Infant industries

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    1/15

    17. INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT

    The argument for protection of an industry based on the usual external

    economies is static in the sense that the assumed distortion due to external

    economies is by implication a permanent characteristic of the technology of

    production that would require correction by government intervention of a

    permanent nature. By contrast, the infant industry argument is explicitly

    dynamic or more accurately it is an argument for government intervention for

    a limited time period only to correct a transient distortion. In the infant

    industry argument, the justification for protection is assumed to disappear

    with the passage of time.

    The infant industry argument of Hamilton and List is usually interpreted

    to imply the need for temporary protection of an industry which would be

    unable to establish itself against free competition from established foreign

    producers. These industries would have to incur temporary excessive costs in

    the initial stages, but they would eventually be able to compete on equal

    terms with foreign producers in the domestic or world market if they were

    given temporary tariff protection to enable them to establish themselves. For

    this argument to be valid, the increase in future national income should

    exceed what it would have been if the infant industry had not been assisted to

    maturity by protection. Protection involves a present cost which can only be

    justified by an increase in fu ture national income above what it would

    otherwise be. Furthermore, to justify government intervention, external

    economies should exist that make the social rate of return differ from the

    private rate of return in the infant stage of production activity. If the higher

    income accrues later to those who incur the costs initially, and if the capital

    market functions efficiently, the investment will be privately undertakenunless the rate of return on it is below the rate of return available on

    alternative investments. In this case the investment would be socially as well

    as privately unprofitable. To provide an argument for government

    intervention, the social rate of return must exceed the private rate of return on

    the investment by a wide enough margin to make a socially profitable

    investment privately unprofitable.

    For example, if as a result of infant production activities the knowledge of

    a certain production technique is acquired by the entrepreneur who has

    undertaken the investment, then the knowledge may be freely applied by

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT 1

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    2/15

    other entrepreneurs with little or no cost of acquiring it. That is, the product

    of investment in the acquisition of knowledge, once created, can be enjoyed

    by additional users without additional cost of production. Then the social

    benefit exceeds the private benefit of investment in learning industrial

    production techniques.

    It takes time for a firm to establish a new profitable business. If allentrepreneurs and bankers know that computer hardware is a potentially

    profitable production activity for Korean firms, they should be prepared to

    accept short term losses as an investment toward long run gains, without any

    government intervention. In order to justify government intervention, there

    should be externalities. For instance, an entrepreneur is not usually able to

    fully capture the benefits of training its employees. Because those

    employees, once they acquire experience and knowledge of a new production

    activity, frequently move to other firms who want to start the same

    production activities, or even start their own firms in the same line of

    business.

    Where the social benefits of the learning process exceed the private

    benefits, the most appropriate government policy would be to subsidize thelearning process itself, through such techniques as financing or sponsoring

    pilot enterprises on the condition that the experience acquired and techniques

    developed be made available to all would-be producers. A possible reason

    why the social benefit may exceed the private hinges on the facts that much

    of the technique of production is embodied in the skill of the labor force, and

    that the insitutions of the labor market give the worker the property rights in

    any skills he acquires at the employer's expense. Consequently, the private

    rate of return to the employer on the investment in on-the-job training may be

    lower than the social rate of return, because the trained worker may be hired

    away by a competitor. The appropriate policy in this case would entail the

    government either financing on-the-job training or establishing institutions

    enabling labor to finance its own training out of the higher future income

    resulting from training. In this case, a subsidy on production or on invest-ment in the infant industry would be economically inefficient in principle,

    since neither type of subsidy would necessarily stimulate the type of invest-

    ment in knowledge subject to an excess of social over private return. In any

    case, the government intervention in the form of tariff protection of the infant

    industry is the second-best policy. The first-best policy is to take care of the

    transient external economies at the source by using tax and subsidy measures

    for a limited time period.

    The private rate of return necessary to induce investment in a certain

    infant industry may exceed the private and social rates of return on alternative

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT2

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    3/15

    investments for a variety of reasons. For instance, entrepreneurs may be

    excessively pessimistic about the prospects of an industry. In this case the

    most appropriate policy would involve publication of expert estimates of the

    prospects for the industry in question. Alternatively, imperfections in the

    capital market may make the cost of financing the investment in a specific

    infant industry excessively high, especially if the industry requires a largeamount of initial investment to acquire the minimum unit-cost plant size. In

    this case, subsidizing the provision of capital would be the appropriate policy.

    The existence of large enough external economies in infant industrial

    production activities that warrant government intervention implies that the

    imputed losses associated with an initial period of low returns must be fully

    recovered (say, by the whole society) with interest at a later date, though not

    by the individual entrepreneur starting up the activity. The case for a time-

    limited government intervention is based on the fact that the positive

    externalities that are generated for a limited period of time from the

    development of an infant activity will accrue to other than those undertaking

    the activity initially such as the whole economy. (See Krueger and Tuncer

    1982.) An industry stops being an infant industry when it stops generatingexternal economies.

    According to the two-factor Heckscher-Ohlin theorem, a developing

    country has a comparative advantage in labor-intensive commodity

    production. If, however, substantial external economies associated with the

    production activities of the labor- intensive commodities exist in its early

    phase of production, those labor-intensive commodities may not be produced

    domestically and exported to international market without government

    intervention in the form of export subsidies financed by tax revenue. The

    government may simply decide to protect the infant industry in which it has

    potential comparative advantage by restricting import as long as the industry

    generates substantial external economies. Sooner or later, the infant industry

    will stop generating any more substantial external economies. By that time,

    the potential comparative advantage may become the actual one, and thedeveloping country may commence exporting the labor-intensive commodity

    a la Heckscher-Ohlin. This latter strategy may be called the import-

    substitution-oriented growth strategy, in the sense that the country gives up

    the idea of exporting the commodities with potential comparative advantage

    and is content with only self-sufficiency in these products until they become

    matured.

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT 3

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    4/15

    Hamilton (1791) and List (1841) argued for the promotion of infant

    manufacturing activities as a vehicle for catch-up; the Pre-War Japan pursued

    the imperialist colonialism with imported Western technologies for catch-up;

    and the East Asian NICs pursued the outward-looking export-oriented

    strategy as a device for catch-up. Myint (1977) acknowledges that the

    outward-looking approach emphasizes the expansion of external trade as theengine of growth but points out its tendency to underplay the fact that a

    country may not be able to take full advantage of its external economic

    opportunities unless its internal domestic economic organization is

    strengthened and improved. Hamilton and List are cited as the original

    contributors of the infant industry argument. Many economists recognize the

    importance of their analysis of the growth-stimulating effect of infant

    industry promotion. But Hamilton and List are not respected as development

    theorists or trade theorists. The traditional criticism against them seems to be

    is that they failed to clarify the concept of the engine of growth and to

    discover the idea of [transient] external economies associated with a dynamic

    learning process, and this failure vitiated their approach to the subject. Kemp

    (1960) even fails to mention List in writing about The Mill-Bastable Infant-Industry Dogma.3 If one, however, reads carefully the writings of Hamilton

    and List, one can feel that these criticisms leveled against them might well be

    unwarranted. The only valid criticism might be that Hamilton and List

    argued for the promotion of infant manufacturing activities without

    particularly warning against the possible undesirable results when import-

    substitution-oriented approach is adopted in pursuing such an object.

    A. Alexander Hamilton

    Hamilton (1791; 1966: 249) believes that manufacturing establishments

    not only contribute to increase national product but they also contribute to

    rendering national product greater than they could possibly be, without suchestablishments. That is, manufacturing activity is the engine of growth.

    Manufacturing activities furnish (ibid: 254-255) greater scope for the

    diversity of talents and dispositions, which discriminate men from each other.

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT4

    3Kemp defines the case for infant industry promotion as follows. Practice makes

    perfect and a firm can learn from its own experiences and from those of other firms in

    the same industry. Even if later profits, suitably discounted, sufficiently exceed the

    losses of the early learning period, firms will not be willing to shoulder the early

    losses if the lessons of its experiences would be freely available to any followers.

    Then the initial subsidy is an essential condition for the establishment of the industry.

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    5/15

    . . And [therefore]. . . the results of human exertion may be immensely

    increased by diversifying its object. When all the different kinds of industry

    obtain in a community, each individual can find his proper element, and can

    call into activity the whole vigour of his nature. Hamilton believes that

    (ibid: 242) manufacturing activities open a wider field to exertions of

    ingenuity than agriculture and that (ibid: 256) the spirit of enterprise. . .must necessarily be. . . expanded in proportion to the. . . variety of the

    occupations and productions (ibid: 156). Hamilton does not only emphasize

    a fuller utilization of the given existing resources but also the longer run

    changes in the supply of productive factors. According to Hamilton (ibid:

    256), manufacturing activities tend to provoke exertion, cherish and

    stimulate the activity of human mind by which the wealth of a nation may

    be promoted which is of greater consequence in the general scale of

    national exertion.4

    Hamilton believes that (ibid: 268), because of the natural disadvantages

    of a new undertaking, to maintain between the recent establishments of one

    country and the long matured establishments of another country, a

    competition upon equal terms, both as to quality and price, is in most casesimpracticable. The disparity. . . must necessarily be so considerable as to

    forbid a successful rivalship, without the extraordinary aid and protection of

    government.

    According to Hamilton (ibid: 266-267), the strong influence of habit and.

    . . the fear of want of success in untried enterprisesthe intrinsic difficulties

    incident to first essays towards a competition with those who have previously

    attained to perfection in the business to be attempted[make the changes

    from agriculture to manufacturing] likely to be more tardy than might consist

    with the interest either of individuals or of the society. . . . . To produce the

    desirable changes, as early as may be expedient, may therefore require the

    incitement and patronage of government [as may be capable of overcoming

    the obstacles]. Hamilton believes that (ibid: 269) the existence of

    assurance of aid from the government. . . may be essential to fortifyadventures against. . . [those who enjoy] the advantages naturally acquired

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT 5

    4Hamilton believes that (ibid: 249) manufacturing activities will have a

    considerable influence upon the total mass of industrious effort in a community that

    will add to the community a degree of energy and effect, which are not easily

    conceived. Hamilton observes that (ibid: 260) the multiplication of manufactories

    not only furnishes a market for [the surplus produce of the soil]. . . but it likewise

    creates a demand for such as were either unknown or produced in inconsiderable

    quantities.

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    6/15

    from practice and previous possession of the ground. . . According to the

    U.S. constitution (ibid: 302-303), the National Legislature has express

    authority to lay and collect taxes, duties, imports and excises. . . and provide

    for the common defense and general welfare. And according to Hamilton,

    the phrase [general welfare] is as comprehensive as any that could have been

    used. Hamilton (ibid:302) believes that it is the interest of the society. . . tosubmit to a temporary expense, which is more than compensated, by an

    increase of industry and wealth, by an augmentation of resources and

    independence; and by the circumstance of eventual cheapness. . . Hamilton

    believes that (ibid: 286) the internal competition, which takes place, soon

    does away every thing like monopoly, and by degrees reduces the price of

    the article to the minimum of a reasonable profit on the capital employed. . .

    In a national view, a temporary enhancement of price must always be well

    compensated by a permanent reduction of it.

    Hamilton and List are often criticized for their failure to understand the

    second best nature of tariff protection of infant industries. Hamilton, as well

    as List, however, seem to have been well aware of the first-best nature of tax-

    cum-subsidy approach. Hamilton states that (ibid: 298-301) pecuniarybounties are the most efficacious means of encouraging manufactures. . .

    overcoming the obstacles which arise from the competition of superior skill

    and maturity elsewhere because they tend to stimulate and uphold new

    enterprises [undertakings]. . . in the first attempts avoiding the inconve-

    nience of a temporary augmentation of price.5

    Hamilton believes that (ibid: 301 & 336) the public encouragement of the

    acquisition of a new and useful branch of industry leads to a permanent

    addition to the general stock of productive labor and hence bounties and

    premiums as well as tariff protections are productive, when rightly applied

    and particularly in the infancy of new enterprises [they are] indispensable.

    Hamilton (ibid: 307) emphasizes the needs for the encouragement of new

    inventions and discoveries, at home, and of the introduction into [the home

    country]. . . of such as may have been made in other countries; particularlythose, which relate to machinery. Hamilton (ibid: 338) recommends the

    creation of a fund for paying the bounties and let the commissioners be

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT6

    5According to Hamilton (ibid: 304), premiums serve to reward some particular

    excellence of superiority, some extraordinary exertion or skill, and are dispensed only

    in a small number of cases. But their effect is the stimulation of general effort. . . they

    address themselves to different passions; touching the chords as well of emulation as

    of interest. They are accordingly a very economical mean of exciting the enterprise of

    a whole community.

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    7/15

    empowered to apply the fund confided to them to defray the expenses of. . .

    manufactures in particular branches of extraor-dinary importanceto induce

    the prosecution and introduction of useful discoveries, inventions and

    improvements, by proportionate rewards, judi-ciously held out and applied

    [and] to encourage by premiums both honorable and lucrative the exertions of

    individuals. Hamilton believes that (ibid: 301) there is no purpose, to whichpublic money can be more beneficially applied, than to the acquisition of a new

    and useful branch of industry. . . [that results in] a permanent addition to the

    general stock of productive labor.

    B. Friedrich List

    The critique of the laissez faire system of Adam Smith by Friedrich List

    (1885: XIX) begins in the following fashon: Adam Smith (Wealth of

    Nations, Book IV, Ch.2). . . urges the following argument against the

    protective commercial policy. . .: A country can indeed by means of such

    [protective] regulations produce a special description of manufactures sooner

    than without them; and this special kind of manufactures will be able to yieldafter some time as cheap as or still cheaper production than the foreign

    country. But although in this manner we can succeed in directing national

    industry sooner into those channels into which it would later have flowed of

    its own accord, it does not in the least follow that the total amount of industry

    or of the incomes of the community can be increased by means of such

    measures. The industry of the community can only be augmented in

    proportion as its capital increases, and the capital of the community can only

    increase in accordance with the savings which it gradually makes from its

    income. Now, the immediate effect of these measures is to decrease the

    income of the community. But it is certain that which decrease that income

    cannot increase the capital more quickly than it would have been increased by

    itself, if it, as well as industry, had been left free.List began his criticism of Smith by pointing that Adam Smith has merely

    used the word capital in that sense in which it is necessarily used by rentiers

    of merchants in their book-keeping and their balance-sheets namely as the

    grand total of their values of exchange in contradistinction to the income

    accruing therefrom. According to List, Adam Smith has forgotten that he

    himself includes [in his definition of capital] the mental and bodily abilities

    of the producers under this term [capital]. He wrongly maintains that the

    revenues of the nation are dependent only on the sum of its material capital.

    His own work, on the contrary, contains a thousand proofs that these

    revenues are chiefly conditional on the sum of its mental and bodily powers,

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT 7

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    8/15

    and on the degree to which they are perfected, in social and political repects

    [especially by means of more perfect division of labor and confederation of

    the national productive powers], and that although measures of protection

    require sacrifices of material goods for a time, these sacrifices are made good

    a hundred-fold in powers, in the ability to acquire values of exchange, and are

    consequently merely reproductive outlay by the nation.According to List, Smith has forgotten that the ability of the whole nation to

    increase the sum of its material capital consists mainly in the possibility of

    converting unused natural powers into material capital, into valuable and

    income-producing instruments, and that in the case of the merely agricultural

    nation a mass of natural powers lies idle or dead which can be quickened into

    activity only by manufactures. . . He [Smith] reduces the process of the

    formation of capital in the nation to the operation of a private rentier, whose

    income is determined by the value of his material capital, and who can only

    increase his income by savings which he again turns into capital.

    List believes that (1841; 1966: 226) the revenue of the nation are

    dependent. . . on the sum of mental and bodily powers and that (ibid: 170)

    aggregate of the productive powers of the nation is not synonymous with theaggregate of the productive powers of all individuals, each considered

    separatelythat the total amount of these powers depend chiefly on social

    and political conditions, but especially on the degree in which the nation has

    rendered effectual the division of labor and the confederation of the powers of

    production within itself. List thereupon visualizes the economic system in

    which the existing incomplete development of economic organization would

    leave room for the nations long-run productive potentialities to be brought

    out more fully by the dynamisms generated by the promotion of infant

    manufacturing activities.

    List further believes that (ibid: 144) history has proved that a manu-

    facturing power developed in all its branches forms a fundamental condition

    of all higher advances in civilization, material prosperity, and political power

    in every nation, and (ibid: 153) the nation which has cultivatedmanufacturing industry in all branches within its territory to the highest

    perfection will therefore possess most productive power, and will

    consequently be the richest. 6 List also suggests a concept akin to the

    Marshallian externality (ibid: 152-153): The productive powers of every

    separate manufactory are also increased in proportion as the whole manu-

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT8

    6List believes that (ibid: 197) the spirit of striving for a steady increase in mental

    and bodily acquirements, of emulation, and of liberty characterize. . . a state devoted

    to manufactures and commerce.

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    9/15

    facturing power of the country is developed in all its branches, and the more

    intimately it is united with all other branches of industry. This sentence can

    be interpreted to imply that production costs of individual firm do not

    decrease only with its own size but also decrease with the size of the industry.

    List apparently understands that the productivity of a firm depends on how

    large an industry it is part of rather than on the size of the firm itself.List does not seem to regard the promotion of infant industry solely as a

    means for import-substitution oriented growth. He apparently takes an

    outward-looking approach and takes the eventual international price-quality

    competition as a natural sequence to follow the promotion of infant industry.

    According to List (ibid: 199): A manufacturer has a hundred times more

    opportunity for developing his mind than the agriculturist. In order to qualify

    himself for conducting his business, he must become acquainted with foreign

    men and foreign countries; in order to establish that business, he must make

    unusual efforts. . . [T]he continual competition of his rivals, which

    perpetually threaten his existence and prosperity, are to him a sharp stimulus

    to uninterrupted activity, to ceaseless progress. . . These circumstances

    produce in the manufacture an energy which is not observable in the mereagriculturist. . . [M]anufacturing occupations. . . develop and bring into action

    an incomparably greater variety and higher type of mental qualities and

    abilities than agriculture does.

    The infant industry argument of List is closely interwoven with the theory

    of development. To List, the manufacturing activity is the engine of growth.7

    He addresses to the long-run mutual interaction between the promotion of

    infant manufacturing activities and economic development, involving

    invention and discovery. He believes that the expansion of manufacturing

    activity would lead to a more than propotional increase in the amount of

    human resource that is devoted to the inventive research activity. He

    apparently understands that technological progress arises in large part

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT 9

    7Adam Smith (1776, 1937: 6) seems to have been a little bit apprehensive about

    agriculture because the nature of agriculture does not admit of so many subdivisions

    of labor and hence the improvement of the productive powers of labor [in

    agriculture] does not always keep pace with their improvement in manufactures.

    List, however, prefers manufacturing activities on a very different ground. List

    believes that (ibid: 197): In a country devoted to mere raw agriculture, dullness of

    mind, awkwardness of body, obstinate adherence to old notions, customs, methods,

    and processes, want of culture, of prosperity, and of liberty, prevail. The spirit of

    striving for a steady increase in mental and bodily acquirements, of emulation, and of

    liberty, characterize, on the contrary, a state devoted to manufactures and

    c om me r ce.

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    10/15

    because of intentional activities taken by people who respond to market

    incentives. According to List (ibid: 200-202): Manufactures are at once the

    offspring, and at the same time the supporters and the nurses, of science and

    the arts. . . in the manufacturing state there is no path which leads more

    rapidly to wealth and position than that of invention and discovery. Thus, in

    manufacturing state genius is valued and rewarded more highly than skill,and skill more highly than mere physical force. . . manufactures operate

    beneficially on the development of the mental powers of the nation. . . the

    competition of. . . talents. . . has a most beneficial influence not merely on the

    further progress of science itself, but also on the further perfection of the arts

    and of industries. . . . The science and industry in combination have

    produced that great material power. . . [Furthermore] a manufacturing nation

    has a hundred times more opportunities of applying the power of machinery

    than an agricultural nation. . . It is evident that canals, railways, and steam

    navigation are called into existence only by means of the manufacturing

    power.

    List believes that the superiority of one country over another in one

    branch of industry, say, manufacturing, often arises simply from havingbegun it sooner (ibid: 316): under a system of perfectly free competition

    with more advanced manufacturing nations, a nation which is less advanced

    than those, although well fitted for manufacturing, can never attain to a

    perfectly developed manufacturing power of its own, nor to perfect

    independence, without protective duties. . . . List states that (ibid: 299-

    300), the reason for this is the same as that why a child or a boy in

    wrestling with a strong man can scarcely be victorious or even offer steady

    resistance. List apparently addresses to a country with potential

    comparative advantages in (say, labor-intensive) manufacturing and the

    problem of converting its potential advantages into the actual ones by

    taking care of the transient externalities. List understands that initi al

    advantage can cumulate over time because such an advantage is self-

    reinforcing due to better flow of information, more flexible labor market,more specialized suppliers of inputs and technical services, and so on.

    According to List (ibid: 294), it is the more difficult to set new business

    going in proportion as fewer branches of industry of a similar character

    already exist in a nation; because, in that case, masters, foremen, and

    workmen must first be either trained up at home or procured from abroad,

    and because the profitableness of the business has not been sufficiently

    tested to give capitalists confidence in its success.

    Many contemporary economists argue that, although individual firms

    may exhaust internal economies of scale at verly low level of production

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT10

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    11/15

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    12/15

    or subsidy for manu-facturing industry would increase the growth rate of an

    economy.

    List believes that (ibid: 226-227) the ability of the whole nation to

    increase the sum of its material capital consists mainly in the possibility of

    converting unused natural powers into material capital, into valuable and

    income-producing instruments, and. . . in the case of merely agriculturalnation a mass of natural powers lies idle or dead which can be quickened into

    activity only by manufactures. List not only emphasizes the vent-for-

    surplus mechanism that is brought into play by the promotion of infant

    manufacturing industry, but also catches a glimpse of the transient nature of

    the infant industry promotion. According to List (ibid: 315), bounties are to

    be justified as temporary means of encouragement, namely where the

    slumbering spirit of enterprise of a nation merely requires stimulus and

    assistance in the first period of its revival, in order to evoke in it a powerful

    and lasting production and an export trade. . . . It is interesting to notice that

    List emphasizes export trade rather than import-substitution.9

    If Adam Smiths trade theory can be considered as an attempt to study the

    long-run mutual interaction between trade and economic development byincorporating the long-run changes in factor supplies (i.e., capital accu-

    mulation) and their productivity (through the division of labor), Hamilton and

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT12

    9List, however, warns against excesses: [P]rotection is only beneficial to the

    prosperity of the nation so far as it corresponds with the degree of the nations

    industrial development. Every exaggeration of protection is detrimental; nations

    can only obtain a perfect manufacturing power by degrees. On that account also,

    two nations which stand at different stages of industrial cultivation, can with

    mutual benefit make reciprocal concessions by treaty in respect to the exchange of

    their various manufacturing products. The less advanced nation can, while is not

    yet able to produce for itself with profit finer manufactured goods [say, capital- or

    technology-intensive goods]. . . nevertheless supply the further advanced nation

    with a portion of its requirements of coarser manufactured goods [say, simple

    unskilled labor-intensive manufactures]. Such treaties might be still more

    allowable and beneficial between nations which stand at about the same degree of

    industrial development, between which, therefore, competition is not

    overwhelming, destructive, or repressive, not tending to give a monopoly of

    everything to one side, but merely acts, as competition in the inland trade does, as

    an incentive to mutual emulation, perfection, and cheapening of production. List

    seems to have anticipated the modern approaches to international trade in terms of

    inter-industry and intra-industry trades. List further suggests that (ibid: 314)

    nations which have not yet made considerable advances in technical art and in the

    manufacture of machinery should allow all complicated machinery to be imported

    free of duty. . . .

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    13/15

    List may be attributed to have focused on the more fundamental dynamic

    nature of trade and growth, i.e., the manufacturing activity as a sharp stimulus

    to human exersion, the spirit of enterprise, invention, discovery, and the drive

    for perfection of domestic economic organization (see Myint, 1977). Smith

    emphasized the division of labor but List emphasized also the confederation

    of the powers of production within a nation.

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT 13

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    14/15

    Central to the Mill-Bastable version of the infant-industry dogma is the

    notion that practice makes perfect and that a firm can learn from its own

    experiences and, possibly, from those of other firms in the same industry.

    Since it is brief and has hardly been improved upon, Mill's account is quoted

    in full.

    The only case in which, on mere principles of political economy,protecting duties can be defensible, is when they are imposed temporarily

    (especially in a young and rising nation) in hopes of naturalizing a foreign

    industry, in itself perfectly suitable to the circumstances of the country. The

    superiority of one country over another in one branch of production often

    only arises from having begun it sooner. There may be no inherent advantage

    on one part, or disadvantage on the other, but only a present superiority of

    acquired skill and experience. A country which has this skill and experience

    yet to acquire, may in other respects be better adapted to the production than

    those which were earlier in the field . . . But it cannot be expected that

    individuals should, at their own risk, or to their certain loss, introduce a new

    manufacture, and bear the burden of carrying it on until the producers have

    been educated up to the level of those with whom these processes aretraditional. A protecting duty, continued for a reasonable time, might

    sometimes be the least inconvenient mode in which the nation can tax itself

    for the support of such an experiment. But it is essential that the protection

    should be confined to cases in which there is ground of assurance that the

    industry which it fosters will after a time be able to dispense with it; nor

    should the domestic producers ever be allowed to expect that it will be

    continued to them beyond the time for a fair trial of what they are capable of

    accomplishing.

    Bastable remarked that the mere prospect of overcoming a historical

    handicap is not enough. It is necessary, further, that the ultimate saving in

    costs should compensate the community for the high costs of the protected

    learning period. It is necessary that, when a suitable discount is applied to the

    early excess costs and to the eventual cost savings, the commodity still shouldbe worth producing. Not only the Mill test but a Bastable test must be

    passed. The Mill-Bastable dogma implies that, if an indsutry passes the Mill

    test and the Bastable test, it should be protected until it can stand on its

    own feet.

    The essential feature is the postulation of a dynamic learning process,

    which relies upon external economies and diseconomies of production. If

    firms can learn from the experiences of other firms and if there is no entry

    barrier to new firms on an equal cost footing with the pioneer firms, the

    entire saving in costs would be passed on to the domestic consumer. It is

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT14

  • 8/13/2019 Infant industries

    15/15

    clear that, in this case, the initial protection is an essential condition for of

    the establishment of the industry. No firm would be willing to shoulder the

    losses of the early learning period if the lessons of the experiences are fully

    and freely available to any follower. In this case, then, the Mill-Bastable

    dogma comes through unscathed. However, if the learning process is

    internal to the firm, that is, if firms can learn only from their ownexperiences, the prospect of later profit may be sufficiently attractive to

    warrant the shouldering of losses during the initial learning period. Then

    there are in this case no grounds for protection. In practice, of course, a

    firm may benefit both from its own experiences and from those of other

    f i r m s .

    REFERENCES

    Bastable, C.F., The Commerce of Nations, rev. T.E. Gregory, London, 1921,

    pp. 140-43, and The Theory of International Trade, 4th ed., London, 1903,

    p. 140.

    Corden, W. Max, Trade Policy and Economic Welfare, London: OxfordUniversity Press, 1974.

    Hamilton, Alexander, Report on M a nu fa ct ures, reprinted in The Papers of

    Alexander Hamilton, edited by H.C. Syrett, New York: Columbia Univer-

    sity Press, 1966.

    Johnson, Harry G., Optimal Trade Intervention in the Presence of Domestic

    Distortions, in Trade, Growth and the Balance of Payments, edited by R.

    E. Caves, P.B. Kenen and H.G. Johnson, Amsterdam: North-Holland,

    1965, pp.3-34.

    Kemp, Murray C., The Mill-Bastable Infant-Industry Dogma, Journal of

    Political Economy, February 1960, pp. 65-67.

    Lipsey, R.G., and Lancaster, K., The General Theory of the Second Best,

    Review of Economic Studies, Volume 24, 1956-7, pp.11-32.List, Friedrich, The National System of Political Economy, London: Long-

    mans, Green & Co., 1885, reprinted by Fairfield: Augustus M. Kelley,

    1977.

    Meade, James E., Trade and Welfare, London: Oxford University Press,

    1955.

    Mill, John Stuart, The Principle of Political Economy, Ashley ed., p. 92.

    Smith, Adam, The Wealth of Nations, New York: The Random House, 1937.

    INFANT INDUSTRY ARGUMENT 15