Legitimacy in Deliberative Democracy.pdf

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/23/2019 Legitimacy in Deliberative Democracy.pdf

    1/18

    Legitimacy Problems in

    Deliberative Democracy

    John Parkinson

    Australian National University

    The classic accounts of deliberative democracy are also accounts of legitimacy: that outcomes are

    legitimate to the extent they receive reflective assent through participation in authentic delibera-

    tion by all those subject to the decision in question (Dryzek, 2001, p. 651). And yet, in complex

    societies deliberative participation by allthose affected by collective decision-making is extremely

    implausible. There are also legitimacy problems with the demanding procedural requirements

    which deliberation imposes on participants. Given these problems, deliberative democracy seems

    unable to deliver legitimate outcomes as it defines them.

    Focusing on the problem of scale, this paper offers a tentative solution using representation, a

    concept which is itself problematic. Along the way, the paper highlights issues with the legitimate

    role of experts, the different legitimate uses of statistical and electoral representation, and differ-

    ences between the research and democratic imperatives driving current attempts to put delibera-

    tive principles into practice, illustrated with a case from a Leicester health policy debate. While

    much work remains to be done on exactly how the principles arrived at might be transformed

    into working institutions, they do offer a means of criticising existing deliberative practice.

    Since democracy theory took a deliberative turn just over a decade ago (Dryzek

    2000, p. v), theorists and practitioners from starkly contrasting traditions have

    applied the deliberative label to everything from radical democracy in the

    public sphere, to consultative forums engaged with the state, to representative

    assemblies, to the determination of public reason by small groups of jurists,

    even to the internal processes of making others present in an individuals own

    deliberations.1

    And yet, despite the bewildering variety of theoretical starting points, deliberative

    democracy does have a core set of propositions that distinguish it from its rivals.

    The essentials are its insistence on some form of inter-personal reasoning as the

    guiding political procedure, rather than bargaining between competing interests;

    the idea that the essential political act the giving, weighing, acceptance or rejec-

    tion of reasons is a public act, as opposed to the purely private act of voting

    (Elster, 1997); and the point that it is democratic deliberation, not deliberation

    without modifier, despite some undemocratic usages of the term. Democratic

    deliberation should somehow embody the essential democratic principles of

    responsiveness to public wishes and the political equality of every member of that

    public (Beetham, 1994, pp. 2631; May, 1978).

    In order to secure genuine deliberation such that no force except that of the betterargument is exercised (Habermas, 1975, p. 108), participants must meet a set of

    procedural conditions which minimally include communicative competence reci

    POLITICAL STUDIES: 2003 VOL 51, 180196

  • 7/23/2019 Legitimacy in Deliberative Democracy.pdf

    2/18

    LEGITIMACY PROBLEMS IN DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY 181

    procity, and inclusiveness (Cohen, 1989; Gutmann and Thompson, 1996), and a

    willingness to be persuaded, to have ones pre-formed preferences transformed in

    the face of a better argument, and thus to set aside strategic concerns and behav-

    iour in the pursuit of those preferences (Dryzek, 2000, p. 2). These procedural fea-

    tures make deliberation much more than mere talk it is a very particular kind of

    public talk. This point is often missed by writers who label as deliberative practices

    which exhibit none of the procedural conditions of genuine deliberation (for

    example, Button and Mattson, 1999). Often this is a function of scale: beyond a

    very small number of participants (certainly fewer than 20) deliberation breaks

    down, with speech-making replacing conversation and rhetorical appeals replac-

    ing reasoned arguments (Goodin, 2000, p. 83n) although I will return to discuss

    rhetoric later. Thus there is very little in mass public communication, including a

    great deal of media debate, large-scale referendum processes, or even public meet-

    ings, which merits the label deliberative (Parkinson, 2001).

    There is a further feature of deliberative democracy which is common to those for-

    mulations which take the democracy modifier seriously. Deliberative democracy

    is also an account of legitimacy, that outcomes are legitimate to the extent they

    receive reflective assent through participation in authentic deliberation by all those

    subject to the decision in question (Dryzek, 2001, p. 651).2 But if we accept that

    classic formulation, then there is a contradiction at the heart of deliberative de-

    mocracy. Because the deliberation of all those subject to a decision or regime is

    impossible (Goodin, 2000, p. 82), deliberative democratic practices cannot deliver

    legitimate outcomes as the theory defines them.

    This is deliberative democracys scale problem deliberative decisions appear to beillegitimate for those left outside the forum, while bringing more than a few people

    in would quickly turn the event into speech-making, not deliberation. It also has

    a legitimacy problem to do with motivations. In order for genuine deliberation to

    take place, those participants who do make it into the forum must meet the

    minimal procedural conditions set out above, including the demands of reciproc-

    ity and willingness to set aside strategic concerns. And yet, peoples pre-formed

    preferences, interests and goals are an essential part of what motivates them to

    enter political arenas in the first place (Rawls, 1996, p. 82). If deliberative democ-

    racy rules those interests out of court, it may seem to people that deliberative

    democracy is procedurally unfair, and thus illegitimate. To take a concrete example,in order to advance her beliefs, why would a religious fundamentalist enter the

    deliberative spirit of toleration of plural truths at all, when to enter that spirit

    means she must abandon her belief in a unitary, revealed truth (Shapiro, 1999,

    pp. 301)?

    In this article I primarily explore the scale problem. After clarifying the concept of

    legitimacy, I survey and find wanting the very few solutions offered so far. I then

    focus on the legitimacy of representation as one step towards overcoming the scale

    problem. The second step is to take a broader view of the deliberative forum,

    drawing on the concept of the deliberative system (Mansbridge, 1999) to imaginethe contribution that different moments in that system might make to overall

    legitimacy which I illustrate with a case from a health services debate in the

  • 7/23/2019 Legitimacy in Deliberative Democracy.pdf

    3/18

    182 JOHN PARKINSON

    The Concept of Legitimacy

    It is remarkable that while the term legitimacy crops up often in the democratic

    literature, it is rarely defined except by implication. In this section, I outline a con-

    ceptual map of legitimacy offered by Beetham (1991) to highlight those aspects

    which are not captured by the deliberative conception, aspects which offer us one

    step out of deliberations theoretical contradictions. While there is a great deal to

    Beethams scheme, for the purposes of this paper I want to draw out a few essen-

    tial features.

    At its most abstract level, legitimacy is the moralization of authority (Crook, 1987,

    p. 553), the moral grounds for obedience to power, as opposed to grounds of self-

    interest or coercion (Poggi, 1978, pp. 1012). It is only when decisions or regimes

    are legitimate in this way that those who refuse to accept them should be coerced

    into following them, on the grounds that their refusal is illegitimate. As well as

    value that springs from our moral convictions, legitimacy also has instrumentalvalue: legitimacy makes political processes more efficient by reducing the costs of

    enforcing compliance. Regimes, institutions or decisions with low legitimacy face

    higher costs associated with uncooperative, strategic behaviour.

    Beetham divides legitimacy into three separate conditions: legality, legitimacy, and

    legitimation. I find the repetition of the legitimacy label unhelpful and so refer to

    them as legality, justifiability and consent. Legality is the rules of the game, and

    is fairly uncontroversially subordinate to the other two, because the rules them-

    selves may be just or unjust according to some external standard. Legality includes

    not just the law of the land, but other rules as well, be they non-legislative regu-lations or social conventions. The rules of the game, whether they are individual

    decisions or the decision-making procedures themselves, need to have a certain

    amount of stability because people need to be able to learn the rules and use them

    if they are to be equally effective members of the polity; if the rules change all the

    time, only those who can bear the cost of re-learning the rules will be enfranchised.

    Thus legitimacy includes what Flathman (1972) calls a stability requirement.

    Legitimacy involves a balance between the deliberative ideal in which the rules

    themselves must be redeemable in discourse and the need to ensure that the rules

    are not up for grabs every single time.

    The next condition is justifiability, which Beetham divides into source norms and

    content norms. The source norms of justifiability concern the rightful source of

    authoritative decisions, which Beetham further divides into sources that are exter-

    nal and internal to society. External sources include appeals to divine command,

    natural law, even scientific doctrine; internal sources are society-as-it-was tradi-

    tion and society-as-it-is the people for whom the decisions are being taken.

    Given the liberal concern with the moral equality of persons, the most legitimate

    source of authoritative decisions is considered to be all those people affected, rather

    than tradition or external sources.3

    What Beetham calls content norms are, in part, about the legitimacy of the rulesfor dividing deciders and followers; thus, Beetham takes the fact of scale into

    account by including division rules in his account of legitimacy While this con

    1'/!(#)2-')34)(05%('!%&'!(4(!#2#)(!*%+(%/#(/6/!#78)+&!, 9%'%&'!(. :+!$'#;3#)2-')3%&'!(2'!"

  • 7/23/2019 Legitimacy in Deliberative Democracy.pdf

    4/18

    LEGITIMACY PROBLEMS IN DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY 183

    decision-making moments that is, a political elite there is nothing in this con-

    struction which suggests that deciders and followers always have to be the same

    from one decision moment to the next: one days deciders could be the next days

    followers. Rather, the important point is that these content norms boil down to

    legitimating divisions of responsibility on the grounds that those who decide rep-

    resent those who follow, that they express what Schaar (1984) calls mutuality,

    identification and co-performance with those who are led.

    The claim of common interest itself requires substantiation by leaders against two

    benchmarks: the degree to which policy outcomes match the substantive goals of

    the society in question; and the degree to which they achieve normatively justifi-

    able or desirable ends. Thus, legitimacy includes a concern about the ends of politi-

    cal life, not just its procedures Estlund (1997) provides a strong defence of a

    similar point. Beetham only goes so far as to give labels to these ends: freedom,

    equality, justice, as well as the mere (but essential) meeting of basic physical and

    emotional needs of life. He argues that in a fully legitimate polity the meanings ofthose terms will themselves be determined by the people in whose names they are

    invoked, although philosophy and other forms of expertise have a role in inform-

    ing the decision-making process, and criticising and challenging the results.

    Thus, for Beetham the knowers (philosophers, technical experts or bureaucrats)

    are subordinate to the people affected. In liberal democracies we tend to demand

    that those most able to serve the common good get leadership positions, and judge

    that ability partly in terms of expertise and experience; that is, we apply a meri-

    tocratic principle (Beetham, 1991, pp. 801). However, in liberal democracies we

    also tend to differentiate between the legitimate decision-making power of repre-sentatives and the more limited advisory power of experts on the basis that rep-

    resentatives derive their authority from the internal source of the people, while

    experts derive theirs from an external source which we regard as less legitimate,

    given the foundational respect for the equality of persons referred to above. In

    terms of deliberative ethics, this means that experts opinions have weight, but

    only in as much as they are offered in a process of public deliberation, and are

    found persuasive by those to whom they are offered, in a context in which the

    substantive goals of society are plural and essentially contested (see Dryzek, 1990,

    pp. 12632, for a similar discussion). The legitimacy of expertise is derived from

    the discursively determined ends of the people at large, and is not internal to ex-pertise itself.

    This leads us to the final element in Beethams scheme of legitimacy, the proce-

    dures by which the people consent to decisions or regimes. While traditionally

    political scientists have concentrated on acts of consent like voting, party mem-

    bership, interactions with elected representatives and interest group participation,

    now one would include a much wider range of participation in civil society, either

    directly oppositional or more collaborative (Jones and OToole, 2001). It is these

    procedures for the creation of public agreements that deliberative democracy is

    particularly concerned with.

    Because of the three-fold nature of legitimacy, it is important to emphasise that

    there is no magic line to draw between decisions or regimes that are clearly legit

    !"#$%&'!(#)insulation *)"*+),*!-).''/0')"'!

    B/!#78)+&!#)2-')"39%'%/>mutuality,identification /!performance, !