33
October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold symposium on advances in semi-classical methods in mathematics and physics 1 / 26

October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    1

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

October 20, 2016

A Deterministic Interpretation

of Quantum Mechanics

Gerard ’t HooftUniversity Utrecht

H.J. Groenewold symposium on advances in semi-classical methods

in mathematics and physics

1 / 26

Page 2: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

A theory attempting to explain the quantum mechanical nature ofthe laws of physics at small scales, starting from non-quantummechanical dynamics

typically:

a set of cogwheels

Cogwheels will be time-reversal-invariant. At a later stage of thistheory, information loss is introduced, leading to a new, andnatural arrow of time.

But we begin with time-reversible situations . . .

2 / 26

Page 3: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

A fundamental ingredient of a generic theory: a finite, periodicsystem: the Cogwheel Model:

3

21

2

1

0

E

U(δt) =

0 0 11 0 00 1 0

= e−iH δt U3(δt) = I

δt = 1 , U →

1

e−2πi/3

e−4πi/3

; H → 2π

013

23

In the original basis:

H = 2π3

1 κ κ∗

κ∗ 1 κκ κ∗ 1

; κ = −12+ i√3

6; κ∗ = −1

2− i√3

6

3 / 26

Page 4: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

A fundamental ingredient of a generic theory: a finite, periodicsystem: the Cogwheel Model:

3

21 2

1

0

E

U(δt) =

0 0 11 0 00 1 0

= e−iH δt U3(δt) = I

δt = 1 , U →

1

e−2πi/3

e−4πi/3

; H → 2π

013

23

In the original basis:

H = 2π3

1 κ κ∗

κ∗ 1 κκ κ∗ 1

; κ = −12+ i√3

6; κ∗ = −1

2− i√3

6

3 / 26

Page 5: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

A fundamental ingredient of a generic theory: a finite, periodicsystem: the Cogwheel Model:

3

21 2

1

0

E

U(δt) =

0 0 11 0 00 1 0

= e−iH δt U3(δt) = I

δt = 1 , U →

1

e−2πi/3

e−4πi/3

; H → 2π

013

23

In the original basis:

H = 2π3

1 κ κ∗

κ∗ 1 κκ κ∗ 1

; κ = −12+ i√3

6; κ∗ = −1

2− i√3

6

3 / 26

Page 6: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

This is an example of a classical system that can be mapped ontoa purely quantum mechanical system.

The example is of course trivial, but can easily be generalised tomuch more complex models . . .

The converse can also be done:

Consider a quantum mechanical system, and try to constructoperators that are beables:

Beables are sets of operators that have the property that thetime evolution law is a pure permutation:

U(ti ) = Pi

or, in the Heisenberg notation:

[O(t1), O(t2)] = 0 ∀(t1, t2) ∈ some large set of times t i

4 / 26

Page 7: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

This is an example of a classical system that can be mapped ontoa purely quantum mechanical system.

The example is of course trivial, but can easily be generalised tomuch more complex models . . .

The converse can also be done:

Consider a quantum mechanical system, and try to constructoperators that are beables:

Beables are sets of operators that have the property that thetime evolution law is a pure permutation:

U(ti ) = Pi

or, in the Heisenberg notation:

[O(t1), O(t2)] = 0 ∀(t1, t2) ∈ some large set of times t i

4 / 26

Page 8: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Examples:

• quantum harmonic oscillator =classical point moving around circle

• chiral Dirac fermion =infinite plane moving with speed of light

• the bulk of a quantized superstring =string on a lattice in transverse space

5 / 26

Page 9: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

The harmonic oscillator.

ϕ↔Unitary

transformation

↔Continuum

limit

Quantum Oscillator ↔ Classical periodic system

6 / 26

Page 10: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Massless, chiral, non interacting “neutrinos” are deterministic:

Second-quantised theory: H = −i ψ† σi∂i ψFirst quantised theory: H = σipiddtO(t) = i [O(t), H]

Beables {Oopi } = {p, s, r} :

p ≡ ±~p/|p| , s ≡ p · ~σ , r ≡ 12(p · ~x + ~x · p) .

|p| = 1 , s = ±1 , −∞ < r <∞

ddt p = 0 , ds

dt = 0 , ddt r = s

These beables form a complete set

7 / 26

Page 11: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

θ

ϕp

r

s

−sThe neutrino sheet.Beables: {p, s, r}

The eigenstates ofthese operators spanthe entire Hilbertspace.

Introducing operatorsin this basis, one canreconstruct the usualoperators ~x , ~p , σi

8 / 26

Page 12: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Interesting mathematical physics:

xi = pi (r − i

pr) + εijk pj L

ontk /pr + (1)

1

2pr

(−ϕi s1 + θi s2 +

p3√1− P2

3

ϕi s3)

θi and ϕi are beables, functions of q .Lontk are generators of rotations of the sheet,s3 = s , s1 and s2 are spin flip operators.

The Hamiltonian of the first-quantised theory has no ground state,but, just as in Dirac’s theory, the second quantised theory doeshave a ground state

9 / 26

Page 13: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Interesting mathematical physics:

xi = pi (r − i

pr) + εijk pj L

ontk /pr + (1)

1

2pr

(−ϕi s1 + θi s2 +

p3√1− P2

3

ϕi s3)

θi and ϕi are beables, functions of q .Lontk are generators of rotations of the sheet,s3 = s , s1 and s2 are spin flip operators.

The Hamiltonian of the first-quantised theory has no ground state,but, just as in Dirac’s theory, the second quantised theory doeshave a ground state

9 / 26

Page 14: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

1st quantization

Hamiltonian with cut-offH|ψi 〉 = hi j |ψj〉

10 / 26

Page 15: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

2nd quantization

Hamiltonian with cut-off

H|ψi 〉 = hi j |ψj〉 −→ H = ψi hi j ψj

Improves locality!And H is bounded from below!

11 / 26

Page 16: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

This we can do with non-interacting neutrinos, not yet with otherfields.

Future strategy: in principle, it may be possible to construct such atheory by replacing other 1st quantized particle systems with 2nd

quantized ones.Add interactions as small corrections: perturbative QFT.

Strategy for obtaining a CA that may lead to a perturbative QFT;

Note, that perturbative QFT are not mathematically perfect, butthey can serve as satisfactory descriptions of a SM for elementaryparticles . . .

12 / 26

Page 17: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Why it is all wrong: Bell’s theorem

III

x

tQP

S

βα

ε

t = t0

t = t1

t = t2

t = t3

t = t4

BobAlice

In the Bell experiment, at t = t0, one must demand that Alice’ssetting a and Bob’s setting b, and the source c , have3 - body correlations of the form

W (a, b, c) ∝ | sin(2(a + b)− 4c)| (or worse)

13 / 26

Page 18: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

But Alice and Bob have free will. How can actions of free will becorrelated to S at time t = t2 � t3?

Answer: They don’t have such free will: superdeterminism.

The Mouse-dropping objection:

Alice and Bobcount the mouse droppings . . .

W

x 2π0

The Mousedropping function, | sin(2(a + b)− 4c)|

14 / 26

Page 19: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

x

tQP

SQA QB

`_

¡

cc ba

t = t0

t = t1

t = t2

t = t3

t = t4

BobAlice

Or, Alice and Bob may register fluctuations coming from quasarsQA and QB .

Correlations in spacelike directions are very strong everywhereW

x 2π0

15 / 26

Page 20: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Conspiracy ?

The ontology conservation law:

If we apply the “true” Schrodinger equation, we can be sure that:

- Original basis elements (ontic states) evolve intoOriginal basis elements (ontic states) ;

- Superpositions evolve into superpositions.

- Neither Alice nor Bob can ever modify their state (applying“free will”) to turn an ontic state into a superposition.

We should not worry about ‘conspiracy’. Ontology is conservedjust like (or better than) angular momentum

Nature’s ontological states are strongly correlated(that’s not in contradiction with causality and/or locality)

16 / 26

Page 21: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

17 / 26

Page 22: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

statesmacrostates

sub-micro

statesmacro

templatesmicrostates

sub-micro

b)a)

18 / 26

Page 23: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Problem with locality:

U(n δt) = e−iH n δt →

Hδt = i logU = π +∑∞

n=11

in δt

(U(n δt)− U(−n δt)

).

Except: vacuum state:U(nδt)|0〉 = |0〉 → U(nδt) = 1 .But: H|0〉 = 0: contradiction

For states close to the vacuum, theexpansion converges badly.

But, U(nδt) connects n neighbours. 0 π 2πω0

π

H

This means that, if H =∑

~x H(~x),H(~x1), H(~x2)] 9 0 when |~x1 − ~x2| 6= 0

Classical locality, but no quantum locality ! Possible remedy:

19 / 26

Page 24: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Second quantization: like with theneutrinos: first construct a classicaltheory for single particles.Now, we allow E > 0 and E < 0solutions.The expansion for H then converges fast.

−π 0 πω

H

π

−π

Therefore, the 1-particle Hamiltonian is local. To get positivity ofthe Hamiltonian, we second quantize: negative energy states areholes of antiparticles (as in Dirac).

Take interactions to be weak; they are obtained by adding localdisturbances in the deterministic evolution.

This may lead to effectively renormalizable QFT. The perturbationexpansion does not converge, but the expansion parameter mayturn out to be sufficiently small.

20 / 26

Page 25: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Time reversibility

So-far, theory was time reversible. The evolution operator U(t) isthen a pure permutator, and its representation in Hilbert space isunitary ⇒ The Hamiltonian is hermitean.

Black holes: non time-reversibility? Break down of unitarity ?

54

3

21

U(δt)?=

0 0 1 0 11 0 0 0 00 1 0 0 00 0 0 0 00 0 0 1 0

.

Introduce: info-equivalence classes: (5) ≈ (3) , (4) ≈ (2)

1

3,5

2,4

U(δt) =

0 0 11 0 00 1 0

.

21 / 26

Page 26: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

Time reversibility

So-far, theory was time reversible. The evolution operator U(t) isthen a pure permutator, and its representation in Hilbert space isunitary ⇒ The Hamiltonian is hermitean.

Black holes: non time-reversibility? Break down of unitarity ?

54

3

21

U(δt)?=

0 0 1 0 11 0 0 0 00 1 0 0 00 0 0 0 00 0 0 1 0

.

Introduce: info-equivalence classes: (5) ≈ (3) , (4) ≈ (2)

1

3,5

2,4

U(δt) =

0 0 11 0 00 1 0

.

21 / 26

Page 27: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

The generic, finite, deterministic, time reversible model:

E

| 1 ⟩

| 0 ⟩

| N −1 ⟩

0

δE

δE +2π

E

0 δEi

E

0

22 / 26

Page 28: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

The generic, finite, deterministic, time non reversible model:

E

| 1 ⟩

| 0 ⟩

| N −1 ⟩

0

δE

δE +2π

E

0 δEi

E

0

23 / 26

Page 29: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

The info-equivalence classes act as local gauge equivalence classes

Maybe they are local gauge equivalence classes!

By construction, these equivalence classes are time-reversible.

So, in spite of info-loss, the quantum theory will be time-reversible:PCT ivariance in QFT.

The classical, ontological states are not time reversible!

Therefore, the classical states carry an explicit arrow of time!The quantum theory does not!

24 / 26

Page 30: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

But conceivable, one first has to add the gravitational force . . .

Changes everything !

Gravitation as a local gauge theory for diffeomorphisms.

Could diffeomorphism classes be info equiv classes?

YES!

Such a theory may help explain why the cosm coupling const, Λ,is small, and why space is globally flat (k ≈ 0):

“The ontological theory has a flat coordinate frame”

25 / 26

Page 31: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

But conceivable, one first has to add the gravitational force . . .

Changes everything !

Gravitation as a local gauge theory for diffeomorphisms.

Could diffeomorphism classes be info equiv classes?

YES!

Such a theory may help explain why the cosm coupling const, Λ,is small, and why space is globally flat (k ≈ 0):

“The ontological theory has a flat coordinate frame”

25 / 26

Page 32: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

G. ’t Hooft, The Cellular Automaton Interpretation of QuantumMechanics,

Fundamental Theories of Physics, Vol. 185,Springer International Publishing, 2016.eBook ISBN 978-3-319-41285-6,DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-41285-6Hardcover ISBN 978-3-319-41284-9, SeriesISSN 0168-1222, Edition Number 1arXiv: 1405.1548 (latest version)

THE END

26 / 26

Page 33: October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum ... · October 20, 2016 A Deterministic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Gerard ’t Hooft University Utrecht H.J. Groenewold

G. ’t Hooft, The Cellular Automaton Interpretation of QuantumMechanics,

Fundamental Theories of Physics, Vol. 185,Springer International Publishing, 2016.eBook ISBN 978-3-319-41285-6,DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-41285-6Hardcover ISBN 978-3-319-41284-9, SeriesISSN 0168-1222, Edition Number 1arXiv: 1405.1548 (latest version)

THE END

26 / 26