64
Making sense of environmental beauty An analysis of beauty discourse in Noord-Holland Primo Reh (10314016) Master thesis Heritage and Memory Studies Written under supervision of: dhr. prof. dr. Erik de Jong mw. dr. Hanneke Ronnes dhr. ir. Rob van Leeuwen Amsterdam, juni 2017

Making sense of environmental beauty

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    2

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Making sense of environmental beauty

An analysis of beauty discourse in Noord-Holland

Primo Reh (10314016) Master thesis Heritage and Memory Studies Written under supervision of: dhr. prof. dr. Erik de Jong mw. dr. Hanneke Ronnes dhr. ir. Rob van Leeuwen Amsterdam, juni 2017

- 2 -

Table of contents

Foreword 3

1 Introduction 4

2 Beauty and preference 14

2.1 Subjectivity or objectivity? 18

2.2 The development of aesthetic preference 24

2.3 Representations of beauty 29

3 Experiencing Noord-Holland 32

3.1 The perception of landscape 36

3.2 Aesthetic appreciation 39

3.3 Towards the aesthetic experience 42

3.4 Who is to aesthetically judge? 45

3.5 Beauty discourse and the aesthetic appreciation of Noord-Holland 47

4 Concluding discussion 50

Notes 56

References 58

Appendix A 63

- 3 -

Foreword

The amount of different subjects a student encounters usually depends on the duration of study. I

have encountered many, of which this master thesis bears witness. Before one begins reading I want

to shortly describe my study path for it is explanatory for my interests and the combination of

subjects and their emphases in the chapters that follow.

Landscape and nature already had my interest when I started studying earth sciences in

Utrecht. I chose to point my focus to geology which is rather technical and thence lacked any cultural

side of study. That changed when I subsequently started studying history in Amsterdam. Especially

the disciplinary achievements after the so-called ‘cultural turn’ were held in high regard and surely

had my attention as well. The critical thinking in the tradition of Jacques Derrida’s (1930-2004)

deconstruction theory appealed to me and in particular semiotic’s bearing on the way present-day

historians approach history: social history and its generalization through processes has been long

forgotten and exchanged for the idea that every culture is completely unique in its own context.

After I acquired bachelor degrees in both earth sciences and history I enrolled in the master

program Heritage and Memory Studies which is interdisciplinary. Compared to the study of history

this field’s focus is more on the present; through the analysis of heritage inter alia situations of

contemporary conflict are encountered. Its relevance to present day societal issues is therefore more

often noticed. Critical thinking and thinking in concepts – such as discourse – are amongst the

master’s main teaching objectives, and, moreover, it aims to provide practical experience in the form

of an internship. My internship was facilitated by MOOI Noord-Holland, an organization in the sector

of environmental beauty. My time as an intern has inspired the speculative framework of this thesis.

This is the path that led me back to the subject of landscape, and, this time, with a particular way of

thinking of which this thesis is the reflection.

- 4 -

1 Introduction Two societal developments are causing conditions that could result in a completely different knowledge of environment and environmental beauty. Instead of experiencing environments in the field we become more and more accustomed to look at them through all sorts of screens – symptomatic for a dispersed image culture and constituting a possible break of beauty discourse. It is therefore the main purpose of this thesis to investigate how our sense of environmental beauty is being established, and what a different beauty discourse could imply for Dutch environmental beauty in the future.

“Na twintig jaar kwam ik in Castricum en kon ‘De rustende Jager’ eerst niet meer vinden, zoo raar stont-i er tusschen. De hoofdstraat, een blootebillen-gezicht en verder overal ‘lieve woninkjes’, God zal ze.” (In Insula Dei (1942), Nescio cited in Van Toorn, p. 51)

Polders stretching beyond the reach of the eye, Amsterdamse School architecture and its immense

influence on later architectural styles, an omnifarious coastal area that surrounds almost the entire

province – ask anyone what is beautiful about the environment of Noord-Holland and they will

probably enumerate a diverse but well-known list of characteristics. There seems to exist a discourse

of ‘beauties’ that moreover corresponds with the images we encounter in textbooks, films,

museums, and on tourist posters and postcards. That agreement incites to question what informs

and what is being informed; does culture inform our sense of environmental beauty, is it the other

way around, or is it both?

Environmental beauty is being regarded as a common phenomenon and people are

accustomed to perceive it in their immediate surroundings. A beautiful environment seems to be

almost a fixed proposition; we often forget that what we live in is carefully designed. Designed with

the spirit of the age in mind and according to its own beauty discourse. Indeed, thinking about

environmental beauty only commenced during the Renaissance; suddenly landscape began being

recognized as potentially beautiful, was therefore subject to artists, and eventually even an art form

itself (Van Toorn, 1998). Although relatively new compared to other beauties, environmental beauty

has still been contemplated – and interventions in the landscape of Noord-Holland subsequently

executed – for ages.

In what is generally believed to be beautiful, some tastes are better represented than others.

Also, for dominant taste is rigid and therefore fragile, hard breaks between two periods of taste are

not uncommon in history. During the Renaissance, for instance, Classicism was the dominant beauty

discourse. Erudite architects were loyal to the canon, repetition was the norm, and this common

culture dictated the rules that were in turn respected by the builders. Consensus was so strong that

- 5 -

ultimately stylistic unity was achieved. It was therefore rather peculiar that in 1747 an effeminate

young man, the Englishman Horace Walpole (1717-1797), began building a house in a radically

different style – the Gothic style. Against all odds it took only a few decennia for Gothicism to turn

the tables and an opposition with the discourse that supported Classicism was the result (De Botton,

2006).

Of course, both Classicism and Gothicism related to more than architecture alone; both styles

embodied a set of ideals that severely influenced the way people thought about, perceived, and

designed all aspects of environment. For environment is all-comprehensive it includes the human-

influenced environment, nature, and anything that is in between. The beauty discourse that applies

to present-day Noord-Holland has no different mechanism; it is apparent in all aspects of

environment, and informed by all aspects of society. As has occurred many times in history, we are

seemingly on the verge of meeting societal conditions that allow for yet another break of beauty

discourse.

To explain I must discuss two societal developments that I noticed during an internship in the

Welstand (‘design control sector’; DCS) which was facilitated by a ‘design control organization’ (DCO)

in Noord-Holland, appropriately named MOOI Noord-Holland. I want to make clear that this thesis is

neither meant to be an analysis of the design control sector, nor to be a recommendation for its

reform. However, to explain how the subjects of this thesis came together, I must describe the place

where the ideas developed.

The first development is the design control sector going through a change of practice in which MOOI

Noord-Holland is a key player. Until only recently it was mandatory to present building plans to

design control commissions in which renowned architects – ‘the experts’ – sit whose job it is to judge

these plans in accordance to design standard policies. However, as a result of an amendment of the

law, municipalities are no longer required to involve design control organizations when dealing with

building applications. Design control organizations see their very existence threatened and hence

reinvention is their retention. Instead of regulation providing income, customer demand is to be

raised. To point out what is being improved – or better to say; the industry’s shortcomings – a short

transcript of an interview I conducted after sitting in at one of the meetings is explanatory:

Primo “Would you have preferred the original plan?”

B “Yes, but we can also adhere to the revised plan. Actually, we submitted the original plan

because we thought the design control commission would support it.”

Primo “Are you annoyed by the fact that you are forced to conform to design control guidelines?”

O “I am, but considering the bigger picture it makes sense.”

- 6 -

Primo “Could you explain?”

O “I prefer just going about my business, but if everyone would it will end in disorder.”

Primo “Do you think agreement would have been reached faster if the plan was presented to the

design control commission at an earlier stage?”

B “Yes I do. During the formation of other plans I have had the opportunity to ask questions. That

way it is easier to conform to written and unwritten design control regulation.”1

(Interview with B (architect) and O (client) conducted on March 7th

2016)

Confusion all over. Architects try to conform their designs to what they think will please the design

control commission. What will be approved and rejected, however, is not always clear to them.

Design guidelines are partly fixed in municipal design standard policies. Besides mandatory

obedience to these guidelines there is room for interpretation on part of the experts in the

commission and it is not always apparent to the client and architect what is desired of them

beforehand. The client and architect therefore often feel at the mercy of the design control

commission which decides whether or not they may move forward. To overcome this inefficiency

design control organizations now try to be involved in the plan process at an earlier stage. This way

client and architect will know what ‘rules’ to abide to when the object is being designed and will not

be surprised later on.

There is, however, a more ideologically infused endeavour that is currently being undertaken

by MOOI Noord-Holland: the democratization of environmental beauty – i.e. transferring aesthetic

‘power to the people’ by asking them directly what they regard as beautiful (MOOI Noord-Holland,

2017). Indeed, the above incomprehension between experts and lay people is a symptom of a deeper

and long-standing problem. Between them, there seem to exist different understandings of what a

beautiful environment is, and more importantly, on what characteristics environmental beauty

depends (Howley, 2011; Kaplan and Kaplan, 1989; Strumse, 2001). The level of education contributes

most to this inconsistency. Experts hold a standard – set by expert training (which is not necessarily

aesthetic training) – against which they compare a particular example that is to be assessed for its

aesthetic value. Lay people do the same thing without this training and have therefore another set of

standards against which environments are measured (Kaplan and Kaplan, 1989).

Traditionally, experts are thought to be better able to ‘separate what they know from what

they sense’ in a justified way, and to be more aware that they unconsciously ‘know more than they

know’. In other words: environments should be compared against the expert standard since lay

people’s standards are influenced by feelings, emotions, and apparently the wrong knowledge. In

this conservative view the expertise of a person is the basis for passing qualified judgement on

environmental beauty (Cold, 2001a; 2001b; Berleant, 2012d). Jargon, moreover, is further

- 7 -

complicating things (Figure 1). Experts tend to communicate in words that are not understood by lay

people. When I was sitting in during commission meetings, it was not uncommon for the client (and

myself) to have that dull stare of a person who is not grasping what is discussed in front of him.

Forthcoming is the so-called ‘expert-lay people gap’ which in fact constitutes a social question: are

environmental aesthetics the monopoly of experts or should public ideas of beauty be more

involved?

Figure 1: Do It Yourself Architectural Dialogue. Table mockingly suggesting that it enables lay

people to speak ‘architect’ (http://isites.harvard.edu).

- 8 -

Consensus about this issue will probably never be attained. We can, however, predict that

with the democratization of environmental beauty comes an aesthetics that leans more heavily on

lay people’s opinion. Emotion and lay people’s knowledge of beauty will therefore inescapably have

a larger influence on future aesthetic judgement of environments. The balance between the

traditional ‘educating the people’ and the more democratic ‘listening to the majority’ is shifting in

the advantage of the latter.

That brings us to the second development that must be discussed. The amount of screens available

to us has been increasing exponentially in the last two decades (Figure 2). Also, consider the amount

of screen minutes we live through every day (Figure 3). The majority’s idea of beauty is increasingly

being shaped by a continuous influx of images. From the moment we wake up until the minute we

fall asleep we spend on average almost seven hours looking at screens. The ‘bombardment of

images’ we endure daily – informed by and at the same time fuelling beauty discourse – comes with

a couple of implications. First of all it emphasizes the visual component of beauty. It follows that the

more we are moulded by digital visual representations of beauty the more we will focus on the

‘analogue’ visual component of beauty in real life. Second, instead of experiencing beauty ourselves

we more and more assume the representations of others. Beauty becomes therefore spoon-fed, and

we, in the meantime, become less and less accustomed to having an open, creative relationship with

real life aesthetic phenomena.

Figure 2: Global shipments of desktops, notebooks, smartphones, and tablets between 1999 and

2013. Data by NPD Display Search (2004-2013 data) and Philips (1999-2003 data) (Morgan Stanley

Research, 2014).

- 9 -

Third, these beauty representations of others are selective. The images we are presented

with are consciously transmitted to us; behind the scenes of beauty is commercial interest and

purpose. We are therefore led to believe in beauty for other reasons than beauty itself. The result is

a falsified idea of beauty which could cloud aesthetic judgement. These clouds directly lead to the

fourth and last implication. Selections are – as the word already implies – narrowing. They limit our

contact with other beauties; we live, to use a fashionable word, in our own bubble – a ‘beautiful

bubble’. The bubble works in at least two ways. First, we become part of various mainstreams

(selections) relatively easier than before. Second, present day technological sophistication has

resulted in software picking up personal preferences. The detected preference is based on your own

digital behaviour and these personalized selections therefore even further narrow down the images

available to you. Allow me to note that in this time of renewed emphasis on national identity – and in

its wake the perceived importance of local identities – we seem to (sub)consciously adhere to a more

and more standardized idea of beauty. The discordance is interesting. The more since our idea of

beauty is in turn connected to the construction of identity.

Figure 3: Average screen minutes in 2014. Survey asked respondents “Roughly how long did you

spend yesterday… watching television (not online) / using the internet on a laptop or PC / on a

smartphone or tablet?”. Survey respondents were age 16-44 across 30 countries who owned or

had access to a TV and a smartphone and/or tablet. The population of the 30 countries surveyed in

the study collectively represent ~70% of the world population (Milward Brown AdReaction, 2014).

- 10 -

Rapid societal change is regularly accompanied by people feeling overwhelmed. The British

writer Sara Maitland, for instance, retreated to a cabin on the heath to avoid society’s noise and to

get acquainted with silence. Experiencing society’s turmoil as too intrusive is of all times. Other

modern examples are the American transcendentalist and radical philosopher Henry Thoreau (1817-

1862) who retreated to Walden Pond because he felt isolation is the necessary condition for a

thoughtful life, and Richard Byrd (1888-1957), the great American explorer, who by himself spend a

whole winter on Antarctica for he wanted to ‘taste’ peace, quietness, and solitude to discover their

inherent sanctity (Maitland, 2008). Escapism is a natural reaction to the feeling of technological

development going too fast, and therefore not uncommon. Some new developments threaten

certainties indeed. Would we, for instance, still be able to separate the virtual from the real in ten

years (Sir Edmund, 2017)? And will our sense of beauty therefore be radically different in future

times? Must we welcome or disapprove of changes such as these?

Without qualifying the above two developments as being good or bad, desirable or undesirable, it

must be recognized that they constitute a current change in design control practice that coincides

with a public sense of environmental beauty that is still in the process of fundamentally changing.

Not only does that raise questions (and sometimes eyebrows), we must at least consider a deeper

epistemological change as well. According to the Dutch Rijksbouwmeester (Chief Government

Architect) Floris Alkemade we have arrived in a new paradigm that comes with another kind of

design challenge. A couple of months ago he delivered a speech in which he called for a

disconnection from past designs and the invention of radically different ones.2 Although Alkemade

was talking about his field of expertise – architecture – and thus conveniently used the term

‘paradigm’, we should, with the above developments in mind, widen the possible scope of change to

the more Foucauldian notion of an epistemological change that transcends the individual sciences

(Foucault, 1966).

This research is not about discourse theory and is certainly not an analysis of different

notions of discourse. However, since there are a couple of great scholars whose names are firmly

connected to the concept of discourse – Jacques Lacan (1901-1981); Thomas Kuhn (1922-1996);

Michel Foucault (1926-1984); and Jürgen Habermas – I feel the need to shortly explain why in this

thesis the notion of beauty discourse is generally aligned with Foucault’s framing. First, the

Foucauldian notion opens up the possibility of radical change of discourse over time: a sequence of

épistèmes.3 This notion therefore allows for the possibility of the perception of beauty entering a

new épistème. Second, since the Foucauldian notion, although it is focused on the sciences, is far

more comprehensive than the paradigmatic change of Kuhn (fitting disciplinary change), it allows for

a change in epistemology (Foucault, 1966). In this case that is the large but at the same time selective

- 11 -

and thus restrictive pool of online information currently changing the conditions under which we

gather knowledge. Part of that knowledge is the knowledge of beauty: how we get to know beauty

and therefore what beauty means to us. And third, focusing not on change, but on the ‘contents’ of

discourse, the Foucauldian notion describes power-knowledge systems (Foucault, 1966). It is

undeniably true that we are relatively easier influenced in what we find beautiful by someone with

authority. Of course authority exists on several levels: from experts putting forward their insights, to

a famous artist talking on television about something he likes, to an esteemed friend’s opinion that

something is beautiful.

Beauty discourse not only dictates how to aesthetically appreciate and what to appreciate,

but also the very inclination to find environments beautiful at all. The idea that environments can be

beautiful is not very old. They were artists, specifically, who in the eighteenth and nineteenth

centuries created a basis of a common cultural and aesthetic perception and hence developed

knowledge of the beautiful environment (Gadamer, 1977). Eventually, the discovery of

environmental beauty even led to the idea that environment must be beautiful. The present-day

framing of environments is (as will become clear) somewhat akin to the notion of place which

describes the ‘aesthetics of everyday life’ and constitutes the feeling of home: an ecological

relationship between people and a setting together with a set of meanings that both emerge from

and inform this experience (Hayden, 1994). The notion of place is widely regarded as being

ideologically driven by fast changing societal and geopolitical circumstances (Ingold, 2007;

Westerman, 2001).

Just as is place, beauty discourse is fundamentally ideological and therefore not only subject

to the appropriations of various forms of power (Dovey, 2001), but also, alike place, expected to

change due to societal developments (which are described above). Although Horace Walpole was

surely inventive and authoritative, his initiative was ‘catalysed’ by developments such as an

increasing historical awareness, the breaking-up of traditional agriculture, improved forms of

transport, and a new clientele that was languishing for stylistic variation (De Botton, 2006). The

transition between Classical and Gothic styles would probably not have happened as fast as it did

without a society that was ready for change.

Similarly, the artists’ sudden creation of a cultural basis for the adoration of nature – and

landscape becoming fashionable in its wake – had been preceded by technical developments that

resulted in a loss of contact with nature, and, subsequently, in people’s longing for wilderness (De

Botton, 2006). Again, transition between beauty discourses occurred rapidly due to societal

developments. You could say that at this moment we are passing through societal developments that

together are similar in regard to their comprehensiveness. First, the environmental beauty industry

changing practically – democratizing; and second, a radical shift in the way we gather knowledge of

- 12 -

the beautiful, caused by an increase of screen minutes. Based on history, it is justified to pose that a

contemporary rapid break of beauty discourse could occur.

We will know when it happens. The future contents of beauty discourse cannot be predicted

scientifically; its analysis is typically done in retrospect. What can be conducted, however, is research

as to discover the direct implications of the contemporary societal change. In context of the

speculative framework set up above, it is the main purpose of this thesis to investigate how our

sense of environmental beauty is being established, and what a different beauty discourse could

imply for Dutch environmental beauty in the future. Nowadays, environment is more and more

studied by the humanities. Literature in this field about the aesthetics of environment is however not

yet that far developed. Moreover, environmental aesthetics and landscape biography, a discipline

and a field that do conduct research on environment and aesthetics, are reluctant to work with the

concept of beauty for it is seen to be too comprehensive and therefore troublesome (Cold, 2001b).

On top of that it is unclear if environment is always meant to be beautiful, or if an

environment in which everything is beautiful would still be considered as such (Van Etteger, 2016).

Still, the subject of research in this thesis is inter alia the design control sector – once created to

safeguard environmental beauty. It would therefore be rather strange to avoid the concept of

beauty. Fortunately, the study of beauty is no longer confined to one discipline (philosophical

aesthetics) and one domain (the creative sector), but is currently rather interdisciplinary. For the first

time, as will be explained in chapter 3, all comprehensive environments can be taken into

consideration and concepts such as discourse, power, and identity can be linked to the concept of

beauty.

Instead of approaching the concept of environmental beauty through the objects of

environment, this thesis will approach the concept through the perception of beauty – through

aesthetic preference and aesthetic experience. The perception of beauty is divided into the idea of

beauty, which is in your head, and the actual experience of the manifestation of beauty. Of course

these two are in a reciprocal relationship; the one does inform the other. This thesis, however, is

written under the assumption that part of their formation is different. Our idea of environmental

beauty is increasingly being formed by beauty representations – which are mediated by others and

for a great part received by looking at screens. Contrarily, the experience of environmental beauty

demands physical presence in that environment, and, moreover, needs a somatic engagement of the

body. The investigation of these two different perceptions of beauty is therefore divided into two

chapters.

Chapter 2 will start off with an analysis of various conceptions of beauty out of the conviction

that it is not possible to write about beauty without, at least for a brief moment, taking note of what

- 13 -

some scholars think beauty actually is. At the same time it will be a warmup for the discussion about

the objective and subjective side of beauty. Subsequently, through an analysis of images of Noord-

Holland we will approach the subject of aesthetic preference. By means of an excursion into the

realm of psychiatry we will investigate whether or not aesthetic preference is susceptible to beauty

discourse. Especially preferences’ developmental process is interesting for it reveals the relative

importance of biology, personality, and culture in the formation of aesthetic preference. An attempt

will be made to build a framework in which the developmental processes of aesthetic preference and

their respective degree of objectivity or subjectivity are conceptualized. Moreover, it will be analysed

to what extent beauty discourses, of various degrees of influence and at work on various societal

levels, can co-exist. What is the mechanism of beauty discourse?

Chapter 3 will take up the issue of the aesthetic experience but will begin with an

investigation into the construct ‘Noord-Holland’; once a conglomerate of islands but presently a

heavily urbanized area. What would problematizing the notion of landscape and connecting it to an

all-comprehensive environment such as Noord-Holland yield? As we will have arrived in a more

concrete section of the thesis an example will show the possible impact of beauty discourse on

environment. Also, we will leave the second chapter’s notion of perception – which was mainly visual

– in favour of a new notion that allows us to experience an environment instead of appreciate a

landscape. A new theoretical section is then inevitable. The subject of aesthetics will be introduced

and subsequently a scholarly debate – which concerns the aesthetic appreciation of nature – will be

analysed for reasons that will become clear. Through thorough analysis we will come to a

comprehensive understanding of what an aesthetic experience is and of what the newly obtained

insights imply for the passing of aesthetic judgement: who is to aesthetically judge?

For the speculative character of the two described societal developments we will conclude

with a discussion that will form the synthesis of this thesis. First, to avoid confusion a short summary

of the gained insights will be provided – call it ‘the results’ if you will. Second, the possible future of

Dutch environmental beauty will be considered: based upon the gained insights it is now possible to

attempt the reciprocation of the second part of the main research question. What could a different

beauty discourse imply for Dutch environmental beauty and our notion of environment?

- 14 -

2 Beauty and preference Anyone with some historical sense knows that the contemporary exclusive and characteristic

meaning of the word art is only two hundred and fifty years old. It was around that time that

aesthetics emerged as a philosophical discipline and that the great German Enlightenment

philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) and his associates began debating the aesthetic

appreciation of the natural world. As a result, the ‘fine arts’ were detached from both the mechanical

arts and art in the technical sense of handicrafts and industrial production. Only with this

emancipation art acquired the quasi-religious function that it possesses for us now, both in theory

and practice (Gadamer, 1977). Subsequently, the concept of beauty became firmly related to the

conception of fine art. It is therefore semantically symptomatic that ‘fine art’ is translated into

German as die schöne Kunst, which literally means ‘beautiful art’. Inter alia these realizations

impelled another German philosopher, Hans-Georg Gadamer (1900-2002), to question in his

influential essay “The relevance of the beautiful” (1977) what beauty means in relationship to art.

Severely influenced by Plato, Gadamer provides us with the story of an old Greek myth that

describes the limitations of man compared to the divine, and his attachment to the earthly burden of

the sensuous life of the body.4 We must keep in mind that for the Greeks it was the heavenly order

of the cosmos that presented the true vision of the beautiful. In the story there is a chariot race to

the vault of the heavens led by the Olympian gods. Human souls also drive their chariots, and when

arrived at the vault of the heavens, they have a glance at the true world. Suddenly, in place of the

disorder and inconstancy that characterize our experience of the world down here on earth, man

perceives the true constants and unchanging patterns of being. Sadly, only the gods can surrender

themselves fully to the vision of the true world whereas the human souls are distracted because of

their unruly nature and sensuous desire. When back on earth only the vaguest memory of the truth

had remained and man was unable to scale the heights of it once again. Luckily, there is one

experience that allows man to yet see the truth: the experience of love and the beautiful, or love of

the beautiful (Gadamer, 1977).

According to Plato, it is by hard (intellectual) effort and the virtue of the beautiful that we are

able to acquire a lasting memory of the true world (Berleant, 2012g). And even then, what man is

able to see is still a mere illumination: “what if”, Plato sighs in his Symposium, “man had eyes to see

the true beauty – the divine beauty, I mean, pure and clear and unalloyed, not clogged with the

pollutions of mortality and all the vanities of human life” (Plato cited in Vacker and Key, 1993, p.

474). The beautiful that is visible to man is a glimpse of the ideal. Beauty that is presented in nature

and art gives us the experience of a convincing illumination of truth and harmony. To Gadamer,

- 15 -

however, the important message that the above story has to teach is that the essence of beauty does

not lie in some realm that is opposed to reality. Contrarily, perceiving something beautiful gives us

the reassurance that the truth is not inaccessible to us, but can be encountered in the disorder that

reality is (Gadamer, 1977). Beauty is here, perceivable, and reserved not only for the gods but for

man as well.

We may be more than willing to believe Gadamer’s claim that beauty is omnipresent and we

could therefore suggest that it should be easily recognizable. As it turns out, however, sometimes

things that are perceived as beautiful at one place are not at another. A decade ago The Washington

Post conducted a famous experiment in the city’s subway. The newspaper asked Joshua Bell, one of

the world’s leading violin players, to play his instrument in one of the hallways. They had taken

precautions as for the crowd not to grow too big since Bell normally performs for kings and

presidents and people are prepared to pay high entrance fees for his concerts. Their anxiety proved

to be in vain. What happened is comical, surprising, and scientifically interesting at the same time:

out of the 1097 people that passed in the 43 minutes of playtime only seven stopped and stayed to

listen for longer than one minute (Sir Edmund, 2016). Another instance is the visit of the British

philosopher Alain de Botton to The Dutch Village in Japan (Sasebo, Nagasaki). Although the royal

palace Huis ten Bosch, several windmills and cheese shops, and even the twelfth century castle

Nijenrode – all Dutch landmarks – have been meticulously reproduced, De Botton experiences the

village as surreal and even uncanny because of the lack of further context in time and place (De

Botton, 2006).

If we cannot count on beautiful things to be beautiful anywhere and at all times, i.e. if we

accept that beauty is heavily context related, what is exactly the truth that is beauty? The following

paragraphs are not meant to be conclusive, but rather to be exemplary and showing a couple of

insights that, amidst the abundance of literature about beauty, caught my attention and interest.

Traditionally beauty is thought to be mainly a visual matter. Interesting is the analysis of the Italian

chemist and writer Primo Levi who compared the beauty of the chemical structure with the beauty

of architecture:

“The [chemical] structure makes you think of something solid, stable, well linked. In fact it happens also in chemistry as in architecture that ‘beautiful edifices’, that is, symmetrical and simple, are also the most sturdy; in short, the same thing happens with molecules as with the cupolas of cathedrals or the arches of bridges. And it is possible that the explanation is neither remote nor metaphysical: to say beautiful is to say ‘desirable’, and ever since man has built he has wanted to build at the smallest expense and in the most durable fashion, and the aesthetic enjoyment he experiences when contemplating his work comes afterwards…the true beauty, in which every century recognizes itself, is found in upright stones, ships’ hulls, the blade of an axe, the wing of a plane.” (Levi, 1975, p. 181)

- 16 -

The conviction that beauty is functional, and, as Levi writes, contextual in time, is shared by the

British historian Simon Schama:

“What lies beyond the windowpane of our apprehension needs a design before we can properly discern its form, let alone derive pleasure from its perception. And it is culture, convention and cognition that makes that design; that invests a retinal impression with the quality we experience as beauty.” (Simon Schama cited in Ingold, 2012, p. 2)

Schama adds to the determinants of beauty an underlying plan: the design. If we think of the typical

design of classical music concerts, it becomes immediately clear that the subway concert of Bell does

not fit the general idea of the circumstances under which such a concert should take place. Its beauty

was therefore simply not recognized. However, the conclusion that beauty can only be recognized

when circumstances measure up to a general design is of course not justified; its absence makes the

recognition of beauty merely more difficult.

An example that has intrigued me for years is the habit of people to listen to (or rather

experience) silence. In fact, whole symphonies have been composed that consist of nothing more

than silence, or framed differently, the absence of sound. It begs the question if beauty is always

associated with pleasure. An example is what has been called the ‘paradox of the sublime’. Some

pleasurable aesthetic experiences are triggered by the encounter with an object or situation whose

quantity transcends the limits of our actual grasp. The so-called sublime aesthetic experience can, at

the one hand, originate from being in a vast mountain range that is all around you. At the other

hand, constituting the paradox, you could think of being in a storm. Although the experience can be

aesthetically stimulating, it is associated with negative pleasure as well since the storm is

intimidating. Also, the concept of ugliness must at least be mentioned since we are talking about

beauty, and, ugliness deserves the same kind of paradox as the sublime. If we believe that beauty

can evoke positive feelings such as hope, we might believe that ugliness evokes, amplifies, and

concretizes a sense of imperfection that is normally thought to be negative (De Botton, 2006).

However, at the same time imperfection is a natural part of beauty for ours is the human beauty –

the strive for the ideal and thus per definition imperfect – and not the divine beauty constituting the

ideal.

When scanning through the vast body of literature it becomes immediately apparent that

beauty is not only visual, but can manifest itself in domains Beyond the visible – to cite the title of the

scholar Rudi van Etteger’s 2016 PhD thesis. According to Van Etteger, it is the design itself that is

beautiful. He writes about landscapes of such a size that some characteristics, such as symmetries or

long stretching tree lines, can simply not be perceived due to their scale. Although related, De Botton

- 17 -

reaches another and more Platonic conclusion. According to him it is about the idea behind the

design. Visuals alone are too arbitrary and pluralistic:

“[W]e must be free to pursue all stylistic options. We should acknowledge that the question of what is beautiful is both impossible to elucidate and shameful and even undemocratic to mention.” (De Botton, 2006, p. 77)

Rather, beyond the visual is the idea behind the design, the idea that constitutes what the meaning

of our existence should be. It is this idea that holds real beauty (De Botton, 2006).

Designs as the expressions of ideals. This way of thinking about beauty is omnipresent in the

architectural world. The Dutch urban planner Ben Eerhart, writing about architecture in Wat heet

mooi? (1980), puts it this way:

“I reserve beautiful for those expressions that constitute an ideal that appeals to me, when it strengthens or broadens my own.”

5 (Eerhart, 1980, p. 32)

Eerhart compared the architectural expression of the Baroque to the one of the remains of Nazi

architecture. During his analysis he reached the conclusion that it was the same aesthetics he

appreciated in Pirro Ligorio’s Villa d’Este in Tivoli and Albert Speer’s Reichsparteitaggelände in

Neurenberg: abundance. However, the villa evoked a feeling of positive excitement – happiness –

whereas Speer’s complex evoked at the same time appreciation for the expediency of the design and

repulsion for the idea behind it. Both are aesthetically rewarding, however, only the villa was

appreciated as beautiful.

Put into theoretical terms by the Danish professor of architecture Birgit Cold:

“An aesthetic experience of quality is a natural part of the perception of beauty, but we do not necessarily find a perception of beauty in any aesthetically qualitative perception.” (Cold, 2001b, p. 73)

It is not only things that are optimal in perspective of function or resources, have an aesthetically

rewarding design, or even conform to an individuals’ ideal or idea of the world. It is all these things

together. There is something about beautiful environments that is playful and creative. It is

structures, patterns, rhythms and symmetries, but also dualities such as order paired with variation,

fitness with small surprises, harmony balanced with minor irregularity, originality with a certain

familiarity, and femininity and sweetness complementing or contrasting masculinity and potency

(Cold, 2001b).

Beauty’s character seems to be intangible. Its perceptions are difficult to order and perhaps

easier to attain in a state of spontaneity and voluntariness. Especially environmental beauty has

- 18 -

something alive to it; the promise of something coming about and openness to further fantasy (Cold,

2001b). This manner of looking at the concept of beauty does call upon our sense of subjectivity. Is it

possible to describe and analyse something as volatile and precarious at all? According to the French

romantic and realistic writer Stendhal (1783-1842) “la beauté n’est que la promesse du bonheur”

(Stendhal in De l’amour, 1822). It is therefore not permanent. It is elusive in character and its

variations seem to be endless. To cite Stendhal again: “there are as many styles of beauty as there

are visions of happiness” (Stendhal cited in De Botton, 2006, p. 112).

2.1 Subjectivity or objectivity?

The nature of beauty as being subjective is often held as axiomatic in contemporary culture. It is

dependent on the contents of human consciousness (Vacker and Key, 1993): when talking about

beauty, who has not encountered the phrases ‘each to their own’ and ‘let us agree to disagree’?

However, if beauty would be solely subjective – as Stendhal suggests – on what foundation do

municipalities build their design standard policies; there must indeed be some objectivity when it

comes to environmental beauty? Fortunately, there are some approaches to beauty that allow for its

analysis, of which aesthetic preference research is an important one.

Preference research suggests that there must indeed be an objective component in the

perception of beauty. The idea that beauty is solely subjective, and subsequently, that the true

beauty of objects cannot be known by man is based on Platonic (and later Kantian) subjectivism and

will be discussed in the next chapter about aesthetic experience. However, before we can turn to

aesthetic theory and the analysis of the aesthetic experience, our idea of beauty beforehand – before

the experience and partly dependent on aesthetic preference – will be analysed. In particular will be

focused on the manifestation of beauty discourse. It is the purpose of this chapter to establish that

the phenomenon of beauty is both unique and universal, that its perception is preceded by aesthetic

preference – both personally developed and conditioned by culture – and that in the middle of all

that subjectivity at least some objectivity can be found as well.

Think of advertisements displaying models. Their visuals are based on extensive preference

research that claims to have found universally preferred attributes: a model is instructed by the

photographer to take a stance or pose that relates in a certain way to the object that is commended

in the advertisement. The model itself is carefully chosen to fit the object and the further visuals of

the ad were carefully chosen to fit the object and the model. It is important to recognize that an

advertisement is already a representation of beauty since it is produced for the purpose of the

advertised object being beheld as a beauty object.

- 19 -

Advertisements respond to a database of universally preferred attributes because they are

designed to address an as large a target audience as possible. At the same time, being part of a

specific beauty discourse, the advertisement itself potentially enlarges the base of customers – the

target audience – by influencing what people view as beautiful. The ad was therefore not only

designed under influence of beauty discourse, but also strengthens it. That mechanism is the same

for beauty representations of landscape. Landscapes are inter alia being designed to be considered

beautiful by their users. The idea of what is beautiful about landscape is being influenced by beauty

discourse, which will therefore influence the design as well. However, as people view the designed

landscape they will become increasingly accustomed to that particular representation of beauty, and

the accompanying beauty discourse is – through its discursive repetition – reinforced.

It is not said, however, that highly endorsed ideas of environmental beauty are created or

strengthened by beauty discourse only. Instead, the collective consideration of certain visuals as

beautiful – both in the case of model ads and landscapes – raises questions. Is the widespread

popularity of these visuals due to an objective congenital agreement on their beauty? Or has a

beauty discourse been created by a group of people that had the authority to do so, and would it

subsequently have created its own target audience? Focusing on the first question, would the

aesthetic preference for some attributes of landscape stem from a more instinctive sense of beauty

that was already present at birth? And, focusing on the second question, can influential beauty

discourses create a sense of beauty that is so common – collective – that it is perhaps better to

understand this ‘objectivity’ as ‘similarity in subjectivity’?

We will return to this problem momentarily. To avoid too much abstractness it is best to relate the

idea of aesthetic preference to landscape – i.e. the totality of our surroundings, man-made or non-

human influenced, or anything in between – first. About a year ago I set up a digital online collection

of beautiful places that are all situated within the geographical borders of the Dutch province Noord-

Holland – and named it the collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland (for a more extensive explanation of the

project, see Appendix A).6 People were invited to submit a couple of photos of their place of beauty

and to add a few words to describe in detail what they experienced as beautiful. The 354 submitters

were all adults, felt (at least) addressed to by the invitation, and amongst them were both experts

working in the field and lay people. The whole thing was not set up as a scientific survey, there was

no targeted respondent group, and the total amount of submissions is too small to deduct empirical

results, but still, some clear trends are recognizable and can be compared to other (scientific) surveys

about aesthetic landscape preference (for an explanation of categories, see Appendix A).

Almost half of the submitters chose a place that was (directly) outside the built environment.

Surprisingly, the amount of submissions representing cities was relatively low and even then

- 20 -

approximately half of them involved some form of nature such as a park or a river. Moreover,

throughout the entire collection ‘nature’ (or nature-like) and ‘water’ are by far the largest categories

(Figure 4). Amongst them coastal areas such as dunes, beaches, lakes and seas are omnipresent, but

also polders, meadows, and bushes are popular (Figure 5). In the pictures of these areas canals,

rivers, hedgerows, treelines, and bulbs are very common (Figure 6), but human built non-natural

objects are abundant as well: ditches, dikes, windmills, and built architecture (Figure 7). The degrees

of quietness and openness seem to be the most important attributes. Other important attributes are

the degree of historicity, the visibility of culture (which is in this collection almost linearly related to

the feeling of historicity), and the possibility of recreation (which seems to be an inclination to be

physically active in the landscape of preference).

Figure 4: Nature and Water. Nieuwe Hondsbossche Duinen – Schagen (Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland,

www.collectiemooi.nl).

- 21 -

Figure 5: Polder and Meadow. Mijzen Polder, Ursem – Koggenland (Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland,

www.collectiemooi.nl).

Figure 6: Treeline and Bulbs. Venhuizen – Drechterland (Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland,

www.collectiemooi.nl).

- 22 -

If we compare these observations to the findings of a couple of environmental preference

studies, it becomes clear that there are a lot of similarities. In Western countries there is a tendency

to value natural landscapes more positively than clearly human influenced landscapes (Howley, 2011;

Strumse, 2001). Especially in the Netherlands a phenomenon can be observed that has been called

‘new biophilia’: ninety percent of the respondents of a survey acknowledged the intrinsic value of

nature, i.e. nature’s right to exist irrespective of its uses and functions for mankind (De Groot and

Van den Born, 2003). And when asked to choose between models of development, another group of

Dutch respondents chose the development of wild natural settings over the plans to develop

Figure 7: Windmill and Dike. Oostdijk – Heerhugowaard (Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland,

www.collectiemooi.nl).

- 23 -

managed settings (Van den Berg and Koole, 2006). Kalivoda et al. (2014) summarized the findings of

numerous environmental preference surveys from all over the world and reached the conclusion that

there are four main rules of thumb that show which landscapes will be aesthetically preferred. First,

this depends on the presence and abundance of vegetation, water, well-preserved man-made

elements, and meadows – which in surveys are the most accentuated elements of landscapes.

Second, this depends on the degree of openness, unity, colour contrast, vividness, and naturalness –

which in surveys are the most preferred attributes of landscapes. Third, within settlements and in

regard to architecture, people tend to prefer traditional architecture, family houses, small lots,

contextuality, and tidiness.

The fourth factor in play is the survey respondents’ characteristics, such as occupation, level

of education, gender, living environment, age, and place of residence. It is suggested that the group

differences in aesthetic landscape preference are relatively small, and, do not weigh in heavily when

compared to the significance of the first three rules of thumb (Kalivoda et al., 2014). Of these, the

first two are focused on the presence of natural elements. Some have even interpreted this focus as

supporting an evolutionary theory of landscape preference whereby it is assumed that similarities in

responses to natural settings outweigh differences across cultures or smaller groups of individuals.

This interpretation is widely debated though, for other research has found substantial individual and

inter group differences in aesthetic landscape preference suggesting that familiarity – getting used to

ones surroundings – is of significant influence (Howley, 2011; Strumse, 2001). Several studies about

landscape preference therefore strongly emphasize the contextuality of their findings, i.e. they

emphasize that there can be considerable (temporal) differences between regions, groups, and

individuals (Van Zanten et al., 2016).

These two approaches to aesthetic preference – advocating preferential subjectivity and

objectivity – are opposite poles in the scholarly discussion. In reality aesthetic preference seems to

be dependent on both. Although lots of scientists point out that it will probably take shape under

heavy influence of culture, there are some trends that suggest a general need for natural

surroundings. It remains unclear, however, what is meant exactly with this ‘objectivity’; what is the

cause of this general need?

“While many take the view as did Kant in his Critique of Judgement that aesthetic quality is a highly subjective matter, by establishing a broad and deep consensus within society we can relatively ‘objectivize’ that quality.” (Kalivoda et al., 2014, p. 43)

Would Kalivoda et al. suggest that objectivity is what I meant with ‘similarity in subjectivity’: common

taste that is created by beauty discourse? Or would this ‘broad and deep consensus’ be meant to be

more intuitively bestirred and thus to be part of the human capacity to prefer at birth? Whether

- 24 -

intuition or (globally) learned behaviour is the most important factor causing preferential objectivity

remains the question. It would be really helpful to understand the development of preference in

support of establishing the importance of culture in its formation, and thus in the understanding of

the susceptibility of our aesthetic preferences to beauty discourse. How widespread must a

preference be endorsed to be considered objective? Below what degree of endorsement does

preference become subjective? And to which extent are we receptive to be persuaded to prefer? We

will now turn to theory in an attempt to clarify the relative significance of biological, cultural and

personal factors in the formation of preference.

2.2 The development of aesthetic preference In the 1990 study A paradigm for landscape aesthetics the American urban and regional planner

Steven Bourassa recognized that there not yet existed comprehensive theory that described the

formation of human aesthetic preference in a landscape.7 In his article two modes of aesthetic

preference are distinguished – biological (innate or intuitive) and cultural (learned) behaviour – and

subsequently it is posed that there is a third that seems to have a certain degree of autonomy from

biological and cultural factors: personal idiosyncrasy and personal creativity.

To support this theory Bourassa borrows heavily from the Russian psychologist Lev Vygotsky

(1896-1934) who proposed that preference is subject to three developmental processes:

phylogenesis (biological evolution), sociogenesis (cultural conditioning), and ontogenesis (individual

development). Bourassa connects these processes with the ‘products of development’, the Umwelt,

the Mitwelt, and the Eigenwelt, which in psychiatrical theory are the three simultaneous modes of

existence. The first two modes respectively stand for the biological world and the social or cultural

world. Eigenwelt stands for one’s personal world or ‘the mode of one’s relationship to one’s self’.

With this last mode it is implied that the individual is mature or has developed to the stage of

intellectual responses; he or she has internalized language and uses it as a tool to influence his or her

own behaviour. It follows that this third mode of behaviour is no longer strictly the result of

biological and cultural factors but is underlain by them; the individual can transcend these

constraints through intellectual activity (Bourassa, 1990).

Under this reading of Eigenwelt personal idiosyncrasy and personal creativity are reserved

for almost all of us, and that subjective part of aesthetic preference is therefore both easily theorized

and highly elusive. It forces us to focus on what in the above section has been theorized as ‘present

at birth’ (biological behaviour, instinctive) and ‘similarity in subjectivity’ (cultural behaviour, learned).

These terms respectively correspond to the developmental processes of phylogenesis and

- 25 -

sociogenesis, and to the products of development Umwelt and Mitwelt. There seems to be some

evidence that these modes of aesthetic preference are not so much intertwined, but rather distinct:

different parts of the brain specialize in innate and learned behaviours and the visual and other

sensory systems have direct connections to each of these parts (Bourassa, 1990). The three modes of

aesthetic preference thus represent three distinct domains that should not be confounded. At the

same time, they should all be taken into account as none can explain the whole range of aesthetic

behaviour alone (Strumse, 2001). These findings give us a glimpse of the different components of

aesthetic preference. However, they do not explain the relative importance of innate and learned

factors in the formation of preference. Also, Bourassa fails (as this was not his main objective) to

analyse the objectivity in preference.

An approach that could provide some clarity as to what objectivity in environmental

aesthetic preference is and where it comes from is ‘The Preference Matrix’ which was proposed by

Kaplan and Kaplan (1989). In their book The experience of nature it is asserted that the study of

environmental preference shows remarkable consistency, despite demographic differences and

across diverse settings. The explanation, they propose, is biological. Human functioning depends on

information which we are constantly recording and processing:

“People seem to be extremely facile in their ability to extract information from the environment. Even the very briefest glimpse of the passing landscape provides information. This information does not depend on posted signs or neon lights. It is far subtler and generally not a part of one’s awareness.” (Kaplan and Kaplan, 1989, p. 50)

The hunger for information and its availability may influence the biological, innate side of our

aesthetic preference. To which extent a landscape allows us to instantly assert its informational value

is of importance, but the promise of discovery while entering the landscape seems to be equally

significant (Kaplan and Kaplan, 1989).

The Preference Matrix, then, schematically displays landscape characteristics that influence

our assessment of whether or not a landscape provides us with these possibilities (Figure 8). It is

divided into two domains that represent critical facets of people’s relationship to information. The

horizontal axis shows the human needs for understanding and exploration, and the vertical axis

shows the degree of interference that is needed to extract the information: we are looking from a

distance – as if it were a two-dimensional picture – or we enter in an environment. From a distance

two important characteristics are of influence. Complexity; the number of different visual elements,

the richness of a landscape. And coherence; which is about the degree of order and is enhanced by

anything that helps organize the patterns of brightness, size, and texture. When we enter the

environment two other characteristics come into play. Legibility; which indicates whether or not the

- 26 -

space is well structured and made up of distinctive elements, and, thus, if it is easy to understand

and remember. And mystery; which carries the promise to learn more, of further information (Kaplan

and Kaplan, 1989).

The Preference matrix suggests that the needs for understanding and exploration are both

important; the one cannot replace the other. Similarly, the desire for both the immediate and the

more inferential coexist. Kaplan and Kaplan conclude:

“It becomes apparent that the spatial definition or structure of an area, the textures that help one decide about the ease of locomotion or visual access, and the invitation to enter the scene to learn what cannot be determined from one’s present vantage point are all powerful yet subtle qualities of the environment.” (Kaplan and Kaplan, 1989, p. 69)

In turn, it seems safe to conclude that aesthetical preference is at least in part informed by a

biological preference for certain features in the landscape, and, moreover, that this preference is

innate and objective for it is part of all of us. We must bring some nuance to this objectivity however.

Although biological preference is innate, is it thought to develop further after birth. Biological

aesthetic preferential objectivity is therefore no absolute; we can merely ascribe certain collective

aesthetic preferences to be grounded in biological evolution. Culture, subsequently, is able to further

develop biologically programmed aesthetic preference.

Are qualities of environment, such as openness, order, mystery, and structure, stimulating our sense

of beauty as well? Would landscapes that are aesthetically preferred because of these characteristics

be appreciated as beautiful too? There is no conclusive evidence as preference studies regularly

avoid the concept of beauty. Yet, the majority of the environments in the collectie MOOI in Noord-

Holland – submitted because of their beauty – display similar characteristics. That could suggest that

our perception of beauty is therefore at least partially objective. Indeed, recall that Bourassa

suggested that our sensory system – with which we perceive amongst others beauty – has a direct

connection to innate behaviour. We will therefore remain focused on the relationship between

biologically determined and culturally conditioned preference a bit longer. In what way do these

components work simultaneously to become an aesthetical preference assessment?

Understanding Exploration

Immediate Coherence Complexity

Inferred, predicted Legibility Mystery

Figure 8: The Preference Matrix. Landscape characteristics that determine the availability of information

(Kaplan and Kaplan, 1989).

- 27 -

While even Kaplan and Kaplan (1989) emphasize the importance of contextuality in the

explanation of group differences, there seem to exist high levels of consistency between these

groups as well. In any case, The Preference Matrix does not conceptualize beauty. It merely describes

conditions to which we all respond with the same kind of aesthetical behaviour. The objectivity in

beauty itself (or truth as Gadamer conveniently puts it) cannot be subsumed scientifically under

concepts, “not even by art criticism which hovers between ‘scientific’ demonstration and a sense of

quality that never becomes purely scientific” (Gadamer, 1977, p. 22). It is impossible to convince

someone of the truth of something beautiful by argument. For it does not comply to the conceptual

universality of the understanding, the objectivity in beauty preference does not fit the universality of

the laws of nature. Although it may not be possible to prove an object beautiful, it is possible – as

Kaplan and Kaplan show – to claim more than merely subjective validity of beauty assessments.

Whether aesthetic preferential objectivity is biologically programmed, conditioned by globally

dispersed culture, or a combination of these two (where innate and learned behaviour meet and

produce more or less the same result); it is clearly in opposition with some local particularities of

beauty that seem to be diversions from this truth.

Figure 9: Graph schematically displaying the three domains of aesthetic behaviour and indicating which

domain is susceptible to discourse (Created 26-3-2017).

- 28 -

What can be learned from psychiatry is that phylogenesis, sociogenesis, and ontogenesis

must all be taken into account to explain aesthetic behaviour. And that at the same time, they are

three distinct domains that should not be confounded. The application of this theory to aesthetic

preference leads to three principles (Figure 9). The first is that there are apparently different versions

of preferential objectivity and subjectivity. At the one hand there is biologically programmed

preference which is already present at birth (and will develop further thereafter). This is one version

of preferential objectivity. Related but not identical to biologically programmed innate preference is

the extreme of culturally learned global preference; although being in fact subjective, it is

‘objectivized’ through similarity in subjectivity. You could say that this is the most objective level of

culturally propelled subjectivity.

Hence the second principle: although both domains – phylogenesis and sociogenesis –

involve preferential objectivity, they should not be confounded. In other words, both ‘objectivities’

are fundamentally different developing behaviours. At the same time, we are not capable of

separating and only displaying one of them. These two principles apply to the subjective end of the

spectrum as well. One kind of preferential subjectivity is ‘personal idiosyncrasy and personal

creativity’ which entails personal taste that develops through intellectual activity. Related but not

identical to personal idiosyncrasy and personal creativity is the extreme of culturally learned

individual preference. Both levels of subjectivity relate to the individual, but at the same time they

are fundamentally different behaviours that have developed through the processes of respectively

ontogenesis and sociogenesis. The first has to do with individual intellectual activity and the latter

with learning from others.

And that is exactly the thing that sets sociogenesis apart from the biological and personal

developmental processes: its resulting behaviour is learned from others. This does inter alia happen

through the influence of culture and our susceptibility to beauty discourse. Moreover, the group size

of the others that we learn from is quite diverse. Between the extremes of global and individual

learned preference are (theoretically infinite) degrees of subjectivity. This is the third principle, i.e.

with a decreasing level of agreement we subsequently move away from objectivized global aesthetic

preference towards (for instance) European preference and subsequently Dutch preference;

subcultural preference; group preference; and ultimately the level of individual (learned) aesthetic

preference. It follows that when only a small group of people is convinced of a certain preference,

the accompanying discourse is less influential (or imposed) than a discourse that comes with fully

dispersed global culture.

- 29 -

2.3 Representations of beauty In what way can we conceptualize the simultaneous existence of different degrees of subjectivity?

How can we explain more and less influential versions of an as absolute thing as the (Platonic) truth –

universal beauty; and in which manner does this coexistence work out in practice?

It has been documented that landscape preferences have evolved over time as individuals

both become more familiar with particular types of landscape and become more aware of

environmental issues – a manifestation of environment discourse if you will. Environmental values

are therefore a very important predictor of landscape preference (Howley, 2011). Particularly in the

Netherlands where 51% of a survey’s respondents has a vision of ‘greatness and the forces of nature’

when asked about their natural landscape of preference (De Groot and Van der Born, 2003).

Moreover, the better a given landscape matches an idealized image of its landscape type – agrees

with the discourse – the lower is the variance in preference judgements: the stronger is the

consensus about its aesthetic quality (Kalivoda et al., 2014). It follows that the aesthetics of a

preferred landscape are themselves preferred as well.

It must, however, be recognized that this survey most probably would have had a very

different outcome when it was conducted in China where environmental values are undoubtedly less

of a priority and public awareness is much lower. Preference does differ between cultures, and

aesthetic preference must therefore differ as well. Exemplary is what the American-Japanese scholar

Donald Keene brought to the fore in The Pleasures of Japanese Literature (1988): the Japanese idea

of beauty used to be very different from the Western ideal. Favoured were irregularity instead of

symmetry; transiency instead of eternity; and simplicity instead of ornateness. The contrast was not

the result of climate or biological differences, but rather of the work of painters, writers, and

theorists who influenced the aesthetic preference of a nation (De Botton, 2006). In terms of beauty

discourse: in Japan a very different but nevertheless strong and culturally determined aesthetic

preference had been around for ages until it was overtaken by Western culture.

To return to the example of the advertisement displaying a model; although its visuals are

based upon a preferential norm that constitutes a widely supported idea of beauty, it is not said that

the visuals of the ad are accepted as beautiful anywhere on earth. Also, there may co-exist multiple

versions of the truth in one place: although the ad could be recognized as beautiful, there can be

other sets of visuals that are locally regarded as beautiful at the same time. And some of these may

even be stronger adhered to than others. To say that beauty is a universal is simply to say that it is a

concept that can be abstracted from a broad range of concrete particulars. The conception of beauty

as universal does not mean that all cultures or societies must ascribe to the same particular

representations of it. Instead, because beauty is a universal it exists across cultures, but it is known

- 30 -

through particulars that are unique to the context of each culture (Vacker and Key, 1993). This

supports the view that subjective aesthetic preference may not be so much culturally relative as

culturally contextual:

“One can observe the different particular standards for Oriental female beauty versus Occidental female beauty and realize that no one template of particular beauty can apply to both cultures. Yet, it is possible for an Oriental to appreciate and value an Occidental beauty and for an Occidental to appreciate and value an Oriental beauty.” (Vacker and Key, 1993, p. 483)

This explanation accounts for the co-existence of multiple representations of beauty at the

same place, of absolute and more ‘contextual truths’, and of more broadly or narrowly dispersed

beauty discourses. It explains why advertisements with Western looking models can appeal to people

of other cultures than the ‘Western culture’, and vice versa. It should be noted that in the last

decades an explosion of global mass communication between cultures has made possible a ‘cross

fertilization’ of subjective aesthetic preference (Vacker and Key, 1993). Also, note that the cross

fertilization of aesthetic preference is in fact the mediation of beauty discourse. Cross fertilization

not only occurs on the global level and between global cultures. Sub-cultures can be conveyed to

others that are nearby, even at the level of groups and individuals cross fertilization can occur.

Moreover, strong local beauty discourse can be transferred – for instance by the use of social media

– to a much wider, global audience and root to become global beauty discourse. When a

representation of beauty becomes culturally protected, which can occur at any societal level, we

speak of ‘institutionalized beauty’; a confirmation of something ‘we know is true’ (Cold, 2001b).

However, in these times of far-reaching globalization and cultural cross fertilization that is

possible between any two societal levels, we are surprisingly more than ever confronted with

particularities. It seems that every transnational, national, regional, and local culture has its own

‘canon of beauties’: certain buildings, natural phenomena, landscapes, and works of art that are

often depicted in textbooks, postcards, or tourist posters. These objects belong to a cultural-historic

convention and a stated canon which everybody within civilized society should know and appreciate

(Cold, 2001a).

Recall that the submissions in the collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland displayed features in the

landscape that are regarded as beautiful all over the world, such as openness of terrain or the liking

of traditional architecture. Also, there were similarities that can be ascribed to be more Western,

such as the tendency to value natural landscapes over clearly human influenced landscapes. But the

centre piece of a lot of submissions (almost 6%) was a windmill. Windmills are a very prominent

member of the Dutch canon of beauties. This is exactly how beauty discourse effects aesthetic

preference. Even in this small collection of places that are submitted for their beauty, various beauty

- 31 -

discourses can be recognized that are at work at different geographical levels. Moreover, the image

of a windmill is part of a beauty discourse that has dispersed not only in the Netherlands, but

considering the vast amount of foreign tourists that visits windmills, has been cross fertilized all over

the world.

One could ask: would a windmill be considered as beautiful by a man that has been living in a

cabin in the woods for many years, completely isolated from humans, and cut off from all the

possibilities of communication with a world other than his own? If we would show this person an

image of a windmill, would it be liked and aesthetically preferred? Or would his aesthetic preference

be different without the constant bombardment of canonical images that the ones that participate in

society endure every day? According to Cold “a canon of beauties can be the worst enemy of

experiencing beauty because convention does not demand a direct and dynamic engagement and

awareness, which is the basis for discovering and experiencing beauty” (2001a, p. 19). If that is true,

we could ask the hermit to leave the cabin and accompany us to a windmill; would his aesthetic

experience be the same as ours? In other words: would the aesthetic experience of someone that has

not been susceptible to beauty discourse for many years be different than the aesthetic experience

of someone that has? It is important to emphasize that these questions are not about truth finding;

we have learned that there can be multiple truths that co-exist. Indeed, we are not to argue with

someone’s aesthetic preference or aesthetic experience since preference and taste are individual

truths in themselves. We can only compare aesthetic preference and aesthetic experience. But

before we do, the difference in formation between aesthetic preference – an idea of beauty – and

aesthetic experience – the act of experiencing beauty – must be analysed.

The next chapter will explore what an aesthetic experience is and in what it is different from

aesthetic preference. It will be shown that even when both terms display the word ‘aesthetic’, and

both can involve the recognition of beauty, they inhabit different worlds. What is it to leave the

screen, go into the real world, and aesthetically experience Noord-Holland?

- 32 -

3 Experiencing Noord-Holland

Experiencing Noord-Holland. It sounds rather simple. However, even when taken apart ‘(aesthetic)

experience’ and ‘Noord-Holland’ are highly complex constructs. Let us begin with the latter. Noord-

Holland is a province of the Netherlands. It is home to almost three million people and includes some

of the major cities of the country. Besides metropolitan areas – including some of the polders – its

geographical borders encompass two seas, countless lakes, dunes and beaches, islands, marches,

rivers, forests, and lots of other natural phenomena (Figure 10). So far so good. But what happens if

we problematize Noord-Hollands as a landscape? There are a great many answers to this question

for any landscape is not only composed “of what lies before our eyes but [of] what lies within our

heads” as well (Meinig, 1979, p. 34).

Figure 10: Map of Noord-Holland showing its diverse landscape. The classification is decided on by Rob

van Leeuwen and of course arbitrary: (1) dunes and sand-ridges; (2) aandijkingen (polders), ‘De

Noordkop’; (3) marine clays, ‘West-Friesland’; (4) moraine, partly covered by sand, ‘‘t Gooi’; (5) peat

bogs; (6) reclamations (MOOI Noord-Holland, 2016).

- 33 -

Depending on the kind of ‘beholding eye’, there are endless variations to what people see

when they look at the physical space comprised by geographical borders that is Noord-Holland. Its

landscape could be looked upon as nature. This idea had its greatest vogue in the eighteenth century

and was based on a longing for wilderness and on a view of nature as pure. However, in recent years

it has been debated whether the idea of a geographical division between nature and culture is still

maintainable since human influence on nature has increased dramatically and all land has been

included in the human domain in a new geological era that has been called the ‘Anthropocene’ (no

consensus on when it started) (Muilwijk and Faber, 2015). The idea of landscape as nature is

especially problematic when applied to Noord-Holland since the area has been shaped by human

hands unlike any other area in the world. In this light, one could argue that Noord-Holland is merely a

habitat to its inhabitants: man and nature are in a reciprocal relationship and landscape is therefore

a blend of man and nature. More unilateral, denying any reciprocal relationship, landscape could be

viewed as artefact: nature is the stage or platform on which man – creator and conqueror of nature –

is ecologically dominant (Meinig, 1979).

It is probably not surprising that these are shifting views; as the contemporary architectural

approach to landscape it is conceptualized as a space that is subject to natural cycles and that is

constantly developing culturally (Steenbergen et al., 2009). A tradition that has characterized Noord-

Holland both as nature and as being merely man-made – and is exemplifying for the impact of beauty

discourse on landscape – is the ‘Fine Dutch Tradition’ of inpolderen (poldering). The first coordinated

polderings were the so-called cope-parcelings that occurred from the eleventh to the fifteenth

century. Technological progress and a consciously implemented population-policy resulted in peat-

cultivation in Utrecht and Holland. Architectural concepts, however, were not yet present: the first

coordinated polderings were merely the result of the conquering of wilderness for social purposes in

what has been called ‘de eerste ontginning’ (primary cultivation) (Reh et al., 2003).

That changed during the period of ‘de tweede ontginning’ (secondary cultivation), which was

a clear break with the period of medieval poldering (Reh et al., 2003). Urban development and

expansion, along with Renaissance ideals, gave birth to the first views on what a polder-landscape

must be and this beauty discourse subsequently had an impact on the landscape of Noord-Holland.

Landscape has therefore also been conceptualized as a transmitter of culture (Meinig, 1979). The

investment in poldering by wealthy urban notables found a cultural legitimation in new esthetical

ideals: the arrangement of land according to a geometrical quadrangular grid. The best well-known

example is the reclamation of De Beemster (1612) (Figure 11). The quadrangular grid of De Beemster

was the perfect expression of the Renaissance’s rational ideal. These were the heydays of

seventeenth century Dutch poldering; between 1597 and 1648 approximately 35000 ha. of land was

reclaimed (Bremer, 2004; Noordegraaf, 2004).

- 34 -

However, in the eighteenth century views on nature, and subsequently landscape, changed.

Nature became to be conceived of as an independent system that was intrinsically valuable (as will

be elaborated on further down). Is was therefore not so much to be conquered as to be respected

(Reh, 1996). A break of beauty discourse was the result and would have a direct impact on

nineteenth century Dutch poldering. That became apparent during another wave of poldering (ca.

46000 ha.) which occurred between 1815-1858. For the first time in Noord-Holland the Renaissance

ideal of ratio was confronted with dominant natural features (Reh et al., 2005). As was generally the

case in the nineteenth century, planners tended to approach natural features more respectfully of

which the poldering of the Anna Paulownapolder (1846) is a good example (Figure 12). The polder-

design was adapted to suit its natural features, resulting in a more differentiated kind of grid.

Figure 11: Map of De Beemster of 1658 (www.ifthenisnow.eu).

- 35 -

Another conceptualization of landscape involves viewing Noord-Holland as a system; in this

view the visible landscape is a façade that overlies systematically linked processes. An example is the

atmospheric water management system in which water is redistributed through processes that are

globally interlinked. Such views on ‘invisible’ landscape are for this thesis only relevant when this

insight or knowledge contributes to – or triggers – a sense of beauty, which it does in case of Van

Etteger’s designed landscapes.

Moreover, following the idea that landscape is not only the result but also a transmitter of

culture, landscape is history. This view includes the idea that life must be lived amidst that which was

made before; it comprises of a sense of chronology and continuity and conceptualizes landscape as

stacked layers of history (Meinig, 1979). Exemplary is a fairly new interdisciplinary field – landscape

Figure 12: Map of the Anna Paulownapolder by H.P. Eskes (1856). Natural features as the Oude

Veer and the shape of the surrounding polders clearly shaped the polder-design

(www.regiocanons.nl).

- 36 -

biography – which aims to write long-term life-histories of landscapes to reveal past representations.

Of course the conceptualization of ‘living’ landscape is instantly problematic since landscapes have

not been born and do not die. However, this example does point out that the concept of landscape is

not only about contemporary conceptualization. It is intrinsically linked to ideas and beauty

discourses from the past.

It becomes clear that perceiving landscape does not stop after the visual act. Looking at

landscape is conceptualizing it at the same time. What happens when the information we obtain with

our senses is subsequently processed by the brain; what is it to perceive landscape?

3.1 The perception of landscape The Belgian surrealist artist René Magritte (1898-1967) once said: “We see [the world] as being

outside ourselves, even though it is only a mental representation of what we experience on the

inside.” (Ingold, 2012, p. 1). It becomes immediately clear that all the ideas above that have been

swiftly touched upon have one thing in common: they are mental representations – incomplete by

definition – of the same objects in the same physical space; i.e. these representations are based on

what is seen in the eye of the beholder. It seems that ‘mental landscapes’ are inherently intellectual

constructs of which the meaning depends on culture, making them culturally determined intellectual

constructs. But then, are there landscapes that are not mental? I believe the vision of the Irish

archaeologist Tadhg O’Keeffe to be right: there would be no landscape without us for the simple

reason of ‘landscape’ being an intellectual construct.8 Landscape has no ontological meaning; i.e. it

has no meaning at all without someone or something giving it meaning. Or as the British

anthropologist Tim Ingold writes; to perceive a landscape is to imagine it (Ingold, 2012). This seems

confusing. If ‘landscapes’ only exist in our heads, do we actually refer to physical objects when we

talk about them?

It becomes more clear by examining the construct ‘natural landscape’ that is being

appropriated throughout all kinds of literature and of which the exact meaning is not always the

same. Most of the time, however, the term is used to describe a selection of non-human (produced)

objects in a physical space. Hence, when we refer to ‘landscape’, we are talking about all the objects

that fall within that physical space. The word ‘natural’ in front of ‘landscape’ merely brings the

selection back to the natural objects that may be positioned in between other sorts of objects. When

we follow O’Keeffe’s vision these objects alone do not make up a landscape since any mental

representation is missing. However, when we think or talk about them they become – through our

mental representation – instantly landscape. According to Simon Schama ‘landscape’ is a unification

- 37 -

of physical substance and ideal form – it is our shaping perception that converts raw material into

the image of a landscape (Ingold, 2012).

Mental representation implies interpretation. According to the Dutch archaeologist Jan

Kolen:

“[…] even the most ‘anonymous’, ‘natural’ and ‘original’ of landscapes bears the imprint of human authorship and personal identity, not only in terms of past human presence and practices, but also in terms of aesthetic experiences, retrospective vision, scientific interpretation and naturalist engagement.” (Kolen, 2015, p. 71-72)

The mental representation of objects as landscape is an interpretation and personal. Since

‘landscape’ is an intellectual construct there is no single definition of the concept. Rather, every

being constructs its own version or understanding of it. The above examples of landscape ideas point

that out as well. It is all about perception, including the visualization of place and the experience of

beauty. What we see when we imagine a landscape is a unique mental representation which,

theoretically, no one else experiences exactly the same way (nor completely different). Thus, a single

physical space filled with objects ends up in infinite ‘parallel’ mental representations of that space.

The objects and mental representations taken together are – according to me – what is commonly

known as landscape.

Still, if any representation of the world ever made by any being is mental, and therefore an

interpretation and inaccurate by definition; has no being ever seen the world for what it really is?

Can we ever know what the real objects are like? This is one of the oldest philosophical questions

and akin to the question whether or not we are even present on earth. More and more physicists are

seriously considering the possibility that the cosmos as we know it is a projection – a hologram (Sir

Edmund, 2017). Intriguing, but for the subject of this section – centered around the mental construct

of beauty – far beyond its scope. However, a short analysis of the stance of the American

psychologist James Gibson (1904-1979) in the debate about the accuracy of our vision allows for the

introduction of both the notions of environment and multi-sensory perception as a prelude to the

next section.

According to Gibson seeing is more than impressions that are stamped upon the surface of

the retina and subsequently processed by the mind. Visual perception is the achievement of the

whole organism as it moves through its environment (Ingold, 2012). Until now in this analysis the

perceiver and the object were at a fixed position, while both are of course – to a greater and lesser

extent – moving entities. The concept of environment adds the factor of mobility in time and space to

this equation (Berleant, 2012b). In the mind of the perceiver the objects and their mental

representations – as theorized above – are still there, constructing the notion of landscape. When we

- 38 -

conceptualize the physical space in which they are positioned as an environment though, movement

of the perceiver and alteration of the object are accounted for: instead of a relationship of ‘subject to

object’ we can think of ‘self to setting’. The setting is the environment in which we exist as a sentient

part: it is our surroundings, always under construction, and we ourselves are part of it (Carlson,

2004). The advantage of the concept of environment then, is its focus on the ability of the perceiver

to move around the landscape and to ‘imagine as he goes’. Moreover, mobility in time allows for the

landscape to develop meaning beyond its present day sensible characteristics – which has been

called the ‘power of place’ by the American historian Dolores Hayden: the power to nurture citizens’

public memory, to encompass shared time in the form of shared territory (Hayden, 1995).

To return to the perception of reality, to Gibson perceiving is something entirely different

than imagining. He argues that real objects can always be visually scrutinized further, whereas

mental representations have limitations to their possible enlargement. For example, a painted leaf

cannot be examined under the microscope for its cellular structure, but a real leaf can. Gibson argues

for the existence of a perceived reality. In this view, the real objects can be known by their

parametric constants; their invariants. I.e. no matter the degree of enlargement, the parameters of

the object will remain the same. The perception of these invariants is – according to Gibson – not

imaginative and thus reality. This view is directly opposed to what this analysis yielded so far: the

imagination – or inaccurate mental representation – of objects, landscapes and environments by the

use of perception. Ingold et al. offer a solution to this problem by reuniting perception and

imagination while yet acknowledging the human condition to be that of a being whose knowledge of

the world is not only shaped by the eyes and the mind, but grows from the very soil of an existential

involvement in the sensible world (Ingold, 2012).

To imagine, they suggest, is not so much to conjure up images of the world ‘out there’,

whether virtual or actual, true or false, as to participate from within the environment – through

perception and action – in the very becoming of things. Perceivers are not passive observers:

“To perceive, as to imagine, is to participate from within in the perpetual self-making of the world. It is to join with a world in which things do not so much exist as occur, each along its own trajectory of becoming. […] If imagination is the work of the mind, then it is a mind that far from remaining disengaged, wrapped up in its own auto-generative deliberations, mingles freely with the world along multiple lines of sensory participation.” (Ingold, 2012, p. 14, 16).

This idea accounts for mental representation and perception of reality as it merges them into a

duality. We are at the same time both real objects and mental representations, both perceiving and

being perceived – as participatory parts in an environment. Moreover, when Gibson suggested that

visual perception is the achievement of the whole body, he means that to visualize is to use your

eyes, to turn your head and to move your body. The same principle applies to perception in general;

- 39 -

to perceive is to use all, but not only the senses. We move through environments by using our body,

what is sensed is processed by the brain, and the brain does not only utilize sensed stimuli but also

prior knowledge to construct image of landscape. In the following section aesthetic appreciation will

be examined which is inter alia driven by knowledge and for which the notion of environment is

important as well.

3.2 Aesthetic appreciation

Now that we have rid ourselves of the static landscape in favour of a flexible environment, the

subject of the perception of beauty can be connected to the latter. To fully understand the concept

of the aesthetic experience, however, we must go back to a time when environment was still

landscape and aesthetic experience was still aesthetic appreciation. Nature, as will be explained, has

been the reason for this conceptual change. Its evolving conception would cause paradigmatic

change on at least two occasions: the conceptualization of nature as landscape (eighteenth century)

and the conceptualization of nature as environment (twentieth century). Moreover, in the wake of

changing conceptions come conceptual problems. Indeed, to some people ‘nature’, and ‘landscape’

or ‘environment’, are close to being synonyms. As has been shown above, however, they can be part

of each other but are not one and the same. To others these concepts are contradictory for

resembling the distinction between ‘wild’ and ‘manmade’ and, in regard to urban environments, the

distinction between ‘living’ and ‘not living’.

Further, since the word ‘aesthetic’, and especially the word ‘beauty’, are prominent parts of

vernacular language, their exact meanings are often diffused. These meanings have to be explored

since it is aspired for this thesis to step out of the realm of experts and to consider the implications of

the vernacular perception of beauty on beauty discourse. As aesthetical philosophy is extremely

complex, and reaches beyond the scope of this thesis, I choose to approach the subject with an

ostensibly simple semantic question: where does the word ‘aesthetic’ come from? When I was

pondering this question I realized that the word is used to describe a variety of things. The two most

common uses of the word refer to the sensory perception of aesthetic properties, and the perception

of beauty (Dovey, 2001). Let us go back to the original meaning of the word for “language represents

the previous accomplishments of thought” (Gadamer, 1977, p. 12).

In the ancient Greek language the word aisthesis means ‘to perceive’. By referring to

something as aesthetic by sensory perception it is meant that a certain amount of the properties of

an object are perceptible by the use of the senses of sound, taste, smell, touch, movement or vision.

This direct aesthetic perception is the gateway to the emotional and cognitive processes, when we

- 40 -

become aware, discover, are stimulated by, recognize and assess the environment (Cold, 2001a). It

follows that an object of which the properties are not perceptible by the senses is ‘anaesthetic’. The

allocation of an object as aesthetic, in this instance however, does not say anything about the quality

of the aesthetically perceptible properties. The terms ‘aesthetically appealing’, ‘aesthetically

rewarding’ and ‘aesthetically appreciative’ merely refer to the sensory perceptibility of these

properties.

Upon sensory perception of an objects’ properties an aesthetic response can be triggered on

part of the perceiver. Aesthetic responses can either be positive or negative. Positive aesthetic

responses are implying that an object is beautiful, picturesque or sublime (although the sublime can

be experienced as negative as well). Negative aesthetic responses are implying that an object is ugly

or uncanny (Van Etteger, 2016). It is important to recognize that in the perception of beauty the

word aesthetic is used to describe a qualitative aesthetic response to the object. It follows that an

object of which the properties are aesthetically perceptible but do not trigger a qualitative response

is ‘unaesthetic’ (Dovey, 2001). In this instance, the terms ‘aesthetically appealing’, ‘aesthetically

rewarding’ and ‘aesthetically appreciative’ are suddenly implying a positive aesthetic quality of the

object. Note that in vernacular language – although it might be subconsciously – the word aesthetic

is often used in the above two manners.

Aesthetic appreciation, then, is not about the object alone. It is the perception of the object

that leaves the perceiver ‘touched’; aesthetic appreciation is the interplay between the perceiver and

the perceived. This is best explained by what Gadamer means by the distinction between Erlebnis

and Erfahrung. For Gadamer, art is not to be understood as a magical, fantastic realm to which we

can escape; we do not encounter the world of art without being transformed in the process. If the

aesthetic appreciation of art would be based on Erlebnis, our experience would leave us unchanged,

we would not have heard the claim art makes upon us: art would be reduced to a mere

entertainment. However, if we undergo the experience of art in the sense of Erfahrung, we will find

ourselves touched and transformed (Bernasconi, 1986).

The same principle applies to all other environments – not art alone. Every time we

aesthetically appreciate we are changed. Our presumptions with which we encounter the next object

are not the same as before; aesthetic appreciation is driven by a growing body of experiences and

adds to our ‘aesthetic knowledge’ continuously. Moreover, knowledge that is used to aesthetically

appreciate environments does not only consist of the kind of knowledge that emerged in the

previous section: the understanding of an environment that influences the way we experience it. It

also consists of an evolving sense of what one finds aesthetically stimulating and the qualitative

aesthetic response to the object will therefore constantly evolve as well. The German philosopher

Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten (1714-1762) called this phenomenon cognitio sensitiva; there is

- 41 -

something in the experience of beauty that compels us to dwell upon the individual experience itself

(Gadamer, 1977).

The continuation of the semantic analysis leads us to a third use of the word aesthetic, which

stems from the reference to the theoretical and philosophical theories of aesthetic criticism in the

arts – aesthetical philosophy – which only emerged as a philosophical discipline (founded by

Baumgarten) during the age of rationalism in the eighteenth century (Gadamer, 1977).9 For the

purpose of this thesis it is best to analyse the scholarly discussion about the aesthetic appreciation of

nature which started around the time that, under the influence of Romanticism, people became

highly interested in the natural world. New present day insights that leave aesthetic appreciation in

favour of aesthetic experience, relate this experience not only to nature but to all-comprehensive

environments (such as Noord-Holland), and open the way for the conceptualization of lay people’s

perception of environment, come forth out of this discussion (Berleant, 2012b; 2012c; 2012f).

Aesthetic appreciation of nature started developing by the work of British and Scottish

philosophers such as Shaftesbury (Anthony Ashley Cooper, 1671-1713), Francis Hutcheson (1694-

1746) and Edmund Burke (1729-1797). It was then solidified by the work of Kant; his was the idea to

disentangle the objects of appreciation and the perceiver from interests – such as the personal, the

possessive, and the economic – with a method that he called ‘disinterestedness’ (Carlson and

Berleant, 2004). Disinterestedness simply signifies the characteristic feature of aesthetic behaviour

that forbids us to inquire after the purpose served by art (Gadamer, 1977). For Kant, aesthetic

appreciation was about experiencing the object with pleasure or displeasure. It follows that a

qualitative response to an object is aesthetic only if it is determined by the pleasurable of

unpleasurable nature of this experience (Budd, 1998a; Berleant, 2012e). The method of

disinterestedness resulted in a rich tradition of landscape appreciation; not only domesticated, rural

countrysides could be appreciated as beautiful, but even the wildest of natural environments could

now be appreciated as sublime (Budd, 1998b).

In between the two extremes of the beautiful and the sublime another mode of aesthetic

appreciation developed: picturesque appreciation. The picturesque (translated as ‘picture-like’)

mode in particular facilitated the aesthetic appreciation of the picture-like properties of sensuous

surface and formal composition. Tourists even used to pursue picturesque scenery with the help of

the ‘Claudeglass’, a small, tinted, convex mirror that helped to see the landscape as they would art

(Carlson, 2004; Berleant, 2012a). In a contemporary guidebook to the Lake District:

“Where the objects are great and near, it removes them to a due distance, and shews them in the soft colours of nature, and most regular perspective the eye can perceive, art teach, or science demonstrate …; to the glass is reserved the finished picture, in highest colouring, and just perspectives.” (Thomas West’s guidebook cited in Carlson, 2004, p. 67)

- 42 -

Ultimately, under influence of eighteenth century disinterestedness theory, landscapes became

firmly embedded into beauty discourse with formalistic picturesque appreciation as the favoured

mode of appreciation (Carlson and Berleant, 2004).

During the mid-twentieth century both disinterestedness and the formalistic picturesque

mode of aesthetic appreciation began to be rejected with the development of the expressionist

theory of art and the rejection reached its climax with the development of the later institutional

theory of art. Both art theories together would generate a paradigmatic shift in the art world: the old

idea of disinterested contemplation of the sensuous and formal properties of isolated and solitary

objects was discarded in favour of a more emotionally and cognitively rich engagement with cultural

artefacts that are intentionally created by designing intellects, and are informed by both historical

tradition and art critical practices.10 As a result the aesthetic appreciation of the natural world was

left behind; in the beginning of the new paradigm aesthetic appreciation was limited only to art

(Berleant, 2012b). Subsequently, as remnants of the old paradigm, landscape architects,

environmental planners and landscape assessors still tended to focus on sensuous and formal

properties of scenery. The urgent need for a new mode of aesthetic appreciation of nature became

apparent (Carlson and Berleant, 2004).

3.3 Towards the aesthetic experience A 1966 essay by the Scottish philosopher Ronald Hepburn (1927-2008) – appropriately titled

“Contemporary aesthetics and the neglect of natural beauty” – preluded the long awaited

paradigmatic shift in the appreciation of the natural world. Besides the fact that for most people it is

impossible to eliminate personal interests and already present knowledge when aesthetically

appreciating nature, Hepburn argued that some features in the natural world are actually sources for

a different kind of aesthetic experience: since nature is not constrained by designing intellects, art

historical traditions and art critical practices, it facilitates an open, engaging, and creative mode of

perception. Besides the two extremes of the single object (i.e. a tree) and the consideration of nature

as a unity – ‘the whole’ – there are a number of additional levels, compared to the aesthetics of art,

on which nature can be aesthetically experienced. Hepburn amongst others named the

contemplation of a natural object in spatial or interpretative context; the humanizing and

spiritualizing of nature; and the emotional quality of natural objects (Hepburn, 2004). This realization

is somewhat akin to Meinig’s ‘beholding eye’: as in the imagination of landscapes, the appreciation of

nature depends on the aesthetic mode with which the perceiver experiences, which, in turn, partly

depends on knowledge.

- 43 -

Building on these findings, the Finnish philosopher Allen Carlson introduced the ‘natural

environment model’ in 1979. Carlson posed that, despite the start of a new paradigm, there still

existed two inadequate models for the aesthetic experience of nature that were inappropriate given

‘the nature of the natural environment’. First, he argued, the object model is inappropriate for it

requires to remove the object from its environment. Even when the object is appreciated just for

what it is (i.e. a rock), contemplative removal from its context and thus conversion into art is

inevitable. Or as Carlson writes: there is a “distinction between appreciating nature and appreciating

the objects of nature” (Carlson, 2004, p. 65). Second, the landscape model – still directly linked to the

idea of the picturesque – encourages the perceiver to appreciate nature as if it were a painting: a

representation from a specific standpoint and distance. It is inappropriate for the natural

environment is not a scene, representation, static, or two-dimensional; the model not only limits – as

does the object model – but misleads (Carlson, 2004). The natural environment model offers a way

of experiencing instead of appreciating and is in line with the theorization of environment at the start

of this chapter:

“It involves recognizing that nature is an environment and thus a setting within which we exist and that we normally experience with our complete range of senses as our unobtrusive background. But for our experience to be aesthetic, this unobtrusive background must be experienced as obtrusive foreground. The result is the experience of a ‘blooming, buzzing confusion’, which in order to be appreciated must be tempered by the common sense and scientific knowledge that we have discovered about the natural environment so experienced.” (Carlson, 2004, p. 72)

The aesthetic experience is not distanced at all; if environments are three dimensional spaces

we must experience them as obtrusive foregrounds instead of two dimensional images of landscape

that are appreciated as unobtrusive backgrounds. Moreover, Carlson strongly emphasises the part of

knowledge in experiencing natural environments ‘on their own terms’. Indeed, not only scientific

(expert) knowledge suffices, but ‘common sense’ can be called upon to make sure that the aesthetic

experience is appropriate for the environment experienced: “We must have a consummatory

experience: one in which knowledge and intelligence transform raw experience by making it

determinate, harmonious, meaningful” (Carlson, 2004, p. 72). The aesthetic experience of nature

became – according to theory – more and more accessible for lay people. However, the emphasis

was still on ‘the right knowledge for the right environment’ whereas the other side of the vernacular

aesthetic experience – emotion and intuition – lacks a conscious mode of perception and is more

intuitive. Would this be what Carlson wanted to indicate with the phrase ‘common sense’?

We will return to emotion and intuition later. First it is important to extract the above

insights and implement them into the notion of environment which we developed in the first section

of this chapter. After all, Noord-Holland consists not only of nature, but of human influenced areas as

- 44 -

well. Moreover, the areal ratio ‘natural’ to ‘human influenced‘ is not constant throughout the

province. It is therefore impossible to always possess the right knowledge for a ‘right’ aesthetical

experience. If the province, which as other all-comprehensive environments is a blend of nature and

human influence, is to be experienced ‘on its own terms’ it must be performed with the help of a

single mode of aesthetic experience that applies to all of our surroundings. This desire seems

paradoxical for at the same time it demands both theoretical generalization (a single mode) and

practical differentiation (‘on its own terms’). What we need, therefore, is a general aesthetical theory

that nonetheless accounts for the diversity of individual experience and divergent cultural factors in

our encounters with different blends of environment within a bigger space of environment such as

Noord-Holland.

The key to a more general aesthetic seems to be the movement in thought Carlson already

suggested – leaving the object as the centre of aesthetic appreciation for the experience of

perception. According to the American aesthetical philosopher Arnold Berleant the focus on

perception rather than the object allows for one and the same mode of aesthetic experience; for all

blended – natural and humanly influenced – environments. The underlying idea is that perceiving is

not just a visual act but a somatic engagement in an environment (Berleant, 2004; Van Etteger,

2016). In what he calls the aesthetics of engagement, Berleant envisions “a universal applicable

aesthetics based not on disinterestedness but on engagement”:

“What we grasp in the wilder states of nature we appreciate too in its more cultivated forms. Those environments where art and nature are deliberately fused, such as gardens […] The same fusion of art and nature occurs in modern architecture that is sensitive to its site, in urban planning that responds to geomorphological and geographical considerations, in site-specific sculpture, and in the design of urban parks. A single aesthetic applies to nature and to art because, in the final analysis, they are both cultural constructs, and so we are not talking about two things but about one.” (Berleant, 2004)

The aesthetic experience is not so much focused on the objects of environment as on their

engagement. With engagement Berleant means the act of perceiving in the form of active

participation. A universally applicable aesthetics is therefore literally an aesthetics of the universe: it

can be applied to any environment, no matter the degree of diversity or size.

Adopting the new ‘participatory aesthetics’ will not only change our aesthetic experience of

environments but the very nature of the experience (Berleant, 2004). We will enter environments

physically, immerse ourselves in their space. And at the same time we will use knowledge to better

understand and experience them. Gradually we will develop a qualitative aesthetic judgement about

the environment. Aesthetic experience eventually leading to an aesthetic judgement is a process that

demands consideration. An aesthetic judgement based on experience is therefore radically different

than an aesthetic judgement based on aesthetic preference; we can judge a picture of an

- 45 -

environment in a magazine in a matter of seconds, whereas we would have to physically travel

towards – and subsequently take time to consider – the environment in question to gain aesthetic

experience. The aesthetic experience is by definition erfahren and therefore conducted in situ.

3.4 Who is to aesthetically judge? Let us assume that the hermit of the previous chapter eagerly accepted our invitation to accompany

us to the mill. However, on the way over he told us that in his time in the woods he was only focused

on surviving and had never taken the time to aesthetically mature. The obvious question –

considering the above section – is whether or not the hermit is qualified to pass aesthetic judgement

on the mill’s environment. It is important to separate three issues this question brings to the fore.

First, and discussed before, anyone is able to pass aesthetic judgement without any prior aesthetic

experience in the specific environment for the validity of the judgement is not dependent on a

person’s familiarity with the objects in the environment but on familiarity with the act of

aesthetically experiencing. In other words: if we take a measure of the hermit’s judgement based on

aesthetic knowledge, we must measure the amount of aesthetic experience he obtained in the

surroundings of his cabin.

But wait a minute, the hermit told us that he gained no aesthetic experience whatsoever. The

previous section implied that to pass qualified aesthetic judgement a person must have had prior

aesthetic experiences: knowledge of the environment is ostensibly replaced by knowledge of the

aesthetic experience. We could therefore be inclined to deny the hermit his aesthetic conception,

and tell him that only we should aesthetically judge because of our prior aesthetic experience. Of

course that would be resembling a situation wherein expert aesthetic knowledge is the condition for

passing qualified aesthetic judgement. If we did, both we and the hermit would be under the

impression that by surviving in the woods – or not consciously practicing environmental aesthetics –

no aesthetic knowledge is acquired. Moreover, it is widely believed that a person who is not an

expert – is not being employed in the field of environmental aesthetics – is not qualified for he or she

has not aesthetically matured ‘the right way’ (Cold, 2001a; 2001b; Berleant, 2012d).

Too often ‘qualified’ is confused with ‘expert’. Therefore second, and building on the

previous issue, genuine aesthetic experiences in unfamiliar environments are not reserved for

experts, because aesthetic experience not necessarily needs expert aesthetic knowledge. An

aesthetics of engagement can be applied by anyone who is physically present in an environment. The

conditions for the aesthetic experience to be genuine is that we engage, participate, immerse

ourselves in the environment and that we experience what we perceive as an obtrusive foreground.11

- 46 -

Qualified aesthetic judgement is qualified because of these two conditions only. If we would explain

this to the hermit, he would probably sigh and enthusiastically tell us about moments he

encountered beauty in the forest. And at the same time he would realize that he has aesthetically

matured indeed; his aesthetic knowledge may have accumulated differently than expert aesthetic

knowledge – less consciously and emphasized – it is nonetheless aesthetic knowledge and it may

even be very valuable for it has not been influenced by expert training, other people’s opinions, or

further beauty discourses.

Still, the amalgamation of Carlson’s natural environment model and Berleant’s aesthetics of

engagement – as presented in the paragraphs above – requires aesthetic knowledge to ensure a

genuine aesthetic experience. But what about emotion and intuition? What if the hermit was

suddenly overwhelmed when facing the sight of the mill and his cognitive functions were suddenly

overtaken by pure emotion? Moreover and more generally, is it not the goal of most (landscape)

architects to play on people’s emotions; and is it not intuition – understanding without reasoning –

that sometimes inspires us towards positive aesthetic arousal? Are aesthetic experiences aroused by

emotion instead of supported by aesthetic knowledge not qualified to base aesthetic judgement on?

Yes they are, according to the well-known American philosopher Noël Carroll. Writing about

the aesthetic experience of nature he realizes that there is a longstanding practice which remains

untouched by Carlson’s natural environment model but needs not to be abandoned: being

emotionally moved as response to the perception of beauty in a natural environment. The key is not

scientific knowledge, common sense, or culture, but common human nature, or as Carroll writes:

“some of our emotional arousals to nature are bred in the bone” (Carroll, 2004, p. 96). An emotional

arousal is thus another kind of aesthetic experience in which we are moved, but our cognitions do

not mobilize the far more formal and recondite systemic knowledge described so far (Carroll, 2004).

This aesthetic experience is not less genuine though, for it meets the two posed conditions.

The hermit’s emotional aesthetic response to the mill therefore qualifies as a genuine

aesthetic experience. However, in what manner can we pass aesthetic judgement based on emotion?

It would not be supported by aesthetic knowledge, would be merely intuitive, and therefore hard to

support with arguments or even to explain. Carroll overcomes this problem with the so-called

‘arousal model’ which is based on the appropriateness of the emotion. For instance, if the hermit

becomes happy (assuming that he was neutral in his emotions before) seeing the mill that is

appropriately only if he is positively aroused by its perception. Finding the mill beautiful would thus

be a valid reason to be happy. However, if the hermit perceives the mill as uncanny, but still becomes

happy, it would be inappropriate. And then, if the emotion of happiness is appropriate – true – for

others as well, we could speak of an objective emotional response (i.e. objective for its

- 47 -

collectiveness; ‘similarity in subjectivity’) (Carroll, 2004). Therefore third, an objective emotional

aesthetic response qualifies to base aesthetic judgement on.

Through an analysis of the aesthetic experience we are apparently back to the subject of

objectivity and subjectivity. To avoid confusion let us disentangle the two different

objectivity/subjectivity discussions immediately. While the discussion of the previous chapter was

related to the development of aesthetic preference formed due to all kinds of beauty

representations, and subsequently to the susceptibility of aesthetic preference to beauty discourse,

is the discussion in this chapter related to the objectivity of an aesthetic judgement based on

emotions that are aroused by a real-life aesthetic experience. Further, although images perceived

with the eyes and off the screen can nonetheless evoke emotion; these emotions are aroused by a

two dimensional beauty representation – when talking about landscape the most related to the

picturesque mode of appreciation – and not by a genuine aesthetic experience in an environment. It

goes without saying that the latter is viewed by many as the right aesthetic mode to base qualified

aesthetic judgement on.

3.5 Beauty discourse and the aesthetic experience of Noord-Holland Admittedly, not all of our emotional arousals in the face of nature should be ascribed to our common

human nature, rather than to what is sectarian in our cultures. In that light, the Canadian aesthetical

philosopher Thomas Heyd proposes to consider a diversity of stories or accounts – another form of

non-expert aesthetical knowledge – as our guides in aesthetic analyses to account for the fact that

people come from a great variety of walks of life and cultures (Heyd, 2004). With stories or accounts

is meant the stories and accounts of others, which with their richness in detail enhance the

possibilities for the play of the imagination while we aesthetically experience an environment. Heyd

distinguishes artistic stories (poems, novels, etc.); non-artistic stories (travel reports); and non-

verbally expressed stories (paintings, films, etc.).

These stories can be about actual places and could be connected to a geographical location.

Also, these stories and accounts are cultural constructs of which the details could be culturally

relative. At first sight Heyd seems therefore to be suggesting that a part of the aesthetic experience is

culturally relative. However, when we further analyse the idea of a story guiding us in our aesthetic

experience, it becomes clear that the author of the story merely describes his or her own aesthetic

experience. A description of a tree branching out will probably not incite you to go out and search for

that exact tree, it will rather encourage you to look up and admire the tree in front of you. Alike

subjective aesthetic preference, the culturally determined part of the aesthetic experience is

- 48 -

therefore not so much culturally relative as culturally contextual. The story does not guide towards a

specific object or a specific environment, but towards a ‘different flavour’ of the aesthetic experience

itself.

What has become clear about the aesthetic experience is that it does not depend on a single

kind of aesthetical knowledge, emotion, or story. To fully experience beauty in the environment of

Noord-Holland we must include what Cold has called the ‘total experience’: “perceptions of beauty

become integrated collections of aesthetic, social, cultural, and emotional impressions in the context

of a place and a situation which, in a ‘magic’ moment, merge and reinforce each other” (Cold, 2001b,

p. 90). However, we cannot avoid questioning the relative importance of the components that

together inform the aesthetic experience, and subsequently, the susceptibility of these components

to beauty discourse. Because of stories and accounts influencing our aesthetic experience by

mediating the aesthetic experiences of others, common sense pushes towards the suggestion that

cultural constructs such as these are only one of the many that inform the aesthetic experience.

This suggestion immediately begs the question whether or not our aesthetic experiences are

prone to be influenced by beauty discourse. No matter the character of the aesthetic experience, it

seems that the product of beauty discourse – ‘cognitive prejudice’ – is a most important factor:

“Contemporary cultural criticism, building on work that has been done over the past century, has shown how deeply and pervasively our cognitive preconceptions direct and color our experience and understanding. Despite perceptual sensitivity, a lively imagination, wide experience with aesthetic matters that extends beyond one’s native culture, and the educational background to focus and direct that experience, the influence of cognitive prejudice may be more pervasive and powerful still.” (Berleant, 2012a, p. 5)

Although I have been expecting it, this outcome is still surprising to me. As we have seen in the

previous chapter, beauty discourse is a key factor in the formation of subjective aesthetic preference.

Apparently aesthetic preference – yet another kind of aesthetic knowledge (‘cognitive prejudice’)

and gathered through all kinds of beauty representations, including two-dimensional images viewed

off the screen – is in turn believed to be heavily influencing the aesthetic experience. To refer back to

the hermit one last time: his aesthetic experience of the environment of the windmill would probably

be different than ours. More generally speaking; the aesthetic experience of someone who has not

been susceptible to beauty discourse will be different than the aesthetic experience of someone who

has.

What are the practical implications of the realization that we are being influenced by beauty

discourse during both the formation of aesthetic preference and the aesthetic experience, and,

moreover, that beauty discourse is indifferent whether or not you are an expert? Is the impact of

beauty discourse on both the formation of aesthetic preference and the aesthetic experience more

- 49 -

significant than the difference between them? What does that say about the difference between

expert’s and lay people’s aesthetic knowledge? And where does that leave us in terms of the

aesthetic experience of Noord-Holland in the wake of a possible break of beauty discourse? These

questions and their implications will be discussed in the next chapter, which shall form the synthesis

of all the previous subjects.

- 50 -

4 Concluding discussion

In the introduction I have described two societal developments that I noticed during my internship:

the Dutch design control sector going through a change of practice, and an increasing amount of

screen minutes we all daily live through. These developments, I posed, could result in societal

conditions that allow for a break of beauty discourse in the Netherlands. The line of reasoning was as

follows. First, if the design control sector yields aesthetic control to the people – democratizes the

oversight of environmental beauty in self-regard – the vernacular sense of environmental beauty will

become increasingly important in environmental decision-making and in the politics of

environmental beauty. Second, since ‘we the people’ spend more and more time looking at screens –

through which beauty representations are constantly mediated to us – the vernacular sense of

environmental beauty must increasingly being constructed by these beauty representations.

A simple reasoning, and merely meant to be the speculative framework for the main

research question of this thesis: how is our sense of environmental beauty being established, and in

the context of the described societal developments, what could that imply for the environmental

beauty of the future? Two common themes cut across the others. First, and coming forth out of the

first reason, the opposition between experts and lay people was investigated. Second, and relating to

the second reason, the concept of beauty discourse was invented to be able to analyse both our

susceptibility to – and the possible influence of – beauty discourse. The analysis was split into two

chapters representing two approaches to environmental beauty. In chapter 2 the establishment of

our sense of environmental beauty was approached through an investigation of the formation of

aesthetic preference. In chapter 3 the establishment of our sense of environmental beauty was

approached through an investigation of the aesthetic experience.

The distinction between aesthetic preference and aesthetic experience also roughly

coincided with the difference between being in front of a screen and being physically present in an

environment. What insights has this analysis produced? Because of the subject’s complexity and for

the sake of discussion a short summary will follow.

Looking at screens. We all do it ever more frequently. At the same time we (sub)consciously

adhere to what we see; we will inevitably come to aesthetically prefer the beauty representations

that are presented to us for a significant part of aesthetic preference is subjective. It has been

demonstrated that beauty discourses of various degrees of influence and at work on various societal

levels are heavily influencing our idea of beauty. Moreover, authority is being exercised through

beauty discourse – a social aspect. The collective (‘objective’) liking of certain environments turns out

- 51 -

to be rooted in both an evolutionary programmed biological aesthetic behaviour, and in a socially

learned cultural aesthetic behaviour. Whether a collective aesthetic preference is biologically

programmed or culturally learned is not always clear for beauty discourse can ‘objectify’ subjective

aesthetic preference. Also, it has become clear that in the formation of aesthetic preference by the

beauty representations of others the visual component of the perception of environmental beauty is

heavily emphasized.

This seems to be completely different when the environment in question is not a two-

dimensional screen but a three-dimensional space which we can physically enter. Nature, and with it

an evolving notion of landscape (ending up in the notion of environment), has been the reason for a

different approach to environmental aesthetics. By focusing on the aesthetic experience instead of

on objects or environments, we have found a general aesthetic theory that nonetheless accounts for

the diversity of individual experience and divergent cultural factors in confrontation with different(ly

composed) environments. The aesthetic experience is then based on a participatory aesthetics: we

somatically engage – and immerse ourselves in – the environment using multi-sensory perception,

(aesthetic) knowledge, and emotion. The aesthetic experience is by definition erfahren and

conducted in situ. An aesthetic judgement based on aesthetic experience is therefore radically

different from an aesthetic judgement based on an aesthetic preference that was formed by beauty

representations on a screen. Moreover, the new participatory aesthetics can be applied by anyone

and therefore breaks through the experts’ monopoly on environmental aesthetic judgement.

However, despite its radically different establishment, the aesthetic experience is still being heavily

influenced by beauty discourse.

The first part of the main research question has been answered by means of the analyses in

this thesis. In what follows I will consider the second part of the main research question. Bearing the

above in mind, what could be the implications of a break of beauty discourse for the future notion of

environmental beauty in the Netherlands? As has been posed, the design control sector is going

through a change that could possibly result in future environmental beauty policy being increasingly

based on lay people’s aesthetic judgement. Moreover, expert aesthetic judgement will more and

more be considered in perspective to lay people’s aesthetic judgement. Vernacular beauty discourse

will therefore have an ever larger influence on future environmental planning.

In what is vernacular beauty discourse different than expert beauty discourse; i.e. what would an

increased environmental expression of vernacular beauty discourse entail? It seems that vernacular

beauty discourse and expert beauty discourse are to a great extent the same. That is not surprising

considering that experts participate in – and are prone to – the image culture that informs vernacular

beauty discourse too.

- 52 -

The conservative conception that experts can switch off the aesthetic preference they have

picked up from various beauty discourses – and therefore are better able to aesthetically judge with

a less biased perception – has been proven wrong. We are all susceptible to beauty discourse, both

in the formation of our aesthetic preference as during the aesthetic experience. Beauty discourse is

not only consciously but also unconsciously interwoven with our sense of environmental beauty.

Moreover, experts are not necessarily trained aestheticians. It is (often) a misconception that

professional education conditions to aesthetically experience the right way. Indeed, the experts in

the design control commissions who judge building applications are not employed for their

education, but for their aesthetic Erfahrung which they built during their professional careers.

Due to beauty discourse having influence on both lay people and experts, it tends to

increasingly inspire designed environments. Vernacular beauty discourse is therefore increasingly the

beauty discourse of lay people and experts. Exemplary are designed environments that radiate the

same visual stimuli as environmental beauty representations do on the screen. The visual language of

the designs of, for instance, malls, airports, or expensive shopping districts, such as Fifth Avenue in

New York, is based on the same two-dimensional displays. Vernacular beauty discourse has

increasingly been expressed in environments for decades already. And that trend is expected to

continue for the amount of time we are exposed to two-dimensional beauty representations is

increasing as well.

The two-dimensional image culture is not only visible in urban environments but in the

construction of ‘nature’ as well. Nature is increasingly being framed as a product for tourist

consumption and is therefore advertised to be entertaining and attractive. These two-dimensional

beauty representations heavily influence the way we look at natural environments. It seems that the

picturesque mode of appreciation has never disappeared and is – with an increasing amount of

screen minutes – more being applied than ever. Indeed, the collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland is

exemplary for the continuation of the picturesque in contemporary image culture: three-dimensional

environments which were submitted for their beauty are for reasons of display reduced to two-

dimensional beauty representations.

If vernacular beauty discourse – causing the trend to look at environment as if it were a two-

dimensional beauty representation – is already so firmly embedded into society, what, then, are the

implications of an overall increase in screen minutes? An overall increasing amount of screen

minutes implies an increasing amount of time in which we are exposed to two-dimensional beauty

representations. We are therefore prone to be even more influenced by the image culture – not

because we are becoming more susceptible but simply due to the longer period of exposure. It must

be unambiguously stated that man has always been exposed to beauty discourse, ever since there

- 53 -

was a sense of beauty and the possibility of social contact. Also, exposure to two-dimensional beauty

representations has been around since the first images were mediated.

That being said, the amount of time spent in two-dimensional environments has been – and

still is – increasing since the beginning of public access to all sorts of screens. Whether or not an

increase of screen minutes results in a decrease of minutes spent in three-dimensional environments

is not clear. We can, however, deduct that two-dimensional environments are relatively pushing

forward. If this trend continues it could very well result in epistemological change; the circumstances

under which we get to know the beautiful (environment) are shifting. The posed conditions that

guarantee a genuine aesthetic experience (to engage, participate, physically immerse oneself in an

environment and to experience what we perceive as an obtrusive foreground) will therefore

generally less and less be met in the future.

Where does that leave us in terms of the future construction of our sense of environmental beauty

and, moreover, the very notion of environment itself? If the formation of our sense of environmental

beauty will be organized differently – will develop more and more by what is viewed on screens

rather than by real-life aesthetic experiences – we could be anticipating an upcoming break of beauty

discourse indeed: in the next épistème environmental beauty will predominantly be an expression of

a two-dimensional visual image culture. Subsequently, by seeing two-dimensional representations on

the screen and by getting used to their expression in real-life three-dimensional environments, we

will come to perceive of environment differently. Our comprehensive notion of what an environment

is will therefore be constructed differently.

It is here that the importance of the aesthetic experience in the fashion of the aesthetics of

engagement must be emphasized. In fact, all-comprehensive environments, such as Noord-Holland,

are essentially three-dimensional spaces that must be experienced in the fashion of the aesthetic of

engagement. As has been analysed above, however, the aesthetics of engagement is a new

participatory aesthetics that even experts not necessarily apply. Their application is a method – a

mode of aesthetically experiencing – that is not yet widely embraced. Instead, the picturesque mode

of aesthetic appreciation – connected to the visual two-dimensional character of the image culture –

has been around for ages and is expected to become the dominant environmental beauty discourse

in the near future. We are therefore on the verge of fully institutionalizing a mode of aesthetic

appreciation that is unfit for the aesthetic experience of environment.

We should go the other way and institutionalize an experiential aesthetics instead. This is not

meant to be a direct recommendation for the design control sector (since the sector’s issues are

mainly an administrative matter and therefore not in my area of expertise), but rather a

recommendation for anyone who is concerned with environmental beauty. Academics, in particular,

- 54 -

should lead the way by conducting more interdisciplinary research on environmental aesthetics –

connecting theoretical disciplines such as aesthetical philosophy to the more practical domains of

design and administration – and by introducing these new insights into the professional sector and to

the rest of society.

Society’s potential is high for anyone is able to aesthetically experience in the fashion of the

aesthetics of engagement. As far as can be argued, it is aesthetic zest in general that incites people to

go out and immerse themselves in any environment. To end this discussion, I want to share two

observations that may offer leads for the future. First, there is something extraordinary about the

environments we directly live in, our habitats. It is the association of these environments with the

notion of place, the aesthetics of everyday life, that automatically leads to a more engaged

aesthetical experience. If any, these are the environments in which we participate and in which we

should be able to apply a participatory aesthetics. People’s aesthetic experience of their direct

environments should be subject to further research for these experiences may hold the key for the

encouragement of a genuine vernacular aesthetical experience.

Second, people can be taught to experience environments as obtrusive foregrounds

relatively easy. I lively remember the first day of an excursion to The Ardennes when I was studying

earth sciences. One of the teachers told us that from then on we would never look at outcrops (bare

rock) the same way; from then on we would always be perceiving geological layers, foliation, and

degrees of metamorphism. Although his speech felt a little weightily at the time, he could not have

been more right: outcrops have never been an unobtrusive background to me again. In regard to the

aesthetic experience of environment it must be the same. Having learned to aesthetically experience

in the fashion of the aesthetics of engagement, you will probably never lose that ability.

When one betakes oneself to the domain of aesthetical philosophical speculation it is all too easy to

get lost. In this thesis it has been attempted to remain scholarly and to limit speculation to the

discussion. Although this research has provided me with so many new insights, it has at the same

time evoked even more questions. Some of these are the questions I started my research with (being

a Heritage and Memory Studies student): the issues I encountered led me in another direction. In my

opinion this thesis’ issues are the necessary steps towards a subsequent part of research that would

inter alia be based on the original questions. Beauty discourse is indeed connected to the heritage

canon – heritage discourse – for their mechanisms, depending on perception, are akin. I would point

the focus of contingent future research towards the following subjects, which are moreover closely

related:

- 55 -

The politics of beauty. Is it important to live in a beautiful environment? Are there people

that profit from this widely endorsed conviction? Who are those people?

Environmental beauty’s connection to identity. What is the importance of beautiful

environments in the performance of place-based social identities? And the other way

around: to what extent does place-based social identity ‘beautify’ environments?

Following the Australian professor of Heritage Studies Laurajane Smith’s notion of

Authorized Heritage Discourse (AHD), which exposes the predisposition of heritage

professionals for tangible, elite ‘heritage’ and the associated widespread belief that heritage

can only be properly interpreted by experts; what are the differences and similarities with

this thesis’ results? Moreover, what would be the importance of beauty discourse both in the

process of heritagization and in the conservation of the heritage canon? Do we live in a

‘heritage bubble’?

There are a lot of studies that have analysed heritage value typologies. Fredheim (2016) has

provided us with an overview.12 In almost all of these studies aesthetics are a factor in the

construction of heritage value. Is beautiful heritage valued differently than heritage that is

not beautiful? Is heritage excluded that is valuable but not for its beauty?

- 56 -

Notes

1 Translated from Dutch (Interview with B (architect) and O (client) conducted on

March 7th 2016):

Primo “Hadden jullie liever het originele plan?”

B “Ja, maar we kunnen ons ook goed vinden in het herziene plan. We dachten eigenlijk

dat het originele plan op meer steun van de Welstand had kunnen rekenen, vandaar

dat we dat hadden ingediend.”

Primo “Vindt u het vervelend dat u rekening moet houden met de Welstand?”

O “Ik vind dat wel vervelend, maar in het grote geheel vind ik het wel logisch.”

Primo “Kunt u dat uitleggen?”

O “Ik ga liever m’n eigen gang, maar als we dat met z’n allen doen wordt het een

rommeltje.”

Primo “Denken jullie dat als het plan eerder voor de commissie was gekomen, er eerder

een akkoord was bereikt?”

B “Ja. Ik heb met eerdere plannen gehad dat ik vragen kon stellen aan de gemeente. Zo

kan je sneller voldoen aan de geschreven en ongeschreven eisen van de Welstand.”

2 On the occasion of the 18th Jan Wilslezing which was held in Alkmaar on 02-12-2016. 3 Foucault defined two épistèmes: Classical (1650-1800) and Modern (1800-

undefined). At the time of writing – 1966 – Foucault anticipated a break of discourse. 4 Mythological story told in Plato’s Phaedrus. 5 Translated from Dutch: “Mooi reserveer ik uitsluitend voor die uitingen waarbij ik

wordt aangesproken door het wereldbeeld, wanneer dat het mijne versterkt of verruimt.” (Eerhart, 1980, p. 32)

6 The collection and the submission form are still online and can be viewed at www.collectiemooi.nl. The collection was developed in co-operation with Rob van Leeuwen.

7 Bourassa writes about modes of ‘aesthetic experience’. In this thesis, however, aesthetic preference and aesthetic experience are disentangled for the first calls upon cultural, biological and personal factors that lead to the behaviour itself and the second calls upon the exhibition of this behaviour in the context of real environments. The distinction is between the conceptualization of experience as being accumulated knowledge and being an act.

8 Articulated by Tadhg O’Keeffe during a lecture he gave at the University of Amsterdam on 12-4-2015.

9 Note that aesthetics as a discipline is a prime example of beauty discourse for since its conception it has defined rules that describe how to appreciate and, what to appreciate, and in the case of landscape even to appreciate.

10 A paradigm indeed for the shift occurred within a discipline and did not generally effect lay people’s epistemological relationship with beauty.

11 Sometimes the engagement during the aesthetic experience is the source of the perception of beauty. In the collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland are included some hundred submissions of children around the age of eleven (not used for the analysis

- 57 -

in chapter 2), and it seems that for them the possibility to be active in the environment not only characterizes the aesthetic experience, but the very perception of beauty itself.

12 Fredheim, L., M. Khalaf. (2016). “The significance of values: heritage value typologies re-examined”. International Journal of Heritage Studies 22 (6), pp. 466-481.

13 Translated from Dutch: “Het verschil tussen de inzendingen zal groot zijn: van bankje, brug, voordeur, huis, kantoor, stal, tot plein, erf en landschap. Alle inzendingen worden op de website geplaats. Het is geen competitie – de collectie bestaat uit louter topstukken. Met de toelichting creëert de curator van OVERMOOI tags waarmee deelcollecties kunnen worden gemaakt […]. Elke inzending draagt daar aan bij; de collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland is een museum met vele routekaarten en steeds meer zalen.” (MOOI Noord-Holland, 2016)

- 58 -

References

Berg, A.E. van den, S.L. Koole. (2006). “New wilderness in the Netherlands: an investigation of visual preferences for nature development landscapes”. Landscape and Urban Planning 78, pp. 362-372.

Berleant, A. (2004). “The aesthetics of art and nature”. In: A. Carlson and A. Berleant (eds.). The aesthetics of natural environments. Toronto: Broadview Press Ltd., pp. 76-88.

Berleant, A. (2012a). “Judging architecture”. In: A. Berleant (ed.). Aesthetics beyond the arts. New and recent essays. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 3-15.

Berleant, A. (2012b). “Art, nature, environment”. In: A. Berleant (ed.). Aesthetics beyond the arts. New and recent essays. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 39-46.

Berleant, A. (2012c). “The art in knowing a landscape”. In: A. Berleant (ed.). Aesthetics beyond the arts. New and recent essays. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 67-79.

Berleant, A. (2012d). “Scenic beauty in a global context”. In: A. Berleant (ed.). Aesthetics beyond the arts. New and recent essays. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 81-94.

Berleant, A. (2012e). “Aesthetics without purpose”. In: A. Berleant (ed.). Aesthetics beyond the arts. New and recent essays. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 149-158.

Berleant, A. (2012f). “The changing meaning of landscape”. In: A. Berleant (ed.). Aesthetics beyond the arts. New and recent essays. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 195-204.

Berleant, A. (2012g). “Beauty and the way of modern life”. In: A. Berleant (ed.). Aesthetics beyond the arts. New and recent essays. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 205-212.

Bernasconi, R. (1986). “Editor’s introduction”. In: R. Bernasconi (ed.). The relevance of the beautiful and other essays. New York: Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge, pp. xi-xxi.

Bourassa, S.C. (1990). “A paradigm for landscape aesthetics”. Environment and Behavior 22 (6), pp. 787-812.

Bremer, J.T. (2004). “Johannes Henricus van Foreest (1825-1895). Landbouwpionier in de Anna Paulownapolder”. In: J. Drewes, R. van der Eerden-Vonk, H. Kaptein, L. Noordegraaf, C. Streefkerk (eds.). Alkmaar, stad en regio. Alkmaar en omgeving in de Late Middeleeuwen en Vroegmoderne Tijd. Hilversum: Uitgeverij Verloren, p. 227-244.

Budd, M. (1998a). “Natural beauty”. The British Journal of Aesthetics 38(2), pp. 1-18.

Budd, M. (1998b). “The sublime in nature”. The British Journal of Aesthetics 38(2), pp. 233-250.

- 59 -

Carlson, A. (2004). “Appreciation and the natural environment”. In: A. Carlson and A. Berleant (eds.). The aesthetics of natural environments. Toronto: Broadview Press Ltd., pp. 63-75.

Carlson, A., Berleant, A. (2004). “Introduction: the aesthetics of nature”. In: A. Carlson and A. Berleant (eds.). The aesthetics of natural environments. Toronto: Broadview Press Ltd., pp. 11-42.

Carroll, N. (2004). “On being moved by nature: between religion and natural history”. In: A. Carlson and A. Berleant (eds.). The aesthetics of natural environments. Toronto: Broadview Press Ltd., pp. 89-107.

Cold, B. (2001a). “Aesthetics, well-being and health”. In: B. Cold (ed.). Aesthetics, well-being and health. Essays within architecture and environmental aesthetics. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 11-23.

Cold, B. (2001b). “Beauty”. In: B. Cold (ed.). Aesthetics, well-being and health. Essays within architecture and environmental aesthetics. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 67-92.

De Botton, A. (2006). The architecture of happiness. London: Hamish Hamilton, pp. 307.

Dovey, K. (2001). “The aesthetics of place”. In: B. Cold (ed.). Aesthetics, well-being and health. Essays within architecture and environmental aesthetics. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 93-101.

Eerhart, B. (1980). Wat heet mooi? Beschouwingen over de ontwikkeling van architectuur en stedebouw na 1900. ’s-Gravenhage: Staatsuitgeverij, pp. 62.

Etteger, R. van. (2016). Beyond the visible. Prolegomenon to an aesthetics of designed landscapes. Wageningen: PhD thesis, pp. 250.

Foucault, M. (1966). The order of things. An archaeology of the human sciences. London: Tavistock Publications Limited, pp. 387.

Gadamer, H. (1977). “The relevance of the beautiful. Art as play, symbol, and festival”. ”. In: R. Bernasconi (ed.). The relevance of the beautiful and other essays. New York: Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge, pp. 3-53.

Groot, W.T. de, R.J.G. van den Born. (2003). “Visions of nature and landscape type preferences: an exploration in The Netherlands”. Landscape and Urban Planning 63, pp. 127-138.

Hayden, D. (1994). “The power of place. Claiming urban landscapes as people’s history”. Journal of Urban History 20 (4), pp. 466-485.

Hayden, D. (1995). The power of place. Urban landscapes as public history. London: The MIT press, pp. 296.

Hepburn, R. (2004). “Contemporary aesthetics and the neglect of natural beauty”. In: A. Carlson and A. Berleant (eds.). The aesthetics of natural environments. Toronto: Broadview Press Ltd., pp. 43-62.

- 60 -

Heyd, T. (2004). “Aesthetic appreciation and the many stories about nature”. In: A. Carlson and A. Berleant (eds.). The aesthetics of natural environments. Toronto: Broadview Press Ltd., pp. 269-283.

Howley, P. (2011). “Landscape aesthetics: assessing the general publics’ preferences towards rural landscapes”. Ecologial Economics 72, pp. 161-169.

Ingold, T. (2007). Lines. A brief history. New York: Routledge, pp. 186.

Ingold, T. (2012). “Introduction”. In: M. Janowski, T. Ingold (eds.). Imagining landscapes. Past, present and future. New York: Routledge, pp. 1-18.

Kalivoda, O., J. Vojar, Z. Skrivanová, D. Zahradník. (2014). ”Concensus in landscape preference judgements: the effects of landscape visual aesthetic quality and respondents’ characteristics”. Journal of Environmental Management 137, pp. 36-44.

Kaplan, R, S. Kaplan. (1989). The experience of nature. A psychological perspective. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 340.

Kolen, J. (2015). “Biographies of biotopes”. In: J. Kolen, J. Renes, R. Hermans (eds.). Landscape biographies. Geographical, historical and archaeological perspectives on the production and transmission of landscapes. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, pp. 71-98.

Levi, P. (1975). Het periodiek system. Verhalen van een leven. Amsterdam: Meulenhoff, pp. 236.

Maitland, S. (2008). Stilte als antwoord. Schiedam: Scriptum, pp. 320.

Meinig, D.W. (1979). “The beholding eye. Ten versions of the same scene”. In: D.W. Meinig (ed.). The interpretation of ordinary landscapes: geographical essays. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 33-48.

Muilwijk, H., Faber, A. (2015). Grenzen voorbij. Handelingsperspectieven in het Antropoceen. Den Haag: WRR, pp. 33.

Noordegraaf, L. (2004). “Droogmakerijen en bedijkingen in Noord-Holland (16e-19e eeuw). Financiën en economie”. In: J. Drewes, R. van der Eerden-Vonk, H. Kaptein, L. Noordegraaf, C. Streefkerk (eds.). Alkmaar, stad en regio. Alkmaar en omgeving in de Late Middeleeuwen en Vroegmoderne Tijd. Hilversum: Uitgeverij Verloren, pp. 51-64.

Reh, W. (1996). Arcadia en metropolis. Het landschapsexperiment van de verlichting. Delft: Publikatieburo Bouwkunde, pp. 515.

Reh, W., C. Steenbergen, D. Aten. (2005). Zee van land. De droogmakerij als atlas van de Hollandse landschapsarchitectuur. Wormer: Stichting Uitgeverij Noord-Holland, pp. 340.

Reh, W., D. Frieling, C. Weber. (2003). Delta Darlings. Uittreeredes van Reh, Frieling, Weber. Delft: Nivo, pp. 112.

- 61 -

Steenbergen, C., W. Reh, S. Nijhuis, M. Pouderoijen. (2009). De polderatlas van Nederland. Pantheon der Lage Landen. Bussum: Uitgeverij THOTH, pp. 639

Strumse, E. (2001). “Reasonable persons and their aesthetic preferences”. In: B. Cold (ed.). Aesthetics, well-being and health. Essays within architecture and environmental aesthetics. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 259-270.

Toorn, W. van. (1998). Leesbaar landschap. Amsterdam: Querido’s Uitgeverij, pp. 133. Vacker, B, W.R. Key. (1993). “Beauty and the beholder: the pursuit of beauty through commodities”. Psychology and marketing 10, pp. 471-494.

Westerman, A. (2001). “Buildings imagined as bodies”. In: B. Cold (ed.). Aesthetics, well-being and health. Essays within architecture and environmental aesthetics. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Company, pp. 290-302.

Zanten, B.T. van, I. Zasada, M.J. Koetse, F. Ungaro, K. Häfner, P.H. Verburg. (2016). “A comparative approach to aesthetic and recreational values in agricultural landscapes”. Ecosystem Services 17, pp. 87-98.

Primary sources:

Blom, B. (2016, March 7). Interview concerning Design Control; personally conducted.

Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland [www.collectiemooi.nl].

Keulemans, M. (2017, March 11). “Het zou dus kunnen dat het allemaal niet echt is”. Sir Edmund, pp. 8-13.

MOOI Noord-Holland. (2017). 10 over MOOI. Alkmaar: MOOI Noord-Holland, pp. 9.

Unknown. (2016, December 3). “Schoonheidstest”. Sir Edmund, pp. 78-79.

Figures:

Figure 1 (http://isites.harvard.edu) Description: “Do It Yourself Architectural Dialogue. Table mockingly suggesting that it enables lay people to speak ‘architect’.” Figure 2 (Morgan Stanley Research, 2014) Description: “Global shipments of desktops, notebooks, smartphones, and tablets between 1999 and

2013. Data by NPD Display Search (2004-2013 data) and Philips (1999-2003 data).”

Figure 3 (Milward Brown AdReaction, 2014) Description: “Average screen minutes in 2014. Survey asked respondents “Roughly how long did you spend yesterday… watching television (not online) / using the internet on a laptop or PC / on a smartphone or tablet?”. Survey respondents were age 16-44 across 30 countries who owned or had access to a TV and a smartphone and/or tablet. The population of the 30 countries surveyed in the study collectively represent ~70% of the world population.”

- 62 -

Figure 4 (Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland, www.collectiemooi.nl) Description: “Nature and Water. Nieuwe Hondsbossche Duinen – Schagen.”

Figure 5 (Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland, www.collectiemooi.nl) Description: “Polder and Meadow. Mijzen Polder, Ursem – Koggenland.”

Figure 6 (Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland, www.collectiemooi.nl) Description: “Treeline and Bulbs. Venhuizen – Drechterland.”

Figure 7 (Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland, www.collectiemooi.nl) Description: “Windmill and Dike. Oostdijk – Heerhugowaard.”

Figure 8 (Kaplan and Kaplan, 1989) Description: “The Preference Matrix. Landscape characteristics that determine the availability of information.”

Figure 9 (Own creation, created on 23-04-2017) Description: “Graph schematically displaying the three domains of aesthetic behaviour and indicating which domain is susceptible to discourse.”

Figure 10 (MOOI Noord-Holland, 2016) Description: “Map of Noord-Holland showing its diverse landscape. The classification is decided on by Rob van Leeuwen and of course arbitrary: (1) dunes and sand-ridges; (2) aandijkingen (polders), ‘De Noordkop’; (3) marine clays, ‘West-Friesland’; (4) moraine, partly covered by sand, ‘‘t Gooi’; (5) peat bogs; (6) reclamations.”

Figure 11 (www.ifthenisnow.eu) Description: “Map of De Beemster of 1658.”

Figure 12 (www.regiocanons.nl) Description: “Map of the Anna Paulownapolder by H.P. Eskes (1856). Natural features as the Oude Veer and the shape of the surrounding polders clearly shaped the polder-design.”

- 63 -

Appendix A

The collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland was commissioned by MOOI Noord-Holland and created by the

landscape architect Rob van Leeuwen and myself. Our job was not only to give examples of

environmental beauty, but also to set examples that could later on be used by MOOI Noord-Holland

to advice customers. In spite of that agenda we tried to set up the collection as unbiased as possible.

The submission form – which is still online (www.collectiemooi.nl/inzendformulier-collectie) –

consists of three simple questions (what?; where?; why?) which were designed to leave as much

options open to the submitter as practically possible. The only two conditions for submission were

that the submitted exists or existed, and is or was visible from a position in public space. Heading the

submission form is this text:

“What is the most beautiful place (landscape, building, object) of the province Noord-Holland? This is an invitation to be a co-creator of the collection MOOI in Noord-Holland. Your object can be big or small, it can be a park or a garden, a shed or a canal. It can be a place which is just beautiful for its own characteristics, or a place that symbolizes what has been: a personal memory or our collective history. But it can be something of the future too, something new that should be a trendsetter in the years to come.” (Collectie MOOI in Noord-Holland, www.collectiemooi.nl)

It is important to note that the submitters probably all had visited their places of beauty prior to

submission. Although the images they submitted are two-dimensional beauty representations, the

aesthetic experience of the submitters that led to submission probably meets the conditions for a

genuine aesthetic experience as defined in chapter 3.

After submission the submitted places of beauty were published online. However, before we

did, they were complemented with ‘tags’ (i.e. keywords connected to the image) by the use of which

a great many sub-collections can be created by the visitor of the online collection. In the project plan

we wrote:

“There will be great difference between submissions: from a bench, a bridge, a front door, a house, an office, and stables, to a square, a courtyard, and a landscape. Without exception the submissions will be published online. It is not a competition – the collection solely consists of showpieces. On basis of the explanation and the image that go with the submission, the curator of OVERMOOI creates tags with which sub-collections can be selected […]. Every submission is therefore important; the collection MOOI in Noord-Holland is a museum with many route maps and ever more rooms.”

13 (MOOI Noord-Holland,

2016)

It is important to note that by the creation of tags, categories were consciously created as well. Is

that bias? I think not for the tags were created – and multiple times revised – according to what was

submitted. The categories of ‘nature’, ‘water’, ‘polder’, ‘meadow’, ‘treeline’, ‘bulbs’, ‘windmill’, and

‘dike’ – which are the titles of the in chapter 2 presented images – are thus coming forth out of what

was submitted.

- 64 -

Is this categorization influenced by beauty discourse then? Yes it is. The tags were created on

basis of what we saw in the images. It can therefore not be denied that the categories are the result

of our personal mode of perception. As has become clear in this thesis perception is consciously and

unconsciously being influenced by beauty discourse. Moreover, by creating the tags on basis of what

was viewed on the screen, we participated in the two-dimensional image culture that has inter alia

been analysed in this thesis. Although the tags were not created to categorize beauty (but merely the

contents of environment – the objects and their associations), we still invented them on basis of the

perception of two-dimensional environments. It is therefore all the more possible that when we

would have visited the submitted environments in person, the system of tags and the resulting

categories would have been different. However, it must be noted that the ‘results’ of the collectie

MOOI in Noord-Holland are in this thesis appropriated to compare them with the results of

environmental preference studies. These studies were conducted in the same fashion: by showing

people two-dimensional images of landscape and by asking them which ones they aesthetically

preferred (Howley, 2011; Kalivoda et al., 2014; Strumse, 2001).