Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    1/37

    Memory at WorkAn analysis of nostalgia in music through digital technology

    Bob Balm & Puck van Sprang

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    2/37

    Digital Music Cultures

    MA Nieuwe Media en Digitale Cultuur

    Authors: Bob Balm and Puck van Sprang

    Student ID: 3218546 and 3253252

    Teacher: Isabella van Elferen

    Institution: Universiteit Utrecht

    January 2011

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    3/37

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    4/37

    Table of Contents

    Introduction (Bob & Puck) 2

    1. Nostalgia (Bob & Puck) 4

    2. Musical Treasures (Puck) 9

    3. Victims of Memory (Bob) 17

    4. Technogical Nostalgia (Bob & Puck) 25

    References 30

    Musical References 34

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    5/37

    2

    Introduction

    The question of what music is and what it does to its listeners is a very broad one, and a

    question that has so far been, and will perhaps forever, remain without a definitive answer.

    One strand of sub-questions we may ask when researching musics place in the world has to

    do with its relation to peoples memories. We all have that one special song that takes us

    back to when we were young and in school, when we met that special someone with whom

    we shared a summer, or when we hung out with friends at the local mall. Whenever such a

    song is played on the radio we are instantly reminded of exactly how it was in those days.

    We recall the people we were with, the environment we are in, perhaps even minor details

    such as a particular smell or sound. Such impulses are generally known to evoke a feeling ofnostalgia (Bull 2009: 86). The central theme of this essay will be exactly that: nostalgia in

    music. We want to place the emphasis on the way nostalgia emerges through listening to

    music.

    Michael Bull, in The Auditory Nostalgia of iPod Culture (2009), gives a description of how

    iPod users experience nostalgia through the devices typical features such as playlists and

    the shuffle function. In his analysis however, he remains rather superficial in dealing with

    the concept of nostalgia itself. Our aim in this essay will be to delve deeper into this concept.

    We will do so by examining a division that has arisen when considering nostalgia. This

    division splits the concept into voluntarily conjured up nostalgia, or voluntary memory on

    the one hand, and involuntarily evoked nostalgia, or involuntary memory, on the other. This

    division is embodied in this essay by two works. First, Taking Your Favourite Sound Along:

    Portable Audio Technologies for Mobile Music Listening (2009) by Heike Weber in which

    she introduces sound souvenirs as a metaphor for voluntary auditory memories. Second, in

    The Musical Madeleine: Communication, Performance, and Identity in Musical Ringtones

    (2010), Imar de Vries and Isabella van Elferen similarly use the madeleine, a type of French

    cookie, metaphorically to explain how mmoires involontaires involuntary (auditory)

    memories are evoked through musical ringtones on mobile phones. While ringtones

    themselves have little relation to this article, the metaphor of the musical madeleine will

    prove to be useful in defining nostalgia more specifically.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    6/37

    3

    In Chapters two and three of this essay, which deal with these two areas of musical

    nostalgia, two philosophical approaches will be used to analyze the process of creating and

    recalling memories. The second chapter will be devoted to Jacques Derridas view on

    archives and will attempt to match it with the concept of voluntary nostalgia and (portable)

    music devices. In the third chapter, a similar analysis is given of involuntary nostalgia using

    the ideas of Gilles Deleuze surrounding memory and time. It must be stressed that we are

    not trying to combine Derrida and Deleuze in order to make a single statement. Rather, the

    philosophers offer valuable complements to the suggested sides of nostalgia we discussed

    earlier. Finally, in chapter four, we will examine how nostalgia unfolds in an age of digital

    music technologies. The core work of this last chapter is the idea of tertiary memory, by

    Bernard Stiegler.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    7/37

    4

    1. Nostalgia

    In The Auditory Nostalgia of iPod Culture Michael Bull uses the concept nostalgia to

    describe memories, meaning and other connotations related to music, using the iPod as an

    example. According to Bull, for the first time in history it is possible - because of

    technological improvements - for listeners to create their own private mobile auditory

    world wherever they go (Bull 2009: 83). Portable music devices such as the iPod are

    symbolic of a culture in which many increasingly use communication technologies to

    control and manage their daily experience (Bull 2009: 83). Bull describes the experience of

    this culture from the perspective of the iPod users:

    [They] often report being in a dream reveries while on the move turned inward from the

    world and living in an interiorized an pleasurable world of their own making, away from

    the historical contingency of the world, and into the certainty of their own past, real or

    imagined, enclosed safely within their own private auditory soundscape. Nostalgia bathes

    these experiences in a warm, personalised glow (2009: 83).

    Bull claims that the value of individualized forms becomes the opposite of culturally

    fabricated forms of auditory nostalgia. We should not look at interrelations between personaland collective memories of popular music as Jos van Dijck states in Audio, Technologies,

    Memory and Cultural Practices, instead the iPod users are prone to listen more individ ually

    rather than utilizing collective music devices such as radio (Bull 2009: 84). By saying this he

    does not mean that we should not take culture into account, but that the practice of listening

    is a moment in which iPod users seek out an individualized moment of consumption.

    These individualized practices he describes as forming a personal soundtrack to daily

    activities. Some of the examples Bull mentions are people listening to personal audio devices

    while shopping, being on public transport or working out in the gym. In doing so, these

    listeners create their own soundscape, a sort of auditory bubble (Bull 2009: 84 -85). This

    allows them to be more connected with their personal memories evoked by the music.

    Nostalgia is Bulls central subject in speaking of contemporary urban experience. It helps to

    locate the subject in the world, it gives a semblance of coherence, and it warms up the space

    of movement in a mobile world in which users increasingly deflect away from the space and

    time traversed (2009: 85). He recognizes a shift of the collectivized auditory nostalgia of the

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    8/37

    5

    twentieth-century Western Society to a more recent individualized form: The segmented

    nature of contemporary [] nostalgic [musical] reception is superseded in the present

    account by the individualized scheduling of music in the most recent of mobile auditory

    technologies, the iPod (Bull 2009: 86).

    In our view, Bulls work on auditory nostalgia archived in and evoked by the iPod remains

    rather superficial. The aim of this essay then is to explore deeper some of the concepts that

    Bull addresses, sometimes unknowingly, in his article. To do so, we will look at two ways in

    which auditory nostalgia appears in music theory. First, there is the area of voluntary

    auditory memory. This term governs those memories that one is explicitly aware of and

    willingly accesses through the listening of a certain (collection of) music. An example of this

    is Jerome, one of the respondents to Bulls inquiry. Jerome explains how he purposefully

    listens to certain music when he is in a particular mood, for example feeling homesick to

    Switzerland, his nation of birth (Bull 2009: 88). The second area is that of involuntary

    auditory memory. This kind of memory is not purposefully accessed, but is accidentally

    recalled through a certain event, such as a song being played on the radio or a playlist on

    shuffle, and takes the listener back to a specific period in his or her life. This type of memory

    is shown in Bulls description of nostalgia experienced by Swiss soldiers stationed in France.

    Upon hearing sounds such as a village bell ringing or shepherds driving their herds, the

    soldiers were reminded of their home in the Swiss Alps.

    It should be noted that these two areas are more or less two sides of the same coin, as we

    believe the mnemonic mechanisms the way in which the actual process of recollection can

    be theoretically conceptualized that drive them both are similar if not blatantly identical. In

    this essay we will nonetheless deal with these two areas separately. The area of voluntary

    auditory memory, will be mostly supported by theories around the construction andexperience of archives, such as work of Derrida. The other path, that of involuntary auditory

    memory, is made up of works surrounding the actual and virtual, which are two connected

    concepts worked out by Deleuze that deal with the perception of time and can be applied to

    memory and nostalgia.

    We can label these two different areas using two concepts that demonstrate somewhat

    metaphorically what the two areas are about. First, labelled onto voluntary auditory memory

    is the idea of sound souvenirs, coined by composer Raymond Murray (1977) as a term to

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    9/37

    6

    describe the way recording technologies are capable of rescuing endangered sounds, such

    as the sounds of pre-industrial life (Bijsterveld & Van Dijck 2009: 12) and is further

    explained by Heike Weber (2009). Weber states that portable audio devices can be

    interpreted as mobile sound souvenirs, they help to configure and shape peoples cultural

    identities when they travel elsewhere [and enable] users to channel their emotions (2009:

    70). But, although it might sound easy, there is not just one way of approaching these

    souvenirs; there are four different modes of using sound souvenirs emerge: the rewind and

    forward modes, and the modes that fostered group and individual identities (Weber 2009:

    70).

    By listening to mobile sound souvenirs, any given spot can be domesticated through a self-

    selected sound track. Users thus have partially regained control over the spaces they cross,

    either by making the unknown territory known through familiar songs, or by turning routine

    activities and commuting into exiting, potentially unique experiences through an

    accompanying selection of music. In the first practice, users create similarity between the new

    territory and home by taking sound souvenirs from a familiar to an unfamiliar situation. They

    go back in time to be able to cope with the present the rewind mode of using sound

    souvenirs. The second practice, however, can be called the forward mode of taking sound

    souvenirs along. By making the routine unique or the familiar unfamiliar with the help of a

    self-created sound track, this practice generates future sound souvenirs (Weber 2009: 80).

    By giving an historical introduction of portable music devices, Weber stresses the importance

    of technologies in our musical experience. Portable electronics have [] become

    intertwined with both the increased spatial mobility and growing individualization of

    society. They have helped to foster and maintain a sense of emotional and cultural identity,

    which appears to have drifted from a group to a more individual basis (Weber 2009: 80-81).

    Though, whether used in rewind or forward mode, and whether as group or individual

    identity, all these sound souvenirs or mediated memories as Jos van Dijck would call

    them (2004) are voluntarily retrieved by people turning on a (portable) music device.

    The second label, placed onto involuntary auditory memory, is that of the musical

    madeleine. A madeleine is a type of cookie that Marcel Proust (1913-1927) dipped in histea,

    the taste of which made him remember his grandmother. A musical madeleine then, is a

    sudden feeling that disrupts the current everyday situation, triggered through music. This is

    described in the article The Musical Madeleine: Communication, Performance, and Identity

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    10/37

    7

    in Musical Ringtones (2010) by Imar de Vries and Isabella van Elferen. [They] consider

    musical cell-phone ringtones as virtual, communicative and cultural performances [and]

    argue that the musical ringtone functions as a musical madeleine [] an involuntary

    mnemonic trigger of a complex web of individual and collective memories (De Vries & Van

    Elferen 2010: 61). Just like Weber they start with a technological introduction with the

    emphasis on mobility. Mobilization has a significant influence on how people experience

    connections they share with other social beings. By studying the ringtone as a virtual

    communicative and cultural performance De Vries and Van Elferen state that the ringtone is

    often an overlooked element of mobile telephony and plays an important role in its uses as

    symbol of economic, social and cultural society (2010: 62). They describe the ringtone as:

    ...virtual because it is always silently present and potentially activated; it is a communicative

    performance because it works as a sign projected by the callee and interpreted by an audience;

    it is a cultural performance because it employs the performative faculty of this communicative

    act in order to stage cultural meanings for its potential audience (De Vries & Van Elferen 2010:

    62).

    The goal of their article then, by approaching the ringtone from these different angles, is to

    conceptualize the ringtone and its cultural work as a way in which possible meanings are

    generated (2010: 62). This constant silent presence and potential of the ringtone (and thus

    its related connotations) will prove to be important later on, when discussing how memories

    can suddenly present themselves in our actual lives. When De Vries and Van Elferen

    consider musical ringtones as cultural performances on the one hand and as musical

    communications on the other, it follows that what is being performed are the cultural

    meanings of the music being played (2010: 66). Meaning is attached to a ringtone and

    enables users to display a certain message and influence the audience; the latter will hear the

    ringtone and possibly recall a related memory. In any case, the hearing of the ringtone itself

    will become a memory to be recalled at a later time, when the same song is heard again.

    From this follows that music is constantly re-contextualised. Original connotations can be

    changed or adjusted. De Vries and Van Elferen consider the ringtone as the involuntary

    memory of a song: [T]his seemingly minute medium inevitable stirs strong memories to

    which new contexts make additions rather than radical alterations (2010: 68). This feeling,

    an unannounced memory without the motivated choice of a person to recall it, can then be

    characterized as a musical madeleine.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    11/37

    8

    Having introduced and explained the motivation behind the structure of this essay, we move

    on to the next chapter, in which we will discuss voluntary memories, mainly by approaching

    it from Jacques Derridas post-structuralist point of view by analysing portable music

    devices as archives. In his book Archive Fever: a Freudian Impression, he states that human

    beings have the immanent impulse to save and maintain everything, because we are afraid to

    lose memories of knowledge. An archive is not a fixed given and is constantly a subject of

    change. These ideas will form the basis of our discussion of voluntary memory.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    12/37

    9

    2. Musical Treasures

    The first time I heard The Highways of my Life (Isley Brothers 1974) it was on the radio just after my first grandfather passed away. Although having a tremendous dislike for

    ballads in general at that time, I was very touched by it. A few years later, my other

    grandfather passed away and I started playing the song over and over again. On the one

    hand it recalled my grief of the time I lost my first grandfather, but on the other hand it gave

    me comfort while grieving about my grandfather now passed away. This weird feeling of

    melancholy and comfort is what I still experience while listening to this song, but growing

    up and beginning to understand the lyrics resulted in yet another connotation.

    Moving down the highways of my life

    Makin' sure I stay to the right

    Moving down the highways of my life

    So I shan't be concerned

    With the other side of the road

    Reading all the signs along the way

    Knowing where I am not what they say

    My destination's closer day by day

    So I can't concern

    With the other side of the road

    []

    Leaving all the sorrows and the pain

    There's no love between us that remains

    Although you are the one

    You're not the same

    So the other side of the road

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    13/37

    10

    Can only take me back home

    The song is about a person describing his life as a journey on a highway, on which he makes

    sure not to go to the other side of the road. The meaning of the song is ambiguous. On the

    one hand it is positive: moving on, coming closer to a certain goal, while staying on the right

    path in your life. On the other hand, we dont know what our destination is, we dont even

    know if we are going forward or backward. The only way to know this is by sometimes

    making mistakes: So the other side of the road, can only take me back home. Now, four

    and a half years later, to me this song is no longer just about grief; its also about life and how

    to live it. First I did not want to hear it when I was in a good mood, because it immediately

    brought me back to these sad memories about my grandfathers. A few years later I have

    grown more comfortable listening to this song. It has become part of my life and I will play it

    whenever I feel like listening to it. Such feelings are what this chapter will be about: the

    voluntary act of conjuring up memories or moods through playing specific songs, the

    influence of the first moment of hearing a song, and the way the accumulation of different

    events can change personal meaning of a song.

    The emergence of digital music, the numerous ways to spread it, and the developed devices

    to carry this music along all contribute to a more personalized and individualized way of

    listening to music. This expansion allows individuals more than ever before to play a song

    that has a certain connotation with a specific memory at will, when- or wherever they are.

    Focussing on the iPod as mobile music device, Bull states that in contemporary culture, the

    technology of the iPod provides an auditory mnemonic for contemporary nostalgic (2009:

    86). In this chapter, by analysing mobile music devices as archives, the emphasis will be on

    voluntary memories as form of nostalgia. We will start by looking at the definition of

    archives as posited by Derrida in Archive Fever: a Freudian Impression (1995). Although his

    book is rather dated given the widespread emergence of digital music devices had yet to

    arrive in the 90s and not specifically related to music, his definition is still useful when

    considering contemporary music devices approached as archives.

    From a post-structuralist and historical (1989) point of view, Derrida states that we will have

    to start examining the word archive in order to understand why human beings collect and

    save things in the first place. Archive is derived from the Greek word Arkh which has two

    meanings. First, it means beginning there where things commence [a] physical, historical,

    or ontological principle (Derrida 1995: 1). Second, it means command there where

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    14/37

    11

    authority [and] social order are exercised [a] nomological1principle (1995: 1). Archive as

    concept, shelters in its name the memory of the word Arkh, but the archive shelters itself as

    well: which comes down to saying that it forgets is own meaning. An archive refers to itself

    in terms of the physical, historical or ontological but at the same time cannot catch its own

    meaning (1995: 2).

    In nomological sense, archive refers also to Arkh as command or order. Arkh and thus

    archive is derived from the Greek Arkheion meaning house or residence. Citizens that

    owned an Arkheion, were considered to possess political power and influence on law. They

    had the power to interpret the Arkheion and therefore the power to construct the law. This

    archontic power gathers functions such as unification, identification and classification

    (Derrida 1995: 2-3). In terms of digital music devices, users employ their contemporary MP3player as such an Arkheion; they possess this device and have the power to fill it with any

    kind of music (or documents, movies and photos). According to Bull:

    Sound is a powerful aphrodisiac when it comes to evoking memory. Memories are largely

    mediated memories in iPod culture, a mediated life through which to filter ones personal

    narrative. This coupling of the personal to the commodity is a hallmark of iPod culture with

    users in potentially constant touch with their narrative past. Musical past also becomes

    reconfigured and rediscovered in iPod culture. Musical identity is inscribed onto a portable

    memory bank giving the user instant access to its contents (Bull 2009: 89).

    In Remembering Songs through Telling Stories, Jos van Dijck Media and Culture

    teacher at the University of Amsterdam uses the Top 2000 of Radio 2 (an annually created

    and played hit list on a Dutch radio station) as example to stress the importance of stories by

    remembering songs. Through comments on the website of the Top 2000, we can learn about

    how people are emotionally attached and what kind of meaning they ascribe to a song (2009:

    109). But connotations change. Memories have the tendency to be altered every time werecollect them (2009: 107); or in Van Dijcks words:

    [I]t is improbable that repeated listening over a life time would leave an original emotion (if

    there was such a thing) intact. Instead, the original listening experience may be substituted

    by a fixed pattern of associations, a pattern that is likely to become more brightly and

    intensely colored over the years. A memory changes each time it is recalled, and its content is

    determined more by the present than by the past. As much as people believe their original

    experiences remain intact, cognitive research confirms that musical remembrance alters with

    1 The science of law making.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    15/37

    12

    age (Van Dijck 2009: 109).

    In a similar vein of thought, Jacques Derrida argues that an archived memory is never the

    same as the original experience of the event the memory refers to (Derrida 1995: 11). The

    technology behind any archive allows for, indeed largely determines a particular type of

    construction of these mediated memories (Derrida 1994, Derrida 1995: 16-17). Thus it can be

    said that the manner in which individuals retrieve memory from songs on their iPod is

    largely determined by the technological properties of the iPod. Bull demonstrates as much in

    speaking of the playlists his respondents use to organize their music. Playlists are something

    typical of contemporary MP3 players and thus influence how the archival memories behind

    the songs in these playlists are experienced. Derrida claims that an archive such as a

    musical collection in the case of an iPod will never be finished but continuously adjusted,

    changed or replaced:

    The question of the archive is not [] a question of the past. It is not the question of a concept

    dealing with the past that might already be at our disposal or not at our disposal, an archivable

    concept of the archive. It is a question of the future, the question of the future itself, the question

    of a response, of a promise and of a responsibility for tomorrow. The archive: if we want to

    know what that will have meant, we will only know in times to come. Perhaps (Derrida 1995:

    36).

    This characteristic of perpetual change of the archive can be traced in the use of MP3 players.

    Playlists are constantly changing: users delete songs, download new ones and rearrange the

    order in which songs are played. Bull gives the example that some people see their iPod as

    the diary or soundtrack of their life; an iPod as personalised archive (2009: 86). Nostalgia

    cannot be approached separately from its mechanical reproduction in contemporary music

    culture. This important aspect of the technology behind recorded music is often overlooked,

    yet it plays an intrinsic part in the act of recollection. There are people prefer the cracking

    sound of LPs above the clean CD versions released later on (Christiansen 2010). This shows

    that the characteristic of the recording and/or equipment defines the experience of the

    moment they heard the song for the first time (Van Dijck 2009: 112). Just like they treasure

    their amateur recordings, not in spite of, but because oftheir obvious technical shortcomings

    (2009: 112). Our personal memories evolve trough the interaction with recent as well as more

    traditional technologies. Every new medium makes the older ones authentic

    meaning that each time a new audio technology emerges on the scene, the older ones

    become treasured as the authentic means of reproduction or as part of the original

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    16/37

    13

    listening experience. In the digital era, scratches, ticks, or noise can be removed from tapes to

    make old recordings sound pristine, but they can also be added to make a pristine recording

    sound old. [] With the new digital technologies, sonic experiences of the past can be

    preserved and reconstructed in the future (2009: 113).

    These new digital technologies undeniably have an influence on the process of remembering

    through recorded music. True collectors both have physical records as well as digital

    updates to be sure not to lose any of their music (Van Dijck 2009: 114). This anxiety to lose

    something is inherent to human beings. There would be no archive desire without

    forgetfulness. The necessity not to forget anything, and therefore the tendency to archive as

    much as possible is what Derrida calls archive fever (1995: 19). Materiality and technology

    are often integral to this memory urge and are unlikely to change with the arrival of digital

    equipment. As long as listening to music remains a mediated experience, memory will be

    enabled and constructed through its material constituents (Van Dijck 2009: 114). This is

    what Van Dijck calls mediated memories: these memories involve individuals carving out

    their place in history, defining personal remembrance in the face of larger cultural

    frameworks (2004: 275).

    Van Dijcks work is usually concerned with the study of interrelations between personal and

    collective memories, but we are particularly interested in the way she describes howmemories be it collective or individual are constructed by the use of different media.

    New digital technologies allow music fans to customize their favourite collections of songs

    and use them as a symbolic resource in the construction of identity and community (2009:

    116). Owners of contemporary MP3 players use their device as a vehicle for individual

    listening and storage of favourite songs, which according to Van Dijck leads to a situation in

    which MP3 players figure as agents in the conscious process of building up a (collective)

    memory. Although Van Dijcks goal is to explain that the storing of music is a shared or

    communal activity (2009: 118), technological developments tend to suggest the opposite

    direction: a more individualistic way of memorizing by creating personal music archives on

    MP3 players.

    Unlike van Dijck, Heike Weber (already introduced in the previous chapter), sees a shift in

    the development of audio technologies in which the personal aspect of music listening

    becomes increasingly important because of a new design feature of music devices, namely

    portability. Both authors use Tia DeNoras (2000) perspective on how music changes the waywe experience time. These musical experiences are what DeNora calls music as a

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    17/37

    14

    technology of the self. Her goal is to ground the various ethnographic studies within a

    theoretical/multi-disciplined aggregate of contemporary thought (Magdanz 2002).

    Remarkable is the different perspectives from which both Van Dijck and Weber approach

    DeNoras book. In order not to stray away too much of the topic voluntary musical

    memories, the distinction between individual and collective memories will from now on

    only be discussed superficially.

    Weber uses both Bulls and DeNoras ideas to argue that users of audio technologies

    employ recorded music to create and maintain emotion, to elicit memories and to activate

    and relax themselves (2009: 69). The importance of the mobility of new media technologies is

    that it reshapes traditional ways of listening to music and normalizes new forms of mobile

    listening practices. Initially introduced as travel companion, mobile music devices becamepopular in all kinds of public spaces. Users have played an important role in shaping the

    meaning of these mobile technologies (Weber 2009: 69-70). Approaching these devices from a

    historical perspective starting with portable radios and traces the development of portable

    audio devices up to the Walkman Weber interprets them as mobile sound souvenirs that

    help to configure and shape peoples cultural identities when they travel elsewhere (2009:

    70). These devices allowed users to channel their emotions and create a personally

    controlled auditory sphere (2009: 70).

    According to Weber, portable music devices became intertwined with the increase of spatial

    mobility and the growing individualization of society (2009: 80). Her core argument is that

    the activity of listening to music becomes increasingly individualized. Although writing

    about portability, she does not give much attention to the way new geographical locations

    influence the construction and evocation of memory in combination with music. Hearing a

    song on a specific location has always had an influence on the way memories were

    constructed, but portable devices geographically caused an enormous growth of options forwhen and where to listen to individually chosen music. Where personal music used to be

    listened to in personal, often domestic locations, and public music was listened to in public

    spaces, technological developments made it possible to expand the musical soundscape of

    personal music into public locations. We are reminded here of work by Michel de Certeau. In

    Walking in the City (1984), De Certeau describes how such practices like walking,

    wandering or window shopping are

    the [activities] of passers-by, [as] transformed into points that draw a totalizing and

    reversible line on the map. They allow us to grasp only a relic set in the nowhen of a surface of

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    18/37

    15

    projection. Itself visible, it has the effect of making invisible the operation that made it

    possible. These fixations constitute procedures for forgetting. The trace left behind is

    substituted for the practice. It exhibits the (voracious) property that the geographical system

    has of being able to transform action into legibility, but in doing so it causes a way of being in

    the world to be forgotten (De Certeau 1984: 131).

    Although not literally speaking of walking through a city with mobile music devices, De

    Certeau provides some useful insights in the way the city can be shaped as a soundscape by

    personal connotation. By looking at how digital music devices now shape the way we look at

    geographical places from his technical semiotic perspective, we would like to stress the

    importance of the portability of music devices in creating new types of auditory memory.

    This portable character of contemporary MP3 players caused a change in the perception of

    the environment of its users. Walking through a city or in terms of De Certeau, walking in a

    city as immersive experience gains an extra dimension when combined with listening to

    music. This geographical expansion of music makes new locations a potential memory object

    to be evoked the next time the song is being played. Consider for example the testimony of

    Jerome in Michael Bulls article, as discussed in the previous chapter. Jerome used his iPod to

    remind him of home while being on the move. This example is a clearly voluntary memory;

    Jerome can choose whether to play this personal music or not. But what about the case of the

    Swiss soldiers stationed in France? With them, bells that sounded like Alpine melodies of

    Switzerland triggered a nostalgic memory. They never asked for this feeling, and yet it was

    triggered; it was involuntary. But before introducing the involuntary side of nostalgia, let us

    briefly summarize the characteristics of voluntary nostalgia.

    Memories and moods are constructed, adjusted and evoked by listening to music. By

    approaching mobile music devices as archives in terms of Derrida, contemporary MP3

    players have become personal archives that can be used by individuals to voluntarily evoke

    specific memories. They can fill their MP3 players with anything they want, and can change

    the content anytime they want. Archives constantly change and are never finished, just like

    the playlist of an MP3 is never complete. The connotation of memories changes every time a

    song is played again because the occasion is never exactly the same as the first time. We have

    also seen that materiality and technology have a big influence on how these memories are

    retrieved. The sound quality of the specific device will in large part determine how a song is

    experienced for the first time. People often have physical as well as digital copies of their

    songs, to make sure that they will not lose these musical memories. The urge that drives such

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    19/37

    16

    collecting behavior is what Derrida calls Archive Fever. Granting their users the ability to

    listen to music anywhere in the world, mobile music devices have caused an expansion of

    geographical memories. They influence the way music is perceived: they are personal

    archives; backups and help users construct their identity.

    As we have stated before, voluntary and involuntary auditory memories are closely related

    to each other. In this chapter, by approaching musical memories through contemporary MP3

    players as personal archives of memory, we spoke about voluntary memories. In the next

    chapter, the focus will be on a sudden, unexpected confrontation with memories. What effect

    does this have on the feelings of individuals? What if a song reminds you of a relation that

    did not end so well? Or maybe an almost forgotten memory pops into your head because of

    a musical tune? The evocation of these involuntary memories will be examined from thepoint of view of Gilles Deleuze, and the emphasis will lie on how the act of remembering

    takes place.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    20/37

    17

    3. Victims of Memory

    In 2001, the Finnish power-metal band Sonata Arctica released their sophomore record

    Silence. While this bands repertoire has no more meaning to me other than being

    generally ok to listen to, the eleventh track on this album, Tallulah, has come to carry a

    great deal of significance for me. I first heard it outside a local bar, almost four years ago, on

    a rainy Sunday morning at around 6 oclock. It was played to me on a cell phone by the girl I

    had just spent the night with dancing and having a great time. We ended up kissing and this

    would be the first day of our relationship. The lyrics tell a tale:

    Remember when we used to look how sun sets far away?And how you said: "This is never over"

    I believed your every word and I guess you did too

    But now you're saying : "Hey, let's think this over"

    []

    Tallulah, It's easier to live alone than fear the time it's over, oo-ooh...

    Tallulah, find the words and talk to me, oh, Tallulah,This could be... heaven

    []

    I see you walking hand in hand with long-haired drummer of the band

    In love with her or so it seems, he's dancing with my beauty queen

    Dont even dare to say you hi, still swallowing the goodbye

    But I know the feelings still alive, still alive

    Like so many relationships, this one too ended, and like so many songs, this one too tells

    exactly how I felt at the time of our breakup, down to the mention of a new love for her and

    awkward meetings afterwards. As this song carried such a connection to the time I spent

    with this girl, I have found it an eerie combination of beautiful and saddening to listen to

    ever since, and tend to stray away from it. Two years ago however, I was at a concert of this

    band, and the song happened to be in their set list. As the first notes of the piano struck my

    ears, I was immediately reminded of all kinds of things surrounding my relationship with

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    21/37

    18

    this girl. This musical occurrence of involuntary memory and the processes that shape it are

    what this chapter is all about.

    The above description is not all that different from the example of Proust and the madeleine

    from De Vries and Van Elferens work (2010) mentioned in the first chapter. In speaking of

    involuntary memory evoked through music, it is interesting to look for a moment at work by

    Tia DeNora, an author who writes in a similar fashion to Michael Bull, whose article we

    mentioned in the introduction. In Music and Self-Identity (2006), DeNora describes how

    she, like Bull, interviewed respondents on their experience with memory and music. One of

    her respondents quite clearly describes the idea behind involuntary memory, when she tells

    of an experience she had when shopping. The song A Whiter Shade of Pale (Procul

    Harum, 1967) was played on the store radio and it reminded her of her time in university

    where she spent time with her future husband. The respondent claimed it takes [her] back

    (DeNora 2006: 141). DeNora starts her article with the assertion that [m]usic can be used as

    a device for the reflexive process of remembering/constructing who one is (2006: 141).

    Upon hearing again the music that was present at the time an experience was turned into a

    memory, most of the respondents described how they relived the experience. It is

    noteworthy how DeNora mentions remembering together with constructing. As we shall see,

    the two are very closely related when it comes to the manner in which memory is

    experienced.

    DeNora, in her analysis, recognizes that there is far more to the combination of music and

    memory than just acknowledging that music is often simply present at the occurrence of a

    memorable event (2006: 143-144). She goes on to find whatever it is that is more by asking

    people what they think it is in certain songs, like particular chords that are used, that makes

    these songs so memorable. In other words, DeNora tries to find the answer in music. In this

    chapter, we take another route by looking at one interpretation of how mnemonic retrieval

    might work on part of the listener. We do this by taking an in-depth look at work of Gilles

    Deleuze on memory. In the chapter Memory as Virtual Coexistence in his book Bergsonism

    (1988), Deleuze gives his own thoughts on work by Henri Bergson, who has written about

    memory in the late 19th century.

    Deleuze, in commenting on Bergson, paraphrases the latter in distinguishing two ways in

    which memory takes shape. First, there is the distinct presence of the past in the present, like

    an ever growing moment in time that contains not only that moment itself but also

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    22/37

    19

    everything that has come before. Second, there is a reference to the past as being behind the

    present in terms of locus, not time and not so much contained within the present but

    acting as baggage to the individual, dragged along as an external load (Deleuze 1988: 51).

    Deleuze explains this further, saying that on one hand, any next moment always contains

    within it the remnants left by the current moment. He calls this recollection-memory. On the

    other, these two moments are always connected to each other, since the current has not

    disappeared when the next arrives. This he names contraction-memory (1988: 51-52). While

    this seems highly micro-oriented, operating on the level of moments, in all their brevity, we

    can translate it to a bigger picture of musical memory. If we imagine the moment of hearing

    a song that reminds us of a period in our past, this moment is in the present, but is also the

    past in the present, actualizing in the moment all the connotations we have to the past,

    labelling this moment in the now with those connotations. At the same time this moment acts

    as a referent to the event in the past that the music reminds us of. It should be noted here

    that it is not the music that is being actualized (as can be said for instance when we see a

    band perform a previously recorded song), but the memory. Reminiscent of DeNoras

    description, the music can be seen as the device, the catalyst of this recollection. Thus, for the

    duration of the song we can say that we find ourselves in a movement [] by which the

    present that endures divides at each instant into two directions, one oriented and dilated

    towards the past, the other contracted, contracting towards the future (1988: 52).

    In examining how one involuntarily remembers a certain event in ones life through music, it

    is interesting to establish a certain process by which memory is accessed. Deleuze gives us

    just such a thing. This is a clearly philosophical process, that is not so much (related to) an

    organic one, although there are some similarities (for one, Deleuze mentions the brain,

    seemingly as a physical organ, in his explanation). According to Deleuze, the process of a

    memory being recalled consists of five steps of subjectivity. He has called these steps as

    follows (1988: 52-53). The first is named need-subjectivity, or the moment of negation. This is

    essentially the moment in which something about an object (in our case the music, for

    example a particular song) draws the attention of the subject (the listener). The second step is

    brain-subjectivity, or the moment of interval or of indetermination. This step is related quite

    closely to the physical organ to which its name refers, in that it is the step where the brain

    offers several possible actions that the subject might take in response to the occurrence of the

    object. The third step is affection-subjectivity, or the moment of pain. There is a certain

    uncertainty on the part of the authors here. Deleuze explains affection as the price paid by

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    23/37

    20

    the brain or by conscious perception (1988: 53). However, our interpretation of the step in

    the entire process also encompasses other feelings, such as pleasure or grief. In our view

    then, this step acts as the moment of recognition, a certain aha-erlebnis where there is a sense

    of familiarity with the object, although it is not necessarily fully defined precisely what is

    familiar. The fourth step is recollection-subjectivity, which can be explained as the moment

    where the connection to (a) memory that the object induces is discovered by the subject. In

    other words, this is the step where the listener suddenly remembers that one summer night,

    that time spent in high school as a kid, or their first kiss. Finally, the fifth step is contraction-

    subjectivity. This final step completes the experience of the memory, in that the memory is

    experienced in its fullest sense. Deleuze describes it as bringing about a contraction of the

    experienced excitations from which quality is born (1988: 53).

    He goes on to divide these five steps into two categories, namely matter and memory. The

    first two steps, need-subjectivity and brain-subjectivity, pertain to the object (matter). In our

    case of studying musical memory, this means that need-subjectivity and brain-subjectivity

    are instigated by the music, then proceed to trigger something within the listener. The last

    two steps, recollection-subjectivity and contraction-subjectivity, are triggered within the

    subject (the memory of) the listener itself. The third step, affection-subjectivity, is the

    connection between the two areas, described by Deleuze as not yet the presence of a pure

    subjectivity that would be opposed to pure objectivity, [but] rather the impurity that

    disturbs the latter (1988: 53). In other words, the step of the aha-erlebnis is instigated by

    neither the music nor the listener, but rather takes place somewhere between.

    As the attentive reader will have noticed, the above suggests a subject/object dichotomy. In

    looking for an answer to the question what is music?, such a dichotomy has long been

    abandoned. That is to say, looking at music as the object and the listener as subject is a rather

    old fashioned and simple method. It should be noted though, that the dichotomy in thedescription above is originally made with reference to memory, not music. Hence we feel we

    must add that when speaking of the object of music, we do so fully aware of the

    awkwardness of such a definition, yet find it applicable in this particular study of mnemonic

    activity.

    One question that were prone to ask when dealing with memory, is where is it stored?

    Where in the subject can we find these memories that are triggered into experience whenever

    we hear a song that takes us back to them? It is tempting here to think of the mind of the

    listener as a kind of reservoir or library of memories, and of music as a trigger, like a

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    24/37

    21

    librarian taking out a certain book or a selective bucket taking a specific water sample of the

    reservoir. However, Deleuze argues that thinking of memories being contained in such a

    place, like the brain for example, is absurd. Rather, he states that recollection [] is preserved

    in itself (1988: 54, emphasis in original). This is a somewhat complex notion that requires

    elaboration. Deleuze does so by first acknowledging that there is a difference between past

    and present. The obvious way to think of this would be that the present is now and the past

    is gone. However, Deleuze more or less turns this conception around. He states:

    We have great difficulty in understanding a survival of the past in itself because we believe

    that the past is no longer, that it has ceased to be. [] Nevertheless, the present is not[] but

    it acts. Its proper element is not being but the active or the useful. The past, on the other hand,

    has ceased to act or be useful. But it has not ceased to be. [] At the limit, the ordinary

    determinations are reversed: of the present, we must say at every instant that it was, and of

    the past, that it is, that it is eternally, for all time. (1988: 55)

    He adds to this that the past is an entity on its own it exists outside of any individuals, as a

    past in general. There are two things to be noted here. First that this past has not passed, but

    is always. We need to step away here from the meaning we are accustomed to give to the

    word past as something that has occurred before the present but occurs no longer. Rather,

    the past is always coexistent with the present. The two always occur together, rather than

    following each other, like a present becoming past the moment it has ceased being present.

    Deleuze describes it as such:

    It is in this sense that there is a pure past, a kind of past in general: The past does not follow

    the present, but on the contrary, is presupposed by it as the pure condition without which it

    would not pass. In other words, each present goes back to itself as past. (1988: 59)

    If we momentarily recall DeNora here, we can see now why music aids not only inremembering who one is, but also in ones construction. As a remembering of the past has

    little to do with going back in time, this act of remembering, through music, at the same time

    constructs a certain present into the past.

    Second, and following from the first notion, the act of recollection exists in stepping into this

    being of the past, which exists outside of oneself, and looking for a memory. This leap into

    the ontology of the past, as Deleuze explains this act, consists of firstly placing ourselves

    into thepast in general, then into a certain region of the past (Bergson in Deleuze, 1988:

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    25/37

    22

    61). These regions are not separate collections of memories but rather always contain all of

    the past, just in different levels of contraction. Finding a memory then, is something like the

    focussing of a camera. [...] Little by little it comes into view like a condensing cloud; from the

    virtual state it passes into the actual.... (1988: 56).

    It is this actualizing of a memory that at the same time allows for the remembering, the

    reliving of the original experience, and adds to the memory, constructing a new present that

    is immediately added to the past. Deleuze states elsewhere that memory is not an actual

    image which forms after the object has been perceived, but a virtual image coexisting with

    the actual perception of the object (Deleuze : 150). Memories then, when not remembered

    by their owner, can be said to be virtual, only being actualized in the act of remembering and

    reliving them. Their being virtual however does not mean that memories have no existence

    prior to be remembered. They are always there, yet lack actualization. Denying memories an

    existence prior to being remembered would be confusing the virtual with the possible. An

    explanation of the difference between the possible and the virtual, is given by Pierre Lvy, in

    the introduction to his book Becoming Virtual: Reality in a Digital Age (1998). He states that the

    possible is opposite to the real, it is all that reality is, only lacking existence (Lvy 1998: 24).

    The virtual on the other hand is already real, it is very much present, but not actualized. In

    this sense it is like the description of the past we have given above, whereas a possible being

    realized is like a present becoming and going back into the past. Lvy describes the virtual as

    a kind of problematic complex, the knot of tendencies or forces that accompanies a

    situation, event, object or entity, and which invokes a process of resolution: actualization

    (1998: 24). An example from Lvys work is a seed before it sprouts into a tree.

    Accompanying the seed is the problem of the shape the eventual tree will take. The shape is

    not predetermined, but is created by the tree along the way, in combination with the

    circumstances the growing tree encounters. It should be added then, that a virtual beingactualized is always a positive process of creation, rather than a negative selection of one

    among many actuals.

    Let us compare this with musical memory. Such memory can never be a possible, which is

    predetermined by the real. If we were to give an overly simplified example of the latter, let

    us consider a set list announced by a band before a tour as a possible. This set being played

    by the band on a show in the tour is the realization of this possible. All the songs on the list

    were already there yet not realized. A memory does not function in this way. As we have

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    26/37

    23

    seen, it is constituted through different presents of remembering the memory, all adding

    their particular connotations, which are not predetermined in the memory itself, to the

    memory. Consider again the example of the song Tallulah from the introduction of this

    chapter, and the moment I heard it again at the concert. At this time, hearing the song live

    was added to the memory, which already contained the connotations of my former

    girlfriend, but this addition was in no way predetermined without realization; it was not a

    possible. Rather, it came to be through a negotiation of a problem the construction of the

    memory by the memory itself in combination with circumstances the concert at which the

    song was played.

    One author who has applied the concept of virtuality to the realm of music is William

    Echard. In an article titled Sensible Virtual Selves: Bodies, Instruments and the Becoming-

    concrete of Music (2006), he applies the concept to the relation between the body and the

    (musical) instrument. While this relation is not directly relevant to the issue at hand, his

    description of the virtual does have some merits for our case. When looking at the virtuality

    of music, he asks how the virtual can be experienced. Considering the explanation the

    workings of the virtual and the actual above, it may be tempting to say that the answer to

    this question is simply that the virtual makes itself known through an actualization, that the

    actual somehow offers a view of the virtual. Deleuze denies this however, stating that the

    virtual and actual are at all times separate. That is to say, they cannot be condensed in a

    single image (Deleuze 1994: 209).

    Echard recognizes this criticism and points to Deleuzes view that certain modes of action

    and thought can engender a sensitivity to the virtual (Echard 2006: 9). Echard discerns two

    methods one can become sensitive to the virtual. One is through multiplicity. He gives the

    example of a musical work being performed on multiple occasions. They all differ from eachother yet point to a virtual object which remains perpetually suggested (2006: 10). Again

    we can look at the example of the song Tallulah. Listening to this song in my room or

    hearing it in concert, in both cases the same memory of my ex girlfriend is referred to, and is

    experienced. In other words, these multiple and different actualizations refer to the same

    perpetually suggested virtual. The second method of achieving sensitivity to the virtual is

    through affect. Echard states: [A] musical work has an affect insofar as it actualizes certain

    capacities. Each work has a distinctive affect because it has its own unique capacities for

    affecting... (2006:10). Here we are reminded of the third step of experiencing memory from

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    27/37

    24

    the beginning of this chapter. A human being becomes sensitive to the virtual (step four and

    five) through experiencing a certain affect in a song (step one through three).

    Here then we seem to come somewhat full circle. Let us recuperate by giving a concrete

    overview of what we have established to happen when a memory is triggered by music. It

    starts with a song being played. The listener is reminded of a memory by first recognizing

    the presence of the song and getting handed several options to respond, which is done by

    the song as object. The affective link is made between the song and the listener. Feeling that

    there is something about the song, the listener as subject recalls exactly what it is, and then

    remembers and relives the memory to the full extent. Zooming in on these last two steps, we

    have determined that the act of recollection consists of stepping into a (the?) past that is both

    a general past and is in the now. We have defined this recollection as a virtual (the memory)

    being actualized into a present, namely the moment of the song. This present fades back into

    the past, which we have translated as the memory being added to. Thus we hope to have

    given a somewhat clear picture of the process of remembering that occurs when a listener is

    exposed involuntarily to a song that is related to an event in his memory.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    28/37

    25

    4. Technogical Nostalgia

    We have initiated a differentiation between voluntary and involuntary auditory memory in

    the first chapter, based on the one hand on the work of Weber, who described sound

    souvenirs as a way of storing and taking along ones memories, to be voluntarily retrieved at

    any time. On the other hand, De Vries and Van Elferen gave the example of Marcel Proust

    who was involuntarily struck by the memory of his grandmother after dipping a madeleine

    in his tea and taking a bite. Having now looked at two aspects of the experience of memory

    that is the organizing of memory in archives and the way in which memory is set in motion

    one question that comes to mind after these analyses is whether a distinction between

    involuntary and voluntary memory is at all relevant.

    After reconsidering voluntary and involuntary memory, the distinction is somewhat void.

    That is not to say that it doesnt exist, rather that it is of less importance when considering

    the process of recollection. Let us imagine again the examples that we have offered before, at

    the start of the second and third chapter. First the example of chapter two in which a

    memory, at first evoked by an accidental song on the radio, gained extra meaning because

    the person hearing it linked it to an occasion that happened just that day, namely the passing

    away of her first grandfather. After the death of her second grandfather, she started playing

    this song and the connotation that was stuck to it, because of the first happening, changed to

    a new memory. The second pertained to a lost love. The person first heard the song at the

    moment he met his future girlfriend. Upon hearing it again in concert, after they had broken

    up, he was reminded of all sorts of things about the girl and the relationship.

    Consider what happens when the two persons hear their songs in present day. Both will

    undoubtedly be reminded of their respective memories. Let us consider where the difference

    is located. It doesnt lie in the outcome, which is the same for both examples. You hear a song

    and are taken back to the event in the past the passing away of the grandfathers and the

    ending of a relationship. We could, like we have suggested at the start of the paper,

    differentiate here between these memories being voluntarily and involuntarily evoked. In the

    first case, this means that whenever we feel like thinking of the past, be it the grandfathers or

    the former girlfriend, we would only have to put up the corresponding song to be taken back

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    29/37

    26

    to that moment. In the latter case, we would be taken back to that moment by the respective

    song incidentally being played on the radio, outside of our control.

    In the end however, these differences may be of less importance when considering the actual

    process of remembering. The effect of being taken back, the process of recollection, is

    arguably exactly the same, with perhaps a difference in severity: We hear the music, we think

    of the event. The distinction between voluntary and involuntary is ultimately one of

    instigation. Proust dipped his madeleine cookie into his tea and was incidentally reminded

    of his grandmother. After this moment, he can always dip his cookie in the tea whenever he

    wants to be reminded of his grandmother, thus voluntarily instigating the same memory that

    De Vries and Van Elferen labelled as involuntary. Likewise, if the owners of sound souvenirs

    in Webers example were to incidentally hear whatever song on a radio somewhere, rather

    than purposefully hear it on the portable audio device they carried, the effect of

    remembering would be the same.

    The preliminary conclusion then, is that there may indeed be a difference in voluntary and

    involuntary recollection through music, but that the question remains whether this

    difference is at all relevant in the bigger picture. Outside of the acknowledgement that this

    difference is there, what does it really matter if the access to the memory was voluntary or

    not, when what we should really be looking at is the experience of the memory itself,

    through the music?

    Let us now take the two approaches of nostalgia that we have used so far, and place them in

    a frame of new music media and digital technologies. With the rise of these new

    technologies, we can say that new possibilities to experience such nostalgia are emerging. We

    have already mentioned De Certeau in the second chapter. When considering his analysis of

    street names in cities, he writes how such names lose over time their original meaning and

    connotations are added by all those who pass through these streets:

    Disposed in constellations that hierarchize and semantically order the surface of the city,

    operating chronological arrangements and historical justifications, these words (Borrgo,

    Botzaris, Bougainville...) slowly lose, like worn coins, the value engraved on them, but their

    ability to signify outlives its first definition. [T]hese names make themselves available to the

    diverse meanings given them by passers-by (De Certeau 1984: 132).

    We can imagine the role of a portable MP3 player in expanding meanings given to (urban)

    landscapes. A user walking through the city wearing headphones will be given a decisively

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    30/37

    27

    different view if view is the correct word when adding audio to the mix of the experience

    of his surroundings than without being plugged into his portable audio device. An entirely

    different set of impulses can be imagined while on the move when listening to music. These

    impulses may affect the memories an individual constructs around these locations that he

    visits.

    This kind of an outsourcing of memory experience construction, maintenance, and

    recollection is one of the merits of the development of new technologies. One philosopher

    who has explored the notion of memory expanded into technology is Bernard Stiegler,

    whose best known work on the subject is Technics and Time, 1: The Fault of Epimetheus (1998).

    In a recent interview, Stiegler gave the example of a wave-power generating factory on the

    north-west coast of France. This device was conceptualised by Simondon as the first time amachine was built that directly employed its environment to perform a specific function in

    just being itself, in this case the natural flow of waves generating electrical power (1989).

    Stiegler suggests that a similar conceptualization is possible when speaking of humans and

    technology. He states that:

    we had developed this idea of a human techno-geographical milieu, according to which it

    would no longer be sea water that informed the process. Instead the issue becomes that of the

    participation of human geography in the process of associated technical milieux (Venn et al.2007: 334-335).

    A participation of human geography would in our case be the memory that is being

    constructed and experienced through the associated technical milieu, the emerging

    technologies of portable audio devices. These devices allow for more and more ways to store

    and organize memory through increased functionality, such as the creation of playlists and

    the shuffle feature. Similar to the waves of the sea in the example of Simondon, it is likely

    that we will not consciously change the way we interact with memories, but that instead, this

    process is a more or less natural one. In other words, we will not have to act differently in

    order to experience these changes.

    Stiegler expands on the idea of technology as being able to fulfil an exteriorizing role for

    memory in his book Technics and Time, 1. He states that through freeing itself from genetic

    inscription (Stiegler 1998: 169) memory pursues a process of liberation. He mentions

    examples of objects that are inscribed with memory, such as books and machines, but also

    and noticeably the madeleine and, with a look at the future, holographic memories

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    31/37

    28

    (1998: 169). Through these objects, memories can be diffused and at the same time

    reorganized and stored. Stiegler defines these objects as tertiary memory. Anything that

    allows for the recording in the broadest sense of the word of memory outside an

    individual falls under this category. The act of inscribing memory through technology into

    an object Stiegler too uses the term out-sourcing he calls grammatization (Barker,

    2009).

    Coming full circle, this grammatization is exactly what is referred to in the works that have

    form the basis of this essay. We see it with Jerome, the respondent whose story Bull used to

    point out the way in which nostalgia is evoked through the iPod. We come across it in the

    portable radios as sound souvenirs, which Weber explained were used by tourists to take

    abroad memories of home. It is also present in Prousts madeleine that De Vries and VanElferen refer to, albeit unknown to Proust at first. The idea of archiving, which can be said to

    be exactly this, grammatization, formed the core of the second chapter. Recollecting memory

    outside oneself stored in an MP3 player? was the basis of the third part. And now we

    come upon it again.

    Finally, if we look at the way technology for music listening is developing, this

    grammatization will keep increasing in presence. We already see cloud computing, which

    has been hailed as the 5thutility, next to water, electricity, gas and telephony (Buyya et al.

    2008: 599) as an emerging trend in the music industry. Services such as Spotify or Pandora,

    allow for the streaming of music from an online database, removing the need for users to put

    copies of the music files on their portable devices. Where first the physical carrier of music

    was removed through the process of digitalization, the music is now not even carried with us

    as code on a hard disk anymore, but stored somewhere out there. This is at the same time

    an increase of grammatization in the sense that there is a bigger distance between the

    listener and the locus of their memories and a decrease, as the need for storage is removed.But these services add more. Consider for instance the sharing of music through public and

    collaborative playlists. This notion carries along a host of new conditions and meanings to

    musical memory.

    We live in an age where the evocation of memories through sounds especially music

    becomes more and more acknowledged. We want to be able to recreate the music that we

    cherish, and technology plays a big part in how we can retrieve and maintain these musical

    treasures. Sound and memory are deeply intertwined, not just trough the commercially

    exploited nostalgia on oldies radio stations, but through the exchange of valued songs by

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    32/37

    29

    means of pristine recordings and cultural practices such as collecting, archiving and listening

    (Bijsterveld & Van Dijck 2009: 219). What will new technological conditions mean for our

    future musical memories?

    [W]e will only know in times to come. Perhaps (Derrida 1995: 36).

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    33/37

    30

    References

    Barker, Stephen. 2009. Transformation as an Ontological Imperative: The [Human] Future

    According to Bernard Stiegler. Transformations, Issue 17. [25-01-2011] -

    http://www.transformationsjournal.org/journal/issue_17/article_01.shtml

    Bijsterveld, Karin and Van Dijck, Jos. 2009. Sound Souvenirs: Audio Technologies, Memory and

    Cultural Practices. Ed. Karin Bijsterveld and Jos van Dijck. Amsterdam: Amsterdam

    University Press.

    Bijsterveld, Karin and Van Dijck, Jos. 2009. Introduction. Sound Souvenirs: Audio

    Technologies, Memory and Cultural Practices. Ed. Karin Bijsterveld and Jos van Dijck.

    Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Bull, Michael. 2009. The Auditory Nostalgia of iPod Culture. Sound Souvenirs: AudioTechnologies, Memory and Cultural Practices. Ed. Karin Bijsterveld and Jos van Dijck.

    Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Buyya, Rajkumar, Chee Shin Yeo, Srikumar Venugopal, James Broberg and Ivona Brandic.

    2008. Cloud computing and emerging IT platforms: Vision, hype, and reality for delivering

    computing as the 5thutility. Future Generation Computing Systems. 599-616.

    Christiansen, Steen. 2010. College 3 DMC: Digitaal Musiceren. November 30. Utrecht:

    Utrecht University.

    De Certeau, Michel. 1984. Walking in the City in The Practice of Everyday Life. University

    of California Press.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    34/37

    31

    Deleuze, Gilles. 1988. Bergsonism. New York: Zone Books.

    Deleuze, Gilles. 1994. Difference and Repetition. London: The Athlone Press.

    Deleuze, Gilles. 2002. The Actual and the Virtual. Dialogues II. Ed. Eliot Ross Albert. New

    York and Chichester: Columbia University Press. 148-152.

    DeNora, Tia. 2000. Music in Everyday Life. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University

    Press.

    DeNora, Tia. 2004. Music and Self-Identity. The Popular Music Studies Reader. Ed. Andy

    Bennett, Barry Shank and Jason Toynbee. New York: Routledge.

    Derrida, Jacques. 1989. This Strange Institution Called Literature. Acts of Literature (1991).

    Derrida, Jacques. 1995. Archive Fever: A Freudian Impression. Chicago: University of Chicago

    Press.

    Derrida, Jacques. 1994. Mal dArchive: une impression freudienne.Memory: The Question of

    Archives. London: June 5, 1994.

    Van Dijck, Jos. 2004. Mediated Memories: Personal Cultura l Memory as Object of Cultural

    Analysis. Continuum: Journal of Media & Cultural Studies 18. P. 261-277.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    35/37

    32

    Van Dijck, Jos. 2009: Remembering Songs trough Telling Stories: Pop Music as a Resource

    for Memory Sound Souvenirs: Audio Technologies, Memory and Cultural Practices. Ed. Karin

    Bijsterveld and Jos van Dijck. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Echard, William. 2006. Sensible Virtual Selves: Bodies, Instruments and the Becoming-

    concrete of Music. Contemporary Music Review. 7-16.

    Garofalo, Reebee. 2008. Rockin Out: Popular Music in the U.S.A. Boston: University of

    Massachusetts.

    Lvy, Pierre. 1998. Becoming Virtual: Reality in a Digital Age. Plenum Press.

    Magdanz, Terasa. 2001-2002. Discourses in Music: Discourses. [24-01-2011]

    http://www.discourses.ca/v3n2a5.html.

    Proust, Marcel. 1913-1927. Remembrance of Things Past. Swanns Way. New York: Vintage.

    48-51. [26-01-2011] - http://www.haverford.edu/psych/ddavis/p109g/ proust.html

    Schafer, Ramond Murray. 1977. The Tuning of the World. London: Random House Inc.

    Simondon, Gilbert. 1989. Du mode dexistence des objets techniques. Paris: Aubier. First edition:

    1958.

    Stiegler, Bernard. 1998. Technics and Time, 1: The Fault of Epimetheus. Stanford California:

    Stanford University Press.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    36/37

    33

    Venn, Couze, Roy Boyne, John Phillips and Ryan Bishop. 2007. Technics, Media, Teleology:

    Interview with Bernard Stiegler.Theory, Culture and Society. Sage Publications. 334-341.

    De Vries, Imar and Van Elferen, Isabella. 2010. The Musical Madeleine: Communication,

    Performance and Identity in Musical Ringtones. Popular Music and Society. 61-74.

    Weber, Heike. 2009. Taking Your Favourite Sound Along: Portable Audio Technologies for

    Mobile Music Listening Sound Souvenirs: Audio Technologies, Memory and Cultural Practices.

    Ed. Karin Bijsterveld and Jos van Dijck. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

  • 8/3/2019 Memory at Work - Bob Balm and Puck Van Sprang

    37/37

    Musical References

    Isley Brothers. 1974. The Highways of My Life: 3+3. T-Neck.

    Procul Harum. 1967. A Whiter Shade Of Pale: Procul Harum. Deram Records.

    Sonata Arctica. 2001. Tallulah: Silence. Tico Tico Studio. Spinefarm.