33
Chapter 4 Martial Law and Massacre: Violence and the Limit In Amritsar, 13 April 1919 was a day marked by the heat and dust char- acteristic of the Punjab at that time of the year. General Dyer, who had been in the city since 11 April, spent the morning marching round the city, reading a proclamation forbidding the residents from leaving the city or gathering in processions or assemblies. By 1:00 P.M., however, finding the weather too hot, he returned to his headquarters. Soon after, he received reports that an alternative procession during the morning was announcing a gathering at Jallianwala Bagh at 4:30 P.M. The city was observing the fourth consecutive day of Hartal or general strike, and there were funerals being held for people shot by the mili- tary on 10 April. Adding to this tension was the fact that many people had come into the city from out of town, as it was the day of the Baisakhi festival—the Hindu New Year. It is estimated that by the after- noon some twenty thousand people had assembled in the bagh, some in open defiance of General Dyer’s proclamation, but others merely in the spirit of the festival, as the bagh was adjacent to the holy Golden Temple. By 4:00 P.M. General Dyer received information that the meet- ing was being held and immediately set out with his troops and armored vehicles. 1 Jallianwala Bagh was actually not a park or garden at all, but an unused ground in the shape of an irregular rectangle about 250 yards long and 200 yards wide. Houses built with their back walls to the area had effectively enclosed it on three sides. The fourth side had a bound- ary wall of around 5 feet, with a few narrow lanes serving as exits. 2 Unable to get his armored cars through these lanes, General Dyer approached the ground on foot and stationed his troops, twenty-five on either side of him. Then without any warning he opened fire. In the 99

Martial Law and Massacre: Violence and the Limit 4 Martial Law and Massacre: Violence and the Limit In Amritsar, 13 April 1919 was a day marked by the heat and dust char-acteristic

  • Upload
    lamdan

  • View
    216

  • Download
    1

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Chapter 4

Martial Law and Massacre: Violence and the Limit

In Amritsar, 13 April 1919 was a day marked by the heat and dust char-acteristic of the Punjab at that time of the year. General Dyer, who hadbeen in the city since 11 April, spent the morning marching round thecity, reading a proclamation forbidding the residents from leaving thecity or gathering in processions or assemblies. By 1:00 P.M., however,finding the weather too hot, he returned to his headquarters. Soonafter, he received reports that an alternative procession during themorning was announcing a gathering at Jallianwala Bagh at 4:30 P.M.The city was observing the fourth consecutive day of Hartal or generalstrike, and there were funerals being held for people shot by the mili-tary on 10 April. Adding to this tension was the fact that many peoplehad come into the city from out of town, as it was the day of theBaisakhi festival—the Hindu New Year. It is estimated that by the after-noon some twenty thousand people had assembled in the bagh, somein open defiance of General Dyer’s proclamation, but others merely inthe spirit of the festival, as the bagh was adjacent to the holy GoldenTemple. By 4:00 P.M. General Dyer received information that the meet-ing was being held and immediately set out with his troops andarmored vehicles.1

Jallianwala Bagh was actually not a park or garden at all, but anunused ground in the shape of an irregular rectangle about 250 yardslong and 200 yards wide. Houses built with their back walls to the areahad effectively enclosed it on three sides. The fourth side had a bound-ary wall of around 5 feet, with a few narrow lanes serving as exits.2

Unable to get his armored cars through these lanes, General Dyerapproached the ground on foot and stationed his troops, twenty-fiveon either side of him. Then without any warning he opened fire. In the

99

panic that followed, some people lay on the ground to avoid the bulletsbut were trampled as others rushed toward the exits. As the crowdthickened around such points, General Dyer directed the fire at them.The firing lasted for ten to fifteen minutes, and a total of 1,650 roundsof ammunition were used. Only after nearly running out of ammuni-tion did General Dyer cease firing and withdraw, without determiningthe casualties or providing for any medical assistance. The official esti-mate later on was that 379 people had been killed, with thousands moreseriously injured.3

This was the infamous Jallianwala Bagh massacre, an incident thatwas neither the beginning nor the end of martial law, but that came todominate the debate around the “disturbances in the Punjab.”4 “Amrit-sar” became a signal event with the years, and one that was seen as con-tributing to the end of British rule in India, or worse, as Alfred Draper’sbook Amritsar: The Massacre That Ended the Raj suggests.5 The officialview was to stress the exceptionality of the event, to concentrate onDyer’s “bad judgement” as his alone. Winston Churchill during theCommons debate on Dyer’s actions somewhat unbelievably declared itto be “without precedent or parallel in the modern history of the BritishEmpire . . . an extraordinary event, a monstrous event, an event whichstands in singular and sinister isolation.”6

The official view, which stressed the singularity of the event, insistedthat what made it without parallel was not only the large number ofpeople killed—and in this they were right—but also the flawed logicwith which Dyer explained his actions. At the center of this charge wasa much quoted statement from the report General Dyer made to hisdivision command on 25 August 1919.

I fired and continued to fire until the crowd dispersed, and I con-sider this is the least amount of firing which would produce the nec-essary moral and widespread effect it was my duty to produce if Iwas to justify my action. If more troops had been at hand, the casu-alties would have been greater in proportion. It was no longer aquestion of merely dispersing the crowd, but one of producing a suf-ficient moral effect from a military point of view not only on thosepresent, but more especially throughout the Punjab. There could beno question of undue severity.7

100 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

It is a remarkable and revealing statement that we shall explicate atsome length later on. To the Majority of the Hunter Committee, how-ever, such an explanation represented a “mistaken conception of duty.”It may have been necessary, they argued, to fire upon the crowd to getit to disperse, “but continued firing upon that crowd cannot be justifiedbecause of the effect such firing may have upon people in otherplaces.”8 In short, much of the immediate reaction to Dyer’s violentresponse was to insist that it had gone beyond the province and pur-pose of martial law. To follow such an insistence, however, is only topush the issue back one stage, where one encounters the question,What, after all, is martial law?

In this chapter, I shall attempt to answer this question in variousways. In the first part, I examine the issue from a more historicist per-spective, tracking the origins and change in the meaning of this legalcategory, from riots in eighteenth-century Britain to nineteenth-centuryinvocations of martial law in the colonies. Later, however, I try toextrapolate the deeper relation between law and violence that martiallaw demonstrates by returning to the exemplary instance of the Amrit-sar massacre through a reading of Walter Benjamin.

The purpose of such a broad approach, particularly the comparisonof colonial martial law to responses to domestic disturbances in Britain,is twofold. First, it allows us to consider the contradictions in a colonialmartial law as examples of the problematic relation between law andviolence in Western legal theory. The problem of placing martial lawinto a contained definition—and I hope to show that this is truly a prob-lem—does not exist outside the problematic of the moment of excep-tion within a liberal-constitutional system. Second, such a comparativeapproach allows us to specify the effects of racial difference on legalconstructs. Thus, as treated here, emergency covers the general situa-tion of jurisprudential doubt that exists on a continuum from militaryaid to civil power to the more intensified manifestation of martial law.This is not to suggest that a martial law response to emergency is iden-tical to a response to a riot—indeed, many commentators on incidentsof colonial martial law charged that the situation was misunderstoodbecause it was compared to a “mere” riot—but it is to argue that theconnections must be substantiated in order that the differences andtheir ideological consequences can be specified with some accuracy.

Martial Law and Massacre 101

Thus, for example, the significance of twentieth-century justificationsfor colonial martial law that emphasize local statutes can only be real-ized if they are read as a movement away from earlier justifications byunwritten prerogative.

From Domestic Riots to Colonial Rebellions

As we approach the definition of martial law, it may be noted at the out-set that the category of martial law occupies a profoundly ambiguousplace in jurisprudential writing. It is considered to be both a properlylegal question and a marker of the law’s absence. On the one hand, thereis recognition of the inevitability of martial law in certain situations.Here it represents the force of the state at its purest, the necessary con-dition if both law and state are to survive. On the other hand, we find aninsistence on rules that determine the moment of emergency—an insis-tence that the law shall appear at its own vanishing point to determinethe rules of its own failure. Martial law, like other responses to emer-gency, simply rested not on the authorization of ordinary law but on thelegal maxim Salus populi suprema est lex (safety of the people is thesupreme law). Notice how in such a formulation martial law is the man-ifestation of both the highest law and of no law at all. But while martiallaw is based on necessity, there are rules that can govern the perceptionof what constitutes necessity, and these rules are historically variable. Itbecomes possible, thus, to approach martial law as a changing cognitivequestion. This is why the legal history of martial law matters.

Within English legal history, it is even more difficult to fix the role ofmartial law. Although the issue of military intervention in civil poli-tics—specifically the aid of the army to civil power in riots and rebel-lions—repeatedly arose from the late eighteenth century onward, thecategory of martial law was not applied to Great Britain. This shouldnot lead one to conclude, as Leon Radzinowicz does, “that the expres-sion martial law is not known to English law.”9 Rather, both militaryand martial law as names and jurisdictions derived from the old insti-tution of the Court of Constable and Marshall, itself an archaism by thelate eighteenth century. Indeed, for Holdsworth, this common geneal-ogy helped explain the persistent confusions over what differentiatedmartial law from the rules of the army.10 Within English jurisprudence,martial law could refer both to the Crown’s right to ordain articles of

102 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

war for army discipline (a prerogative wholly absorbed later by statu-tory Mutiny Acts) and to the suspension of ordinary law by a militarycommander in moments of necessity. Indeed, the notion of necessityprovides the main anchor in this entire juristic questioning. The maximof Salus populi suprema est lex is the one “unbroken sequence of author-ity from the earliest Year Books.”11 Vigorously debated under the Stu-arts and limited to wartime emergencies by the Petition of Right,12 mar-tial law as the concession of civil power to military authorities overcivilians, however, fell into domestic disuse from the Restorationonward. Yet the questions that arose upon its return in the colonies inthe mid–nineteenth century were largely familiar, similar as they wereto the earlier debates over the proper relation of military to civil powerin moments of unrest.

Despite the place of martial law in English history, and the legalaffinity between martial law and responses to domestic riots, there wasa persistent tendency in English jurisprudence to banish martial lawfrom the confines of law proper. Thus we have the Duke of Welling-ton’s famous definition of martial law as “neither more nor less thanthe will of the general who commands the army. In fact, martial lawmeans no law at all.”13 If throughout the nineteenth century the maximof Salus populi suprema est lex provided a rationale for acts of necessityand emergency, then another maxim, inter arma silent leges, explainedthe lack of a judicial or constitutional authority for those acts—explained, in other words, why in war the law was simply silent. Actsof emergency may happen, but there could be no room for a prior legalauthority to military adjudication in an ideology of a rule of law. As Imentioned in the introduction, no one is more emphatic about this thanDicey, who insisted that the British Constitution was distinguished bythe fact that it did not cover any sense of a state of siege.14 Dicey distin-guishes between two senses in which martial law is used in Englishjurisprudence: as what is “employed as a name for the common lawright of the Crown and its servants to repel force by force in the case ofan invasion, insurrection, riot or generally of any violent resistance tothe law”15 and as what is used to label the condition where military tri-bunals supersede the civil judicature.16 It is only the first definition,Dicey insists, that is acceptable to English law. The military may beresponsible for a whole area under martial law but still does not pos-sess the right to capital punishment. Citing Wolf Tone’s case (1798),

Martial Law and Massacre 103

Dicey points out that the power of execution can only rest in the civilcourts.17 Even, however, as he effectively banishes a form of martiallaw that had been used in the colonies in his own lifetime, Dicey pro-vides us with a valuable clue: in order to understand the ideologicaland jurisprudential significance of martial law, we must read it withinthe general prerogative of the Crown to resort to violence to check achallenge to its authority—read it, in other words, in connection withthe form of response to domestic riots and rebellions.

With regard to the response to domestic riots, in addition to theaccepted prerogative of the Crown to repel force by force, there existedthe common law responsibility of all to protect and prevent the prop-erty of His Majesty’s subjects from destruction. This responsibilitytraced back to the institution of the posse comitatus. Indeed, for Black-stone, the institution of the posse revealed that “our antient law, previ-ous to the modern riot act, seems pretty well to have guarded againstany violent breach of the public peace.”18 Failure to join the posse comi-tatus when required was itself an offense against the king’s prerogative.While the posse comitatus was invoked into the nineteenth century,19

increasingly the need for disciplined force and the blatant lack of neu-trality of those who came out against the rioters (in the agriculturaluprisings, for example, it was most often landlords) led to a moreexclusive utilization of the army as an aid to civil power.20 The specificlegal questions that arose out of such interventions are remarkably sim-ilar to those later on concerning the conduct of authorities under mar-tial law: essentially such questions came down to the correct amount offorce that could and should be employed in moments of unrest. InEngland, trying to determine this quantum produced some signalinstances in which magistrates and military were blamed for doing toolittle or too much.

The Act of 1 Geo. I, c. 5, commonly known as the Riot Act, was theofficial and statutory response to unlawful assemblies.21 But as Brack-ley Kennet, the Lord Mayor of London during the Gordon riots of 1781,discovered, its particular provisions and requirements were far fromclear. In Rex v. Kennet, Lord Mansfield stated that a failure such as Ken-net’s to read the Riot Act and to call out the military, no matter howpure the intention to shield innocent people from accidental death, wasprima facie a criminal neglect of duty. Moreover, the hour window pro-vided for in the act did not prevent the instant use of force if so

104 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

required.22 How much force would be appropriate, however, was leftan open and vexing question. Half a century later, the courts attemptedto formulate an answer in the case against another magistrate, CharlesPinney, the mayor of Bristol during the riots of 1831. In Rex v. Pinney,Justice Littledale set down a chilling exactitude as the correct response:

Now a person, whether a magistrate, or peace officer, who has theduty of suppressing a riot, is placed in a very difficult situation, forif, by his acts, he causes death, he is liable to be indicted for murderor manslaughter, and if he does not act, he is liable to an indictmenton an information for neglect; he is, therefore, bound to hit the preciseline of his duty.23

This call for a precision of force was to be repeated and used as a stan-dard not only in the instances of other riots but also as the extant law inthe infamous case of Governor Eyre and martial law in Jamaica.24

The military, in fact, fared no better than the magistrates, caughtbetween protecting the state’s interest through the use of violence, onthe one hand, and protecting the state’s legitimacy and legality by notusing too much force, on the other. In 1812, Lord Mansfield ruled thatthe soldier during a moment of unrest was legally no different than anordinary citizen, subject to no special exemption.25 The soldier was,however, subject to court-martial for disobeying orders. Nonetheless, itremained a tacit assumption in English law that an order if illegal wasno defense later on. No one objected to this situation more vehementlythan Sir Charles Napier, who insisted that it in effect left the soldierthinking “shall I be shot for forbearance by a Court-Martial, or hangedfor over-zeal by a jury.”26 For Napier, part of the problem lay in the easewith which magistrates called out the army and then refused to letthem take action. Somewhat excitedly, he suggested that the army onlybe called out when firing had become inevitable and not for a relativelyminor unrest. “I would rather,” he declared in an interesting momentthe significance of which will emerge later, “see a few mischevious menmake a slight breach in the law . . . than myself break the law to piecesby firing on the people.”27 He charged the ministers with leaving thingsundefined so as to have an officer to “sacrifice” should circumstancesrequire it.28

It had been hoped that Sir Robert Peel’s 1829 bill to establish a met-

Martial Law and Massacre 105

ropolitan police would eventually relieve the army from intervening incivil disorders. As the nineteenth century drew to a close, however, thearmy was called in to aid the civil authorities in Yorkshire in 1893,where riots in the coalfields “revealed that substantial disorders couldstill exhaust the resources of the police with alarming speed [and] thatthe dependence of the authorities on the army had diminished but hadnot disappeared.”29 Constitutional theory as a discourse was muchslower to respond to these instances than the army, which speedilyanswered further “invitations” from the civil authorities in Belfast in1907 and Dublin in 1914. Throughout these instances, the notion thatthe military had to “hit the precise line” between too little and too muchforce proved to be less than handy in the exigencies of the moment. AParliamentary Select Committee was constituted after Belfast in 1908 inorder to create some ground rules for future situations. Only then wasit fully realized that in terms of legal theory, tabulating the conditionsof emergency intervention was an even more anxious task. In ananswer particularly telling for later discussions of martial law, RichardHaldane, the Liberal secretary of state for war, insisted that “the judgeshave laid down, over and over again, that a man is on the verge of twoprecipices, and has to get along, and he does get along.” When asked ifit was possible to draw up specific regulations that would prevent thesoldier from falling, Haldane replied, “If you do you will make the lawgo over the precipices.”30

It is this anxiety, this notion that a state of emergency not onlyrequires a special law but threatens something fundamental about lawin general that we must try to explicate. Even though there is a differ-ence between a colonial martial law and responses to domestic unrest,as the former suspends the entire operation of ordinary law in a giventerritory while the latter still works within ordinary law (although itmust be noted that even this difference was not agreed upon), the legalmode is quite similar.31 In both cases a state of necessity is the initialjustification, a post facto indemnification is often the result, and animpossible demand for a precision of force regulates the authority. Thisis, of course, why judges attempting to determine an abuse of authorityunder a colonial martial law could turn to domestic cases followingriots as a legal guide. But beyond these specific connections, theresponses to domestic unrest and martial law show a commonality intheir discursive revelation of the law’s ambivalent relation to vio-

106 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

lence—both the specific act of violence and the general effect producedby it.

Because a given act of violence contains no integral differencewhether executed by those under legal authority or by those set againstit, the law in resorting to violence, a material act of killing, produces anintensified need for the external signature of legality in order to distin-guish the two. Indeed, it is this identity between the force within lawand that without that produces a situation whereby the greater theneed for an immediate use of force outside the ordinary protocols oflegal procedure, the greater the need for that very regulative proce-dure. The effect of a generalized situation of violence thus becomes athreat not to this or that property or individual right but to the lawitself. As Walter Benjamin once noted, the law’s fear of such violence isdifferent from its fear of crime. Crime is a transgression against the lawthat may be checked by it. A more general unrest threatens not so muchto transgress the law as to set up an alternative logic and authority toit.32 I will later return to this issue of generalized violence and emer-gency, but here should point out that such a perception is not limited toa more abstract level of theorizing. Here is Lord C. J. Tindal during theBristol charge:

Each individual breach of the law, tends to counteract and destroythis its primary use and object, yet do general risings and tumul-tuous meetings of the people in a more especial manner produce thiseffect, not only removing all security, both from the persons andproperty of men, but for the time putting down the law itself, anddaring to usurp its place.33

Thus, in the British case martial law must not be seen as an issue onlyin colonial territories, nor as one that did not disturb the liberalarrangements of the metropole. While it is true that martial law wasproclaimed only in colonial areas, its source remained the common lawof England. And it is not entirely axiomatic that the jurisprudential ret-icence surrounding emergency had to do with the English social andpolitical animus toward state power. In any case, recent scholarship hasshown that that animus may have been seriously misunderstood byhistorians.34 While Charles Townshend, whose comprehensive workon civil emergency provides much of the historiography on the subject,

Martial Law and Massacre 107

is correct in noticing that “in Britain . . . unlike the German Notrecht,the claim of necessity has always had to struggle to be accepted,” hemay be too hasty in ascribing the motive for that to resistance toward alarge state.35 As John Brewer has argued, the hesitation over wide exec-utive powers produced an ideology of legitimacy that in fact produceda “military-fiscal juggernaut” of a state. Additionally, the claim ofnecessity and the legal condition of emergency itself prove historicallyvariable, and it is an attention to this variability that may loosen theunchanging postures of state.

In the colonies martial law was frequently resorted to throughoutthe nineteenth century: Barbados in 1805 and 1816; Demerera in 1823;Jamaica in 1831–32 and 1865; Canada in 1837–38; Ceylon in 1817 and1848; Cephalonia in 1848; Cape of Good Hope in 1834 and 1849–51; andthe Island of St. Vincent in 1863.36 All of these instances, particularlythose of Demerera in 1823, Ceylon in 1848, and Jamaica in 1865, pro-duced debate, controversy, and an effort at justification. Thus we findno shortage of documentary material with which to answer our ques-tion of what is martial law. The approach by which such an answermay be achieved, however, is more problematic. As we have alreadynoted with regard to domestic unrest, the logic of necessity is deeplyembedded in the rhetorical structure of a liberal-constitutional system’sresponse to emergency. This axiomatic condition is so massive that toquestion martial law frontally, to ask directly why it is needed, is toproduce tautologies. Martial law, after all, is the last resort when allorder has broken down. Under the imminent threat of collapse andchaos, the normative structure of the constitution is obviously sus-pended. Indeed, this rhetorical armor is what has precisely precluded aproper critique of martial law, for its origins are always already as con-tingent as they are axiomatic. The English constitutional authoritybefore Dicey, Henry Hallam, conceded as much and was quoted byEyre’s supporters in the Jamaica case: “there may indeed be times ofpressing danger, when the conservation of all demands the sacrifice ofthe legal rights of a few.”37

To discover the full significance of martial law, then, we have to fol-low through on the question asked of it in English constitutional theoryitself: When is the moment of necessity? More useful for disclosing theambivalent connections between law, violence, and the state, in short,for disclosing the constitutive conditions of legality itself, is to ask,

108 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

Where does martial law come from? When does it become necessary,and what does it hope to achieve? We can clarify this question furtherby noting two separate but related issues that will map our inquiry.First, the legal issue relates to the introduction of martial law andinvolves the changing rules for defining “necessity,” the move betweenjustifications by prerogative or statute, the relation between coloniallegislatures and the imperial Parliament, and so on. Second, there iswhat may be called the cognitive-political issue, which involves gen-eral questions of the law’s relation to violence, and the object of martiallaw and its use of force.

Indeed, the rhetorical structure of martial law begins to crumble themoment one asks for some exactness to the description of “pressingdanger.” The category “necessity” is itself a temporal condition. That is,it must be represented as an interruption in the otherwise smooth func-tioning of lawful politics. Only its minute by minute narrative, itsalways so closely anticipated ending, can make legitimate the exerciseof violence. Thus Lord Brougham during the Demerera debate in 1823severely qualified the explanation of necessity: “It would be the worstof all conceivable grievances—it would be a calamity unspeakable—ifthe whole law and constitution of England were suspended one hourlonger than the most imperious necessity demanded.”38 And Sir JamesMackintosh, in that same debate, somewhat unwittingly revealed theideological stakes involved in such a calamity: “if it survives the neces-sity on which alone it rests for a single minute, it becomes a mere exer-cise of lawless violence.”39 What keeps the line between very similaracts of violence intact here is a correct cognition of necessity. And it isthe particular burden placed on this category of necessity that allows usto make a specific distinction between the domestic situation and thecolonies. In those colonies where a social situation of racial differenceexisted, the legal definition of necessity would prove more varied andvexing. Here the ideological stakes in emergency would be moreexplicit. This was the singular lesson of the controversy over GovernorEyre and the events in Morant Bay, Jamaica, in 1865. The narrative ofthose events and their aftereffects in England is by now familiar andsomewhat settled.40 We may briefly reconstruct the story, highlightingthe legal issues.

Prior to October 1865, the situation in Jamaica had been tense, withincreasing disputes between blacks and whites over rent. The situation

Martial Law and Massacre 109

was at least partly exacerbated by the revolutionary promptings of PaulBogle, a black landowner in St. Thomas in the east, and George WilliamGordon, a prominent mulatto, and a member of the Jamaica House ofAssembly. On 12 October a protest outside the courthouse in MorantBay turned violent, and a number of people were killed. GovernorEyre, himself suspicious of black intentions, and responding to whitefears of a black conspiracy to expel all whites from the island, sum-moned the Council of War to declare martial law.41 By the provisions ofa recent local act (9 Vict., c. 35), martial law could only be declared “bythe opinion and advice of a Council of War, as aforesaid; and at the endof thirty days from the time of such Martial Law being declared, it shallipso facto determine.”42 The governor together with the Council of Warproclaimed martial law on 13 October for all of the county of Surreyexcept Kingston. Martial law remained in force for its full statutorylimit, and the reprisals against the resisters seem to have beenextremely violent: even by the official account of the Royal Commis-sion appointed to investigate in January 1866, 439 people were put todeath, either by being shot on the spot or hanged after court-martial,600 men and women were publicly flogged, and over 1,000 cottageswere burned down.43

As news of these punishments started reaching London, an immensecontroversy erupted. In December 1865, the Jamaica Committee wasformed by a number of prominent public figures, including John StuartMill, Charles Buxton, John Bright, Charles Darwin, and Thomas Hux-ley, in order to pressure the government to inquire into the reports.Ultimately, however, the committee focused its efforts not on the gen-eral incidents of troop atrocities, but on the specific issue of the execu-tion of Gordon. In a meeting of the committee in July 1866, John StuartMill declared that “the objects of this committee are simply to ascertainwhether there exists in this country any means for making a Britishfunctionary responsible for blood unlawfully shed, and whether thatbe murder or not.”44 In response, by August 1866 an Eyre DefenseCommittee was formed, with Carlyle, Ruskin, Dickens, and Tennysonamong others as members.

The legality of the proceedings against Gordon, even by the looserstandards of emergency rule, certainly seems to have been suspect.While Gordon had been responsible for a number of inflammatorystatements prior to the outbreak, he was not in Morant Bay when the

110 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

violence started but was staying in Kingston, a town exempted fromthe jurisdiction of martial law. Eyre, however, arrested Gordon on 17October and brought him over to Morant Bay for a trial under a mili-tary tribunal. Accordingly, on 21 October, Brigadier Nelson puttogether a tribunal of some very junior officers with Lieutenant Brandas its president, and the tribunal found Gordon guilty and sentencedhim to death.45 The proceeding, however, violated a number of basicjudicial rules. Nelson had put together two charges against Gordon onthe basis of some documents and affidavits: high treason and complic-ity with certain rebels. Capital punishment for an action in which therewas no direct involvement, and based on circumstantial evidence atbest, may have been excessive. Even more problematic was the fact thatGordon was forcibly brought into the jurisdiction of martial law. Onthe morning of 23 October, however, Gordon was executed.

Such an outcome was a substantial circumvention of a procedurallegality. More important, it could not even be squared with an Englishdoctrine of necessity. Gordon was not an insurgent, imminentlyinvolved in violence against the state at the moment of his execution.The justification for martial law that rested on the assertion that rebelsessentially became soldiers and thus forfeited the claim to a civil legalresponse thus could not immediately be applied in this case. EvenGeoffrey Dutton, in his pro-Eyre account, is forced to concede that Gor-don was “morally guilty and legally innocent.”46 What would then beneeded, as I indicated earlier, was an altogether different conceptual-ization of necessity, one that highlighted the social situation of a colonywith a racially distinct conquering class. Such a conceptualization,however, was not without ideological consequences. Specifically, itwould create a split between the legal identity of the metropole and thecolony. As we have already seen, English colonialism had long recog-nized that it could not bring English law wholesale to the colonies, thatit would have to recognize cultural and social differences. It had, how-ever, hoped to resolve these differences by positing an essential legalidentity between metropole and colony at the constitutional level, par-ticularly through the assertion of a single form of procedure and guar-antee. Emergency, however, made sociological differences intervene inthis legal-constitutional identity.

We can explicate this argument by reading the trials in England thatfollowed the incident of martial law in Jamaica. Two separate efforts

Martial Law and Massacre 111

were made to indict those involved in the Gordon case in front of agrand jury, both of which were unsuccessful: the first against BrigadierNelson and the president of the court-martial that tried Gordon, Lieu-tenant Brand, in 1867; and the second against Eyre himself in 1868. Inboth cases the judges—Lord C. J. Cockburn in the case against Nelsonand Brand, and Justice Blackburn in the Eyre case—had to determinethe law as it applied to the issue of martial law in order to give instruc-tions to the jury, which led to a rare and public disagreement betweentwo of England’s most prominent jurists.

Regina vs. Nelson and Brand came up before Sir Alexander Cockburn,Lord Chief Justice, at the Old Bailey in 1867.47 Cockburn, who tookmore than six hours to persuade the jury to find a bill against the two,rejected the argument that martial law meant no more than the will ofits administrators responding to necessity. No such force, he argued,resided in any servant of the Crown since the Petition of Right, andsuch force was deeply inimical to all declared law. Cockburn began hischarge by reiterating the circumstances of the outbreak of violence.These, he suggested, warranted emergency action. What was unwar-ranted, according to him, was the prolonged continuation of martiallaw, when in fact the rebellion had immediately collapsed upon thearrival of troops. Since Jamaica was a settled and not a conqueredcolony, which meant that English common law had been brought to itby the settlers, the standard of emergency would have to be that of En-glish common law: the only authorized force, thus, would be againstinsurgents in the act of imminent violence. The continuation of martiallaw and the execution of Gordon after such violence had been sup-pressed would, according to Cockburn, presumably be illegal.

For Finlason, a contemporary jurist, absolutely prolific in his cover-age of the Jamaica case and in his support for Eyre,48 the charge of theLord Chief Justice entirely missed the crucial racial dimension of thesituation. The fact that the ratio of the black population to the whiteswas 450,000 to 13,000, and that the whites feared a planned conspiracyto expel or kill them, meant for Finlason that the response to the rebel-lion had to look beyond the imminent violence.49 The Lord Chief Justicehad, according to Finlason, made the mistake “that he looked only tothe outbreak, and forgot the rebellion of which it was the outbreak. Inother words, he was thinking of a riot or a casual revolt.”50 This is aninteresting twist on the connection we have already noted between the

112 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

legal understanding of responses to domestic riots and colonial martiallaw. Finlason’s argument consists of denying that connection, of insist-ing that a common law understanding of necessity could not bestretched to cover the actual necessity of a colonial emergency. And ateach step of his argument, it is race that undermines the legal identitybetween metropole and colony.

The English common law as it existed in Jamaica, according to Finla-son, was meant for English-born subjects and their descendents and notfor Africans. Sir Alexander Cockburn had thus “fallen into” the fallacyof the counsel for the prosecution, in presuming “that because the com-mon law was carried to Jamaica by the English settlers as theirbirthright, therefore it precluded martial law against the Africans,except when allowed by the common law here.”51 For Finlason, whathad resulted in Jamaica was not the common law version of emergencyat all, but a true martial law responding to a different standard of neces-sity.52 To object to a deterrent measure, such as the summary executionof Gordon, beyond the incidence of immediate violence, was to pre-sume “not only legal, but actual and social identity between this coun-try and the colony.”53 Finlason’s criticism of the chief justice’s chargeends then with an explanation of dizzying circularity:

He utterly failed to realise the danger of the rebellion, and thereforehe of course failed to recognise the necessity for deterrent measures,of which the necessity could only be recognised by realising the dan-ger, and without realising which severities would easily appear tohave been cruelties.54

Martial law appears here as a deeply cognitive problem. We can nowrecognize the anxiety over the slippage between the same act of vio-lence as it can appear within the authority of the law and opposed to it,so that an excessive cruelty can easily be mistaken for a warrantedseverity. Necessity is the legal category of a correct cognition—nothingnew there—but what Finlason discloses with a startling simplicity isthat, unlike some other legal rules, necessity cannot avoid the explicitrecognition of the sociological, and in this case of the racial. What Fin-lason discloses, in other words, is the fact that the authority for martiallaw would have to be found not in the self-regulating discourses oflegality but in the unspoken and violent origin of the state.

Martial Law and Massacre 113

For colonial ideology, however, to concede to Finlason’s assertionwould be to posit a separate legal standard for segments of the popula-tion that were, after all, “Her Majesty’s Subjects.” To insist, as Finlasonhad done, that the English common law standard of necessity was onlyapplicable to English subjects and their descendents, but not toAfricans, was to raise the logical extension of that assertion: that mar-tial law of the Jamaican variety could be applied to Ireland. This con-nection was not lost on Irish liberals in Parliament, whose objection toit even Finlason had to notice:

As an Irishman, he [Major O’Reilly] said the subject had a vital andthrilling interest. It touched him and his countrymen more than ittouched England and Englishmen. To them it was a vague traditionof the past; but to Irishmen, almost within the memory of living men,it had been a bloody and cruel reality, and even within his lifetime ithad been clamoured for by those who ought to have known better.55

Like the earlier questions of an absolute sovereignty for the colonies,martial law could not be exclusively situated in the colonial realm; itsideological consequences would inevitably return to Britain itself.

The juries refused to find a “true bill” in both proceedings. For JohnStuart Mill, “it was clear that to bring English functionaries to the bar ofa criminal court for abuses of power committed against Negroes andmulattoes was not a popular proceeding with the English middleclasses.”56 In other words, to the philosopher of liberalism, the racial-ism that a colonial emergency made explicit equally barred an effectivecheck on the authority of the state. Carlyle’s critique, on the other hand,focused on the necessarily violent underpinnings of even a liberal state.In Regina v. Nelson and Brand, Sir Alexander Cockburn had taken sixhours to read his charge to the jury. When the grand jury, however,refused to indict, Carlyle took it upon himself to explain why:

Nobody answers this remarkable Lord Chief Justice, “Lordship, ifyou were to speak for six hundred years, instead of six hours, youwould only prove the more to us that, unwritten if you will, but realand fundamental, anterior to all laws and first making written lawspossible, there must have been, and is, and will be, coeval with

114 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

Human Society, from its beginnings to its ultimate end, an actualMartial Law, of more validity than any other law whatsoever. Lord-ship, if there is no written law that three and three shall be six, doyou wonder at the Statute Book for that omission.”57

Even as he dismisses them under the inexorable logic of an originalsovereign might, Carlyle neatly catches the enduring concerns ofjurisprudence: the origin of legal authority and lawfulness, and therelated question of the cognitive conditions for distinguishing lawfulviolence, distinguishing, following Kelsen, “between the state and agang of racketeers.”58 It is this concern that animates both modernjurisprudential analysis and the more important constitutional cases inthe former British Empire. For Carlyle, the justification for martial lawmust be sought in the unspoken and violent origin of the state. In thecase of the colonies, however, where this origin is both more suddenand more specific, the ideological disclosures forced by martial law aremore dramatic.

The Eyre case then is a crucial moment in the story of how the cate-gory of martial law changes through its experiences in the colonies—asa moment in the gradual enlargement of the temporal structure of mar-tial law, of what is permissible and for how long. It was more or lesssettled after the events in Jamaica that the fear of conspiracies againstthe state was more real in the colonies than at home, and martial law assuch could be kept in force beyond the immediate acts of violence thatprovoked it in the first place. This, however, still did not mean that theauthority for martial law could be legislated in advance. Despite JusticeBlackburn’s legal opinion emphasizing the right of a colonial legisla-ture to statutorily permit martial law, the entire tenor of both Englishlaw and political policy continued to be one of discouraging the stipu-lation of an emergency condition in advance, of insisting on a case-by-case basis. This was the declared policy of the Colonial Office in a cir-cular sent to all colonial governors soon after the Eyre case.

An enactment which purports to invest the Executive Governmentwith a permanent power of suspending the ordinary law of thecolony, of removing the known safeguards of life and property, andof legalizing in advance such measures as may be deemed con-

Martial Law and Massacre 115

ducive to the establishment of order by the military officer chargedwith the suppression of disturbances, is, I need hardly say, entirelyat variance with the spirit of English law.59

Notice how in such a formulation the colonial enactment is in conflictnot with the substance of English law, which may or may not apply tothe colony, but with an English constitutional understanding of legal-ity, which is always to be applicable to the colony. Such a “spirit” of thelaw would, of course, mean that the Jamaica statute recognized by Jus-tice Blackburn would have to be ultra vires. The circular posits thelegitimacy of the empire in terms of a legality, and it posits that legalityin terms of the legal identity between metropole and colony. It instructsall colonies to submit to their local legislatures “an Act repealing somuch of the law as authorizes the proclamation of martial law.”60 Thisis not to be construed, the circular goes on to explain, as a prohibitionagainst martial law, but only as a directive that the governor cannot “berelieved from the obligation of deciding for himself.”61 If that decisioninvolved continuing martial law beyond the incidence of an imminentviolence, a post facto act of indemnity, taking into account the exigen-cies of a colonial situation, could be successfully resorted to. Thus theJamaica case emphasized the need for tying a decision of emergency tothe necessity of the moment, even as it gave greater latitude to the def-inition of that emergency.

Within English constitutional debates, however, the initial conditionthat could justify martial law was also historically variable. For a longtime, it was taken as settled doctrine that the operative rule waswhether the civil courts could actually, physically sit and convene.Only their inability to do so was to be taken as a condition of war.62 In1902, during the Boer War, however, the Judicial Committee of thePrivy Council considered the question in Marais v. General Officer Com-manding; Ex Parte D.F. Marais and found that because the theater of warhad so extended itself and the conditions of emergency had become sodiverse, this rule could no longer be upheld.63 The Lord Chancellorstated the court’s position: “The fact that for some purposes some tri-bunals had been permitted to pursue their ordinary course is not con-clusive that war was not raging.”64 Once martial law had beendeclared, the court stated, military decisions were not justiciable by theordinary courts. In addition, here we once again find an effort to disso-

116 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

ciate the emergency conditions in the colonies from instances of domes-tic unrest. Thus, the court found that it might be the case with a “mereriot” that the decision of military intervention was unduly severe andquestionable on those grounds. This, however, did not preclude thepermissibility of martial law “once let the fact of actual war be estab-lished.”65 But by removing the inability of ordinary courts to functionas a necessary precondition, the Privy Council gave more latitude to theestablishment of the “fact” of war. The case of Marais, then, continues atendency in English law from the mid–nineteenth century onward towiden the scope of the condition of necessity.

The Marais decision generated some criticism and led to a series ofarticles in the Law Quarterly Review. In placing the decision within amore general and historical context, the various authors were able toisolate some of the persistent themes constitutive of martial law. ForFrederick Pollock, martial law could not be dissociated from the consti-tutional rules of the English common law, and he doubted whetherthere was “any jurisdiction under the British flag where these rules arenot assumed to have become part of the local law.”66 This meant thatthe final authority to decide whether there had been an excess of dutyduring martial law would have to reside in the civil courts, once theywere able to function again. For Earle Richards, however, althoughsuch a proposition may be the desired form of legal functioning, thelogic of the Marais ruling seemed to suggest the opposite: that oncemartial law had been declared, the power of the civil courts to inter-vene was entirely superseded.

Indeed, if it once be admitted that the courts have no power to inter-fere at the time, it seems to us to follow that the right is gone alto-gether. To suspend the law in such circumstances is in general toannul it altogether. To refuse to interfere at any rate in the case of aprisoner condemned to death is not suspension of law but abrogation;it is not a postponement of justice but a denial of the only remedy.67

The Marais ruling thus significantly increased the scope of power avail-able to martial law. It also, in a move that Earle Richards approved of,dispensed with the “artificial rule” that functioning courts precluded aconclusion that war existed. For Earle Richards, “war is self-evident,and the fact that the courts may continue to sit cannot prevent the exis-

Martial Law and Massacre 117

tence of war.”68 Reading the case, however, it would seem that war isanything but self-evident. From the Petition of Right onward, the pur-pose of this so-called artificial rule was to prohibit an “expectancy ofdanger” as a condition of emergency itself. The Marais ruling increasedthe latitude for deciding on a condition of emergency, by allowing suchan expectancy of danger as a condition of emergency itself.

It is reasonably safe to conclude then that the English law of emer-gency as it met the condition of the colonies became less rather thanmore narrow. This movement was to create one of the conditions forthe possibility of a disaster such as the Amritsar massacre in 1919. Oneof the more exemplary cases of colonial martial law, it is to that situa-tion in the Punjab, India, in 1919, that we now turn. In doing so, wemove chronologically forward from the nineteenth century into thetwentieth century. But we must also now move analytically forward,from examining the source of martial law and the moment of its intro-duction to the question of the proper object of martial law. What is itexactly, we must ask, that martial law hopes to accomplish? On the faceof it, the answer to such a question seems obvious: martial law is theultimate force needed to restore a situation of law and order. However,just as the condition of necessity that justifies the introduction of mar-tial law turns out to be anything but straightforward, so the object ofmartial law turns out to be a problematic question, and one that revealsthe contradictions inherent in ordinary law and state power itself.

Emergency and Law’s Violence: The Amritsar Massacre

So far, I have argued in terms of a corrective logic. That is, I have triedto argue against the self-evident and unchanging postures of emer-gency by showing the historical malleability of martial law, its tempo-ral expansions, its changing cognitive conditions, in order that we maybe in a better position to evaluate the rules that apply in emergency. Butnow, I would like to shift the register of analysis and turn from a cor-rective answer to what I consider a foundational question. So I shall tryonce more to answer the question of what martial law is by focusing onwhat it does. Let me say outright that the questions of punishment andorder, while they may form a part, are not the whole of the answer here.We must not too readily presume the effectiveness of martial law asremedy to an ordinary lawlessness. Reading the documentation of

118 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

martial law, it is striking that martial law in its operations as thereplacement of civil authority is not as efficient as one would presume.Power may transfer from the lengthy procedures of civil adjudicationto military tribunals, but repeatedly we encounter the picture CharlesTownshend has drawn of officers struggling with Banning’s MilitaryLaw Made Easy. What martial law does, and does terribly well, becomesclear only if we nuance the catchall phrase “law and order,” distin-guishing issues of force and order from issues of authority. It is thereconstitution of the general authority of the state that martial law per-forms, and while this involves the exercise of violence, it is a specificform of violence.

If we are to explicate the function of violence in martial law, to expli-cate its extreme condition, we shall have to reemphasize the limit con-dition to which it responds—the inscription of racial difference. Thepresence of race must here be more than an acknowledgment of a racialanimus that would putatively explain the vigor and venom of much ofthe rhetoric. Rather, we must once again view race as the limit condi-tion within the articulation of both the liberal conditions of rule and ofpositivist legality.

There is perhaps no other text in the liberal canon where the racialdifferentiation of subjects and the criteria of forms of rule are woventogether more tightly and with more clarity than John Stuart Mill’s Con-siderations on Representative Government.69 The embryonic ideas of thistext, as Homi Bhabha reminds us, were first formulated in precisely thecontext of debate on morality and education: in response to LordMacaulay’s infamous 1835 Minute on Indian Education, with its clarioncall for the creation of “a class of persons Indian in blood and colour,but English in tastes, in opinions, in morals and in intellect.”70 Facedwith the task of convincing the reader of the ideality of the specific formof representative government, distinguished in degree and kind fromdespotism on the one hand and direct democracy on the other, Millmust specify the optimum conditions in which such a form may suc-cessfully operate. It is clearly not suitable to all: “a rude people, thoughin some degree alive to the benefit of civilized society, may be unable topractice the forbearances which it demands . . . in such a case, a civi-lized government, to be really advantageous to them, will require to bein a considerable degree despotic.”71 The virtues of order and obedi-ence are what colonial government has to offer to the natives, but Mill

Martial Law and Massacre 119

insists that “there are different degrees of obedience,” and the mostdesirable form is obedience of a general order, of “mandates issued inthe deliberate form of laws.”72 After all, Mill asks us, what is it that dis-tinguishes a slave from a savage, making the former preferable in theevolutionary scheme of ordered government? The answer is a develop-mental scale of modes of obedience: the slave is in advance of a savage,for “he has learnt to obey. But what he obeys is only a direct command.It is characteristic of born slaves to be incapable of conforming theirconduct to a rule or law.”73

This story of the stages of civilization and of the corresponding, pro-gressive scale of juridical subjects is reasonably well known, and weneed not dwell on it much longer. But what is more important to thoseinterested in reading the reflections and refractions of modern lawthrough the prism of colonial discourse is the way in which the distinc-tion that organizes Mill’s scale—the distinction between types of force, and thedistinction between command and rules—is also the initial and animatingcondition of much positivist jurisprudence. We shall now turn to that the-ory and to the work of H. L. A. Hart in particular before returning toIndia.

Hart’s theory is cast in the form of a historical Bildung: a primitivesociety may have law to the extent that it contains primary rules ofobligation, but it cannot be considered a mature legal system until ithas a secondary set of rules—rules directed not to the general populacebut to officials who determine, declare, and enforce the law. Indeed, asHart tells it, the mode of obedience (whether subjects obey the law outof a sense of fear or social conformity or moral bearing) becomes lessimportant than the development of an official legal establishment: “Thehistory of law does, however, suggest that the lack of official agenciesto determine authoritatively the fact of violation of rules is a muchmore serious defect.”74 In fact, by the end of Hart’s story, the definitionof law does entail more than notions of command and obedience, ifonly because it has jettisoned the concern over why people obey thelaw, content with the fact that they just do, and has more vested in howofficials determine with certainty the validity of a rule and its potentialviolation.

I am, however, going to dwell on the original problem that Hartbegan with: the distinction between rules and commands, and the rela-tion between obedience and authority. Certainly, Hart is successful in

120 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

trying to diffuse the force of law, to insist that the effect of rules uponthe naked power of the gunman is not so much a masking as it is medi-ation. Indeed, in its attempt to decenter the simple act of force associ-ated with the gunman, by introducing secondary rules that stipulatewho gets to make the law in the first place—“persons qualified in cer-tain ways to legislate by complying with a certain procedure”75—Hart’s text is saturated with tropes of immediacy versus mediate force,face-to-face commands versus general declarations. The maturation ofa legal system, in Hart’s Bildung, builds in distance between the sourceand object of violence. It is precisely such distance that Stanley Fishcalls our attention to in his reading of The Concept of Law. “Notice howmuch distance there is,” Fish points out, “between the source of powerand the object of its exercise. In the gunman scenario the coercion isdirect and discrete; in the world of rule the coercing agent stands at theend of a long and articulated chain, beginning with the rule itself,which mandates not an act but a procedure.”76

Legal control, Hart argues, could not be implemented through a sys-tem dependent on face-to-face commands, if only for logistical reasons:“no society,” Hart correctly points out, “could support the number ofofficials necessary to secure that every member of the society was offi-cially and separately informed of every act which he was required todo.” But what follows such a declaration is a curious sentence, seem-ingly commonsensical and cursory, but one that requires some furtherelaboration. “Instead such particularized forms of control,” Hart con-tinues, “are either exceptional or are ancillary accompaniments or rein-forcements of general forms of directions.”77 Now what remains some-what obscure is both the substantive content of these particularizedmoments and their relation, whether directly causal or otherwise, to thesmooth functioning of a generalized legality. We could accept that suchparticular moments refer to the face-to-face orders of a policeman,addressed to motorist or vagrant (examples that Hart himself offers), oreven the performative speech of a judge faced with a defendant. Itwould, however, be curious to identify Hart’s particularized formswith these mundane encounters, if only because such examples do notso much represent a “reinforcement” of the law as they do its enforce-ment in the first instance. All law, after all, has to be enforced on bod-ies—protocols of interpretation, procedures of institutions, require thebody, require its constraint and movement, signature and utterance.

Martial Law and Massacre 121

Certainly, given the tenor of some analysis of legal interpretation, it isnecessary to be reminded of law’s essential dealing with force—with itsability and desire to enforce—and it is precisely such a necessity andsuch a reminder that give the opening sentence of Robert Cover’s nowfamous essay “Violence and the Word” its puncturing effect: “Legalinterpretation takes place in a field of pain and death.”78 But surely forHart’s purposes, and indeed ours, a reminder that violence is imbri-cated in law at every level cannot be sufficient. After all, might therenot be another mode of violence, one that not only enforces a priorsanction but also, and this is Hart’s vocabulary, relates particularizedinstances to generalized forms? What would such an establishing vio-lence look like? Readers familiar with Walter Benjamin’s essay “Cri-tique of Violence” will have already noticed in my vocabulary ofenforcing and establishing violence an echo of the crucial distinctionbetween “law-preserving” and “law-founding” violence that struc-tures Benjamin’s essay.79

“Zur Kritik der Gewalt”—the original title is important here, as itpoints to the evaluative and demarcational project of Kritik, and to thedouble meaning of sanctioned force and violence that make up the Ger-man Gewalt—was first published in 1921. One of Benjamin’s moredense and difficult essays, “The Critique of Violence” combines Ben-jamin’s terse, aphoristic style with his Marxism and messianic sensibil-ity. The essay begins with a series of rigorous distinctions between pos-itive and natural law, means and ends, only to abruptly catapult us intothe apocalyptic arrival of a final and divine violence that will expiatethe “rotten” and “bloody” violence of lawmaking. This final condition,by which, as Peter Demetz points out, “the essay subverts its own fun-daments in order to enact something of the ontological ‘break’ in whichthe old world is suddenly transformed into a new,” adds to the diffi-culty of assimilating Benjamin’s insights.80 Indeed, “The Critique ofViolence” offers us no totalizing theory of violence, but at the level ofaphoristic suggestion it is invaluable.

Earlier I emphasized the tropes of distance and proximity, meansand mediation, which occupy Hart’s text, and it is now significant tonote that a topology of means and ends also animates and frustratesBenjamin’s effort. Indeed, Benjamin’s essay begins with an awarenessof the fact that the circular justifications of ends and means in naturaland positive law threaten to eclipse the object of critique: “natural law

122 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

attempts, by the justness of the ends, to ‘justify’ the means, positive lawto ‘guarantee’ the justness of the ends through the justification ofmeans.”81 The escape from such casuistry comes with Benjamin’s deci-sion to focus on positive law because its effort to render violence legiti-mate is also to render it historical. That is to say, positive law focusesprimarily on the quality of means, on their origin and authority, pre-cisely by drawing a distinction between sanctioned and unsanctionedforce (authorization), which for Benjamin is done by asking of all vio-lence the “proof of its historical origin.” “The Critique of Violence”employs the German mittel which can be translated variously as means,mediate, and mediation. Benjamin plays with the word and its deriva-tives, such as unmittelbare (unmediated but also immediate), reineunmittelbare (purely unmediated), and eine nicht mittelbare (non medi-ate), in order to designate the modalities of violence within positivelaw.82 The modes of violence are represented in the essay as a dyad:violence, Benjamin insists, is either “law-preserving” or “law-found-ing.” Violence that preserves that law is a mediated mode, in that itsimmanent application is mediated through and by a prior rule that dic-tates the form and content of the instance and that crucially makes sucha violence “subject to the restriction that it may not set itself newends.”83 This is distinct for Benjamin from that other form of violence,which seems to dispense with the question of ends as a prior stipula-tion altogether. Thus the archetype of law-founding violence is “myth-ical violence”—the representation of the anger of the gods in mythol-ogy—and its exemplary story, for Benjamin, is the legend of Niobe.Apollo and Artemis’s reaction to Niobe’s arrogance, sparing the life ofthe mother but in a whimsy of fate subjecting her children to a crueldeath, could perhaps be read on some level as a punishment, but if so itis a strange punishment, neither particularly rehabilatory nor retribu-tive in its effect. Rather, Benjamin notes, “mythical violence in its arche-typal form is a mere manifestation of the gods. Not a means to theirends, scarcely a manifestation of their will, but first of all a manifesta-tion of their existence.”84

It is these moments of law-founding violence that Benjamin locatesin the modalities of positive law. Foundational is perhaps a misleadingdescription, to the extent that it suggests the singular instance of an ori-gin. Benjamin certainly wants to retain some sense of the ideologicallabor performed by the notions of origin and foundation, but also

Martial Law and Massacre 123

wants to locate such moments in their episodic (perhaps even atavistic)repetition. Thus when he turns to the agency of enforcement—the mod-ern police—the rigor of the distinction gives way, not so much to a blur-ring as to a “spectral mixture.” The police in their discretion necessarilymix the right of disposition (to enforce a prior sanction) with right ofdecree (to insist on the instance of a need for a sanction). Thus Derridanotes that “what threatens the rigor of the distinction between the twotypes of violence is at bottom the paradox of iterability. Iterabilityrequires the origin to repeat itself originarily.”85 It is, however, this veryparadox—this understanding of a certain kind of legal violence as theepisodic repetition of the origin, or analogous to Hart’s vocabulary, asthe particular and episodic reinforcement of the general form, whichconstitutes one of Benjamin’s essay’s more profound insights.

We may return then, with Benjamin’s insights, to the question ofemergency and martial law in general, and the situation in Amritsar inparticular. Here, two related questions highlight the disjunctionbetween rules and violence. First, what is it that the law permits emer-gency measures to accomplish—what were the rules that governed itsspecial use of force? Second, what was perceived as the need for mar-tial law in the spring of 1919 in the Punjab? Let us recall and considerwith a seriousness, a deadly earnest if you will, Carlyle’s insistence onthe priority of martial law—“real and fundamental, anterior to all lawsand first making written laws possible”—and we must not miss the dou-ble sense of priority here, in terms of an importance and a temporaloriginality. Martial law seeks to effect not just the restoration of orderbut the restoration of the general authority of the state. In doing so, ittakes advantage of the absence of normative constraints on power notjust to punish more—which it may or may not do—but to punish out ofa different logic. This punishment, if we can even call it that, is notcaused by questions of innocence or guilt or a specific transgression ofthe law, nor is it particularly rehabilitory or retributive in its effect.Rather, it is a purely nonmediate form, purely performative, the pur-pose of which is the sheer manifestation of power itself. It is the form ofviolence that Walter Benjamin called “mythical violence.”86 It is in thissense, perhaps, that martial law “saves” the state, by re-creating theconditions for the possibility of its existence. Specifically how it does sowill become clearer as we return to the example of martial law in colo-nial India.

124 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

The Indian Minority Report had strongly disagreed with Dyer’sremarks. To them such an explanation echoed “Prussian tactics,” notunlike those used by German military commanders in Belgium andFrance.87 They saw General Dyer’s “moral effect” as “terror” andexplained its source thus.

People like General Dyer have the fixed idea that the effective way ofgoverning India is force. It is the same idea that General Drake-Brockman of Delhi gave expression to in his written statement atDelhi: “Force is the only thing an Asiatic has any respect for.”88

On the other hand, General Dyer was to protest against these chargesby pointing out that force was, in fact, required, and that the MajorityCommittee was placing soldiers in an impossible situation: “if theyconsider only the immediate needs of the moment, they are liable to becondemned for not looking further ahead . . . if they consider the situa-tion as a whole . . . they are liable to be told that they must not lookbeyond the dispersal of the crowd.”89 Indeed, the British governmentand the secretary of state for India, Edwin Montagu, while agreeingwith the committee that Dyer had a mistaken conception of duty, didrecognize the problem for the military to which Dyer referred. Accord-ingly, it ordered the Indian government to prepare a martial law man-ual for future use.90

I list these responses here in order to emphasize how little haschanged from the earlier instances of military intervention. For anevent that was supposedly singular, the Amritsar massacre promptedrhetorical responses that were considerably timeworn. General Dyer’sprotest against the difficult position the military were placed in duringmoments of civil unrest may as well have been taken from Sir CharlesNapier and the debate following the Bristol riots and Rex v. Pinney.91

On the other side, the Minority Report’s statement that General Dyer’smentality was of the sort that believed that a rule of force was appro-priate to India only meant that he belonged in a long tradition of Britishideology that advocated a paternalist despotism as the best mode ofBritish governance of India.

The Amritsar massacre and, indeed, martial law in the Punjab arebest understood, then, as the culmination of several intensely ambigu-ous discourses, some specific to an English political imagination’s

Martial Law and Massacre 125

negotiation between the military, state power, and a rule of law, othersthe result of that negotiation in a regime of conquest. It is thus not sur-prising that the official British response to the massacre focuses not onthe number of people who were killed or their particular guilt or inno-cence, but the reasons for their death. That is, it focuses not so much onthe substance of Dyer’s actions, but the logic with which they areexplained. Everywhere in these official documents one finds confusedanswers to a question, sometimes tacit, sometimes explicitly asked:What is the proper object of martial law? It is answered by placing themassacre and martial law in the Punjab itself in its wider political con-text.

Discussions over the object of martial law are linked to questions ofthe causes for the unrest, that is, to the reasons why martial law mayhave been needed in the first place. Although social and economic con-ditions in the Punjab, following World War I, contributed to the “dis-turbances” there—notably the influenza epidemic of 1918–19, highinflation of basic goods prices, and aggressive troop conscription in thecountryside92—the immediate catalyst for the agitation and subsequentdeclaration of martial law was, ironically enough, an emergency law.On 18 March 1919, the imperial council placed on the statute book theEmergency Powers Bill, or the so-called Rowlatt Act, after Justice Syd-ney A. T. Rowlatt, the main author of the Report of the Committeeappointed to investigate Revolutionary Conspiracies in India.93 The commit-tee had painted a picture of elaborate conspiracies in India and had rec-ommended the continuation of some wartime measures, including thesuspension of certain civil liberties. The Rowlatt Act was passed againstthe express urging of nationalist leaders, who saw it as a betrayal ofpromises made by the British during the war to extend Indian politicalparticipation. To that extent, it was seen as mitigating the effect of thealready meager political changes of the Montagu-ChelmsfordReforms.94 Gandhi denounced the act and called for a civil disobedi-ence movement to protest it on 7 April 1919. Two days later Gandhiwas forbidden to enter the Punjab and was arrested attempting to doso. By 10 April, the arrests of Drs. Satyapal and Kitchlew in Amritsarhad provoked further unrest.

The agitation against the Rowlatt Act, particularly Gandhi’s Satya-graha, is given a causal force in the Hunter Committee’s inquiry afterthe fact. On the one hand, “rumors” are blamed for producing a general

126 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

misunderstanding of the scope of the act, portraying it as increasingexecutive interference in daily life.95 On the other hand, the civil dis-obedience movement is expressly criticized, not for its opposition to theact, but for asking people to disobey the laws of the act. In India’s par-ticular state of political development, we are told, to permit disobedi-ence to one law is to invite a more general and complete disobedienceto all law.96 This was equally Lord Chelmsford’s explanation for the sit-uation in 1919. In a letter from the government of India to the secretaryof state in London, he hoped that politicians would from now onrefrain from “invoking forces which they can neither direct nor con-trol.” He went on to explain why:

when this movement (Civil Disobedience) was initiated, it wasapparently not obvious to its promoters, as it was to all thoughtfulpersons, that in India in its present state of development (whatevermay be the case in other countries) the unsettling effect of the adviceto the public in general to break selected laws was likely to lead to asituation which might involve the overthrow of all law and order.97

Lord Chelmsford’s understanding of the effects of civil disobedience inIndia is curious but significant. A developmental scale of judicial sub-jects is set up here, whereby more developed (read civilized) subjectsare able to distinguish between specific laws, which may appear tothem to be wrong for some reason, and the general authority of thestate that subtends those laws. Thus, they are able to selectively “dis-obey” a specific law without threatening the overall authority of thestate. In India, however, where the subjects are presumably unable toappreciate what John Malcolm nearly a century before had called “themore artificial systems of jurisprudence,”98 no such cognitive distinc-tion is possible. Here, Lord Chelmsford suggests, echoing once again athematic of despotism, every law is a personal and direct manifestationof the sovereign. To call for even the nonviolent disobedience of theRowlatt Act is to unleash a more general “disturbance” that threatensthe authority of the state. Thus, the real need for martial law is notmerely to put down this or that outbreak of violence but to restore thisauthority.

Although Lord Chelmsford is at pains to confine such a dynamic tocountries lower on his developmental scale, it is not that different from

Martial Law and Massacre 127

the understanding we encountered earlier of the effects of violent riotsin England. There, we may recall, the fear was that such violence didmore than disobey a single law, that it set up a logic parallel to the lawitself, daring, as C. J. Tindal put it, “to usurp its place.”99 The under-standing of the conditions that require martial law in the Punjab, then,is an intensification of such a dynamic. What is required of martial lawis a corrective to this “unsettling effect,” as Lord Chelmsford calls it—perhaps in the form of the “moral effect” that General Dyer stated to behis proper object and aim.

Once one explicates the state’s understanding of this “real” need formartial law, the logic of its violent actions becomes clearer: not the pun-ishment of the guilty, not the end to specific transgressions, but therestoration of a general condition. Moreover, it is crucial to once againremind ourselves that this general condition cannot be reduced tonotions of public peace and order. In fact, in each explanation for anaction by an officer, there is a will to generality—an order whose obe-dience will itself teach the subject about general rules. As I indicated atthe beginning of this chapter, both General Dyer’s explanation for hisactions and the official response to his explanation are saturated withthis ambivalence about specific tasks and general ends. In GeneralDyer’s statement we get an uncanny reflection of the relation betweenperformative violence and a return to legality, and the distinctionbetween such violence and mere mechanical notions of force and thepreservation of order.

The schism between the immediacy of violence and the putativeobject of its accomplishment saturates the dialogue of criticism anddefense of Dyer’s actions, making it into an uncanny reflection of therelation between a performative violence and a return to what Hartwould call “legal control”—a reflection of the gap between the mechan-ics of force and the preservation of order. As I mentioned at the start ofthis chapter, the Parliamentary Inquiry into Dyer’s actions would con-cede that the firing was crucial to the “stability” of the entire Punjabregion, but could not allow itself to concede that such “excessive force”was “justified because of the effect such firing may have upon people inother places.” General Dyer’s statement in his own defense, in fact,rather astutely picks up on this aphasic moment. Dyer insists that forthe firing to be considered excessive, one would first have to agree onits putative object, in order to determine what it is in excess of—“if I

128 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

was not confined to the bare mechanical operation of getting the crowd‘to move on’ then no evidence or ground is anywhere suggested toshow that the force I used was in the least degree excessive.” Dyer’sargument is that his actions can only be understood as excessive if theyare contained within a closed economy of transgression and punish-ment, disturbance and the restoration of order. But Dyer insists that hisobject was not specific—rather it was a specific action taken to establishrather than merely enforce a general rule. This is then General Dyer’s“moral effect throughout the Punjab,” but it is a mode not confined tohim alone. Throughout the inquiry report one finds instances of officialactions that seem to move away from specific objects to the more gen-eral object of revealing the power of the state.

The actions of Lieutenant Colonel Johnson in Lahore demonstratethis desire to reveal the power of the state. After government procla-mations posted on the walls of the Santan Dharm College were founddefaced, Lieutenant Colonel Johnson made the students and professorsmarch in the hot sun through the city and then interned them for morethan three hours in the Red Fort. When pressed by the Minority Com-mittee’s investigation, Johnson admitted that there was no evidence tosuggest that any of these people had been directly responsible for thedefacement of the posters. In fact, detection and punishment of theguilty was not the object. Rather, Johnson admitted that he was “long-ing for an opportunity to show them the power of martial law.”100

Indeed, this remark is an uncannily accurate example of Benjamin’snotion of mythical violence—of a violence that is not so much aboutmeans and ends as it is about the manifestation of power.

What the power of martial law is used for becomes apparent fromsome of the other incidents that the committee investigates. In Kasur,the committee found that Captain Doveton had resorted to “fancy pun-ishments,” designed in order to counter the effect of people chanting“Hukum kya chiz hai, hum koi hukum nahin jante—what is an order; weknow of no such thing as an order.”101 The punishments then were onlymeant to reinforce the general notion of the command itself. Indeed,this logic can become increasingly general, as is evidenced by the com-mittee’s findings in Gujranwala. There the local commander issued theinfamous “salaaming [greeting] order,” which required Indians whenthey encountered European officers to leave their conveyances andsalaam. When pressed by the committee to explain the purpose of such

Martial Law and Massacre 129

an order, the commander insisted that it was not meant to humiliateIndians, but only to reinforce a general sense of respect for authority.This sense had been breaking down, according to the commander, at alllevels of Indian society: “The tendency of the present day is to abolishrespectfulness. The Indian father will tell you that sons are not respect-ful even to their parents.”102

Obviously, these instances are different from the Amritsar massacre,as they contain a more psychic rather than physical violence. What isnot very different, however, is the mode of explanation. For these armycommanders, as much as for General Dyer, the object of martial law isthe restoration of what legal theorists like to call the “habit of obedi-ence.” It is difficult to miss the performative and very general nature ofthese instances. We are now far from the “precise line” standard setdown in Rex v. Pinney, if only because it is difficult to make a judgmentof precision on an act that seems to have no precise and immediateobject: remember, for Dyer the aim was more than dispersing thecrowd but something else; for Colonel Johnson it was more than pun-ishment for defacing the posters but something else. In fact, we areprobably closer to the Duke of Wellington’s understanding of martiallaw as not a legal but a sovereign act, not only because it was broughtforth under the Crown’s prerogative but also because, as we may recall,for Wellington martial law was the expression of a pure will. It is theexpression of this will, this sovereignty, that is required as the priorcondition before law and state resume their normal course. And thenecessity of this condition is more than just a pragmatic one. That is, itis not just a question of martial law applying to a situation where youmust expend more force than you would normally, in some total quan-tum of ergs. Rather, it seems a deeper, almost conceptual necessity.And what happens when the law returns, so to speak; when the parlia-mentary committee considers these instances in the form of their nor-mative and normalizing narrative? The Majority of the Hunter Com-mittee find themselves unable to object too much to these odd displaysof power.

After all, the question is not one of words but substance. The powerof ordinary law to preserve order lies, not in its ability to enforceitself on every subject, but in the fact that with all subjects save a few,no need of enforcement will arise. It depends upon the law-abiding

130 The Jurisprudence of Emergency

instincts of the great majority and upon the authority of the govern-ment being a received fact. In India at present ordinary methods ofgovernment depend for their possibility—not merely their effi-ciency—on the existence of this relation between people who areIndian and a Raj which is British.103

As this report suggests, something other than authority is seen asneeded to counter a breakdown in authority. What follows at this pointin the report is the by now inevitable comparison between the situationin the colony and domestic riots. The Majority Committee commendsthe Punjab government for not viewing each outbreak of unrest as anisolated riot and responding accordingly. That mode, we are told,would only suffice “upon the condition that the authority of Govern-ment in the main be respected.”104 Thus, at each point we get a sensethat martial law in the colony is a return to a prior condition, before lawand before state legitimacy. It is what is needed to construct the state allover again.

To the official mindset, however, the troubling aspect of such a for-mulation was that it placed this coercive force at the heart of law andmade such force a condition for the very possibility of law’s existence.Thus, we get the not surprising result of the Hunter Committee con-demning each of these punishments, even as it concedes their efficacy,indeed, their indispensability. The committee compulsively returns toan ambivalence, unable either to condemn or condone these actions.Critical of the form of these actions, the committee nonetheless con-cedes their indispensability. And we are left with this object of perfor-mative violence as it floats in and through the text, foundational to thelanguage and action of legal positivism that the committee employsand yet everywhere disavowed.

Martial Law and Massacre 131