46
Natural human languages Bill McGregor

Natural human languages

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Natural human languages. Bill McGregor. My purposes: Highlight some features of natural human languages, distinguishing them from other communicative systems; Mention some functions of language – and why language has the properties it has. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Citation preview

Page 1: Natural human languages

Natural human languages

Bill McGregor

Page 2: Natural human languages

• My purposes:

– Highlight some features of natural human languages, distinguishing them from other communicative systems;

– Mention some functions of language – and why language has the properties it has.

• Jan focussed on grammar and meaning – what is internal to language;

• I shift focus somewhat, looking outward, to language in its contexts.

Page 3: Natural human languages

Three preliminary remarks

• Linguistics is descriptive, not prescriptive.

Page 4: Natural human languages

• Speech is primary, writing secondary

– Humans have been speaking for at least 50,000 years;

– Earliest writing is only about 6,000 years old

• All writing represents features of speech, more or less;

• Speech does not represent features of writing.

Page 5: Natural human languages

• There are striking differences between speech and writing

– Beyond the obvious of aural vs. visual modes.– Next slide shows wave form for my production of the

farmer kills the duckling

Page 6: Natural human languages

0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1.0 1.1 1.2 1.3 1.4 1.5 1.6

Notice that there seems to be a constant stream of sound – it isn’t broken up into pieces like words and letters of writing.

The same holds true for speech production

Th e f ar m er k I ll s th e d u ck l i ng

Page 7: Natural human languages

• Strikingly, despite the analogue nature of the signal, we interpret it in a digital way

– Called categorical perception, we perceive the first sound as a voiced ð rather than a voiceless θ

– We don’t perceive gradations in the ð as actually exist in the sound.

– This feature is illustrated in the following artificially generated speech:

Page 8: Natural human languages

• Speech – language – is not an isolated phenomenon

– It is part of a larger system of communication, including:

• Gestures• Eyegaze• Head movements

– These things go together with language in ordinary speech.

– Try tying someone’s hands, and ask them to tell you how to get to the railway station

Page 9: Natural human languages

Features of natural human language

• Animal communication systems

• Hockett’s design features of human language

Page 10: Natural human languages

• Many animals have systems of communication

– Vervet monkeys have at least 20 different vocal calls:

• Alarm calls warning of different types of predator, including:

– high pitched chutter warns of the presence of a snake;

– a chirp (short but loud barking call) gives warning of leopards and lions;

– a rraup or short cough-like call is given as warning of an eagle

• Also calls indicating emotional states.

Page 11: Natural human languages

• Animals can learn bits of human language.

– Chimps have been taught to use signs from American Sign Language

• In the early 1970s Nim Chimpsky learnt c. 125 signs, and understood at least 200

• He even made up “sentences”, his longest was:

– give orange me give eat orange me eat orange give me eat orange give me you

Page 12: Natural human languages

• But human language is unique to human beings.

– Perhaps uninteresting – barking is unique to dogs: so what?

– In fact it is a fruitful way of grasping the nature and origins of human language.

• The linguist Charles Hockett suggested a number of design features of human languages, distinguishing them from

– Communication systems of other animals;– Other communication systems of humans;– Formal languages.

Page 13: Natural human languages

• Hockett’s list has undergone changes over the years, but it remains basically the same.

• Here are a few, that may be relevant to thinking about natural vs. artificial human languages.

Page 14: Natural human languages

• Reflexivity – use of language for communicating information about language, as we are doing now.

• Productivity – creativity in use of system: users are not restricted to delimited system of possible meanings they can make, but can make novel meanings. Language is an open system.

• Interchangeability – switching of roles of speaker and hearer.

• Feedback – users monitor their output/ production.

Page 15: Natural human languages

• Prevarication – messages can be false, deceptive, or meaningless (e.g. twas brillig and the slyithy toves did gyre and gimble in the wabe).

• Cultural transmission – the system is learnt in a social context, and is not instinctive (like barking of a dog).

• Displacement – we often use language to communicate about events and things not present.

Page 16: Natural human languages

• Of these reflexivity seems to be the most robust in distinguishing language from other animal and human (e.g. traffic lights) communication systems.

– No natural communication system of any animal has this property

• The vervet monkey calls are not used to talk about calls

– No evidence that animals taught human language use it reflexively.

Page 17: Natural human languages

• Productivity, cultural transmission, and prevarication are also robust:

– Most animal communication systems are closed.

– Most are instinctive – even in primates; cultural transmission is found in some bird songs.

– Deception (prevarication) occurs in other primates, but is limited compared to humans.

• These are also limited in occurrence in systems taught to animals.

Page 18: Natural human languages

One illustration of productivity in language

Page 19: Natural human languages

Ontogenesis of language

• I’ve already mentioned cultural transmission

– We aren’t born to speak Danish, English, Gooniyandi, or Mohawk.

– The child learns the language spoken around it, regardless of their genetic lineage.

– But we are probably born to speak a language – at least we have the necessary biological hardware.

Page 20: Natural human languages

• Children acquire language – they are not taught it.

– Cf. writing, which is usually taught rather than acquired.

– Children acquire language in stages, which are fairly comparable from child to child

• In order, though not in timing• Next slide shows an overview.

Page 21: Natural human languages
Page 22: Natural human languages

• Attempts to teach children do not work effectively, unless the child is ready.

• A well known illustration:

Page 23: Natural human languages

• Strategies for child acquisition

– Conditioned-response learning (behaviourism)

• Not given much credence these days

– Imitation

• Clearly plays an important role• But is inadequate as a mechanism of language acquisition

– Hypothesis testing (theory theory)

• Advantages and disadvantages

– Innateness – genetic coding, Language Acquisition Device

• But clearcut biological evidence in favour of LAD is lacking.

Page 24: Natural human languages

• Social-interpersonal theories of acquisition• Various investigators have stressed the role of

the individual’s interactions with others in development of human thought and language.

– Vygotsky – sophisticated thought and language emerges through internalisation of interpersonal processes.

– Michael Tomasello and Peter Hobson argue compellingly for a social (usage-based) approach, though from somewhat different perspectives.

• Both stress the significance of engagement with others in development of symbolic thought and language.

Page 25: Natural human languages

• Dyadic engagement with another (generally caregiver) in 1:1 interactions

– Revealed especially in responses and reactions to facial expressions.

– Infants are highly attuned to others from a very early age.

• Face-to-face dyadic mimicking of behaviour.• Exhibit reactions to non-reactions on part of adult

they are engaged with – e.g. distress, disengagement.

Page 26: Natural human languages

• Triadic engagement where the child relates to another person’s relation to things and events in the world.

– At about age of 1 year, child begins to engage in triadic interactions, where the focus of attention is on an external object.

– Both participants constantly monitor one another’s attention to the object, and to themselves.

– This establishes a joint attentional frame within which communication can occur.

Page 27: Natural human languages

(b) Joint attentional frame

(c) Referent event

(a) Perceptual situation

Tomasello 2002:26: The basic adult-child communicative situation (slightly emended for clarity)

Page 28: Natural human languages

• The child’s understanding of other persons’ intentional relations with the world leads them to attend to the means by which the adult achieves those ends.

– Child imitates the intentional actions of adults.– Thus leading to role-reversal.

• A major reason for the child’s development of language – and symbolic thought – is to affect the minds and actions of others.

Page 29: Natural human languages

• Tomasello:

– The child’s understanding of adult intentionality and role reversal is facilitated by the constant imputation of intentionality to the child’s actions by the adult.

Page 30: Natural human languages

Why is language as it is?• Many linguists believe that some features of

language are not arbitrary:

– That there are features of language that reflect the uses to which it is put.

• “Language is as it is because of the functions it serves in the life of man”, as Michael Halliday has put it.

• Note I said “many”, not “all” – there are linguists who take the view that all is arbitrary, i.e. not motivated by external considerations.

– Major division between functionalist and formalist linguists.

Page 31: Natural human languages

• In the preceding quote Halliday takes a fairly extreme functionalist view: everything in grammar is functional.

• This seems certainly to be false –like other biological phenomena, language holds residue of a-functional things (like the appendix)

– An example: English has a number of prepositions, words like to, at, for

– These are functional, meaningful– But their placement before the noun is not – it is a

residue of historical changes.– You can’t say the dog to or the to dog

Page 32: Natural human languages

– On the other hand, the possessive –’s is attached at the end of the NP, although it conveys the same type of meaning as of

• The person you were talking to’s dog died cf. The dog of the person you were talking to.

• The horse that fell’s rider cf. The rider of the horse that fell

• Functionally motivated things in grammar are however numerous, e.g.:

– Word order in many languages

Page 33: Natural human languages

• Recall Jan’s discussion of word orders in the world’s languages:

– SOV– SVO– VSO– VOS– OVS– OSV (e.g. Urubú, Nadëb)

• Order can be seen as functionally motivated (in “fixed” word order languages).

Page 34: Natural human languages

• This is for the following reasons: order distinguishes who is doing what to who (simplifying a lot!)

• Obviously something we need to do in language, if it is going to be a useful system in communication.

• If we change order of phrases, different meaning arises:

– The farmer kills the duckling;– The duckling kills the farmer

» Notice the crucial importance of the existence of contrasts (absent in the case of preposition ordering)

Page 35: Natural human languages
Page 36: Natural human languages

• The “function” distinguishing who does what to who can be achieved in other ways than word order.

– Some languages use case marking instead, and leave word order “free”.

– One of the best known (allegedly) radically free word order languages is the Australian language Warlpiri.

Page 37: Natural human languages

• The words of the following sentence can be permuted in any way, and the “meaning” remains the same – ‘the dog is biting the little child with its blunt teeth’.

– The only restriction:

• ka must be in second position.

• How do we know who is biting who?

– By the case-marking– And knowledge of the world

• Which precludes interpretations like ‘the tooth is biting the little child with its blunt dog’

Page 38: Natural human languages

• One of the crucial problems in grammar in my view is to arrive at independent ways of delineating between the motivated and unmotivated in language

– Or in other words between the semiotically significant and the semiotically non-significant.

Page 39: Natural human languages

Phylogenesis of language

• I’ve already said that we are in some sense born speakers.

– Most linguists agree that something is genetically encoded.

– The big disagreement is how much:

• Genetic encoding of language faculty (one extreme);

• Language ready brain (other extreme – basically my view)

Page 40: Natural human languages

There has been a rash of work on language origins and evolution in recent years – it’s a hot topic – but most of the ideas are no better or worse than this theory

Page 41: Natural human languages

• Was language invented?

– Perhaps – though obviously not by one person

• Could have been a story somewhat like the invention of writing, which first emerged gradually in Mesopotamia from marks on clay representing ideas rather than words.

• Making it like many other cultural artefacts.

– My view inclines this way.

Page 42: Natural human languages

• I don’t have time to get into this issue.• Suffice it to say that I am currently working on a

theory of language origins that:

– Traces language back to earlier systems of action on objects;

– Which came to symbolise – in increasingly symbolic species – actions on con-specifics;

• We are the only species that act on conspecifics by acting on objects

– By processes of abstraction, we arrive at action on objects that are themselves symbols, this being the crucial step in emergence of natural language.

– My guess is that language goes back to c. 60,000 years, coterminous with the explosion of cultural artefacts and processes.

Page 43: Natural human languages

Languages change• Languages change rapidly

– Much more rapidly than biological systems:

• The basic biological features of plants and animals were set down billions of years ago, and have not changed.

• Can trace back all living things to single-celled forms

– Languages change so rapidly that all traces of relatedness “disappear” within 10,000 years or so.

• Beyond that, it is impossible to separate retained characteristics from accidental similarities.

– In the lifetime of an adult they will be able to recognise change in progress in their language.

Page 44: Natural human languages

• These changes are rarely deliberately engineered.

– Deliberate engineering of language (speech) is usually as unsuccessful as teaching the child.

• Most changes come about through unconscious consensus of speakers.

– Some variations in speech catch on for one reason or another, and are adopted (e.g. the Parisean uvular trill in C17);

– Others don’t catch on, and die a rapid death on their production;

– Still others catch on for a while, and die in a generation (e.g. slang)

Page 45: Natural human languages

Conclusion• The major concluding statement I want to

draw out, that picks up on various notions scattered throughout the paper is:

– Natural human language is a mode of action, rather than a means for reflection on the world, a tool for thought.

– The raison d’être of language is interpersonal – to facilitate action on other human beings

Page 46: Natural human languages

Some references on human language

• Aronoff, Mark & Rees-Miller, Janie. 2001. The handbook of linguistics. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

• Hudson, Richard. 1984. Invitation to linguistics. Oxford: Blackwell.

• Matthews, Peter H. 2003. Linguistics: a very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

• McGregor, William B. 2005. Understanding linguistics. Manuscript.