23
JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW *Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* ***Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public Law at the University of Cambridge. Linda Whittle is a research assistant at Robinson College, Cambridge. This Lecture is an extended version of a lecture given by Christopher Forsyth at the University of Canterbury Mian Ali Haider L.L.B., L.L.M (Cum Laude) U.K.

JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW*Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle*

***Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public Law at the University of Cambridge. Linda Whittle is a research assistant at Robinson College, Cambridge. This Lecture is an extended version of a lecture given by Christopher Forsyth at the University of Canterbury

Mian Ali HaiderL.L.B., L.L.M (Cum Laude) U.K.

Page 2: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

INTRODUCTION The last fifty years of the twentieth century was a

period of unparalleled judicial creativity in the field of administrative law.

Not only were the grounds of judicial review significantly extended, but the range of bodies subject to judicial review was also much widened.

The functional justification for this growth in judicial review is obvious: there had been very considerable growth in the powers of government and, particularly when where there were few other effective forms of accountability, it is appropriate and necessary that the courts should ensure that these powers were fairly and reasonably exercised

Page 3: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

MATERIAL QUESTIONS But what was the constitutional justification for

this extension of judicial review? Where was the legal rule or rules that gave the

power to the judges to intervene? Put more directly what was the answer to the

officious but pertinent question asked of our judges:

who are you to interfere in the exercise of a discretion entrusted to a democratically accountable decision-maker by a democratically elected Parliament?

Page 4: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

The orthodox foundation of judicial review was long thought to be the doctrine of ultra vires and several recent House of Lords decisions have upheld a form of the doctrine in terms. The traditional ultra vires doctrine holds that when the judges

review, and in certain cases, quash the decisions of ministers and officials, they are simply policing the limits of the powers granted to the relevant decision-makers by Parliament.

However, this traditional account seemed increasingly implausible as non-statutory bodies were subjected to judicial review - there could be no question of policing the statutory limits of their powers.

Moreover, as the grounds of judicial review became more subtle it could hardly be said that Parliament ever had a specific intention in regard to every nuance of the increasingly complicated grounds of judicial review

Consequently, several leading scholars and judges attacked the ultra vires doctrine as a justification of judicial review - often using such an assault as a stepping stone to an attack on the sovereignty of Parliament.

Page 5: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

Professor Paul Craig He contended that the flaws inherent in the ultra vires doctrine

were so numerous and of such magnitude that the principle should be abandoned altogether, going on to suggest that the true foundations of judicial review lay instead in the common law.

The core idea here is that when the courts impose the principles of good administration upon decision-makers, they are applying rules that do not derive from the intent of Parliament but from the common law.

This debate over the true foundations of judicial review stimulated by this exchange of views has formed a prominent and lively part of discussion in public law in England over the past six years.

Given its similar constitution, public lawyers may have a contribution to make. They should in any case be interested in what has been a fiercely argued and impassioned debate about the background of a crucial component of a just legal system.

Page 6: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

THE NEED FOR A CONSTITUTIONAL JUSTIFICATION OF JUDICIAL REVIEW Before we ask ourselves what is the true basis - or justification - for

judicial review,

we must first consider why it is necessary to find such a justification.

After all, the desirability of judicial review as an aspect of the British legal system is beyond doubt.

However, it is generally recognised that it is an exceptional remedy.

It is premised upon bringing before the unelected judiciary a challenge to a decision made outside of the courtroom;

one made by an individual, or a body, that may well derive its power to determine such matters from statute, this being the law as put into place by the elected representatives of the people in Parliament.

Page 7: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

The decision-maker himself or herself will be elected, or accountable to an elected representative.

There may also be statutory rules or guidelines on how the decision is to be reached that will come into play.

We are back at our officious question: where do the courts derive the power to interfere in the making of such decisions?

Without an answer, we are unable to explain the merging of the spheres of power that seems to occur when judicial review is sought and brought.

Solid constitutional foundations are a very necessary element of the power, force and utility of judicial review.

How, consistently with the democratic nature of our constitution and the doctrine of the separation of powers, can a non-elected element of the constitution override the decision of a democratic element?

Page 8: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

In the light of the difficulties surrounding ultra vires - set out above — the common law might seem an attractive answer.

However the apparent simplicity of such an approach belies the quite real and serious difficulties that arise were ultra vires to be abandoned altogether.

First of all, 'the common law' is an exceptionally broad term. Unlike ultra vires, it gives a judge no concrete starting point for her or his

consideration of the legality of a decision. Ultra vires, at least, provides that the court examines whether the

particular decision is consistent with the powers of the decision-maker - a quite clear objective, albeit sometimes difficult to realise.

But the judge is directed to the terms of the relevant statutes and seeks to find there the answer to the question

In contrast, there simply is not found in the capacious bosom of the common law answers to precise questions posed by judicial review,

e.g. those concerning the level of natural justice to be applied in each particular case. It can be seen that relying on the common law, rather than ultra vires, would provide us with far less coherent and indeed less principled reasoning.

But there are even graver consequences.

Page 9: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

The Common Law Challenge to Sovereignty

And an immediate such consequence would be that the sovereignty of Parliament would be challenged.

Consider a situation in which the legislature had the power to disapply the principles of good administration, for example if it were able to order that a decision

might be made without heeding the rules of natural justice.

This is certainly a realistic scenario in the United Kingdom and we expect that it would be relatively uncontroversial in Pakistan

Suppose Parliament were to decide, and make its intent clear

Page 10: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

For example, as part of the war against terrorism – that certain immigration decisions could be made without heeding the

rules of natural justice, so that there was no obligation, as there would usually be, to disclose to the would be immigrant the source and nature of the immigration officer's doubts about his or her suitability for admission.

There would be dismay in many circles over this but there would be little doubt that the legislation would be valid and the judges would loyally uphold the legislation.

All this is straightforward if ultra vires is the foundation of judicial review.

But the difficulty that the common law theorists face in these circumstances is this: if the decision-maker complies with all the requirements of the statute,

express or implied, for the validity of his or her decision, then the court cannot add an additional requirement 'drawn from' the common law without challenging Parliament's power to lay down the requirements for validity - that is, without challenging sovereignty.

Such a difficulty does not arise with the ultra vires doctrine because all that is happening is 'the application of the law itself, and the law of Parliament to boot'.

Page 11: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

Carrying out Parliament's will is precisely what the court sets out to achieve.

In other words, to adopt the common law as the foundation of judicial review is in fact to challenge the sovereignty of Parliament.

The logic of this argument is unanswered and indeed is unanswerable for as long as Parliament is sovereign.

This is recognised in terms by Trevor Allan - no friend of the ultra vires doctrine - in his recent article.

It can be seen, then, that the effect of abandoning ultra vires would be to abandon the need for the courts to respect the legislative intent of Parliament.

Such a consequence does not seem to concern some advocates of the common law approach. One reason for this is their constant refrain that the ultra vires doctrine is

'artificial' or as

Craig puts it, 'does not accord with reality'.

It is argued that in relying upon ultra vires, we are not really applying the will of Parliament at all; therefore it is safe to dispose of the doctrine

Page 12: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

ARTIFICIALITY - REAL OR APPARENT? It may be doubted whether this criticism is quite as convincing

as it at first appears. Of course, those who make the case for ultra vires readily

acknowledge that certain aspects of the doctrine may appear artificial and can take this point on board when making their case.

The doctrine is not negated by its perceived artificiality. This is partly because artificiality is not always present.

Ultra vires requires that we uphold the intention of Parliament; and this the court can be said to be doing if it applies the doctrine so as to enforce the express provisions of a particular statute.

There is nothing artificial about the working of ultra vires in such a case.

Page 13: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

The idea of 'artificiality' only becomes relevant

when the wording of an Act is not clear,

or when conditions are implied into a statute.

Even in this kind of case, the matter is not clear-cut.

Critics argue that it is straining the ultra vires doctrine for the courts to say that they are acting as Parliament intends them to act in cases where precise provisions or instructions from Parliament are not forthcoming.

The difficulty with this line of argument is that it supposes that everything Parliament intends, and indeed stands for, is contained entirely within the express provisions of statute.

But, as one of the authors of this article argues elsewhere,

even though a particular Act may well lack explicit guidance on how decision-makers are to reach their conclusions, 'it is not unreasonable or implausible to impute to Parliament the intention that decision-makers should comply with the principles of good administration'

Page 14: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

In such a case, it should be evident that the courts are bringing forth a perfectly reasonable, realistic and valid Parliamentary intention — not a manufactured one.

It might be argued that even if real, the intention has been derived by 'artificial' means - that is, by drawing inferences, etc. –

But this is not entirely supportable, either, as the starting point, and the focus of any such enquiry will always be the statute itself.

The speech of Lord Bridge in Lloyd v McMahon illustrates the point. In well known words he said:

The so-called rules of natural justice are not engraved on tablets of stone ... [W]hat the requirements of fairness demand when any body, domestic, administrative or judicial, has to make a decision which will affect the rights of individuals depends on the character of the decision-making body, the kind of decision it has to make and the statutory or other framework in which it operates.

In particular, it is well-established that when a statute has conferred on any body the power to make decisions affecting individuals, the courts will not only require the procedure prescribed by the statute to be followed, but will readily imply so much and no more to be introduced by way of additional procedural safeguards as will ensure the attainment of fairness

Page 15: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

This dictum explains the judicial task in setting the measure of natural justice applicable in any particular circumstances, but without any mention of the common law.

True enough the duty of fairness is engaged when the statute empowers a body to make decisions affecting individuals.

So sometimes that trigger may be the individual's common law rights.

But the common law has no further role to play. The 'character of the decision-making body' - are its decisions

determined by policy or through the application of rules of law? –

Which must be considered but that is plainly determined by the statute setting it up.

Similarly, 'the kind of decision' which is made must be determined by the statute granting to the body the power to make the decision in question

Page 16: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

And 'the statutory ... framework' is self-evidently determined by the statute.

Thus the judicial task of laying down a procedure that would achieve fairness is structured by the statute and infused by conclusions drawn from the statute.

The creativity of the judiciary should not be underestimated but it is not something that takes place in isolation from the statute.

Indeed the role of the statute in this context is as vital as it is inevitable:

how, other than by looking to the statute, is the court to know the context in which it must secure fairness?

Rather than conjuring an indefensible notion of an intention out of thin air - as the term 'artificial' suggests –

the courts instead are able to adopt a structured approach in order to derive Parliament's intention, founded on the basis Parliament has given them - that is, the statute.

The intention is being sought, quite rightly and properly, in the place in which it has been manifested.

Page 17: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

Practical Problems: Ouster Clauses and Collateral Challenge

A typical ouster clause may provide that regulations or decisions made 'in terms of the Act' shall not be challenged in the courts.

However, as we have seen, the ultra vires doctrine allows us to imply the grounds of judicial review from the Act.

With this is mind, it follows that a decision in breach of natural justice - where that is express or to implied from the Act — for example, is not made 'in terms of the Act' - and the ouster

clause does not bite, i.e. is ineffective to prevent judicial review.

This was what happened in the case of Anisminic Ltd v Foreign Compensation Commission.

Page 18: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

When ultra vires is abandoned a decision made in breach of natural justice - which now comes from the common law — will naturally always be made ' in terms of the Act'. And the ouster clause will be effective.

This was the view taken in the South African case of Staatspresident v United Democratic Front.

So the abandonment of ultra vires means that straightforward ouster clauses would become effective.

This amounts to a substantial evisceration of the reach of judicial review and a profound derogation from the principles of the rule of law.

It is, of course, not intended by the common law theorists but it is perfectly logical and this logic has been adopted in terms by the highest court at the time in South Africa. It requires a cogent response from those that would abandon ultra vires.

Page 19: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

Professor Craig Craig's response is that this is not the unavoidable

outcome when judicial review is stripped of its ultra vires roots.

He goes on to explain the way in a which a court could rely on 'a common law constitutional principle' in order to prevent the working of the ouster clause;

That is by recognising that 'the inherent power of the courts should not readily taken to be wholly excluded from review'.

The court could then go on to consider the nature of the alleged error before them;

The ouster clause would only be effective if the error was not one challengeable under standard heads of review.

Page 20: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

Craig's argument does not stand up to scrutiny. For one thing, we are yet again faced with the parliamentary

sovereignty issue: the statute appears to say clearly that the decision should not be challenged.

Only the ultra vires doctrine allows us to review the decision without setting up the supposed 'inherent power' of the courts against the will of Parliament.

But there is a more specific and fundamental problem underlying Craig's logic.

He asserts that no court would necessarily reason as the South African court did in the UDF case, nor indeed as the House of Lords did in Anisminic; therefore neither case aids the proponents of ultra vires. It is true enough that neither case was a foregone conclusion -

but then, no case is. So, even if the inherent judicial power to which Craig refers can be shown to exist there is nothing to say the court would use it, or how they would use it

Page 21: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

It is not justified for Craig to tell us on the one hand that the court would not be forced into the reasoning of the UDF case, and on the other to state that '...a judge would reason as follows...’. He or she might not necessarily reason in the way he argues at all.

The outcome would not be certain.

Thus, Craig's supposed common law safeguard against ouster clauses moves us no further forward at all.

The fact is that this perfectly logical reasoning was accepted in the UDF case and, if ultra vires were abandoned, it could be adopted in other cases.

The case of Boddington v British Transport Police illustrates another major problem that would surface were ultra vires to be abandoned.

This case established that an individual could defend themselves against a criminal charge brought under a particular bylaw by arguing that the bylaw itself was invalid

They were not restricted, as some cases, had suggested that they could only challenge the validity of the bylaw by way of an application for judicial review.

Page 22: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

After all, said the courts, judicial review for any one of a number of reasons - delay, denial of leave, insufficient means — might not be possible.

If the court were then to insist that the challenge could only made by means of judicial review, it can be seen that a person could be sanctioned for breaching a bylaw that was in fact itself illegal.

Hence the acknowledgement of the possibility of this defensive, or collateral, challenge.

But if ultra vires disappears, then so too would collateral challenge. This is because ultra vires makes possible such a challenge. Magistrates' courts do not have the power to issue certiorari; they cannot quash an invalid bylaw

However, they will not enforce bylaws that are void, because to do so would be to give effect to legal nullities.

But a bylaw is void because it has been made ultra vires; an intra vires bylaw would typically be considered merely voidable, i.e. as an existing law that is liable to be set aside.

Page 23: JUDICIAL CREATIVITY AND JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW * Christopher Forsyth * Linda Whittle* *** Christopher Forsyth is a Reader in Public

The magistrates' court cannot strike the law down or ignore it; it is bound to follow it, and collateral challenge would therefore fail.

Collateral challenge is thus quite clearly wrapped up in the concept - and practical application - of the ultra vires doctrine.