

affected by each. Some of them make men sad and grave, like the so-called Mixolydian,

others enfeeble the mind, like the relaxed modes, another, again, produces a moderate andsettled temper, which appears to be the peculiar effect of the Dorian; the Phrygian inspires

enthusiasm. The whole subject has been well treated by philosophical writers on this

 branch of education, and they confirm their arguments by facts.The same principles apply to rhythms; some have a character of rest, others of 

motion, and of these latter again, some have a more vulgar, others a nobler movement.

Enough has been said to show that music has a power of forming the character, and

should therefore be introduced into the education of the young. The study is suited to thestage of youth, for young persons will not, if they can help, endure anything which is not

sweetened by pleasure, and music has a natural sweetness. There seems to be in us a sort of 

affinity to musical modes and rhythms, which makes some philosophers say that the soul isa tuning, others, that it possesses tuning.

126

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 127/138

Aristotle, Metaphysics, last chapter of last book.

There are seven vowels, the scale consists of seven strings, the Pleiades are seven,

at seven animals lose their teeth (at least some do, though some do not), and the champions

who fought against Thebes were seven.

Aristotle, On Philosophy Frag. 25, ed. Ross,  Eudemus, Frag. 47, ed. Rose, apud Ps.-

Plutarch, De Musica, 1139b—1140b (tr. Andrew Barker; rev. B.A.M.).

 Harmonia is celestial, having a nature godlike, noble, and inspired. Being by nature

fourfold in capacity, it has two means, arithmetic and harmonic, and its parts, magnitudes,

and excesses appear in accord with number and equal measure. For mele are rhythmized intwo tetrachords.94

‘He [Aristotle] said that its body is made up of dissimilar parts, which neverthelessare in concord with one another, and also that its means are concordant in correspondence

with numerical ratio.

Thus the highest note is attuned to the lowest in duple ratio, and yields the concord

of an octave. It has, as we said earlier, a highest note of 12 units and a lowest of 6, and its

 paramese, which forms a concord in hemiolic ratio with hypate, has 9 units: mese, we said,

contains 8 units.And it turns out that the most fundamental intervals of music are constituted out of 

these—the fourth, which corresponds to epitritic ratio, [d] the fifth, which corresponds to

hemiolic, and the octave, which corresponds to duple.The occurrence of the ratio 9:8 is also justified, since it is the ratio of the tone.

Further, the amounts by which the parts of the harmonia exceed and are exceeded

 by the means are the same, both arithmetically and in terms of geometrical operations, asthe amounts by which the means exceed and are exceeded by the parts.

Thus Aristotle ascribes the following properties to the means.

 Nete exceeds mese by a third part of itself, [e] and hypate is exceeded by mese in

the same way: hence these excesses are relational, since the terms exceed and are exceeded

 by the same parts.

(Thus the extremes exceed and are exceeded by mese and  paramese in the same

ratios, the epitritic and the hemiolic.) That, then, constitutes an excess of the harmonickind.

By contrast the excesses belonging to nete and to the arithmetical mean exhibit

differences that are equal.(The case of the excess of  paramese over hypate is the same, [f ] since  paramese

exceeds mese in the ratio 9:8, and again nete is double hypate,  paramese is in hemiolic

ratio with hypate, and mese is tuned in epitritic ratio with hypate.)

This, then, is the natural constitution of  harmonia in respect of both parts and numbers,

according to Aristotle too.

94 That is, tunes are arranged according to number in two tetrachords.

127

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 128/138

John Philoponus, Commentarius in De Anima, 141.33-142.6, 144.21—145.7, F 45 R 3

(tr. ed. J. Barnes, The Complete Works of Aristotle, vol. two, p. 2401).

Some…thought that the soul was an attunement of the body, and that the different

kinds of soul answered to the different attunements of the body. This opinion Aristotlestates and refutes. In the present work [i.e. the de Anima] he first merely records the

opinion itself, but a little later on he also sets out the arguments that led to it. He had

already opposed this opinion elsewhere—I mean, in the dialogue  Eudemus —and beforehim Plato in the Phaedo had used five arguments against the view….These are Plato’s five arguments. Aristotle himself, as I have said, has used the

following two arguments in the dialogue  Eudemus. One goes thus: ‘Attunement’, he says,

‘has a contrary, lack of attunement; but the soul has no contrary. Therefore the soul is notan attunement’…. Secondly: ‘The contrary of the attunement of the body is the lack of the

attunement of the body; and the lack of attunement of the living body is disease, weakness,

and ugliness—of these, disease is lack of attunement of the elements, weakness lack of attunement of the uniform parts, ugliness lack of attunement of the instrumental parts. Now

if lack of attunement is disease, weakness, and ugliness, then attunement is health, strength

and beauty; but the soul is none of these—I mean, neither health nor strength nor beauty;Thersites, the ugliest of men, had a soul. Therefore the soul is not an attunement.’

(Cf. Theophrastus in Fortenbaugh’s collection)

§4. ACCORDING TO THE ARISTOTELIAN TREATISE DE MUNDO AD ALEX .

( De Mundo ad Alex. 5, 396b 15-17).

The art of music simultaneously mixes ‘voices’ (= ‘notes’) high and low, and longand short, and perfects a single harmony in different sounds.

§5. ACCORDING TO ARISTOXENUS OF TARENTUM.

Aristoxenus, Elementa Harmonica, II (tr. H. S. Macran).

Of the melodic and the unmelodic our predecessors have given no account

whatever, while as to the distinctions between systemata, some people did not even attempt

to enumerate them, devoting their research only to the seven octachords which they calledharmoniai.

§6. ACCORDING TO NICOMACHUS OF GERASA.

Nicomachus of Gerasa, Enchiridion, ch. 9.

Even the most ancient writers show agreement with what we have explained. Their 

name for the octave is ‘harmonia’….

128

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 129/138

§7. ACCORDING TO MARCUS TULLIUS CICERO.

Marcus Tullius Cicero, Tusc. Disp., 1.18 (tr. B.A.M.).

But we can know a harmony from the intervals of the notes, the differentcomposition of which also produces many harmonies.

§8. ACCORDING TO ST. THOMAS AQUINAS.

The definition of consonance simpliciter .

Consonance is a ratio, that is, a proportion in numbers according to the high and

low. ( In II Post. An., lect. 1, n. 8)

Consonance is a ratio in high and low numbers. ( In II Post. An., lect. 1, n. 8)

Consonance is a numeral ratio of the high and low. (adapted from  In II Post. An.,lect. 1, n. 8)

The definition of harmony.

Harmony properly so called is a consonance in sounds. ( In I De Anima, lect. 9, n. 4)

Harmony is the consonance of sounds that results from strings (or flutes or the like)

when they are well ordered. (adapted from In I De Anima, lect. 9, n. 7)

A harmony results from a proportion of contrary sounds, namely, of the low and

high. (adapted from In I Meta., lect. 7, n. 12)

A determinate proportion according to certain numbers of the high and low is thecause of a harmony in sounds. ( In II De Caelo, lect. 14, n. 3)

Musical harmony is constituted from low and high ‘voices’ (= ‘notes’). ( In V Meta.,lect. 2, n. 32)

For a harmony in sounds is caused by a due proportion of numbers. ( In Dionysii De Div. Nom., c. 4, lect. 5)

Harmony is a complexion and proportion and temperament in composed and mixedthings (= harmony commonly speaking). ( In I De Anima, lect. 9, n. 3)

The proportion that exists between the contraries in composed and mixed things is

called a harmony and the form of the composite. ( In I De Anima, lect. 9, n. 3)

Every due proportion in things composed of different parts, as well as in things

mixed from contraries (is given the name ‘harmony’). ( In I De Anima, lect. 9, n. 4)

129

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 130/138

In bodies mixed from contraries, the ratio of these, i.e. the proportion, is called a

harmony. ( In I De Anima, lect. 9, n. 7)

For harmony is nothing other than the consonance which consists in being of one

mind (= an analogous use of harmony). ( In Dionysii De Div. Nom., c. 11, lect. 2)

The two ways in which ‘harmony’ is said (or the two things which one can call‘harmony’).

‘Harmony’ is said in two ways: in one way, of a composition itself; in another way,

of the ratio of the composition. (Summa Contra Gentes II, c. 64, n. 4)

One can call two things ‘harmony’: either the composition or mixture itself, or the

 proportion of that composition or mixture. ( In I De Anima, lect. 9, n. 4)

XIII. ON THE PRINCIPAL MEANINGS OF HARMONIA.

1. According to its first imposition.

Means of joining, fastening; joint; in Anatomy, suture, union of two bones by mereapposition, pl. adjustments; framework, esp. of the human frame. (Liddell Scott Jones,

Greek-English Lexicon)

L. harmonia, a. Gr. a(rmoni/a joining, joint, agreement, concord of sounds, music, f.

stem a(rmo- of a(rmo/j joint, a(rmo/zein to fit together, arrange. (Oxford English

 Dictionary)

Outside musical contexts, (harmonia) means ‘fitting together’, ‘adapting’ or ‘adjusting’

one thing to another. (Andrew Barker, Greek Musical Writings v. I, Chapter 10, AppendixA: the harmoniai)

harmonia (a(rmoni/a; m. pr. armonía; from the verb a(rmo/zein or a(rmo/ttein,

harmozein or harmottein = to fit or bind or fasten together, to join, to adapt); joining or fitting together, adjustment; also joint and means of joining (LSJ). (Solon Michaelides,

The Music of Ancient Greece: An Encyclopaedia, s.v. harmonia)

The word harmonia meant primarily the joining or fitting of things together, even the

material peg with which they were joined (Homer, Od . V, 248). (W. K. C. Guthrie,  A

 History of Greek Philosophy, I. The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans, Ch. IV: Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans)

a(rmoni/a properly signifies an adjustment or fitting together of parts. (H. S. Macran,

The Harmonics of Aristoxenus, Notes)

 Harmonia is a blending either of opposites or of parts, in such a fashion that they fit well

with each other. (Barnes, 488-495)

130

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 131/138

 Harmonia comes to be in all respects out of opposites: for  Harmonia is a unification of 

things mutually mixed, and an agreement of things that disagree. (Philolaus, DK fr. 10; tr.Andrew Barker, Greek Musical Writings v. I)

 Now the things which were like and related needed no harmony; but the things which wereunlike and unrelated and unequally arranged are necessarily fastened together by such a

harmony, through which they are destined to endure in the universe. (Philolaus, DK fr. 6;

tr. Kathleen A. Freeman)

The word “harmonia” derives from the Greek  a(rmo/zw, which means to fit or bind

together, and harmonia comes to indicate the state of unlike things brought together into an

orderly arrangement. (Denise Davidson Greaves, Sextus Empiricus, Against the Musicians,

from footnote 33)

‘Harmony’ is an adjustment or ‘fitting together’ of dissimilar things, as of different parts in

a composition (like the flesh and bones of the body) or of contraries in a mixture (like thehot and the cold of health). (B.A.M.)

2. By further impositions.

The word harmonia then meant especially the stringing of an instrument with strings of different tautness (perhaps thought of as a method of  joining the arms of the lyre, see Kirk,

 HCF , 208), and so a musical scale. (W. K. C. Guthrie,  A History of Greek Philosophy, I.

The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans, Ch. IV: Pythagoras and the Pythagor-

eans)

In Music, stringing, method of stringing. (Liddell Scott Jones, Greek-English Lexicon)

That which is formed from all eight strings (sc. of the lyre). (adapted from Plato,  Republic,

III, 671b)

The word harmonia has many uses, but here its primary significance is ‘attunement’,

specifically ‘pattern of attunement over the span of an octave’. Its principal application is

to the organisation of intervals between notes sounded by the strings of a lyra or a kithara.

(Andrew Barker, Greek Musical Writings v. II, Introduction: The harmoniai)

The primary use of  harmonia is probably the adjustment or tuning of the notes of an

instrument. What is created by tuning is a ‘fitting together’ of notes, a structure of relationsthat can be used to form the basis of melodies. (Andrew Barker, Greek Musical Writings v.

I, Chapter 10 Appendix A: the harmoniai)

In Plato, harmonia conceived generally is the melodic counterpart to rhythm: it is the

scheme of order that distinguishes the notes used in a piece of music from a mere

collection of pitches. (Andrew Barker, Greek Musical Writings v. I, Chapter 10 AppendixA: the harmoniai)

§

131

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 132/138

XIV. ON COMPOSITION (THE GENUS OF HARMONY).

St. Thomas Aquinas, In V Meta., lect. 3, n. 3 (tr. B.A.M.).

 Now among those things from which a thing is made into a whole, [I] somethinghas itself in the manner of a subject, just as parts, and the other things mentioned before;

 but [II] other things have themselves as the ‘what it was to be’, namely, a ‘whole’, a

‘composition’, and a ‘species’, which pertain to the notion of  form, according to which thewhatness of a thing is completed.

1. For it must be understood that sometimes one thing is of one matter simply, like

the silver of a drinking vessel; and then the form corresponding to such a matter can becalled a ‘species’. 2. But sometimes many things put together with each other are the

matter of some thing, which happens in three ways.

(a) For sometimes they are put together according to an order alone, like men in anarmy, or households in a city; and thus to the form corresponds a ‘whole’, by which name

an army or a city is designated.

(b) But sometimes they are put together not only by order, but by contact and by binding together, as appears in the parts of a house; and then to the form there corresponds

a ‘composition’.

(c) But sometimes over and above this the alteration of components is added, which

happens in a mixture; and then the form is the mixture itself, which is still a certain  speciesof composition.

 Now the quid est  of a thing is taken from any of these three, namely, fromcomposition, and species, and whole, as is clear if one were to define an army, a house, and

a drinking vessel. Thus, then, we have two modes of cause.95

St. Thomas Aquinas, In I Polit., lect. 3, n. 6 (tr. B.A.M.).

Therefore, he says first that whatever things are constituted from many things suchthat one common thing result from them—whether the many be conjoined, as the limbs of 

the body are conjoined for the constitution of the whole, or whether they be divided, as

from many soldiers one army is constituted—in all these there is found a ruler [or ‘what is principal’] and a subject [or ‘what is subject’]: and this is natural and advantageous, as will

 be clear by taking individual cases.96

95  inter ea autem ex quibus res integratur, aliquid se habet per modum subiecti, sicut partes et alia quae

 praedicta sunt; alia vero se habent ut quod quid erat esse, scilicet totum, et compositio, et species, quae

 pertinent ad rationem formae, secundum quam quidditas rei completur. sciendum est enim, quod quandoque

una res simpliciter est alicuius materia, sicut argentum phialae; et tunc forma correspondens tali materiae

 potest dici species. quandoque autem plures adinvicem adunatae sunt materia alicuius rei. quod quidemcontingit tripliciter. quandoque enim adunantur secundum ordinem tantum, sicut homines in exercitu, vel 

domus in civitate; et sic pro forma respondet totum, quod designatur nomine exercitus vel civitatis.

quandoque autem non solum adunantur ordine, sed contactu et colligatione, sicut apparet in partibus

domus; et tunc respondet pro forma compositio. quandoque autem super hoc additur alteratio

componentium, quod contingit in mixtione; et tunc forma est ipsa mixtio, quae tamen est quaedam

compositionis species. ex quolibet autem trium horum sumitur quod quid est rei, scilicet ex compositione et 

 specie et toto: sicut patet si definiretur exercitus, domus et phiala. sic ergo habemus duos modos causae.96

 dicit ergo primo, quod quaecumque sunt constituta ex pluribus ita quod ex eis fiat unum commune, sive

illa plura sint coniuncta, sicut membra corporis coniunguntur ad constitutionem totius, sive sint divisa sicut 

132

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 133/138

St. Thomas Aquinas, In V Meta., lect. 8, n. 5 (tr. B.A.M.).

Then when he says,  But further , he adds another mode to the ones mentioned,

which is not taken by reason of indivision, as in the case mentioned, but rather by reason of 

division.And he says that sometimes some things are called ‘one’ solely by reason of con-

tinuity, but sometimes not, except something be a whole and perfect; which, in fact, hap-

 pens when it has some one species, not indeed as a homogeneous subject is called ‘onespecies’, which pertains to the second mode set forth earlier, but according as the speciesconsists in a certain totality requiring a determinate order of parts; just as it is clear that we

do call something ‘one’, like a work produced by art, when we observe the parts of a shoe

composed in any way whatsoever, except perhaps according as ‘one’ is taken for the con-tinuous; but we do say all the parts of a shoe are one when they are so composed that there

is a shoe and it have some one species, namely, of a shoe.97

St. Thomas Aquinas, In I Ethic., lect. 1, n. 5 (tr. B.A.M.).

But it should be understood that this whole which is the civil multitude or thedomestic family, has only a unity of order, according to which it is not something one sim-

 ply. And so a part of this whole may have an activity which is not the activity of the whole,as a soldier in an army has an activity which is not that of the whole army. Nevertheless,

the whole itself has a certain activity which is not proper to any of its parts, but to the

whole, e.g. a battle of the whole army. And the pulling of a ship is the activity of the wholemultitude pulling the ship.

There is also a whole which has a unity, not only by order, but by composition, or 

connection, or even by continuity, according to which unity something is one simply; and

therefore, in this case, there is no activity of the part which is not that of the whole. For incontinuous things the motion of the whole and of the part is the same, and likewise in com-

 posed or connected things, the activity of the part is principally that of the whole.And so it is necessary that, in such a case, the consideration, both as to the wholeand to its parts, pertain to the same science. But it does not pertain to the same science to

consider the whole which has only a unity of order, and its parts as well. 98

ex multis militibus constituitur unus exercitus, in omnibus his invenitur esse principans et subiectum: et hoc

est naturale et expediens, ut per singula patebit exempla.97 deinde cum dicit amplius autem addit alium modum a supradictis, qui non sumitur ex ratione indivisionis

 sicut praedicti, sed magis ex ratione divisionis; et dicit, quod quandoque aliqua dicuntur unum propter 

 solam continuitatem, quandoque vero non, nisi sit aliquod totum et perfectum; quod quidem contingit 

quando habet aliquam unam speciem, non quidem sicut subiectum homogeneum dicitur unum specie quod 

 pertinet ad secundum modum positum prius, sed secundum quod species in quadam totalitate consistit 

requirens determinatum ordinem partium; sicut patet quod non dicimus unum aliquid, ut artificiatum,

quando videmus partes calceamenti qualitercumque compositas, nisi forte secundum quod accipitur unum pro continuo; sed tunc dicimus esse unum omnes partes calceamenti, quando sic sunt compositae, quod sit 

calceamentum et habeat aliquam unam speciem, scilicet calceamenti.98  sciendum est autem, quod hoc totum, quod est civilis multitudo, vel domestica familia habet solam ordinis

unitatem, secundum quam non est aliquid simpliciter unum; et ideo pars huius totius potest habere

operationem, quae non est operatio totius, sicut miles in exercitu habet operationem quae non est totius

exercitus. habet nihilominus et ipsum totum aliquam operationem, quae non est propria alicuius partium, sed 

totius, puta conflictus totius exercitus. et tractus navis est operatio multitudinis trahentium navem. est autem

aliud totum quod habet unitatem non solum ordine, sed compositione, aut colligatione, vel etiam

continuitate, secundum quam unitatem est aliquid unum simpliciter; et ideo nulla est operatio partis, quae

133

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 134/138

1. Definitions.

COMPOSITION (SUNTHESIS, COMPOSITIO). (1) A species of whole the parts

or matter of which is put together from many things by order, by contact, and by binding

together or connection99 (cf. St. Thomas Aquinas,  In V Meta., lect. 3, n. 3, but worded byB.A.M.); or otherwise, (2) that which is constituted from many things such that one com-

mon thing results from them, where the many are conjoined, as are the limbs of the body,

for the constitution of the whole

100

(cf. St. Thomas Aquinas,  In I Politic., lect. 3, n. 6, tr.B.A.M.).

2. The first text in sum:

I. the subject, as parts

II. the ‘what it was to be’, a whole, a composition, and a species

1. what has one matter simply, like the silver of a drinking vessel

2. many things put together with each other as the matter of one thing

(a) by order alone, like an army or a city(b) by order, by contact, and by binding together 

(c) in addition, by the alteration of its components, as in a mixture

 Note that II.2(b) = ‘by continuity’.

3. The second text in sum:

I. something is called ‘one’ solely by reason of continuity

II. sometimes not, except something which is whole and perfect, which happenswhen it has

1. some one species, according as the species consists in a certain totality requiring a

determinate order of parts, as opposed to what has2. some one species as an homogeneous subject (= II.1 the first schema given above)

non sit totius. in continuis enim idem est motus totius et partis; et similiter in compositis, vel colligatis,

operatio partis principaliter est totius; et ideo oportet, quod ad eamdem scientiam pertineat consideratio

talis totius et partis eius. non autem ad eamdem scientiam pertinet considerare totum quod habet solam

ordinis unitatem, et partes ipsius..99

  quandoque autem non solum adunantur ordine, sed contactu et colligatione, sicut apparet in partibus

domus; et tunc respondet pro forma compositio. “But sometimes they are put together not only by order, but

 by contact and by binding together, as appears in the parts of a house; and then to the form corresponds a

‘composition’.”100 dicit ergo primo, quod quaecumque sunt constituta ex pluribus ita quod ex eis fiat unum commune, sive

illa plura sint coniuncta, sicut membra corporis coniunguntur ad constitutionem totius, sive sint divisa sicut ex multis militibus constituitur unus exercitus, in omnibus his invenitur esse principans et subiectum: et hoc

est naturale et expediens, ut per singula patebit exempla. “Therefore, he says first that whatever things are

constituted from many things such that one common thing result from them—whether the many be

conjoined, as the limbs of the body are conjoined for the constitution of the whole, or whether they be

divided, as from many soldiers one army is constituted—in all these there is found a ruler (or ‘what is

 principal’) and a subject (or ‘what is subject’): and this is natural and expedient, as will be clear by taking

individual cases.”

134

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 135/138

4. The ways in which a thing is ‘one’:

When a thing is one:

I. what has one matter simply, like the silver of a drinking vesselII. many things put together with each other as the matter of one thing

(1) by order alone, like an army or a city

(2) by order, by contact, and by binding together (3) in addition, by the alteration of its components, as in a mixture

(a) a thing the parts of which are divided: e.g. an army (a discrete quantity)

(b) a thing the parts of which are conjoined (both being a ‘composition’):e.g. the body (a continuous quantity)

e.g. the lukewarm (a mixture of hot and cold)

A composition may require a determinate order of parts or not.

(a) a composition not requiring a determinate order of parts: a cup of silver (the conjoined)(b) a composition requiring a determinate order of parts: a shoe (the divided)

A composition may have size or not.

(a) a composition having size: e.g. a house, the human body, a lyre

(b) a composition not having size: e.g. a universal whole, like a genus, which is composed

of its several species, as the genus ‘animal’ of ‘man’ and ‘ox’

A thing may have size or both size and motion.

(a) a thing having size: e.g. the body as put together from parts

(b) a thing having both size and motion: e.g. the strings of a lyre, or more than one aulos

The parts of a composition are put together by order, by contact, and by bindingtogether or connection.

5. Melos (melody or song): some definitions.

Melody is the order of high and low sounds in the movement of the voice.

(Aristotle, Problems XIX.27, 919b 33)

Melody is an intertwining of notes which are unlike in being high or low. (Aristides

Quintilianus, De Musica)

Melody produced with rhythm and words is called complete, or perfect, melos

(‘song’). (Aristides Quintilianus, De Musica)

 Melos or song consists of three things: speech ( logos), harmonies (harmoniai, =

tunings or attunements), and rhythm (ruthmos). (Plato, Rep. III, 398d)

135

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 136/138

6. Compositon in harmony and melos.

A harmony is not a form, but the disposition of the matter for a form. 101 But a

disposition is an order of parts in a thing having parts, which happens in three ways, the

third of which is kata eidos, according to form or species. A harmony is an order of partsin this third way, the ‘form’ or ‘species’ being a composition.

In a melos, its parts are bound together by frequent recourse to the mese, which actslike the  sundesmoi or ‘connectives’ of speech, whose function is to make its many partsone. (Cf. the overtone series in relation to a ‘root’.)

In lexis, a  sundesmos or ‘connective’ is defined communiter as a non-significativevocal sound which is naturally apt to produce one significative vocal sound out of more

than one such sound, such as ‘and’, and which is naturally apt to be placed at the extremes

as well as in the middle (of speech), unless it should not be placed at the beginning of speech by itself, such as –te when it is to be followed by kai. (cf. Poet . 20, rev. B.A.M.; but

see my separate discussion for a more complete restoration of this definition)

In melos, a  sundesmos may be defined as a note which is naturally apt to produce

one order of high and low sounds out of more than one order of high and low sounds, and

which is naturally apt to be placed at the extremes as well as in the middle, sc. of the

melos. As we have said, the note which performs this function is the mese, which is itself ‘principal’, and therefore ‘low’ and ‘predominant’.

7. Some further definitions.

Order is in the before and after of things.

Position as situs is an order of parts according to place.

Position as dispositio is an order of parts according to form or figure (or according to thespecies and figure of the whole).

Composition is the placing of parts next to one another; or that which consists in the putting together from many things of a certain matter by order, by contact, and by binding

together or connection; or otherwise, the constituting of one common thing from many

things, where the many are conjoined, as are the limbs of the body, for the constitution of the whole.

8. Supplement: On the ways in which things come to be simply.

Aristotle, Phys., I. 7 (190b 4-9) (tr. R. Glen Coughlin).

101 Cf. St. Thomas Aquinas,  In I De Anima, lect. 9, n. 13 (tr. B.A.M.) : non tamen quod harmonia sit forma,

 sed dispositio materiae ad formam. Of course, St. Thomas means to say that a harmony is not a  substantial 

form; that it is a forma accidentalis is evident from the fact that it is a dispositio, which comes under the first

species of quality, habitus, and hence is an accident.

136

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 137/138

73. Things which come to be simply, however, come to be either by change [5] of shape,

like statues, or by addition, like things which grow, or by subtraction, like the Hermes fromthe stone, or by composition, like a house, or by alteration, as things which turn in regard

to their matter. But it is apparent that all things which to be thus come to be from some-

thing underlying.

•  by change of shape (= with respect to quality)

• by addition (= with respect to quantity)

•  by subtraction (= with respect to quantity)

•  by composition (= with respect to place)

•  by alteration (= with respect to substance)

St. Thomas Aquinas, In III Sent., dist. 13, q. 2, art. 2b, c. (tr. B.A.M.).

DS13 QU2 AR2B CO

ad secundam quaestionem dicendum, quod in

corpore naturali invenitur quadruplex uniomembrorum ad invicem.

 prima est secundum conformitatem naturae,

quia omnia membra constant ex eisdem simili- bus partibus, et sunt unius rationis, sicut manus

et pes ex carne et osse;

et sic dicuntur membra unum genere vel specie.

secunda est per colligationem eorum ad invicem

 per nervos et juncturas, et sic dicuntur unumcontinuatione.

tertia est, secundum quod diffunditur vitalis

spiritus et vires animae per totum corpus.

quarta est, secundum quod omnia membra

 perficiuntur per animam, quae est una numero

in omnibus membris.

To the second question it must be said that in a

natural body a fourfold union of the memberswith each other is found.

The first is according to a conformity of nature,

since all the members consist of the same simi-lar parts, and are of one account, as the hand

and foot from flesh and bone;

and in this way the members are called one in

genus or species.

The second is by their being bound to each other 

 by sinews and joints, and in this way they arecalled one by continuation.

The third is according as the vital spirit and

 powers of the soul are diffused throughout the

entire body.

The fourth is according as all the members are

 perfected by the soul, which is one in number in

all the members.

9. In sum:

•  by conformity of nature

•  by being bound to each other by sinews and joints

•  by having the vital spirit and the powers of the soul poured out through the body

•  by all the members being perfected by the soul, which is one in number in all the

members

§

137

7/28/2019 On Sound and Voice.

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/on-sound-and-voice 138/138

Supplement

Cf. R. H. Robins, “Grammar, Meaning, and the Study of Language” (First Published in:

Canadian Journal of Linguistics 9 [1964] 98-114) (In: Diversions of Bloomsbury: Selected 

Writings on Linguistics. Amsterdam, 1970, pp. 104-105):

Discourse consists of meaningful stretches of speech produced and understood in terms of recurrent arrangements of recurrent elements. These [elements] are referred to as morphemes

(or other grammatical units) at the morphological level, and as phonemes (or other phono-

logical units) at the phonological level. Native speakers can produce and understand sen-

tences that are new to [104-105] them as easily as sentences that they have heard or uttered be-

fore (this is a central fact about language), because they know (performatively) how to use

the components of their language, and, again in Firth’s terms, the meaning of any language

element is how it is used.

The linguist tries to state just how language elements are used, and as far as he can he tries

to state a semantic function (“meaning” as ordinarily understood) for the recurrent bits and

 pieces of sentences. As these meanings are particular, and as particular facts are treated in

the lexicon of a language, particular meanings are stated in the lexicon as far as is possible;

 but this does not imply that lexical and semantic statement are the same thing. A specific

meaning can generally be assigned to most words because words are, by the most useful de-

finition, free forms, potential sentences in their own right, that is to say unitary seman-tically

functioning stretches of speech.

§

(c) 2013 Bart A. Mazzetti. All rights reserved