52
Naming & Necessity

Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Naming & Necessity

Page 2: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism
Page 3: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism
Page 4: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism
Page 5: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism
Page 6: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Classical Descriptivism

Page 7: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Representation

Words/ thoughts have meanings.

They are about things. Why do words, for example, represent the things that they do, instead of other things or nothing at all?

Page 8: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Classical Descriptivism

For every name N, there is a description D that we associate with N such that:

1. If x satisfies D, then N refers to x.2. If N refers to x, then x satisfies the description.

Page 9: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Classical Descriptivism

We may say, following Russell: the name “Moses” can be defined by means of various descriptions.

For example, as “the man who led the Israelites through the wilderness”, “the man who lived at that time and place and was then called ‘Moses’”, “the man who as a child was taken out of the Nile by Pharaoh's daughter” and so on.

Page 10: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Classical Descriptivism

Moses:• Lead the Israelites out of Egypt• Parted Red Sea• Given 10 commandments by God

Page 11: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Classical Descriptivism

This guy

Lead the Israelites out of Egypt Parted Red Sea Given 10 commandments by God

Page 12: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Classical Descriptivism

Moses refers

Page 13: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Classical Descriptivism

This guy

• Lead the Israelites out of Egypt• Parted Red Sea• Given 10 commandments by God

Page 14: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Classical Descriptivism

Moses refers

Page 15: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Kripke against Descriptivism

Page 16: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Saul Kripke, 1940-

• Published first completeness proof for modal logic at 18.

• Highly influential in philosophy of language and mind.

• Developed the causal-historical theory of meaning

Page 17: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Saul Kripke, 1940-

Kripke’s account is developed in his Naming and Necessity.

The background is that he’s arguing against views on which the meanings of names are descriptions or definitions.

Page 18: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Against Descriptivism

Kripke argues that for any name N, there is no description D that we associate with N such that:

1. If x satisfies the description, N refers to x.2. If N refers to x, then x must satisfy the description.

Page 19: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Ignorance & Error

He argues against each claim as follows:

Against #1: Arguments from ignorance. Sometimes lots of things satisfy the descriptions we associate with N, but only one is N.

Against #2: Arguments from Error. Sometimes nothing satisfies the descriptions we associate with N (or some non-x does), but N still = x.

Page 20: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Ignorance: Feynman

What people know:• He’s a physicist• He’s famous• He’s dead• He worked on quantum

mechanics

Page 21: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Ignorance: Feynman

But Bohr:He’s a physicistHe’s famousHe’s deadHe worked on quantum

mechanics

Page 22: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Ignorance: Feynman

it’s not true that ‘Feynman’ means Bohr and it’s not true that it means nothing. How is that possible for the descriptivist?

Page 23: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Error: Einstein

Who is Albert Einstein? What people believe:• Einstein is the inventor of the

atomic bomb.

Page 24: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Error: Einstein

But “the inventor of the nuclear bomb” can’t be the meaning of ‘Einstein’ because then ‘Einstein’ would refer to Leo Szilard (or whoever).

Page 25: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Causation & Representation

Page 26: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Mirror Universe

Page 27: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Secondary Qualities

Page 28: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Possibility of Massive Error

Page 29: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Coordination across Theories

A related upshot is that two people with radically different theories can nevertheless be talking about the same thing, and hence be meaningfully disagreeing with one another.

Page 30: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Causal-Historical Account

Page 31: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Kripke’s Picture

“Someone, let’s say, a baby, is born; his parents call him by a certain name. They talk about him to their friends, other people meet him.

Through various sorts of talk the name is spread from link to link as if by a chain…”

Page 32: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Kripke’s Picture

“A speaker who is on the far end of this chain, who has heard about, say Richard Feynman, in the market place or elsewhere, may be referring to Richard Feynman even though he can’t remember from whom he first heard of Feynman or from whom he ever heard of Feynman.”

Page 33: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Kripke’s Picture

“A rough statement of a theory might be the following: An initial ‘baptism’ takes place. Here the object may be named by ostension, or the reference of the name may be fixed by a description…”

Page 34: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Kripke’s Picture

“When the name is ‘passed from link to link’, the receiver of the name must, I think, intend when he learns it to use it with the same reference as the man from whom he heard it.”

Page 35: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Causal-Historical Theory

Let’s call that baby ‘Feynman’

FeynmanFeynmanFeynmanFeynman

Page 36: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Causal-Historical Theory

Let’s call that baby ‘Feynman’

FeynmanFeynmanFeynmanFeynman

Historical Chain of Transmission

Page 37: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Causal-Historical Theory

Denotation

FeynmanFeynmanFeynmanFeynman

Page 38: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

No Connotations

The causal-historical theory, unlike the other theories, does not use mental facts (idea, experience, definition) to determine a referent.

Denotations are determined by non-mental facts.*

*Plus one intention for each link in the chain.

Page 39: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Natural Kinds

Kripke and another philosopher Hilary Putnam wanted to generalize what was true of names to “natural kind terms” (a phrase introduced by Quine).

Page 40: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism
Page 41: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Causal-Historical Theory

Let’s call that thing a “tiger.”

TIGERTIGERTIGERTIGER

Page 42: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Ignorance: Water

In Hilary Putnam’s classic “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’” he argues that “meaning just ain’t in the head.”

In particular, he presents his famous Twin Earth thought experiment, which is intended to show that what the word ‘water’ is true of is not determined by what we know or believe about water.

Page 43: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Twin Earth

Twin Earth is a planet on the other side of the galaxy. In most ways, it is just like Earth, down to the smallest detail.

You have a twin on Twin Earth who’s just like you, I have a twin who’s just like me, they’re sitting in a twin classroom, and my twin is giving a lecture just like this one to your twin.

And so on and so forth.

Page 44: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Earth Twin Earth

Page 45: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Twin Earth

There is however one difference between Earth and Twin Earth. On Earth, all the watery stuff is H2O. On Twin Earth, the watery stuff is composed of a complicated chemical compound we can abbreviate XYZ.

H2O and XYZ look and behave exactly the same. They taste the same, they boil at the same temperatures at the same distance above sea level, their conductance is the same, etc.

Page 46: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Twin EarthConsider two twins, Arnold on Earth and Twin Arnold on Twin Earth.

Neither knows any chemistry. What they know/ believe about the stuff they call ‘water’ is the same. Q: Would it be true for Arnold to call the stuff on Twin Earth ‘water’?

Page 47: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Twin Earth

The intuition is supposed to be that, no, Arnold’s word ‘water’ is true of all an only H2O, whereas Twin Arnold’s word ‘water’ is true of all and only XYZ

Page 48: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Moral

The conclusion Kripke and Putnam draw from such cases is that we fix the referent of ‘water’ by a description like “the stuff around here in lakes and rivers and streams that falls from the sky and quenches thirst.”

But this description only fixes the referent. If you replaced all the H2O on Earth with XYZ, there wouldn’t be any more water here.

Page 49: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

Epistemic & Modal Arguments

Page 50: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Epistemic Argument

Kripke had two other arguments against description theories (which he took to support his own account). First, suppose someone says “Aristotle means the last great philosopher of antiquity.” It is true that if x is named ‘Aristotle’ then x was the last great philosopher of antiquity and vice versa. So this is not a Feynman or an Einstein case.

Page 51: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Epistemic Argument

However, it still seems as though you don’t have the same sort of epistemic access to this fact as to other clearer cases of definition like ‘bachelors are unmarried men.’ You don’t know for sure that Aristotle was the last great philosopher of antiquity. It could turn out false. It could turn out that Aristotle was just a medieval forgery. If it were a definition, you should know for sure. But you don’t.

Page 52: Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism

The Modal Argument

Finally, Kripke argues that the modal properties of names are different from those of definitions:

FALSE: If things had gone differently, Aristotle might not have been Aristotle.TRUE: If things had gone differently, Aristotle might not have been the last great philosopher of antiquity.