13
Irony, Allegory, and Metaphysical Decay Author(s): Gordon Teskey Source: PMLA, Vol. 109, No. 3 (May, 1994), pp. 397-408 Published by: Modern Language Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/463076 . Accessed: 17/11/2013 11:25 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Modern Language Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to PMLA. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Irony, Allegory, and Metaphysical DecayAuthor(s): Gordon TeskeySource: PMLA, Vol. 109, No. 3 (May, 1994), pp. 397-408Published by: Modern Language AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/463076 .

Accessed: 17/11/2013 11:25

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Modern Language Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to PMLA.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Gordon Teskey

Irony, Allegory, and Metaphysical

Decay

GORDON TESKEY, associ- Ahnlich Hallmann, wie er diese Tugend an der zichtigen Agytha illustriert,

ate professor of English at deren "Geburts-Glied" noch viele Jahre nach ihrer Bestattung unverwest im Grabe gefunden worden sei.

Cornell University, teaches rae e e Walter Benjamin

Spenser and Milton. This essay will appear, in somewhat differ- It is the same in Hallmann, as he illustrates this virtue in the chaste Agytha,

ent form"Geburts-Glied" (birth-member, ie. womb) is book Allegorysaid to have been found still undecayed in her grave.

and Violence, to be published

by Cornell University Press.

UNTIL COLERIDGE the dominant conception of alle-

gory was never far removed from the rhetorical definition standardized by Quintilian: "continued metaphor."' It is still a

commonplace of encyclopedias and handbooks of literary terms. Quintilian says more about allegory than this, but for subsequent critical theory his presentation of irony as a species of allegory is especially relevant. Irony is inverted "other speaking": "On the other hand, that class [of allegory] in which opposites are shown [quo contraria ostenduntur] is irony" (8.6.54).2 Because the latter claim is incompatible with the first (one cannot, by extending a metaphor, say the opposite of what one means), postclassical theory of allegory tends to leave irony off to one side. Quintilian elsewhere states that irony can manifest itself either in the realm of figures or in that of

tropes and that figurative irony can have nothing to do with tropes like metaphor and its extended form, allegory (9.1.3-7; 9.2.44-47). Even for him there are species of irony that appear to escape enclosure by allegory, though their escape is equivocal.

The first of these equivocal escapees "derives its name from negation" and is called antiphrasis.3 In its most radical form an- tiphrasis implies the negation of the very subject that speaks, as if to say "I" and "Not I." Quintilian's uncertainty whether irony is included in allegory turns on whether antiphrasis is a sport of irony

397

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Irony, Allegory, and Metaphysical Decay

or its radical essence. If antiphrasis is irony's essence, then all forms of irony must threaten from their place on the inside of allegory the existence of what allegory cannot help affirm- ing. What allegory cannot help affirming is the logocentric plurality of its meanings, grounded in the material unity of its signs-in a word, polysemy. A sign can mean different things in different contexts because all signs participate in one unifying truth. Nothing in an allegory is absolutely opposed to anything else. Antiphrasis and polysemy are therefore as rigorously incom- patible as are the relations of the different to the same and the part to the whole. But they ap- proach chaos, and rise out of it, along similar roads.

We might want to know if they meet some- where before the gates of this chaos-chaos as the potential to which knowing as schematizing responds (Heidegger 84)-or if there is always a median between them. In either case we are concerned with the "primal scene" of the encoun- ter between polysemy and antiphrasis, inasmuch as that scene-a place of increasingly bold juxtaposition, unrestrained analogy, violence, struggle, and noise -holds the underlying sub- stance of allegorical expression.4 The potential for the imprinting of schematic form in this substance rests in two interwoven constraints. Total substitutability is constrained just enough to become polysemy, and total noncoincidence is constrained just enough to become antiphrasis, such that the two roads form a grid where each alternately goes under the other to assert itself as the more fundamental. Polysemy wants to infect antiphrasis with likeness, to make it a witty affirmation of a sameness that is hidden in difference. Antiphrasis wants to cut every synec- dochal relation within polysemy, forcing the elements to stand apart as opposite terms. Such an encounter, at once conflictual and productive, may be represented by an allegorized (but origi- nally ironic) myth: Venus and Mars struggling in the net of the logos, at once copulating and struggling to break free (Buffiere 168-72). We will not return to this image until we conclude, but it may serve as an emblem of the turbulent substratum in which allegory imprints its forms.

In trying to penetrate the veil of those forms,

one either uses polysemy to interpret, thereby doing what allegory wants one to do, or one ironizes and demystifies, using antiphrasis as a kind of abrasive to scrape away the allegorized gods that have, as it were, coagulated on top of the substance. (Of course one cannot really use irony: it is not an implement but an ethical category. One can be ironic, like Socrates, or a little like him. But when irony is objectively determined by markers -changes of expression and tone, or the marginal notation ironice-it spoils.) It may be possible to assert that the abrasive of irony is all that is left when the gods have been scraped down to noise. But one would first have to explore the possibility that a residue is left and that it is what one would least expect it to be a historical event.

To speak of this event as a substance means that beneath the visible events of literary history there is a much slower event (optimistically referred to as a tradition) for which I shall have to justify the term metaphysical decay. For the moment this event can only be described as emerging from ancient polytheism, articulating itself to the world as medieval polysemy, and concluding in Enlightenment insubstantiality, where allegory is a species of "wit," in Addison's (Lockean) sense (Spectator 62).5 It might there- fore be asked if the event, having gone through these phases, resolves itself in antiphrasis and then generates the symbol to compensate for allegory's loss (Halmi 13-14). Or is the symbol, like Agytha's womb, all that is left of something that has rotted away?

The ambiguity of the relation of irony to allegory in Quintilian can be understood in terms of a grammatical metaphor that structures them both from below. The deviation of allegory from its proper sense is comparable to the declination of nouns from the nominative, or "upright," case. Allegory can thus be thought of as leaning away at various oblique angles from soldierly directness, where what is said and what is meant coincide. When the discourse bends around to the point (six o'clock) where it can only turn upward again, it is no longer just deviating from but opposing uprightness. This is the position of irony, the topological nadir. Anything pos-

398

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Gordon Teskey

ited here is posited as absolute, nondialectical negation.

The last statement belongs to (indeed, it pos- sesses) Paul de Man in a lecture called "The

Concept of Irony." De Man is aware of the irony of this, even as he warns us away from the thought that anyone, least of all the ironist, could have irony under control. The warning may itself be ironic (he warns of this, too), at once affirming and negating the truth of the discourse in which it appears and for which it speaks. In de Man's account, however, it is precisely this excessive- ness with regard to all systems (beginning with the one that posits a subject) that makes irony productive of every possibility of system to ob- tain among the less rigorously oppositional tropes, for irony isn't a trope. It is not necessary here to go into the intricacies of de Man's

argument, which involve an account of the gene- sis of synthetic and analytic determinations from oppositional positing and of the emergence of the entire system of tropes from that process. It is enough to say that the power of the argument lies in the inversion of the classical account, where tropology deviates from upright, subject- centered, nominative, straightforward speaking. Speaking against now comes before, and enables, speaking other.

In the classical account of tropology as devia- tion it is possible to imagine getting back, by interpretive correction, to the upright position of a linguistically omnipotent self, one that both intends and deflects its intentions in a language it "uses." Irony upsets this account because it speaks not from an angular but from an opposite position, where the continuity of the circle is broken: "I" and "Not I." Every ironic statement says both of these things, and says that it says them. (Samuel Beckett's play Not I is the purest example of sustained dramatic irony.) Out of that abyss of the infinitely possible is generated every possibility of figurative language.

In developing this argument, de Man gives an account of how the theory of irony in Friedrich Schlegel derives from Fichte's analysis of the subject as the radically nondialectical positing of opposite terms. This radical element in Schlegel's theory aroused considerable irritation in some very considerable figures, such as Hegel and

Kierkegaard (that's not, as de Man says, n'im- porte qui). But the force of this radicalism does not derive from the impossibility of interpreting irony. It needs no Schlegel come back from the

grave to tell us a person, a voice, or a discourse can never again be reliably straightforward after once being ironic. What Schlegel has come back to tell us-and it is a secret de Man claims (but with how much irony?) the entire academic discipline of Germanistik is devoted to hiding- is that irony is unlimited in its scope: everything we say, and everything we are, is but a temporary escape from its field. The silence behind irony is the silence of the grave, which opens beneath all

possibilities of figurative language, including al-

legory. Allegory is now a species of irony rather than the other way round. Irony devours its host from within.

An anxiety similiar to that caused by Schlegel underlies the reluctance of postclassical literary theory to include, as Quintilian does, irony within allegory. Thus Puttenham, otherwise Quintilian's spaniel, departs from him here: "Al-

legoria is when we do speak in sense translative and wrested from the owne signification, never- theless not altogether contrary but having much conveniencie with it" (3.18; emphasis mine). Clearly the reluctance to make irony a species of

allegory has much to do with irony's not requir- ing metaphor. But a deeper objection to the inclusion in allegory of what is "altogether con- trary" is the entirely negative disposition of irony with respect to interpretation. There is nothing objectively there for the listener or the reader to interpret. In the classical account of allegory the reader interprets by recognizing all points of correspondence in an objective "conveniencie," as when the state is recognized in the tale of a ship heading into rough seas. Postclassical the- ory of allegory likewise assumes that figurative obliquity is merely rhetorical and can at any moment be corrected. Thus Isidore of Seville definesfigure as "a fault that occurs with reason" (1.35.71; Minnis and Scott 133). But by Putten- ham's time it is recognized that any effort to stabilize a theory of allegory with irony inside it would be undermined by irony's power, which, as Kierkegaard says, lies in "infinite, absolute negativity" (26). Better to keep it outside.

399

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Irony, Allegory, and Metaphysical Decay

The postclassical exclusion of irony from alle- gory made it possible to defer at some length (and it is this historical length that is reckoned with here) the Enlightenment conception of alle- gory as a mechanical exercise in wit. In other words, the practice of allegory from late antiq- uity to the Enlightenment is made possible by suppressing antiphrasis in favor of polysemy, drawing the grid inward so that it looks like a perspectival regress to an origin that remains out of sight. As a result, the temporal experience of reading is registered in the subject as movement within what Coleridge, speaking of The Faerie Queene, calls "mental space" (Lectures 409-10). The resonance throughout that continuum, how- ever, is given off not by polysemy alone but by polysemy in its struggle with antiphrasis, a strug- gle from which is produced the sense of the sacred within: "There are many mysteries con- tained in poetry," Sidney confides, "which of purpose were written darkly, lest by profane wits it should be abused" (121). It is hardly news to say that this assumption upholds allegorical ex- pression from antiquity to the Enlightenment. The point is that the assumption is no less arbitrary than irony in the way it posits a subject thinking below (hyponoia) an impenetrable dis- course. The subject of irony splits whenever we try to locate it and leaves behind the sense of our being held in an aggressively mobile attention. The subject of allegory withdraws from wherever we try to locate it and leaves behind the sense that our aggressive attention has failed to grasp what is there. But the mystery of those mysteries to which Sidney refers is that they descend into chaos, not into truth. That descent is the sub- stance of allegorical expression from antiquity to the Enlightenment, giving allegory the luminous- ness in obscurity that Spenser calls "darke con- ceit" (737), the sense of an immanent mind working within. The history of allegory, from antiquity to the Enlightenment, is impelled by the suppression of irony and the haunting of noise.

The constitution of such a history is the main point of contact between allegory and psycho- analysis, which must likewise recur to "histories" made possible by the suppression of irony and the haunting of noise. The unconscious is an

underlying continuum of thought wherein forms come into being and then pass away; but like Aristotelian substance, the unconscious is pure potency, or dynamis, and can never be seen in itself. If allegorical interpretation makes a differ- ence distinct from that made by psychoanalysis (and how distinct is a real question), it is like its modern successor in one important respect: its mediation of the transference. Allegory breaks down the division between the mind of the text and the mind of the reader as the two are engaged in a circuit, and the other that thinks in the text has the same transformational effect on all input as does the unconscious. The concept of the unconscious is structured as a positive subject that is always negating itself: "I" and "Not I." Through that dynamic the unconscious develops a polysemous interaction between the most het- erogeneous orders to appear on its ground. I observed earlier that for allegory such a ground is woven together as the grid of antiphrasis and polysemy, each being inimical to and bound up with the other. Allegory cannot emerge or take place there without a logocentric regrounding by which polysemy is made the more fundamental. An indication that this has occurred is the post- classical exclusion of irony from allegory. The grid is drawn inward toward a center like the vanishing point in linear perspective - or, to use a modern cosmological term, the singularity. Considered formally, a singularity is an irra- tional point outside a system on which the possibility of ordered relations inside the system is based. Once that irrational ground is estab- lished, all relations can be understood as parts of a whole.

But this whole will be disrupted at every point by the antiphrastic dynamic it has tried to ex- clude and partly suppressed. Because of the resonance of its visible forms, the system forgets the disruption and interprets the noise as the resonance of truth. Such is the interpretation of nature Baudelaire invokes in "Correspon- dances" when he speaks of all things responding to one another remotely, like echoes that from a distance are lost in each other as one: "Comme de longs echos qui de loin se confondent / Dans une tenebreuse et profonde unite" (18). In a system of this kind every determination of mean-

400

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Gordon Teskey

ing is rendered unstable by the almost limitless correspondences with other determinations, for these are only limited at the limit, by the configu- ration of the system as a totality. The instability that antiphrasis introduces throughout can be overcome not by any logical operation-the system can never be made clean-but only by the continual interpretation of noise as the reso- nance of truth. This act of interpretation is what de Man, speaking of the genesis of the tropes, calls the performative. Interpretation makes what it then claims to be its justifying ground, "une tenebreuse et profonde unite."

The claim that is made for the tropical pro- ductiveness of antiphrastic irony may seem un- persuasive, at least in the compressed form offered by de Man. There needs to be some mechanism to get from the moment of contra- diction to the tropical unfolding of determinative statements. I come back to this point near the end and raise it here only to indicate that polysemy and antiphrasis establish incompatible but parallel relations with disorder, the one working by analogy, the other by absolute (i.e., nondialectical) negation. If disorder is under- stood as unrestricted analogy, where anything can be made to mean anything else (the state of crisis reached by allegory in Benjamin's account of it), polysemy, mobilizing a theory of corre- spondences, is the most direct means of produc- tion out of that state. Antiphrasis imposes on disorder a rudimentary, nondialectical order of the different and the same: "I" and "Not I." Polysemy draws out of the fund of disorder arbitrary juxtapositions that look like the rela- tions of parts to a whole. These relations evoke correspondences in a forest (the word forest evoking its esoteric sense as substance, silva) of symbols that look back at us as if they had minds of their own: "L'homme y passe a travers des forets de symboles / Qui l'observent avec des regards familiers" 'Man walks within these groves of symbols, each / Of which regards him as a kindred thing' (Baudelaire 18; 19). A mul- titude of dialectically negative associations ("Not I") is evolved for the purpose of extending the self through an alien text or, as in the Baudelaire sonnet, through an alien but textual- ized (hence familiar) nature: "I, but also my

other, my id, which must ultimately lead back to me."

Polysemy is only a more hermeneutically ac- tive form of this primitive sense of the text as an observing, ironic other. Instead of positing the "Not I" as an indeterminate void, polysemy finds an other to engage in a circuit that progresses or ascends. In this way allegory generates state- ments out of disorder and acquires the mental characteristics of any system with multiple feed- back loops. The longer a text understood to be polysemous is interpretively engaged, the more it will seem to have a mind of its own capable of explicating anything introduced into its struc- tures (exegesis being always a function of eis- egesis, or input). The text seems to contain under its surface not just a meaning but a reasoning power, a logos, which when carried to its limit is the logos upholding the world.

The system in which polysemy dominates an- tiphrasis is largely dispelled in the Enlighten- ment, with the result that allegory is pushed to its extremes in apocalyptic vision and satire. The entire intermediate realm of analogies and cor- respondences, the "forest" through which alle- gorical narratives pass, no longer exists. In its place is an ideal of noiseless communication between minds that are perfectly detached from the channel between them. The more obvious historical consequences of this change are that allegory loses much of its narrative and icono- graphic complexity, that the theory of allegory is reoriented from the cosmic mysticism of the Renaissance to the rhetorical model of angular speaking, and that the examples of allegory thought to be most worthy of imitation are late antique ecphrases like Lucian's "Calumny of Apelles" and the anonymous Tablet of Cebes. The absurdities remarked in Spenser by eigh- teenth-century critics would have been under- stood by the poet not as breaking the rules but as breaking through familiar patterns of thought to deeper and more difficult thought. So com- pletely is this probing of noise rejected by En- lightenment theorists under the influence of Lockean psychology that the power of allegori- cal works to generate meaning from an underly- ing disorder is taken away. The disorder is now nothing other than the proclivity of ideas to

401

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Irony, Allegoty, and Metaphysical Decay

associate randomly and is regarded as absolute error. As interpretation is supplanted by judg- ment, polysemy is untangled and forced into two levels, the figurative and figured, each coherent in itself and rigorously distinct from the other.

That which defers until the Enlightenment the reduction of allegory to a species of wit is des- ignated by terms like numen, resonance, mystery, and vision. Although such words are inadequate to what this phenomenon is, they have a func- tion to perform on its behalf. As versions of the promise that what lies beneath visible signs is something other than absolute noise, they can be accommodated to the methods and aims of poetics, as I have attempted to do elsewhere ("Allegory"). But while such an accommodation may be an inevitable preliminary, it can contrib- ute nothing to what is undertaken here. Nor is the frame of cultural anthropology more useful than that of poetics. Both these discourses must exclude as obscurantist a more radical question- ing of what the essence, or ground, of the numinous is, a ground that is at once historical, inasmuch as it changes, and metaphysical, inas- much as it concerns what is not supposed to be subject to change: the divine. But it is just one event unfolding-and opening the space into which it unfolds -from antiquity to the Enlight- enment. In it is imprinted the succession of events called literary and cultural history.6

"Succession of events" is a drastic simplifica- tion. It would be more responsible to speak of locally autonomous arrays complicating and di- versifying themselves over time-for example, the development of erotic allegorical poetry in France from Raoul de Houdenc to Jean de Meun or the development of typological iconography from the Abbey of St. Denis to Chartres and Reims. But what all allegorical works in such arrays have in common is their rootedness in an event we participate in when we have the sense of an immanent mind withholding something more. This withholding cannot be explained away either as a technical requirement of alle- gory or as a cultural predisposition. To account for it in such terms is to skip over the otherness of what one wants to explain and enlist it in the task of explaining. We want to know why the

effect is sought in the first place and why the predisposition is there. To skip over the other- ness of what is being explained is to bring the thing around to our side for use, making it an implement so as not to have to contemplate its strangeness. We think we attend to something else, and when it too becomes strange we skip over the strangeness by bringing the new "ob- ject" (that which is "thrown against" conscious- ness) around. It is hard to do anything else. The only other possibility is to keep the thing where it is, in the strangeness that comes from its being an event that is opening its time. The numinous event is the substance of allegorical expression in a way that it cannot be for irony, because irony, as an ethical state, is never placed before the self as an other, ready to be left where it is or brought around for use as an implement. Irony is already totally confined to the subject. What power does it then have?

Irony can disrupt everything, since there is nothing into which its disintegrative force cannot reach and nothing above which its scorn cannot rise. But it can do so only where everything is gathered for it in the realm of the subject. As Schlegel says in one of his literary aphorisms, even with the help of the most open explanation, irony remains a riddle to anyone who does not inhabit it as an ethical state: "Wer sie nicht hat, dem bleibt sie auch nach dem offensten Gestand- nis ein Ratsel" 'To him who has it not, even the most open explanation remains a riddle' (160; my trans.). This is not altogether to its advan- tage. If irony seems infinitely strong in itself, it is utterly weak before the brutality of power, whether the power of history, of oppression, or of physis itself: "error, madness, and stupidity." As de Man says in "The Concept of Irony," what Schlegel is referring to in these words may be taken, in the most extreme sense, as the absolute disorder out of which the world is raised by understanding: "Und ist sie selbst diese un- endliche Welt nicht durch den Verstand aus der Unverstandlichkeit oder dem Chaos gebildet?" 'Is not this entire infinite world built out of non-understanding, out of chaos, by means of understanding?' (Schlegel 370; trans. de Man, "Concept").7 The noise of the event must be skipped over by understanding, which brings

402

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 8: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Gordon Teskey

around to its side what it now instrumentally understands "by means of understanding." One cannot, after all, understand the event in itself as the substance of allegorical expression or use it to understand something else. One has to leave it there in its uselessness and try to bear witness to what occurs on its scene.

De Man mobilizes these passages from Schlegel in his assault on the efforts of Schlegel's interpreters, including Kierkegaard, to under- stand the event as a substance, "to invoke history as hypostasis as a means of defense against this irony" ("Concept"). He is attacking the desire of these interpreters to make the synecdochal order of narrative more fundamental than irony, so that history will stand as proof against irony's disarticulating power. De Man is obviously right: there can be no objective defense against a weapon that is purely subjective. It is therefore strange that in his next sentence - the penulti- mate one of the essay -he says that "irony and history seem to be curiously linked to one an- other," when this linkage can be nothing more than the ability of the one to unlink any narrative link in the other. Irony and history seem to be curiously unlinked. Each is the absence of the other.

Allegory is linked to history, however, through its relation to metaphysical decay. Polysemy is the interpretive resonance of this decay, wherein the independence of metaphysical beings is bro- ken down by their absorption into the unifying order, or frame, of correspondences. This frame is evoked in the mind, and activated through it, by narrative. While individual elements of the narrative will stimulate associations between themselves and their manifold correspondents, the unfolding narrative yields the frame up to the substance of history. A decayed theology is yielded up to further decay, until it is nothing more than a background for the spectacle of coming to be and passing away in human affairs. The process of decay is accelerated by allegory's being increasingly subject to the logical weakness of universal analogy, until anything can be sign of anything else. The passing away of allegory's claims to logical order calls forth some of Ben- jamin's most morbidly lyrical passages on his- tory and impels allegory to what he describes as

its moment of dialectical transcendence and his- torical crisis (166, 232). What is coming to be in the midst of this increasing disorder is not the symbol but history itself. History emerges, in all its romantic triumphalism, as a myth of human progress and, in all its romantic dismay, as a reflection on human insignificance against the background of natural time.

In its most critical state of alienation from nature (in the seventeenth century), allegory reduces everything in the material realm to a substance. Allegory thus augments its power to lay hold of the temporal, objectifying what it makes as belonging to the very substance of history rather than to the realm of ideas. Al- though such narratives will always be vulnerable to ironic disarticulation in the realm of the subject, irony cannot stop allegory's blindly ag- gregative work in the realm of the object, the realm of politics as well as of nature, where error, madness, and above all stupidity ("Wer sie nicht hat . . . ") reign. The basis of allegory in this realm is, for the passersby of "Correspon- dances," both a logical substance and a historical event, a decaying forest of symbols. But it must also be named and described on its own, meta- physical terms. As such, the substance that lies beneath allegorical works belongs originally to the supercelestial realm of metaphysics, of ob- jects par excellence.

To be concerned with metaphysics in late antiquity is to be concerned with the gods, but in the quasi-philosophical light with which they were invested at a time when belief in them was in an advanced stage of decay. Moral, physical, and philosophical interpretation of the gods goes back at least to the sixth century BC; but it is no accident that the gods could be involved in allegorical expression only in a culture linguisti- cally alien to that in which they arose. The Homeric theomachia, or "battle of the gods," is allegorized from an early date but is not a means of allegorical expression until Prudentius's Psy- chomachia. The gods are allegorized in Greek but only become allegorical in Latin.

When Aristotle divides theoretical knowledge into three kinds, physical, mathematical, and metaphysical, the word he uses for the last is theologike 'theological': the knowledge of things

403

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 9: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Irony, Allegory, and Metaphysical Decay

that have both independent being and freedom from change (1026al5; 1064b3). By late anti- quity, theology and metaphysics are indistin- guishable: people can interpret the gods and say prayers to the "inconceivable idea" of the sun. This phrase is from Wallace Stevens's "Notes toward a Supreme Fiction," the first section of which lucidly evokes what the poet calls the "weather" of late antiquity. It does this by showing metaphysical decay as an event:

The death of one god is the death of all. Let purple Phoebus lie in umber harvest, Let Phoebus slumber and die in autumn umber,

Phoebus is dead, ephebe. But Phoebus was A name for something that never could be named. There was a project for the sun and is.

There is a project for the sun. The sun Must bear no name, gold-flourisher, but be In the difficulty of what it is to be. (381)

How is this death historically determined "to be" an event or, as Stevens calls it, a "project"?

The event, given its psychological structure, does not submit readily to an objective construc- tion; we can know it only, as Vico would say, from the inside. Its truth is true not because it reflects something objective but because it emerges (like a performative) from cultural work. In a more narrowly technical sense (as something one brings around in order to know something else) the event can be seen anthropo- logically, as a process of symbolic displacement effecting real change in a world organized throughout by patterns of exchange (Geertz 142- 69). In areas of social practice determined by this anthropological sense-law, education, re- ligious worship, and trade -the impact of the event may be even more evident than it is in the arts. Its manifestation in poetic practice, how- ever, is not just exemplary but constitutive of these other realms and demands to be spoken of first in imaginative terms. Only thus is it possible to witness what occurs on its scene without bringing it around to explain something else. The cause of the resonance in allegorical forms is an underlying metaphysical decay. Hence the gal- vanic liveliness of the personified virtues and

vices, the personified arts, and the personified stages of love (Fletcher 41). Metaphorical lan- guage derived from the body -survival, develop- ment, rebirth, transformation, decay-cannot be entirely avoided in matters of cultural change. The point is to avoid the premature reduction of such language to the narrower categories of social description, brilliantly evoked as they are by Coleridge (Notebooks 3203). It is therefore imperative to state that by "metaphysical decay" in late antiquity I do not mean the suppression of pagan forms of worship or the growing sense of the futility of classical idealism. Momentous as these events are, they follow from and are made possible by the event I am speaking of here: the rotting of the classical gods.

The question, then, is not so much one of what Jean Seznec classically described as the "sur- vival" of the pagan gods as it is a moribund bearing up from below by the gods of all visible cultural forms, even forms with which the gods have nothing to do iconographically (Benjamin 226). But as the gods decompose into their elements (cultic, etiologic, theurgic, physiologi- cal, euhemeristic, iconographic, cosmic), they continue to give off from below, together with the smell of decay, an aroma of Olympian ozone that communicates danger. That is why, when their classical forms were literally raised out of the earth, it could seem to Pater's Christian ascetic "as if an ancient plague-pit had been opened" (121). Boccaccio found the gods in much this condition when-as he describes in the front matter to his Genealogy of the Ancient Gods-he gathered them up like the scattered remains from a shipwreck. When they appear in medieval literature, as in Huon de Meri's Tourneiment Anticrist, the gods seem not to have descended from on high but to have escaped from the earth. In Sir Gawain and the Green Knight a green Mars (complementing Stevens's purple Phoebus) resides in what looks like a burial mound. The event of the rotting of the classical gods is registered anthropologically in the process of symbolic mutation by which a new, more authoritative structure of symbols emerges. America is haunted by the names the aboriginal peoples have given its places, and the old names are preserved because they seem to

404

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 10: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Gordon Teskey

have a numinous connection to what those places are metaphysically: a vast cultural body, now in an advanced stage of decay. What is being suggested here is that a similar but more exten- sive and layered process (because it lacked the suddenness of conquest and genocide) took place in early Christian Europe and that its cultural effects were felt through a period coextensive with the trajectory of allegory as the most authoritative literary form.

In a poetics of allegory the event of the rotting of the classical gods is registered in the numinous effects of the singularity, the vanishing point into which the grid is drawn. As a fiction of presence the singularity is at the opposite discursive ex- treme from the abyss of antiphrasis, but it is no less chaotic and no less productive. Indeed, the way in which the singularity could be produc- tive is much clearer, at least on the level of poetics, because there is a positive mechanism for it: interpretation. Interpretation imposes con- straints on disorder.

While interpretation is in theory as unlimited as disorder itself, it is typically guided in allegori- cal works toward an apocalyptic conclusion. Vision moving inward toward the goal of total identification is at the opposite discursive ex- treme from the antiphrastic structure of irony, in which it seems as if language itself were being torn into fragments. These extremes are marked with great precision in Dante. Language de- scends into the abyss of incoherence in the Inferno and disappears into the silence at the end of the Paradiso. The typical elements of an allegorical work-personifications as actants in a landscape of significant forms -unfold be- tween these linguistic extremes, which are the radicals of polysemy and antiphrasis (Quilligan 163). Any poetics of allegory must confront this primary structure, whose extremes cannot be treated as aberrations to be excluded as faults (as they were in the Enlightenment). Irony is presented in allegory as if it were recuperable to a unified intention, even in the sparagmatic rhetoric of A Tale of a Tub, which is always saying "I" and "Not I." But to recuperate irony to the work of the whole is not to dispel the abyss that irony opens; it is to conceal such a prospect

in a mystical embrace that is no less chaotic than its opposite bodily expression, tearing apart. The singularity is a different interpretation of the chaos into which antiphrasis more openly leads, a rhetorical spin given to antiphrasis to make it look like its opposite. This means that there is, after all, a mechanism within poetics for the generation of the tropes out of antiphrasis as well as out of polysemy. But the mechanism is simply an act of persuasion, the persuasive transference of nondialectical opposition into the logically alien field of the synecdochal, where elements belong to one another as parts of a whole. Just as metaphor may provoke one to assume a more primitive ground in synecdoche-a mystical sense in which lion and hero are parts of a whole

so antiphrasis can be assimilated to the logo- centric imagination as a more radically articu- lated, more recondite expression of polysemy. For Dionysus the Areopagite, only the most monstrous forms can be likened to God (Roc- ques 429). The truth holds every opposite in its embrace and is most present where it is most opposed.

Once this transference of antiphrasis is accom- plished, the starkest disjunctions can be mobi- lized in a narrative allegory, even a narrative like Hegel's. On the level of poetics the opposition of unity and plurality has been persuaded to be- come polysemously as well as narratologically productive. As Chapman puts it, "One no num- ber is; but thence doth flow / The powerful race of number" (5.339-40). The singularity, like the transference of antiphrasis, is an act of persua- sion in the sense de Man applies to Pascal (and with respect to the same mathematical question):

[T]he homogeneity of the universe is recovered, and the principle of infinitesimal symmetry is well estab- lished. But this has happened at a price: the coher- ence of the system is now seen to be entirely dependent on the introduction of an element-the zero and its equivalences in time and motion - that is entirely heterogeneous with regard to the system and is nowhere a part of it. The continuous universe held together by the double wings of the two infinites is interrupted, disrupted at all points by a principle of radical heterogeneity without which it cannot come into being. ("Pascal's Allegory" 10)

405

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 11: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Irony, Allegory, and Metaphysical Decay

These reflections on Pascal's Reflections on Ge- ometry are hard to take out of their context, in which the linguistic equivalent of the arithmet- ical zero tropically undermines all nominal def- initions and the structures of homogeneity ("synecdochal totalizations") that arise from them: zero no number is. Its relevance here is confirmed by de Man in "The Concept of Irony." There the linguistic equivalent of the zero, that which disrupts polysemy at every point, is named and submitted, with inevitable irony, to nominal definition: "irony is the permanent parabasis of the allegory of tropes." Zero is no number, irony no trope.

It looks as if we shall have to go into de Man's "allegory of tropes" after all. Earlier it was sufficient to characterize that allegory as an argument about the genesis of figurality from the positing of nondialectically opposite terms. In the language I have been applying to that argu- ment here, the genesis of polysemy from an- tiphrasis is the suppression of the one by the other, of irony by allegory, so that what is thought to exist out of time is given a temporal form. This "allegory" (in de Man's sense of the word) is a more radical model of tropological development than the ancient model of tropol- ogy as grammatical declination, for it emerges from the failure of the latter to account for antiphrasis. But to "go into" the genesis of figurality from the positing of opposite terms is to do more than to give to that process an allegorical form. It is to enter the scene of genesis and to engage an incoherence one had only attempted to witness before. Likewise, de Man's definition of irony-"permanent parabasis of the allegory of tropes" -involves more than the mere witnessing of logical disruption at all points in the tropological system. It implies direct interference, the ironic disruption of one's own act of telling how the tropes are turned out of the place of linguistic uprightness. (That is the sense in which irony and theory are, for de Man, one and the same.) The evolution of the tropes is not a logical act available to understanding. It is a more radical performance, achieved by means of understanding ("durch den Verstand"), where understanding is a kind of stage prop for

completing the action in a larger, irrational scene.

In a sense, that performance is a narrative one (de Man calls it an allegory). But it is also a spectacle in which we are confronted by the peculiarly theatrical irony of being able to watch without the knowledge of those one observes, like the Wolf Man as he watches his struggling parents. (By their position, they in turn re-create the ironic structure of watching, for the father watches the mother without being seen.) But like the Wolf Man one surrenders, or represses, that irony when imaginatively placing oneself in the scene as an actor, for in the moment of entry the spectacle is transformed into a narrative, and antiphrastic opposition (pleasure and mutila- tion) is compelled to give way to a polysemous dialectic of the self. That dialectic takes the shape of a story of development from childhood, the history of an infantile neurosis, a medieval pil- grimage of the life of man. It is the story (and a persuasive one) of the ego transmitting itself through the "Not I" of the id to anchor every deviation in the ego's past in the uprightness to which it returns-the ego at home, in the nomi- native case.

If de Man's definition of irony as the "perpet- ual parabasis" of the genesis of tropes cannot escape its own irony, my attempt to look in on the scene where allegory starts and to bear witness to the essence of what allegory is violence emerging from noise-is much worse off. Not only can the attempt not escape the antiphrastic dissonance it tries to drown out, it must enter into what it represses. Such engage- ment opposes itself to the dream of escape that sustains ironizing irony to any number of pow- ers. The attempt to define allegory is left trying to hear itself above the noise it has entered, which gets louder by the moment, as Freud stands where Quintilian stood and as the parents of the Wolf Man are transformed into Venus and Mars. The scene where allegory is gathered before its emergence was disclosed earlier in the geometric form of a grid where polysemy and antiphrasis alternately go under each other and where the grid is drawn inward so that it seems to lead into a center. The invisible hand that draws the net in and then hoists it up is that of

406

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 12: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Gordon Teskey

Hephaestus, the demiurgic eiron who has caught Venus and Mars in flagrante delicto. But in what position are they commiting the crime? When this scene is contaminated by the "primal scene" in Freud, the opposite principles the gods repre- sent (concord and discord) are juxtaposed to similarly opposite acts: the positing of the self by the copula ("I am") and the negation of the self in the spectacle of a copulation a tergo ("I" and "Not I"). In the former, the ego as father enters the other to return to itself, as in the classical model of declination from and return to the upright position. In the latter, the ego as mother never has to depart from itself to achieve its desire, but that desire is achieved at the annihi- lating price of castration (Freud, "History" 34- 37). The contradiction is identical in form to the genesis of the tropes out of that which is in a state of "permanent parabasis" from them. But because the subject of irony does not depart from itself into the realm of the nonself, it never establishes limits that could give it any definite form. Irony is therefore unlimited in its scope but powerless before real power -that is, before those who are not just, as Schlegel says, unable to "have" irony but also politically determined not to hear it.

Allegory is not so impotent as irony is, but neither is it so readily dissociated from the interests of power. On the contrary, its essence is violence emerging from chaos to impose sche- matic order on historical process, on the rotting of the classical gods. Beneath the conventional unity of its iconographic system, allegory strug- gles to bring forth from the union of Venus and Mars (even as they embrace in the grave) a world we can value and a narrative in which we can live: the child it hopes for is Harmony. Allegory is, at this level, the creative but also nauseating drive to force heterogeneities together, even as these struggle to break free and die on their own. We can watch them as they effect what the Neoplatonists called the copulation of the world: subject and predicate, idea and substance, mind and nature, institution and body, ethos and history, promise and act, human and inhuman, doing it like wolves.

Notes

19.2.46. "Allegory, which is translated in Latin by inversio, either presents one thing in words and another in meaning, or else something absolutely opposed to the meaning of the words. The first type is generally produced by a series of metaphors" (8.6.44). That the second type, which is "opposed to the meaning," is irony is made clear at 8.6.54. The standard discussion of irony and allegory for the Middle Ages is in Isidore of Seville (1.37.22-26). Allegory is alieniloquium 'other speaking,' and irony, as a species of allegory, is a kind of discourse that indicates an opposite meaning by its tone. This somewhat crude insistence on a marker allows Isidore to distinguish irony from antiphrasis.

2An important reservation is communicated at 8.6.58, where Quintilian notes that other writers deny that irony belongs to allegory as species to genus, because the genus, instead of being lost in its species, retains an attribute that is proper to itself: obscurity. Allegory must therefore be a species alongside and excluding irony. Quintilian has no answer to this objection except to say that it is of no practical interest to the orator. While irony is discussed both as trope, in the eighth book, and as figure, in the ninth, allegory is restricted to tropes. Thus there is some ambiguity even in Quintilian about whether irony can be contained by allegory. I do not recall ever seeing it noted that the canonical definition of allegory as "continued metaphor" occurs as an aside in a discussion of irony: "Ut, quemadmodum a&Xkryoplav facit continua neTa4opa, sic hoc schema faciat tropos ille contextus" 'Just as continued metaphor makes an allegory, so a series of linked tropes would make this figure [irony]' (9.2.46). See MacQueen 49 and Whitman 265.

3"There are, however, certain kinds of this figure [irony] which have no connexion with tropes. In the first place, there is the figure which derives its name from negation and is called by some antiphrasis" (9.2.47).

4"Noise is to the logos what matter was previously to form. Noise is the ground of information" (Serres 22; my trans.).

5Addison cites Locke on the difference between judgment and wit. For a good example of an Enlightenment allegory, see Spectator 63. For allegory as "unsubstantial," see Cole- ridge, Lay Sermons 30.

6See de Man: "The dialectical play between the two modes, as well as their common interplay with mystified forms of language (such as symbolic or mimetic representation), which it is not in their power to eradicate, make up what is called literary history" ("Rhetoric" 226).

7Just before this passage Schlegel speaks of the way any system, including that of the world, is anchored to a single point that is left in obscurity. "Error, madness, and simple- minded stupidity" is de Man's rendering of a passage in Schlegel's Gesprach uiber die Poesie in which an aesthetic system, articulated throughout by an exchange between enthusiasm and irony, must allow to shine through at all points its origin in contradiction (Schlegel 319). Cf. Freud's remark on the "navel" of an otherwise interpretable dream, "the spot where it reaches down into the unknown" (Inter- pretation 525).

407

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 13: Irony, Allegory, And Metaphysical Decay

Irony, Allegory, and Metaphysical Decay

Works Cited

Addison, Joseph. The Spectator. Ed. Donald F. Bond. Vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon-Oxford UP, 1965.

Aristotle. Metaphysics. Ed. W. D. Ross. Vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon-Oxford UP, 1924.

Baudelaire, Charles. The Flowers of Evil. Bilingual ed. Ed. Jonathan Culler and James McGowan. Trans. James McGowan. New York: Oxford UP, 1993.

Benjamin, Walter. The Origin of German Tragic Drama. Trans. John Osborne. London: Verso, 1977.

Boccaccio. Ioanis Bocati Peri genealogias deorum libri quin- decim. Basel, 1532.

Buffiere, Felix. Les mythes d'Homere et la pensee grecque. Paris: Belles Lettres, 1956.

Chapman, George. "Hero and Leander." Marlowe's Poems. Ed. L. C. Martin. New York: Gordian, 1966. 67-139.

Coleridge, Samuel Taylor. The Collected Works of Sam- uel Taylor Coleridge. Kathleen Coburn, gen. ed. Bollin-

gen Series 75. 13 vols. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1969- 87.

Lay Sermons. Vol. 6 of Coleridge, Collected Works. Lectures, 1808-1819, on Literature. Ed. R. A.

Foakes. Vol. 5 of Coleridge, Collected Works. . Notebooks. Vol. 2. Ed. Kathleen Coburn. New York:

Pantheon, 1961. de Man, Paul. "The Concept of Irony." Aesthetic Ideology.

By de Man. Ed. Andrzej Warminski. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, forthcoming.

."Pascal's Allegory of Persuasion." Allegory and Representation. Ed. Stephen J. Greenblatt. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1981. 1-25.

"The Rhetoric of Temporality." Blindness and In- sight. Essays in the Rhetoric of Contemporary Criticism. 2nd rev. ed. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1983. 187-228.

Fletcher, Angus. Allegory: The Theory of a Symbolic Mode. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1964.

Freud, Sigmund. "The History of an Infantile Neurosis." Freud, Standard Edition 17: 7-122.

The Interpretation of Dreams. Freud, Standard Edi- tion 4: 1-338; 5: 339-627.

The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Ed. and trans. James Strachey. 24 vols. London: Hogarth, 1953-74.

Geertz, Clifford. The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic, 1973.

Halmi, Nicholas. "An Anthropological Approach to the Romantic Symbol." European Romantic Review 4 (1993): 13-33.

Heidegger, Martin. The Will to Power as Knowledge and as Metaphysics. The Will to Power as Knowledge and as Metaphysics [and] Nihilism. Ed. David Farrell Krell. Trans. Joan Stambaugh, Krell, and Frank A. Capuzzi. San Francisco: Harper, 1991. Vols. 3 and 4 of Nietzsche.

Isidore of Seville. Etymologiarum sive originum. Vol. 1. Ed. W. M. Lindsay. Oxford: Clarendon-Oxford UP, 1911.

Kierkegaard, Soren. The Concept of Irony, with Continual Reference to Socrates. Ed. and trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1989.

MacQueen, John. Allegory. The Critical Idiom 14. London: Methuen, 1976.

Minnis, A. J., and A. B. Scott. Medieval Literary Theory and Criticism, c. 1100-c. 1375. The Commentary Tradition. Oxford: Clarendon-Oxford UP, 1988.

Pater, Walter. "Winckelmann." Selected Works. Ed. Richard Adlington. New York: Dull, 1948. 97-124.

Puttenham, George. Arte of English Poesie. 1589. Ed. Gladys Doidge Willcock and Alice Walker. Cambridge: Cam- bridge UP, 1936.

Quilligan, Maureen. "Allegory, Allegoresis, and the Dealle- gorization of Language: The Roman de la rose, the De

planctu naturae, and the Parlement of Foules." Allegory, Myth, and Symbol. Ed. Morton W. Bloomfield. Cam- bridge: Harvard UP, 1981. 163-86.

Quintilian. Institutio oratoria. Vol. 3. Trans. H. E. Butler. Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1920.

Rocques, Rene. "Teratologie et th6ologie chez Jean Scot Erigene." Melanges offerts d M. D. Chenu. Ed. Andre Duval. Biblioth&que thomiste 37. Paris: Vrin, 1967.

Schlegel, Friedrich. Charakteristiken und Kritiken I (1796- 1801). Ed. Hans Eichner. Munich: Sch6ningh, 1967. Vol. 2 of Kritische Friedrich-Schlegel-Ausgabe. 35 vols. 1958-91.

Serres, Michel. Genese. Paris: Grasset, 1982. Seznec, Jean. The Survival of the Pagan Gods. The Mytho-

logical Tradition and Its Place in Renaissance Humanism and Art. Trans. Barbara Sessions. Bollingen Series 38. 1953. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1972.

Sidney, Philip. Miscellaneous Prose. Ed. Katharine Duncan- Jones and Jan van Dorsten. Oxford: Clarendon-Oxford UP, 1973.

Spenser, Edmund. The Faerie Queene. Ed. A. C. Hamilton. London: Longman, 1977.

Stevens, Wallace. The Collected Poems of Wallace Stevens. New York: Knopf, 1980.

Teskey, Gordon. "Allegory." The Spenser Encyclopedia. Ed. A. C. Hamilton et al. Toronto: U of Toronto P, 1990. 16-22.

Whitman, John. Allegory. The Dynamics of an Ancient and Medieval Technique. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1987.

408

This content downloaded from 201.234.181.53 on Sun, 17 Nov 2013 11:25:13 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions