15
 1 23/06/15 André Laks Some thoughts about Empedoclean cosmic and demonic cycles 1 . in: A.L. Pierris (éd.), The Empedoclean Cosmos : Structure, Process and the Question of Cyclicity  (Proceedings of the Symposium Philosophiae Antiquae Tertium Myconense, 2003), Publication of the Institute for Philosophical Research, Conference Series, Vol. III, 2005, p. 265-282.  I take it that Empedocles presents us with two distinct, though related stories. The first story is that of the cosmos as a whole – I shall call it the cosmic story. The second story narrates the fate of some divinities which Empedocles calls daimones. This is the demonic story. I am not interested here in asking whether these two stories belong to the same poem or not. This question, though not trivial, is a relatively minor one, it seems to me, compared to whether these stories are distinct or not, and even more so, if so, how they are distinct. What I call distinct here refers to some basic or structural features of these two narratives, which  prevent them from collap sing into a single o ne or to be integrated into one another. A s a matter of fact, it might be useful to distinguish between two interpretative models, the integrative model, and the correspondence model 2 . For some reasons, which have to do with a set of definite expectations about what a philosophical system, and an archaic philosophical system at that, can or should be, the idea of correspondenc e is not one that most interpreters think with, even if they are not unitarian. This is the one I myself f avor not only because the data, incomplete and difficult as they are, seem to me to point in this direction, but also  because I think th is correspondenc e model can be seen, interestingly e nough, as a first expression –an archa ic, pre-conceptual expre ssion, so to speak-- of a move which was to  become a typica lly philosophical one , and which con sists in differentiating and articulating various fields or spheres of reality (the distinction between physics, ethics and for that matter dialectic also has a past). Of course, the question of distinction is an issue not least because there are strong similarities between the two stories. As a matter of fact, these similarities have provided the 1  The scholarly apparatus of this text, which was written to focus an overcomplicated debate by drawing attention to one single point, is deliberately reduced. Many thanks to Glenn W. Most for revising the English. 2  Primavesi 2001, p. 16, thus speaks in a programmatic way of an "integrazione della daimonologia nella fisica". His position is complicated by the distinction between two demonologies, the first esoteric (the integrated one), the second exoteric (see infra, p. **). In the latter case, Primavesi speaks of an "equivalente essoterico-populare" (p. 37). I am interested in what "equivalent" means.

Laks A. - Some Thoughts About Empedoclean Cosmic and Demonic Cycles - 2003

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Empedocles

Citation preview

  • 1 23/06/15

    Andr Laks

    Some thoughts about Empedoclean cosmic and demonic cycles1.

    in: A.L. Pierris (d.), The Empedoclean Cosmos : Structure, Process and the Question of Cyclicity (Proceedings of the Symposium Philosophiae Antiquae Tertium Myconense, 2003), Publication of the Institute for Philosophical Research, Conference Series, Vol. III, 2005, p. 265-282.

    I take it that Empedocles presents us with two distinct, though related stories. The first

    story is that of the cosmos as a whole I shall call it the cosmic story. The second story

    narrates the fate of some divinities which Empedocles calls daimones. This is the demonic

    story.

    I am not interested here in asking whether these two stories belong to the same poem or

    not. This question, though not trivial, is a relatively minor one, it seems to me, compared to

    whether these stories are distinct or not, and even more so, if so, how they are distinct. What I

    call distinct here refers to some basic or structural features of these two narratives, which

    prevent them from collapsing into a single one or to be integrated into one another. As a

    matter of fact, it might be useful to distinguish between two interpretative models, the

    integrative model, and the correspondence model2. For some reasons, which have to do with a

    set of definite expectations about what a philosophical system, and an archaic philosophical

    system at that, can or should be, the idea of correspondence is not one that most interpreters

    think with, even if they are not unitarian. This is the one I myself favor not only because the

    data, incomplete and difficult as they are, seem to me to point in this direction, but also

    because I think this correspondence model can be seen, interestingly enough, as a first

    expression an archaic, pre-conceptual expression, so to speak-- of a move which was to

    become a typically philosophical one, and which consists in differentiating and articulating

    various fields or spheres of reality (the distinction between physics, ethics and for that matter

    dialectic also has a past).

    Of course, the question of distinction is an issue not least because there are strong

    similarities between the two stories. As a matter of fact, these similarities have provided the

    1 The scholarly apparatus of this text, which was written to focus an overcomplicated debate by drawing attention to one single point, is deliberately reduced. Many thanks to Glenn W. Most for revising the English. 2 Primavesi 2001, p. 16, thus speaks in a programmatic way of an "integrazione della daimonologia nella fisica". His position is complicated by the distinction between two demonologies, the first esoteric (the integrated one), the second exoteric (see infra, p. **). In the latter case, Primavesi speaks of an "equivalente essoterico-populare" (p. 37). I am interested in what "equivalent" means.

  • 2 23/06/15

    basis for an extremely powerful Neoplatonic line of interpretation, represented above all in

    Hippolytus Refutation of all Heresies, VII, 29-31, where the two stories overlap thanks to an

    allegorical interpretation of the physical story in terms of the demonic story. It seems clear to

    me that we should not take this interpretation as a report (as C. Osborne did3), but this does

    not mean that the similarities on which the allegory relies are not crucial for assessing the

    relationship between the two stories. In fact, I would argue that these similarities become

    meaningful only if we are able to see them within the encompassing framework of the basic

    differences between the two narratives: this is the whole point of the correspondence

    approach.

    In what follows I shall concentrate, in accordance with the main focus of the

    conference, on one specific feature of the stories, which is their cyclicity.

    Empedocles himself uses the term circle (kuklos) in relationship with the cosmic

    story, when he says:

    i d diallssonta diamperw odam lgei,

    tauthi d' afin asin knhtoi kat kuklon.

    (B17, 12-14 DK=31B; the lines recur in B26 DK, 11-13 = 68B).

    Although this is not the main point in the context, which describes how the four roots,

    by eternally exchanging their places, paradoxically remain cyclically immobile , the

    reference to the circle does suggest that the unfolding of the universe will lead it back, in due

    course, to the point from which it started, exactly as a circle leads back to its starting point.

    Aristotle (Lambda 6, 1072 a9ss.) uses the word periodos to designate the span of time which

    brings the restauration of the initial state, and apokatastasis, restoration, is the very word

    we find coupled with periodos in Simplicius introductory sentence to his quotation of B17 in

    his commentary on Aristotles Physics4. It is clear even more from B26, which makes the

    ultimate unification in the One the true telos of the process of alternation5, than from B17, that

    this starting and ending point is not just any point in the story of the universe the

    Nietzschean notion of a return of the similar6, but a most special point, corresponding to the

    state of total fusion under Love that Empedocles calls Sphairos.

    3 Osborne 1987 and in the present volume. 4 tn kat perodon pokatstasin, In Phys., p. 157, 25ss., cf. p. 34, 6. The term is elsewhere used in Simplicius (especially in the De Caelo commentary) to describe the return of a star to its initial position. 5 efisken n sumfunta t pn pnerye gnhtai, fr. B26, 8. 6 I leave aside here the fact that Nietzsches Wiederkehr des Gleichen is not the return of the same ( . des Selben ), but of the similar.

  • 3 23/06/15

    We have no indication, nor for that matter any reason to suppose, that Empedocles also

    used the word kuklos in relationship with the demonic story. But we are entitled to describe it

    as cyclic as well, for it is cyclic by implication. Since the banishment of the culprit divinity is

    said to last 30.000 seasons (B115, 6), the divinity must recover its primitive satus once this

    period is over7. This restitution in integrum amounts to yet another apokatastasis kata

    periodon tina.

    What is the relationship in terms of similarity and difference-- between the cosmic and

    the demonical cycles? The crucial point here, I think, concerns the question of how both

    cycles, cosmic and demonic, start. I shall claim two things. First, that we are entitled to speak

    of necessity in the case of the cosmic cycle (as Aristotle does) as well as in that of the

    demonic circle, although it looks as if Empedocles used the word necessity (anank) only in

    the latter case (the reverse of what happens with kuklos, which occurs in relationship only

    with the cosmic cycle, not with the demonic one8); second, that although we are entitled to

    speak of necessity in both cases, we should carefully distinguish between the two cases, and

    indeed between two kinds of necessity.

    That necessity plays a role in the case of the demonic cycle is unquestionable, since we

    have Empedocles own verses to this effect at the beginning of B 115 :

    stin ngkhw xrma yen crfisma palain,

    idion platessi katesfrhgismnon rkoiw

    Matters are more complicated in the case of the cosmic cycle, and interestingly so.

    Aristotle suggests in Phys. Theta 1, 252 a2ff. and again in Met. B4, 1000b12ff. that

    alternation between Philia and Neikos in the cosmical cycle is ultimately due to anank, but it

    is most probable that he is not relying here on Empedocles own wording. Here are the two

    texts:

    Phys. Theta 1, 252 a2ss. If, then, this is impossible, it is clear that motion is eternal

    and cannot have existed at one time and not at another : in fact, such a view can hardly be

    described as anything else than fantastic. And much the same may be said of the view that

    such is how things naturally are and that this must he regarded as a principle, as would seem

    to be the view of Empedocles when he says that the constitution of the world is of necessity

    7 Primavesi 2001, p. 22, refers, for the notion of a demonological cycle to a study by S. D'Onofrio (Tesi di Laurea presented at the University of Trieste in 1998/99), to which I have not had access. He furthermore adduces the testimony of Plutarch (De Is. et Osir., 361C) and Clement of Alexandria (V, 122, 3, introducing a quotation of B147). 8 There might be deep reasons for this state of affairs. Some suggestions in Laks 2004, p. 48.

  • 4 23/06/15

    such that Love and Strife alternatively predominate and cause motion, while in the

    intermediate period of time there is state of rest 9

    Met. B4, 1000b12ss. : And at the same time Empedocles mentions no cause of the

    change itself, except that things are so by nature : But when strife waxed great in the

    limbs/And sprang to honour as the time was fulfilled/Which is fixed for them in turn by a

    mighty oath 10

    It is true that in the first passage, the sentence w t kraten ka kinen n mrei tn

    filian ka t nekow prxei tow prgmasin j ngkhw does look like a paraphrase of some

    Empedocles verses. The expression n mrei, in particular, appears in B 17, 29 (=31B.) and

    B26, 1. It should be noted, however, that what Empedocles is talking about here is the

    alternate domination of each of the four roots (however we may understand this alternation,

    which is not obvious), not that of the two forces. Aristotle might have some other lines in

    mind, although this is not very plausible. Rather, he uses one Empedoclean formula to

    summarize another one, namely llote llote, which does typically apply to the two forces

    (B17, 6f., B 26, 5f.= 68B.). As far as j ngkhw is concerned, it clearly functions as an

    alternate formulation for Aristotles own otvw pfuken, which refers to "the state of affairs as

    they are", the facticity of what happens. Since otvw pfuken, in turn, already reflects

    Aristotles reading of Empedocles, j ngkhw seems even more remote from the original

    three steps from the king, so to say.

    The second passage points in the same direction, for not only does the word ngkh not

    appear in the 3 verses that Aristotle quotes in order to illustrate the alternation between Hatred

    and Love (B30=126B.) something that he does not do in the Physics text--, but by

    comparing the commentary with the quotation we can also see more clearly that the word

    nagkaon, which ngkh in the next sentence picks up, plays an interpretive role here, and

    how it does so --it interprets the expression teleiomnoio xrnoio.

    The suggestion that necessity in these two passages belongs to Aristotle, rather than

    Empedocles, is further reinforced by a passage in Simplicius' commentary on the Theta 1

    passage, p. 1184, 5ss. (=109 Bollack).

    9 efi d tat' dunata, dlon w stin diow kinhsiw, ll' ox t mn n t d' o: ka gr oike t otv lgein plsmati mllon. moivw d ka t lgein ti pfuken otvw ka tauthn de nomizein enai rxn, per oiken Empedoklw n efipen, w t kraten ka kinen n mrei tn filian ka t nekow prxei tow prgmasin j ngkhw, remen d tn metaj xrnon. 10 ka ma d atw tw metabolw ation oyn lgei ll' ti otvw pfuken:"ll' te d mga nekow n melessin yrfyh, | efiw timw t' nrouse teleiomnoio xrnoio | w sfin moibaow platow par' llatai rkou:" w nagkaon mn n metabllein: afitian d tw ngkhw odemian dhlo.

  • 5 23/06/15

    What is the difference between saying that things naturally are that way and

    necessarily if one does not add the cause ? Now this is what Empedocles seems to say when

    he says

    and in turn they dominate, according to times revolving

    And when he makes necessity responsible for what happens :

    there is an oracle of necessity, ancient decree of the gods,

    eternal, sealed by wide oaths

    For it is because of necessity and these oaths that, he says, each of them dominate in turn.

    Empedocles says this also about the domination of Hatred :

    but when strife waxed great in the limbs/And sprang to honour as the time was

    fulfilled/Which is fixed for them in turn by a mighty oath.

    This, says Aristoteles, if no cause is mentioned, amounts to saying nothing else than things

    naturally are that way 11

    It is in order to illustrate Aristotle's assimilation of "factuality" (pfuken otvw) to

    necessity that Simplicius quotes in a row B17, 20 (or a version of 17, 20 that Bollack

    identified as 120 B.), B 115, 1-2 or two lines that strongly resembles the 2 first lines of 115

    (on which see below), and finally B126 the same 3 lines which are quoted by Aristotle in the

    Met. Beta passage.

    At first blush, it certainly looks as if Simplicius did not find in Empedocles any

    assertion either to the effect that the alternation is a matter of fact (pfuken otvw) or that it

    happens by necessity (j ngkhw). To have Empedocles say this needs some interpretive

    work, which Simplicius thinks Aristotle must have done. This is the implication of oike

    lgein he seems to say, which Simplicius takes up from Aristotle. One should stress that

    the restrictive formula applies in Simplicius not only to the quotation where ngkh does not

    occur, but also, and more remarkably, to the quotation where it does appear, namely in B115,

    11 Ti d diafrei to t lgein afitian m prostiynta; tata d Empedoklw oike lgein n t:

    n d mrei kratousi periplomnoio xrnoio: ka t' ngkhn tn ginomnvn afititai: stin ngkh xrma yen sfrgisma palain, idion platessi katesfrhgismnon rkoiw: di gr tn ngkhn ka tow rkouw toutouw kteron par mrow pikraten fhsi. lgei d ka tata

    Empedoklw p tw to Neikouw pikrateiaw: atr pe mga Nekow n melessin rfyh w timw t' nrouse teleiomnoio xrnoio, w sfin moibaow platow parellatai rkou.

    tata on fhsi xvrw afitiaw legmena odn llo lgein stn .

  • 6 23/06/15

    1. The sensible conclusion to draw is that neither this line nor the following ones (that depend

    on it) bore on the cosmic cyle.

    Now J. Bollack has argued that Simplicius did find the two verses he quotes in a cosmic

    context, and makes them his fragment number 110 in his edition of the physical poem. His

    hypothesis is supported first, at a general level, by stressing that Simplicius, Neoplatonist as

    he may be, is no more interested than Aristotle in Empedocles' daimones, and that he never

    quotes elsewhere from the demonic story, and second, at a textual level, by insisting that the

    lines quoted by Simplicius are not in fact identical with the opening of B 115.

    But one can reply that Simplicius would have quoted the lines in the first location, not

    in the second one, if they had straightforwardly exemplified what Aristotle says about

    Empedocles12. More importantly, as I have already mentioned, if the quotation came from a

    physical context, Simplicius would not have said that Empedocles seems to say that the

    alternation between Love and Hatred happens by necessity, but that he does say it. In other

    terms, the quotation must leave room for interpretation. In this case, the (Neoplatonic)

    interpretation is encapsulated in the sentence di gr tn ngkhn ka tow rkouw toutouw,

    which makes the link between what Empedocles actually says in the quotation, which

    includes the word ananke, and what he must have said elsewhere, namely that kteron par

    mrow pikraten fhsi, which most probably refers to B 17 (par mrow, like n mrei in the

    preceding text, translating llote llote). The link between the two contexts is provided by

    the term rkoi (serments) which appears both in B30, 3 = 126B. (cosmic cycle) and in B115

    (demonic cycle). The idea is that the tight association between ngkh and rkoi in B115 is

    enough to read ngkh into B30 as well which might well be true in a certain sense, but, as

    we shall see shortly, in a certain sense only13.

    As for the claim that Simplicius never quotes from the demonic context because

    Aristotle is not interested in this subject, it allows for an exception in an exceptional case14,

    which might well be what we have to do with here(Simplicus is looking for a

    confirmation)15. There is no reason to doubt that Simplicius had access to the Catharmoi

    12 Bollack, vol. III.1, p. 150 (ad 109) thinks that Simplicius quotes the first text for the equivalence pfuken otvw = n mrei, the second for the equivalence ngkh= rkoi, the third for the equivalence rkow = par mrow. But this does not reflect Simplicius presentation. 13 I agree on this with OBrien 2001, p. 86-88. As far as I can see, doxography (e.g. Aetius I, 26, 1) is dependant on Aristotle. Note the interesting assimilation, in I, 7, 28 of necessity with the one , which points to yet another interpretation. 14 Aristotle would be doing the same in the Poetics, 1457b13 (= fr. 138 DK), if the half-line quoted there were from the demonic story. But this has recently been contested (Picot 2004). 15 In this sense, the formula faute de mieux seems to me acceptable. Contra, Primavesi 2001, p. 14, n. 39; see further OBrien 2001, p. 88s., note 21.

  • 7 23/06/15

    as well as to the Physics (to adopt the two-poems language), be it, on the worst

    hypothesis, indirectly, namely through the Neoplatonic tradition, where the fragment was

    extremely famous, as is easily seen from the apparatus criticus of B. 11516.

    There remains Bollacks textual argument, for the first line of Simplicius quotation

    differs from what we find in Plutarch and Hippolytus in three respects : the absence of ti after

    stin, angkh in the nominative instead of the genitive, sfrgisma instead of cfisma.

    Hence the text of Bollack's fr. 110:

    stin ngkh, xrma yen, sfrgisma palain,

    idion, platessi katesfrhgismenon rkoiw:

    in which xrma would not have the (exceptional) sense of "uttering", "declaration", as

    in the juncture ngkhw xrma, but, in apposition to ngkh, that of "posession" (Bollack

    translates "Elle est, Ncessit, apanage des dieux"). Tempting as this is, especially in the

    perspective of a correspondence model, and even more in view of the fact that the new

    Strasbourg Empedocles might present us with another such "quotation" of one poem by

    another17, I remain unconvinced. Apart from the fact that the existential statement about

    necessity seems to hang in the air18, the word sfrgisma, which Bollack translates with "law"

    but which means "seal" (or "sealed thing"), does not make very good sense, even less so if it

    is emphatically taken up by katesfrhgismenon in the next line, which on the other hand can

    easily explain the substitution of sfrgisma for an original cfisma, to which the participle

    of course applies well (the decree is sealed). As for the other two variations, they may easily

    be interpreted as the result of minor corruptions19.

    Thus Ananke as a cyclic force may have been restricted in Empedocles to the demonic

    context, whereas the cosmic cycle was presented as depending on the fulfilling of time

    (teleiomnoio xrnoio)20. This does not mean, however, that Aristotle's interpretation should

    16 Note that the first two lines were quoted by Porphyrius in his Peri tou ef'hmin, (fr. 271F, 23-24 Smith). 17 Fr. 139, quoted by Porphyrius in his De abstinentia, shows up with textual variations in ensemble (d), 5-6. Martin and Primavesi take the text transmited by Porphyrius for a corruption of the sole original text, represented by the papyrus. Decisive at this juncture is a difficult metrical problem. See the discussion in Martin and Primavesi 1999, p. 301f. 18 Bollack III.1, p. 151, comments: "Il faut donner stin sa valeur pleine. La ncessit du devenir surgit de l'tre". What this necessity consits in, namely the alternation of Love and Strife, would have been spelled out in the following lines (as in B 115). 19 At stake is one haplography (ti) and a badly resolved abreviation (h for hw). Burkert expressed doubts about Bollacks text in the review of his edition (1972, p. 438). 20 This of course does not preclude the occurrence of ngkh in other physical contexts. As a matter of fact, the Strasbourg papyrus now gives us such a case in (d)2, where we read anagkaihw upo lugrhw (Primavesi 2001, p. 14, n. 39, seems to me to misuse the argument). The necessity is here that of the destruction of the compounds, i.e. of death. Conversely, every occurrence of ananke in the demonic context need not have refered to the initial decree. This might be the case of fr. 116 (stugeei dustlhton anagkhn), if the subject of the verb is xariw, as is

  • 8 23/06/15

    be rejected. On the contrary, there is nothing wrong with calling "necessary" what is going to

    happen after the due time has elapsed. Aristotle might even be simply articulating, at an

    explicit level, Empedocles own interpretation of the relationship between the two cycles a

    relationship which might conveniently be summarized by the following analogy : sworn

    fulfilling of time /alternation = necessity/exile. We might want to distinguish the

    interpretative, Aristotelian necessity from Empedocles explicit necessity by writing

    necessity in the first case, and Necessity in the second one.

    The question arises, of course, why Empedocles himself did not call the triggering

    factor of his cosmic cycle ananke, as he no doubt could have done it. Although any answer to

    this question is doomed to remain speculative, some clue can be gained from a closer analysis

    of the analogical relationship. There are two crucial differences between cosmic necessity

    and demonic Necessity:

    a) whereas the cosmic cycle is regulated by an absolute necessity, a necessity no

    matter what, the demonic cycle is regulated by a hypothetical necessity of the form: if

    then

    b) whereas the beginning of a new cycle is prompted, in the cosmic cycle, by the

    disruption of Sphairos by Neikos, the beginning of a new demonic cycle is prompted by the

    crime of a divinity.

    Only a minority of interpreters have denied the second point, and tried to have both

    events coincide, but the first one needs to be stressed. Surely, if there is a criminal, a victim,

    and a weapon to shed the blood, we already are in a differentiated world ? And no less surely,

    the history of the world, that is the fact that the world has a history, does not hinge on the

    crime committed by a divinity, which we should think of being committed at regular intervals,

    in order to square with what we know about the cosmic cycle ? 21

    Now once we allow for the difference, important consequences follow as to the nature

    of the relationship between cosmic cycle and demonic cycle. It is important to find an

    appropriate way to describe this relationship, for interpreters remain rather vague here. The

    distinction between exoteric and esoteric (whether the divide is traced, as is usually the case,

    between physics and demonology, or, in Primavesi's version, between an esoteric form of

    implied by the way Plutarch introduces the fragment, although in the absence of any reliable context, it is difficult to derive definite implications from it. 21 The coincidental view is defended most notably by C. Osborne (see especially Osborne, 1987b, p. 48, as well as her contribution to the present volume). Most interpreters reject it. To name just three of them: OBrien 2001, p. 138ss. ; Primavesi 2001, p. 27f. Bollack 2003, p. 123ss.

  • 9 23/06/15

    physico-demonology, on the one hand, and an exoteric demonology, on the other22) will not

    do. It is true that the demonic cycle develops an argument addressed to a community (and

    those who advocate the existence of two poems will insist that this was done in a separate

    poem, the Katharmoi, whose exotericity is illustrated in the most cogent way by the fact that

    it it reported to have been sung in Olympia23), whereas the cosmic cycle is part of a

    specialised knowledge, which is accordingly directed to a single person (Pausanias). But the

    exoteric/esoteric distinction is useful only as far as it goes, for there are at least two ways to

    look at it. Either exoteric refers to a way of articulating the same content in different terms,

    which would entail a rhetorical interpretation of the distinction24. Or it adresses another

    content, which amounts to a substantial interpretation of the distinction. I take it that this

    second line is the right one, and also the more interesting one25. The category of myth

    (perhaps even that of Platonic myth) may be useful here, for one can argue that the demonic

    story is mythical in a way the cosmic one is not.

    One substantial difference introduced by the distinction between absolute and

    hypothetic necessity concerns, so to speak, the cyclicity of the cycle. The cosmic cycle, in the

    sense of the return of some special state of the cosmos , or rather of what is , repeats

    itself an infinite number of time26. This repetition amounts to saying that the fight between

    Love and Hatred is itself eternal, that it will never be settled by the victory of one of the

    participants.

    Things are different in the case of the demonic cycle, which is informed by the structure

    of punishment. The punishment itself consists in an exile (no longer being where you belong).

    The cycle corresponds to the time it takes for the punishment to be completed. As such, it

    does not imply repetition indeed, automatic repetition would clash with the very logic of

    punishment. Far from there being any necessity that the cycle or cycles repeat themselves an

    indefinite number of times, it would go against legitimate expectations. The punishment

    22 See supra, note ** 23 Diogenes Laertius, IX, 63. 24 I take it that Hippolytus Neoplatonic interpretation is one specific instance of this rhetorical model. 25 This is the one advocated by Bollack 2003. 26 The clearest text here is Simplicius on De Caelo 10, 279b 14s., p. 293, 18ss. tinw d tn genhtn legntvn fyartn lgousi, dixw d toto: ofl mn gr otvw fyartn, sper tion llo tn sunistamnvn tmvn, oon Svkrth fyeirmenon paj ka mhkti nakmptonta, ofl d nallj ginesyai ka fyeiresyai tn atn ka plin genmenon plin fyeiresyai lgousi, ka idion enai tn toiathn diadoxn,sper Empedoklw tn Filian lgvn ka t Nekow par mrow pikratonta tn mn sungein t pnta efiw n ka fyeirein tn to Nekouw ksmon ka poien j ato tn sfaron, t d Nekow diakrinein plin t stoixea ka poien tn toioton ksmon. These lines are followed by a quotation of the six first lines of B 17 (that is before the line which refers to the circle ) and by a telling parallel with Heraclitus and the Stoics. Here I differ from Bollacks attempt to make this testimony square with the view that the Empedoclean cosmic story is the story of

  • 10 23/06/15

    restores an order which is then maintained, unless it is broken anew. Accordingly, Necessity

    is not the name of the force that prompts the divinity to commit the crime. Rather, repetition

    is dependent, in accordance with hypothetical necessity, upon the repetition of the crime.

    Hence there is no sense that the conflict between the two forces is doomed to be eternal, and if

    it is eternal, it does not have the quasi-mechanical character of the repetition of the cosmic

    cycle. On the contrary, the implication is that there is, at least in principle, a possibility of

    avoiding the punishement. Nothing tells us that the crime must of all necessity be committed.

    The cosmic and demonic cycles are very different in this respect. In the one case : there will

    necessarily be cycle and repetition ; in the other case : it is necessary that there be cycle, under

    certain conditions. We need not assume that Empedocles read Aristotle's Analytics to claim

    that he grasped the difference between the two.

    At this point it might be useful to take a look at Plato's Phaedrus, in order to draw a

    comparison between the Phaedrus central myth and Empedocles demonic story. It is

    obvious that the two texts belong to the same tradition, and are directly or indirectly related

    (directly, if Plato writes with Empedocles in mind, which seems extremely probable ;

    indirectly, if both simply depend on the same Orphic tradition). Of course, this does not let us

    draw inferences from one text to the other. As in the case of the relationship between

    Empedocles own cosmic and demonic cycles, the differences between Empedocles demonic

    story and Plato myth of the soul are no less significant than their similarities which does not

    mean, of course, that they are significant in the same way27.

    One extremely interesting point of similarity, which I mention just in passing, is that

    both stories are essentially related to the question of how human beings should feed

    themselves (or what constitutes their selves) how the soul should positively feed its wings,

    in the case of the Phaedrus, what men should negatively avoid eating, in Empedocles case28.

    But apart from this, both stories are informed by a similar narrative pattern, according to

    which the blissfulness of a primitive state enjoyed by a certain kind of entity is interrupted by

    a negative event, which represents the application of a decree (that of Necessity in

    Empedocles, that of Adrasteia in Plato29) punishing the entity in question to an exile which

    a single process. Not that I think this is radically false, but the idea cannot be established except through a complicated hermeneutical operation (see Laks 2004, p. 48), not on the basis of any textual evidence. 27 There is astoninshingly little on the subject, and what exists is rather superfical (Nicolai 1981, Ebert 1993). The indications that follows do not claim more than to draw attention to the problems involved in a comparison, which should be pursued systematically. 28 The point does not seem to have attracted the attention it merits. 29 Phaedrus, 248c2.

  • 11 23/06/15

    takes the form of a series of reincarnations, some of which are better and more valuable than

    others, and which are followed by a return to the primitive state at the end of the period of

    punishment. The differences bear on the nature of the entity concerned (some divinity, in

    Empedocles; imperfect or human souls, in Plato); the nature of the negative event (a blood

    crime in Empedocles, a cognitive deficiency in Plato30); the location of the fault

    (indeterminate in Empedocles case, at least if the divine criminal is not to be identified, as I

    believe it might, with one of us31; the heavens in Plato); the length of the exile period (30 000

    seasons in Empedocles, 10 000 years in Plato --unless this amounts to the same32); the kind

    of lives the incarnated entity goes through, in what order and according to what principle. A

    difficult and important feature concerns the possibility of escaping from the cycle before its

    completion. In Plato, it is clear that the soul which has nourished its wings in the appropriate

    way and chosen the philosophical life three times in a row wil be able to rejoin the heavenly

    procession of perfect (divine) souls after three periods of 1000 years = 3000 years, which

    amounts to a shortcut33. In Empedocles, it is not clear that there is a corresponding

    possibility : even the four examples of what humans can achieve in matters of intellectual and

    social excellence in B 146, 1-2 seem to lead ( nyen in line 3) to a further stage, that of

    (re)divinisation proper, whose state is then described in B 147 (the banquet of the gods)34.

    Be that as it may, what I would like to stress here is that the Phaedrus story of the fallen

    souls is even more cyclic, so to speak, than Empedocles story of the exiled demons. Apart

    from the fact that the Platonic gods move in circle, and go on doing so, while feeding their

    intellect (Empedoclean gods remain seated at the banquet table, they are homestioi according

    to B147, 3)35, it should be stressed that the Platonic psychic cycle is cyclic in the same sense

    as Empedocle's cosmic cycle (as opposed to the demonic one) is cyclic, that is, that it is

    supposed to repeat itself without ending.

    As a matter of fact, the cognitive deficiency which triggers the fate of the fallen souls in

    Plato is a necessary one, even if the description of the circumstances under which the

    30 With a difficult relation to moral fault. 31 I shall explore this hypothesis elsewhere. 32 See Rashed 2001, p. 251. 33 The incarnated philosopher is winged, like the unincarnated soul, hence he is already unincarnated in a certain sense. 34 B 146: efiw d tlow mnteiw te ka mnoploi ka fihtroi/ka prmoi nyrpoisin pixyonioisi plontai/nyen nablastosi yeo timisi fristoi. B 147: yantoiw lloisin mstioi, atotrpezoi /ntew, ndreivn xvn pklhroi, teirew. 35 Note the parallel between mstioi, in B 147, and moptrouw at Phaedrus 257d8-e2, ll fann bion digontaw edaimonen met' lllvn poreuomnouw, ka moptrouw rvtow xrin, tan gnvntai, gensyai. Although the Phaedrus passage refers only to the second best kind of loving souls, the description applies a fortiori to the first.

  • 12 23/06/15

    cognitive deficiency occurs is highly ambiguous, and most certainly intentionnally so, for

    some features of the myth suggest that souls are responsible for their fall, others that it is a

    question of (mis)fortune. Ultimately, however, the fall is grounded in the fact that there are

    two distinct types of souls, divine and human ; human souls are temporarily associated with

    the divine ones, but even though they all strive to remain in their company, and some of them

    might indeed succeed in doing so for a whole cycle, the rule is that they have to fail, because

    of their essential defectiveness. The reason for that, in turn -- and here we meet with the

    second, deeper reason why the Platonic psychic cycle has to be cyclic, i.e. to repeat itselfis

    that there simply would be no living beings if their souls could avoid falling. For the

    definition of a living being (a zoon) according to the myth is just this, namely the encounter

    and union of a fallen soul with a body36. This implies a constant supply of fallen souls for life

    to persist. And this is the reason why from the outset there are two categories of soul, the

    divine ones and the defective, potentially human ones: the second category is by nature linked

    to the explanation of life. We have no reason whatsoever to think that the same articulation

    holds for Empedocles. According to him, there is no specific, independent principle of life,

    such as a Platonic soul is. Empedoclean life is so to speak embedded from the outset in the

    roots: All have their part of intelligence (phronesis) and thought (nma), says B 110, 10 (=

    578B.). Demons pass through all forms of life (B 115, 7), but do not constitute them.

    Accordingly, the fall of the culprit divinities in Empedocles fulfills a different function than

    the fall of souls in Plato does --a function that is not physical, but, as we might say,

    religious or ethical, and in any case eschatological in the proper sense of the word. For

    although Platos story of the fallen souls in the Phaedrus is also eschatological in some sense,

    in fact it is but a pseudo-eschatology, since the life process never comes to an end: in order

    that life may persist the cycle is going to repeat itself, no matter what. By contrast,

    Empedocles eschatology may be considered truly eschatological, inasmuch as it is

    independent of an explanation of life. Once the fallen divinities have regained their status,

    they remain the divinities they are by nature --at least in principle, since nothing prevents us

    from imagining them as sinning again37.

    We might want, then, to replace the exoteric/esoteric distinction with, or more exactly

    to subordinate it to, the distinction between theory and practice, which is no more, of course,

    36 Phaedrus, 246c 37 It should be added that Empedocles cosmic cycle displays, in relationship to the demonic cycle, the same pseudo-eschalotogical feature that characterizes Platos psychic cycle. On this, see Laks 2004, p. 48.

  • 13 23/06/15

    than a reformulation of the old distinction between science and religion. As I suggested at the

    beginning, what Empedocles is doing by setting up two structurally distinct although related

    stories is articulating the problem of the relationship of (human) responsibility and action

    (ethics) with the objective course of events (physics). The fact that his treatment is less

    conceptual than narratological, and that the sphere of the practical appears deeply linked with

    religious practice, does not fundamentally affect this claim, although it does raise a number of

    interesting questions, hermeneutical and otherwise, about the beginnings of philosophy.

    What does the articulation consist in, then, or more exactly how does it function ? I

    submit that an essential point lies in an obvious fact which I have not yet mentioned, namely

    that the two principles which govern the cycles, apart from Necessity, are the same on both

    sides : Neikos and Philia (or their representatives). It is not easy to decide whether this

    identity is to count as a similarity between the two stories a particularly strong form of

    similarity, namely identity-, or, rather, in spite as the identity of names, as a difference. It

    seems to me that the problem is akin to the one raised by Ananke, and is in fact dependent

    upon it. For it makes a great difference, does it not, whether Neikos and Philia are active in a

    sphere (I do not say a world) which is regulated by absolute necessity, or in one regulated by

    hypothetical necessity. The difference is simply that whereas in the former case, there is no

    choice open between two courses of actions, in the latter one, you can decide to embrace one

    of the two parties. That this is what is at stake in the demonic story is abundantly clear both

    from the protreptic fragments which call upon men to stop murdering living beings (fr. 136),

    and from the picture of an ideal society built upon non-animal sacrifices (fr. 128) --which

    should not be taken, I think, to refer to a stage of the cycle which was closer to the Sphairos,

    as an integrative interpretation would claim, but to a possibility that may be realized again,

    because it happened once. In the framework of the cosmic story, Philia and Neikos play quite

    another role. This role is in fact so different that it is in some sense at odds with the other one.

    For the world as such depends for its existence upon the force of Hatred. A world of perfect

    Love is no world in the proper sense of the term, because a world demands differentiation,

    which in turn presupposes the presence of Hatred. And neither human beings nor daimones,

    whether we consider them as building some kind of society or as individuals, aim at

    disappearing into the Sphere of Love, no more than into the whirl of hatred. Of course,

    unification with the whole, abolition of self-identity, is an available scheme for interpreting

    Empedocles, one which has been put to use by Hlderlin and Schopenhauer. But we have no

    reason to think that this was Empedocles view. When the exiled divinity laments about his

  • 14 23/06/15

    former honors and blessedness38, his longing is not to return to abolish himself in the

    unlimited mass of the blithful god Sphairos, but to be seated again with the other gods at their

    table.

    A further question would be to ask whether Philia and Neikos are primarily principles

    of cosmic processes or of human (and demonic) action. Some will probably deny that the

    question may be answered, or even that it makes sense at all. I think, on the contrary, that this

    is the very question that Empedocles wants us to ask. After all, if the author of the Lille

    Papyrus is Stesichorus, as there are good reasons to think, Empedocles had before him a

    model according to which Neikos and Philia, his own cosmic forces, were taken, naturally

    enough, as the leading principles of human actions. Jocaste, there, counters Tiresias prophecy

    according to which either Thebes will be saved, and her sons perish, or her sons will survive,

    but the city be destroyed, by arguing that hatred, for mortals, is no more necessary than love

    is:

    For it is false, first, that always equally

    Immortal gods have,on sacred earth

    Made Hatred immutable for mortals

    Nor, of course, Love either39.

    Empedocles would subscribe to this idea of an alternation between Love and Hatred,

    but at the cosmic level, not at a human one. And he would differ from Stesichorus inasmuch

    as he would have advocated the possibility, in principle, that the alternation of hatred and love

    on earth be interrupted by the establishement of a city, or a civilization, of peace. This is what

    is at stake in the difference between a cosmic and a demonic cycle.

    Bollack, J. Empdocle II. Les Origines. Edition et traduction des fragments et tmoignages et III (1 et 2). Les Origines. Commentaire, Paris, 1969.

    Bollack, J., Empdocle. Les Purifications, Paris, 2003. Burkert, W., review of vol. II (Edition et traduction des fragments et tmoignages) et III

    (Commentaite, I/2) of J. Bollack, Empdocle. Les Origines, Gnomon, 1972, 432-442. Ebert, Th. A Presocratric philosopher behind the Phaedrus : Empedocles , Revue de

    Philosophie Ancienne, 11, 1993, 211-227. Laks, A. Le Vide et la Haine. Elments pour une histoire archaque de la ngativit, Paris :

    PUF, 2004.

    38 j ohw timw te ka ssou mkeow lbou ..., fr. 119 39 Fr. 222 (b) Davies.

  • 15 23/06/15

    Martin, A./Primavesi, O., L'Empdocle de Strasbourg (P.Strasb.gr. Inv. 1665-1666), Berlin - New York 1999.

    Nicolai, W. Der Mythos vom Sndenfall der Seel (bei Empedokles und Platon) , Gymnasium, 88, 1981, 512-524 .

    OBrien, D., "Empedocles: the wandering daimon and the two poems", Aevum N.S.1, 2001, 79-179.

    O'Brien, D., Pour interprter Empdocle, Paris-Leyde, 1981. Osborne, C. (a), Rethinking Early Greek Philosophy. Hippolytos of Rome and the

    Presocratics, London 1987. Osborne, C. (b), "Empedocles Recycled", Classical Quarterly, 37, 1987, 24-50. Picot, J.-C., Les cinq sources dont parle Empdocle , Revue des Etudes Grecques, 117,

    2004, 393-446. Primavesi, O., "La daimonologia della fisica empedoclea", Aevum N.S.1, 2001, 3-68. Rashed, M., "La chronologie du systme d'Empdocle: documents byzantins indits", Aevum

    N.S.1, 2001, 237-259.