Kotan. Can Economists Make People Happier. the Free Mind. 2007

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/4/2019 Kotan. Can Economists Make People Happier. the Free Mind. 2007

    1/616 the free mind|issue 04|October 2007

    GUEST WRITING

    Can Economists Make People Happier?The insufficiency of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics

    Guest Writing

    By Murat Kotan1

    1. Introduction

    Economists have great influence worldwide on the

    design and implementation of policies. In the Ne-

    therlands, for example, no political party can escape

    running their proposed policies through the eco-

    nomic models of the Centraal Plan Bureau. The

    models predict the impact of these policies on for

    instance national income growth, inflation, unem-

    ployment and government finance. In view of the

    great importance attached in the media to these ty-pes of variables, people generally think that econo-

    mics is all about money and nothing else.

    Fortunately, this is not the case. In fact, there is gene-

    ral consent in economics that variables such as nati-

    onal income have onlyderivedvalue: they are of im-

    portance as far as they contribute towelfare. Whatever

    welfare may mean in ordinary use, in mainstream

    economics it ultimately means utility: the experienceof pleasure and the absence of pain.2 Simply put:

    economists are - just like psychologists concerned

    1 Faculty of Economics and Business, University ofAmsterdam; e-mail: [email protected]. I would like to thank Petra Bo-ers and Geert Reuten for their textual comments, which much impro-ved the accessibility of the paper.2 Some economist may object that in welfare economics(see text) it is the satisfaction of preferences on which the evaluationof economic policies and economic structures is based. But, as Sen(1991: 19) rightly notes: In the welfarist approach dominant in tra-

    ditional welfare economics the case for basing the social evaluationof states on individual preferences turns on the correctness or falsityof the identification of preference with welfare or utility.

    with making people happier.

    Within the field of economics, welfare economics is

    concerned with the evaluation of different eco-

    nomic policies and structures. Given that utility is

    the variable of interest, welfare economics should

    thus be expected to investigate into the many ways

    in which the economy and economic policies affect

    individuals experience of utility. Unfortunately, this

    is not the case. The main focus in mainstream eco-

    nomics has been the satisfaction derived from the

    consumption of commodities, instead of utility in

    general. Among others because of this, competitivemarkets are seen by mainstream economics as the

    ideal economic system.

    Much of the pleas for competitive markets are ba-

    sed on an important theorem in welfare economics,

    the so-called First Fundamental Theorem of Welfa-

    re Economics. But, as I argue, mainstream welfare

    economics narrowness of view concerning well-

    being, makes it unfit for the evaluation and recom-mendation of economic structures and policies.

    In this paper I broaden the view by treating two

    sources of well-being which have been commonly

    neglected in mainstream welfare economics. Both

    sources I believe to be relevant for the evaluation

    of economic policies and structures and thus should

    be taken into account when designing policies and

    institutions. The first is procedural utility. It concerns

    among others the fact that individuals well-being is

  • 8/4/2019 Kotan. Can Economists Make People Happier. the Free Mind. 2007

    2/6the free mind|issue 04| October 2007 17

    Guest Writing

    affected by the specific procedures under which they

    participate in the economy and interact with each

    other. The second source is social well-being, arising

    from the social embeddedness of individuals.

    Before treating these two sources of well-being in

    section 3, I explain the First Welfare Theorem for

    non-economists in section 2. Can economists make

    people happier? They can, concludes section 4. But

    not without the help of psychologists and social psy-

    chologists.

    2. The First Fundamental Theorem of Welfare

    Economics: Competitive markets lead to maxi-

    mum utility achievable

    Competitive markets are advocated by mainstream

    economists on utility grounds. Much of the pleas of

    economist for markets and competition are (im-

    plicitly) based on a major theoretical proposition in

    welfare economics: the so-called First FundamentalTheorem of Welfare Economics.

    This theorem, henceforth referred to as the first wel-

    fare theorem (FWT), states that competitive markets

    lead to an economic state of affairs in which every

    individual achieves maximum utility from the con-

    sumption of commodities, given his scarce resour-

    ces, and in which firms provide these commodities

    at the lowest possible cost.3

    As Gowdy (1) notes this is not an innocent theoreti-

    cal result lacking practical consequences:

    3 There is, as might be expected, also a Second Fundamen-tal Theorem which will not be treated here. The second theorembasically states that any allocation of commodities that satisfies the

    first welfare theorem can be achieved by an initial redistribution ofresources. For a treatment and more formal statement of the welfaretheorems, see any introductory microeconomics textbook.

    Armed with the two fundamental Pareto theorems

    [the fundamental theorems of welfare economics],

    economists attack any problem by attempting to

    create the conditions for a competitive economy

    Welfare economic models are much more than mild-

    ly interesting theoretical toys. These models lie be-

    hind the pronouncements of leading economists on

    a variety of critical issues including global warming,

    international trade and development policies, and bi-

    odiversity protection.

    To illustrate the intuitive idea behind the FWT, con-

    sider a situation in which no exchange is possible,

    compared to a situation in which exchange is pos-

    sible.

    Assume Adam has six pears in his possession and

    no apples. Assume also that Adam derives pleasu-

    re both from the consumption of pears and from

    the consumption of apples. However, the additio-nal amount of satisfaction he obtains from pears or

    apples decreases with the consumption of an ad-

    ditional unit of that fruit. Thus the first pear may

    provide Adam a lot of pleasure. The second he also

    enjoys but less so then the first. Even the sixth pear

    provides him some satisfaction, but little compared

    to the first pear.4 The following utility function gi-

    ves the relation between the amounts of apples and

    pears Adam consumes and the amount of utility heexperiences:

    UA

    = a1/2 + p1/2 ,

    where UA

    is Adams utility level, ais the amount of

    apples and p is the amount of pears he consumes.

    4 The decrease in the additional satisfaction obtained froman additional unit of a good is called decreasing marginal utility ineconomics.

  • 8/4/2019 Kotan. Can Economists Make People Happier. the Free Mind. 2007

    3/618 the free mind|issue 04|October 2007

    This utility function is used to obtain the tables be-

    low.

    No fruit market

    When no exchange is possible Adam can only con-

    sume the pears he has. Table 1 illustrates the amount

    of utility Adam experiences from each amount of

    pears consumed.

    Table 1: Adams level of utility when no market

    for fruit exists

    Pears utility

    0 0

    1 1

    2 1.41

    3 1.73

    4 2

    5 2.24

    6 2.45

    Thus, when no exchange is possible, the maximum

    level of utility Adam can achieve is 2.45.

    Fruit market

    Now look how the maximum amount of utility

    Adam can achieve changes when trade becomes

    possible and he can exchange pears for apples. As-

    suming he could exchange one pear for one apple,table 2 illustrates different feasible combinations of

    pears and apples Adam can consume, and his corre-

    sponding levels of utility.

    Table 2: Adams level of utility when a market

    for pears exists

    Apples utility Pears utility Total

    utility

    6 2.45 0 0 2.45

    5 2.24 1 1 3.24

    4 2 2 1.41 3.41

    3 1.73 3 1.73 3.46

    2 1.41 4 2 3.41

    1 1 5 2.24 3.24

    0 0 6 2.45 2.45

    The maximum amount of utility Adam can achieve

    when there isa market for apples and pears becomes

    3.46. This is more than the U= 2.45 he can achieve

    when there is no market. In other words: the market

    makes Adam a happier man.

    This result holds in general (under the assumptions

    of the model behind the FWT): when trade is possi-ble the outcome of the trading process will lead to a

    higher level of utility achievable compared to when

    trading is not possible. This is in its simplest form

    the reason why a lot of economists plea for compe-

    titive markets.5 But is Adam really a happier man?

    3. Two shortcomings of the First Welfare The-

    orem

    Quite a few things can be said against the significanceof the First Welfare Theorem in any real-world situ-

    ation. Here I want to draw attention to two sources

    of well-being that are generally neglected in welfare

    economics and are left out of consideration in the

    model behind the FWT: procedural utilityand social

    well-being.

    5 The other major reason is the idea that competition leadsto cheaper and/or better products.

    Guest Writing

  • 8/4/2019 Kotan. Can Economists Make People Happier. the Free Mind. 2007

    4/6the free mind|issue 04| October 2007 19

    3.1 Procedural Utility

    Procedural utility means that individuals do not care

    only about outcomes, but also about the conditionsand

    processesthat lead to these outcomes (2).

    Procedural fairness

    For example. Let us assume Adam (see example sec-

    tion 2) considers it unfair he gets only one apple per

    pear. In other words: he considers the price unfair.

    When this is the case, consuming the same amount

    of apples and pears his utility derived from con-

    sumption may nevertheless be lower than the 3.46 in

    table 2. It may even be lower than the 2.45 in table

    1.

    Frey and Pommerehne (3) find that in a situation

    in which unexpected shortages exist, people find

    the process through which markets deal with these

    shortages (namely by raising prices) unfair. Compa-

    red to the market mechanism, other procedures ofdealing with the shortage, such as using the principle

    of first come first served or letting local authorities

    distribute the goods according to their own judg-

    ment, are perceived to be more fair. Only randomly

    assigning the goods to individuals is perceived to be

    less fair than the market process.

    Competition and well-being

    A laboratory study by Brandts et al. finds that gene-ral subjective well-being and the emotional state of

    players strongly depend on the competitiveness of

    the institution players participate in as well as their

    position in the competitive environment. (4)

    It is important to note that the effects of competi-

    tion on well-being and emotions go beyond the ef-

    fect it has on material payoffs or consumption. For

    example, if Adam gets excluded from trading pears

    for apples because the apple seller chose to sell his

    limited amount of apples to Eve, Adam will have to

    do with the pears he has. Referring back to table 1,

    one may expect in line with economic theorys out-

    come orientation, that Adams utility level will be the

    same as when no market existed (UA

    = 2.45) and he

    had to consume the six pears he had. But this is not

    true. When procedural utility is taken into account,

    competition is detrimental for the subjective well-

    being and emotional state of those who are as a con-

    sequence of competition excluded from trade. This

    means that Adam will experience less well-being

    than in the situation where no markets existed.

    Brandts et al. (4) find that competition lowers subjec-

    tive well-being and triggers more negative emotions

    like sadness, envy, anger, irritation and contempt

    for those excluded from trade as a consequence of

    competition, compared to those who do not expe-

    rience competition. This study provides evidence

    that markets affect procedural utility and therebywell-being in ways that are usually not accounted for

    in mainstream welfare economics.

    Thus the exclusive focus on the outcomesof econo-

    mic and social processes leaves out import ways in

    which economic and social structures and policies

    affect well-being. People also derive utility from and

    their well-being is affected by processes: not only

    what they have, but also howthey got it matters tothem (5). Further research is necessary to assess the

    relative importance of material sources of well-being

    compared to intangible sources such as procedural

    utility. One such research is provided by Frey and

    Stutzer (5). The authors argue based on empirical

    evidence from Swiss survey data that political par-

    ticipation rights have a positive effect on subjective

    well-being. According to this study the (procedural)

    utility derived from participation rights, contributes

    to well-being over and above the favorable outcomes

    Guest Writing

  • 8/4/2019 Kotan. Can Economists Make People Happier. the Free Mind. 2007

    5/620 the free mind|issue 04|October 2007

    the political process generates. The authors under-

    take a quantitative comparison between the effects

    of participation rights and income, concluding that:

    ... if the full range of participation rights is con-

    sidered, procedural utility accounts for larger diffe-

    rences in subjective well-being than the full range of

    individual income. (Frey and Stutzer, 2004: 106)

    Frey and Stutzer hypothesize that the positive well-

    being effects of political participation rights stem

    from a feeling of self-determination, control and

    influence.

    3.2 Social Well-being

    Another relation between the economy and well-

    being that is commonly neglected is the effect that

    economic structures and policies have on social well-

    being: that is, well-being stemming from individuals

    being embedded in social structures and communi-ties and facing social tasks and challenges (6). Eco-

    nomic environments affect individual behaviour,

    which in turn affects individuals (social) well-being.

    The marketization of society (making market-like

    relations the cornerstone of social interaction or the

    impinging of markets on all domains of social life)

    has undesirable as well as desirable consequences

    for individuals well-being in ways not taken into ac-

    count by the analysis underlying the FWT. Referringback to Adam, it may well be that he is more satis-

    fied consuming his 3 apples and 3 pears than having

    to consume 6 pears. But if this situation also entails

    that nobody shares any of his or her fruits anymore

    with anyone, Adam may well be less happy living in

    such a society.

    Specifically the social and economic environments

    in which individuals live their daily lives, affect (by

    affecting the behaviours of others) their experience

    of social integrationand social acceptance. Keyes (6) de-

    fines social integration as: the evaluation of the

    quality of ones relationship to society and commu-

    nity. And social acceptance as: the construal of

    society through the character and qualities of other

    people as a generalized category. He finds that so-

    cial integration and social acceptance are negatively

    correlated with indicators of subjective well-being

    such as anomieand dysphoriaand positively with such

    indicators as global life satisfactionand global happiness

    with life.

    Is there reason to believe that economic structures

    affect social well-being? One answer is provided by

    laboratory experiments in social psychology and ex-

    perimental economics. These experiments show that

    social preferences, that is the way people rank dif-

    ferent allocations of material payoffs to themselves

    and others (7), depend on the framing of the situ-

    ation and the conditions under which individuals in-teract. For instance, one experiment (8,9) finds that

    when a game is framed as Wall Street Game, the

    subjects behave less socially (donate less money to

    the other), than when the same game is framed as

    Community Game. Similarly, Hoffman et al. (10)

    find that subjects donate less money to an other per-

    son when a game is framed as an exchange in which

    the proposer is called seller and his counterpart is

    called buyer compared to when the same game isframed as divide $10. Carpenter (7) conducts a se-

    ries of experiments to measure the effects of insti-

    tutions on peoples social preferences. He finds that

    anonymous bargaining (which he associates with

    markets) and being exposed to competitive markets

    generate more asocial players.

    How does this link with social well-being? It seems

    to me that it is plausible to expect that the strength

    of social preferences affect the social integration

    Guest Writing

  • 8/4/2019 Kotan. Can Economists Make People Happier. the Free Mind. 2007

    6/6the free mind|issue 04| October 2007 21

    and social acceptance that individuals experience,

    and hence their (social) well-being. This is more ap-

    parent if one considers the determinants of social

    integration and acceptance. Keyes operationalizes

    these concepts in the aforementioned study by the

    degree of agreement with the following statements6:

    You dont feel you belong to anything youd call a

    community (-), You feel close to other people in

    your community (+) (social integration), You belie-

    ve other people are kind (-), You believe that people

    are self-centered (-), You think that people live only

    for themselves (-) (social acceptance) (6).

    Economic environments that foster social prefe-

    rences will thus, ceteris paribus, facilitate social well-

    being by facilitating social integration and social ac-

    ceptance.7

    In sum: Economic structures are not neutral me-

    chanisms that merely regulate production and prices.Markets and economic and social structures in ge-

    neral, affect well-being by affecting peoples behavi-

    ours and stance towards each other.

    4. Conclusion

    Can economists make people happier? In this pa-

    per I pointed out and gave examples of two com-monly neglected sources of well-being: procedural

    6 A minus behind a statement indicates that stronger ag-reement with the respective statement contributes negatively to socialintegration or social acceptance, and a plus indicates that strongeragreement contributes positively.7 The ceteris paribus clause is important. Institutions thatfacilitate social preferences and thereby social well-being, may at thesame time undermine other elements of well-being. For example, insmall villages social preferences may be higher because there is greatersocial pressure in the form of norms and less anonymity, which faci-

    litates the enforcement of these norms. But while social pressure mayfacilitate social preferences and thereby social well-being it may at thesame time lower well-being by undermining for example autonomy.

    utility and social well-being. Research shows that in

    considering the relation between the economy and

    well-being, it is not enough to take the consumption

    of commodities into consideration. The examples

    also caution against the rash and sometimes dogma-

    tic tendency of economists (and others) to provide

    competitive markets and commodification as the

    solution to any social problem.

    The First Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Eco-

    nomics points at a beneficial aspect of competitive

    markets. This is a partial truth. In order to evaluate

    the well-being effects of competitive markets and

    other economic structures, and in order to design

    future policies and institutions with a view to further

    human well-being, we need a more comprehensive

    approach. The divers elements and sources of well-

    being and the divers channels through which the

    economy affects peoples lives should be taken into

    account.

    Such an undertaking necessitates an interdisciplinary

    spirit and cooperation between scientists with diffe-

    rent scientific backgrounds. A crucial role is gran-

    ted for psychology and social psychology as fields

    concerned with inquiring into human well-being and

    behaviour. I would like to encourage students and

    researchers in these areas to get more involved in

    discussions concerning the desirability of economicand social policies and direct more of their research

    efforts in this direction. Perhaps economists and

    psychologists together can make Adam a happier

    person.

    Guest Writing