21
IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY B B C. F I P In the philosophy of science, identity over time emerges as a central concern both as an ontological category in the interpretation of physical theories, and as an epistemological problem concerning the conditions of possibility of knowledge. In Reichenbach and subsequent writers on the problem of indistinguishable quantum particles we see the return of a contrast between Leibniz and Aquinas on the subject of individuation. The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain logical diculties, leading us inexorably from ontology into epistemology. For the epistemological problem we attend to the dierences that emerged between the (neo-)Kantian and logical empiricist traditions, also saliently displayed in Reichenbach’s writings. After examining the contrast between Kant’s and Leibniz’s conceptions of empirical knowledge, specifically with respect to the irreducibility of spatiotemporal determinations, we explore an application of a neo-Kantian view to the same problem of indistinguishable quantum particles. Arguments and views concerning identity and individuation resurfaced in the twentieth century in philosophical discussion of quantum mechanics connected with discernibility. Much dealt mainly with the conditions of poss- ibility of being, that is, the conditions under which named or described entities are identical or distinct. Beginning with Kant, however, traditional ques- tions of metaphysics were transposed into a transcendental enquiry, that is, enquiry into the conditions of possibility of knowledge. Accordingly, we shall address this topic in two parts. I. CONDITIONS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF BEING In general, the conditions under which something can be the case are not the same as those under which it can be known to be the case. It does not follow that something can be the case even if there are no possible conditions under which it can be known to be so. But the distinction suces to allow us to start with the former. In doing so, we may engage in realist metaphysics – or, on the contrary, bring realism’s limits to light. The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. , No. January ISSN doi: ./j.-...x © The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly Published by Blackwell Publishing, Garsington Road, Oxford , UK, and Main Street, Malden, , USA

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    9

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

B B C. F I P

In the philosophy of science, identity over time emerges as a central concern both as an ontologicalcategory in the interpretation of physical theories, and as an epistemological problem concerning theconditions of possibility of knowledge. In Reichenbach and subsequent writers on the problem ofindistinguishable quantum particles we see the return of a contrast between Leibniz and Aquinas onthe subject of individuation. The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibleshas certain logical difficulties, leading us inexorably from ontology into epistemology. For theepistemological problem we attend to the differences that emerged between the (neo-)Kantian andlogical empiricist traditions, also saliently displayed in Reichenbach’s writings. After examining thecontrast between Kant’s and Leibniz’s conceptions of empirical knowledge, specifically with respect tothe irreducibility of spatiotemporal determinations, we explore an application of a neo-Kantian viewto the same problem of indistinguishable quantum particles.

Arguments and views concerning identity and individuation resurfaced inthe twentieth century in philosophical discussion of quantum mechanicsconnected with discernibility. Much dealt mainly with the conditions of poss-

ibility of being, that is, the conditions under which named or described entitiesare identical or distinct. Beginning with Kant, however, traditional ques-tions of metaphysics were transposed into a transcendental enquiry, that is,enquiry into the conditions of possibility of knowledge. Accordingly, we shalladdress this topic in two parts.

I. CONDITIONS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF BEING

In general, the conditions under which something can be the case are not thesame as those under which it can be known to be the case. It does not followthat something can be the case even if there are no possible conditionsunder which it can be known to be so. But the distinction suffices to allow usto start with the former. In doing so, we may engage in realist metaphysics –or, on the contrary, bring realism’s limits to light.

The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. , No. January ISSN – doi: ./j.-...x

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical QuarterlyPublished by Blackwell Publishing, Garsington Road, Oxford , UK, and Main Street, Malden, , USA

Page 2: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

I.. The problem of individuation

Under what conditions are entities distinct? The traditional answer to this‘problem of individuation’ seems to have been ‘If and only if they aredifferent in some way’: no distinction without a difference. If this is denied, onefaces a new question: how can entities be distinct, if they do not differ in anyway?

Historically, there have been four types of views on this. Two of these,which we shall describe as the ‘ubi ’ solution and the principle of identity ofindiscernibles (henceforth PII), entail that distinct entities are discernible.The other two, which we shall call the ‘haecceity’ solution and ‘weak dis-cernibility’, allow for distinct entities which have no discernible difference:whatever is true of the one is true of the other.

Aristotle’s Metaphysics took up individuation for composite substances,such as humans, which have a form as well as matter. It is the matter thatindividuates them:

There is in the composite, for example, in Callias or Socrates, such and such a formin their particular flesh and bones; and though they differ in matter, for each has hisown, father and son may share one form, for the form is indivisible.1

One may wonder why the accidental features are not mentioned. Socrateshas a snub nose but Callias does not. Accidental features can be shared. Ifthat suffices to deny that accidental features can individuate, then it isimplicitly allowed that two substances could both have the same form andthe same accidents. Callias’ and Socrates’ different flesh and bones are de-scribable parts. Their matter – in the sense indicated, hence consideredseparately from the form and from accidental features – is not differentlydescribable. It could perhaps be indicated ostensively: Socrates has this

matter, Callias has that.2 This is how Aquinas seems to read it in De Ente et

Essentia, explicitly using the word ‘this’. The Summa also explicitly uses theindexical:

For it is manifest that the reason why any singular thing is ‘this particular thing’ isbecause it cannot be communicated to many: since that whereby Socrates is a man,can be communicated to many; whereas, what makes him this particular man, is onlycommunicable to one. Therefore, if Socrates were a man by what makes him to bethis particular man, as there cannot be many Socrates, so there could not in that waybe many men.3

1 Aristotle, Metaphysics Ζ a –, tr. R. Hope (Univ. of Michigan Press, ).2 See further N. White, ‘Identity, Modal Individuation, and Matter in Aristotle’, Midwest

Studies in Philosophy, (), pp. –.3 Summa Theologica, I q , a (Benziger Bros edn, ).

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 3: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

But besides the ‘this matter’ solution for composite substances, Aquinasintroduces two other forms of individuation. Angels, that is, immaterialintelligences, have no matter and never did have matter. Accordingly, notwo angels have the same form: ‘... such things as agree in species but differin number, agree in form, but are distinguished materially. If, therefore, theangels be not composed of matter and form, as was said above, it followsthat it is impossible for two angels to be of one species’ (Summa, I q , a ).Souls on the other hand may differ solely in their history, that is, in that theywere the souls of distinct human beings before death:

... the individuation of the soul depends on the body, in an occasional manner, as toits inception, for the soul does not acquire for itself individual existence unless in thebody of which it is the act. But nevertheless, if we subtract the body, the individuationdoes not perish because, since the soul was made the form of a given body, the formhas absolute existence from which it has acquired individuated existence, and thisexistence always remains individuated (De Ente et Essentia, ch. V).

In the different treatment of these cases, two options are explored by laterscholastics. One is to insist on a difference that can be described in terms ofproperties, whether essential or accidental. The other is to insist on adistinction in number made on a different basis.

The appeal to the soul’s history is of the first kind, as is the differentiationof angels by their forms. Also of the first kind is the proposal that there is auniquely distinguishing accident, the ubi, that is, the quality something hasby virtue of being where it is. This is a kind of accident that can vary with timebut can never be shared by distinct individuals, and so can individuate. Thesecond option is to introduce something that might neither be an accidentnor yet belong to the form. This may be read into the salient use of index-icals. Scotus’ haecceitas, the ‘thisness’, in contrast with the quiddity whichconsists of all the determinations of the entity apart from the haecceity,exemplifies this second option. Robert Adams insists that haecceity is aproperty.4 But if this solution is to differ significantly from the ubi solution,then haecceity cannot be an accident, that is (in our terms), it is not a pro-perty or quality or attribute.

Leibniz’s teenage work Disputatio Metaphysica de Principio Individui ()shows that he was well acquainted with the scholastic discussions; in hismature work, even if not without precedent, he takes the first option in anew way.5 In his view, the complete concept of an individual contains allfacts about the world it is in, and how it is situated there. He claims that it

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

4 See R. Adams, ‘Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity’, Journal of Philosophy, (),pp. –.

5 A solution attributed to Porphyry and Boethius presaged the PII: see C. Leijenhorst, TheMechanisation of Aristotelianism (Leiden: Brill, ), p. .

Page 4: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

follows from this ‘that it is not true that two substances may be exactly alikeand differ only numerically, solo numero, and that what St Thomas says onthis point regarding angels and intelligences ... is true of all substances ...’(Discourse on Metaphysics IX). In fact this inference is not logically compulsory,except on the assumption that an individual’s full concept is unique to it –which would beg the question if meant as a justificatory argument. Leibniz’sPII is a logically contingent principle: there is no (numerical) distinction withouta (discernible) difference (cf. The Monadology, §).

The PII encounters putative counter-examples. One is Max Black’sexample of a universe consisting of two spheres which have the same vol-ume and composition. Another is absolute space; assuming that points areentities, they seem no different one from the other. Stachel suggests in retortto such puzzles that an entity may acquire ‘a certain measure of individ-uality ... from its position within a structure’.6 The points of space havenothing intrinsic either to characterize or to differentiate them, but theybear spatial relations to each other: each occupies a position in a relationalstructure. However, since there are symmetries of the space enough to takeany point into any other one, whatever we can say about any point, evenabout its relational position, we can say about each of them. Therefore thisresponse works only for structures already reduced modulo all such sym-metries, and not for space as ordinarily conceived.

A Leibnizian complete concept includes relational attributes, specifyinghow the individual is related to other elements having various other pro-perties or standing in still further relations to further elements, and so forth.To be discernible, individuals cannot be alike both in the qualities they haveand in their place in the relational structure in their world.7 So if theseexamples, Black’s spheres and points in absolute space, are admitted at all,they do violate the PII.

So we turn to the question how it is possible for individuals to be distinctif there is no discernible difference between them. There are two options:an individuating factor that does not imply discernibility (haecceity), and acondition explored by Simon Saunders.8 To the remark that spatial pointsare not discernibly different, Saunders, following Quine, retorts that there

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

6 J. Stachel, ‘Structural Realism and Contextual Individuality’, in Y. Ben-Menahem (ed.),Hilary Putnam (Cambridge UP, ), pp. –.

7 Kant discussed this critically (/); but see A. Jauernig, Leibniz Freed From EveryFlaw: a Kantian Reads Leibnizian Metaphysics (Princeton University: PhD thesis, ), chs , .There have also been arguments to the effect that relations cannot provide the ground forindividuality since they presuppose relata, which require prior individuation. This is notlogically compelling as it stands. (Thanks to an anonymous referee for this point.)

8 S. Saunders, ‘Physics and Leibniz’s Principle’, in K. Brading and E. Castellani (eds),Symmetries in Physics: Philosophical Reflections (Cambridge UP, ), pp. –, and ‘AreQuantum Particles Objects?’, Analysis, (), pp. –.

Page 5: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

are irreflexive relations between them. Any point x is one metre from somepoint y, but not from itself. He therefore calls the points ‘weakly discernible’.

The condition of weak discernibility certainly entails distinctness. Butfirst, such a predicate as ‘is one metre from some other point but not fromitself ’ also applies to all points, and so does not express a difference betweenthem. Secondly, the deduction that there are at least two Xs if some X bearsan irreflexive relation to some X does not require the PII. It assumes only itsconverse, that is, substitutivity of identity. So although we shall stay withSaunders’ terminology, we find it thoroughly misleading, for this use of theword ‘discernible’ is misplaced. Still, we have here a fascinating answer tothe question how could there be more than one point, although they are notdifferent in any way, even in the terms described in relations to other points.What Saunders, following Quine, effectively pointed out is a conditionwhich entails that there is more than one entity of the given kind, withoutimplying that there are specifiable differences that distinguish them.

The problem of individuation can therefore apparently be met in variousways, all of them displaying conditions which imply numerical multiplicity –some requiring discernible differences and some not.

I.. Identity and individuation in twentieth-century physics

Particles characterized by the same constant features, such as mass orcharge, are generally called ‘identical particles’. They can still differ becauseeach particle is capable of a range of states. If two particles are of the samekind, and have the same state, nothing in the quantum-mechanical descrip-tion distinguishes them. Yet this is possible. We seem to have a dilemma: eitherthis possibility violates the PII, or the quantum-mechanical description ofnature is incomplete. We shall consider Margenau’s and Reichenbach’sarguments, which show both options.

A special complication: the elementary particles fall into two large classes,fermions and bosons. The former obey Pauli’s exclusion principle, which isusually stated informally as No two can be in the same state. At first blush, then,the above dilemma would not apply to them. Pauli introduced the exclusionprinciple originally for electrons in a description of atomic structure. Thiswas very fruitful: the shell structure of atoms could be deduced, andspectroscopic as well as magnetic properties understood. For example, eachelectron in an atom has its state completely characterized by its fourquantum numbers. The qualitative statement of the principle amounts tothe assertion that two such electrons cannot have identical sets of quantumnumbers. So understood, it seems that the principle follows at once from thePII, given the completeness assumption that an electron is completely charac-terized by its constants plus the four quantum numbers.

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 6: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

But it was precisely the fermions that were first cited as in violation of thePII. Henry Margenau pointed out that the informal statement of the prin-ciple does not fit well with its later mathematical formulation.9 An ensembleof electrons is a composite system, which has a quantum state taken as awhole. The general principle of which Pauli’s is a special case says that anensemble of particles of the same kind must have a state which is ‘sym-metrized’, that is, invariant under permutation. In this respect, the fermionsare like the bosons: ensembles of particles of the same kind can only have asymmetrized state.

Margenau asks now whether there are any observables, pertaining toeach particle individually, which have different values. The answer in bothcases, for fermions as for bosons, is ‘None’.10 In fact, if we ask for theprobability of the outcome of measuring an observable which pertains to asingle particle, the answer we receive does not depend on that particle atall.11 Margenau then (p. ) adds as a consequence that the exclusion prin-ciple ‘so far as it goes, contradicts Leibniz.... The two particles, as we haveseen, differ in no observable respect. Nevertheless quantum mechanicswould lead to entirely erroneous results if they were treated as a single entity.The particles, though they cannot be labelled individually, can be counted.’To be precise, the ‘size’ of an ensemble of particles (i.e., the number of itselements) is a quantum-mechanically representable quantity (the numberobservable). So we can say that there are n electrons, for example, but thatthey are all in the same state. This clearly asserts a distinction without adifference. Margenau continues (ibid.) ‘But if number is an observable pro-perty, have we any right to say that two electrons in an atom do not differ inobservable respects? Yes indeed, for the number is not the property ofeach electron, but of the composite system.’ This is a prime example of hol-ism in the quantum world.

Simon Saunders suggests that the description of the ensemble should beread as

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

9 H. Margenau, ‘The Exclusion Principle and its Philosophical Importance’, Philosophy ofScience, (), pp. –. For a recent discussion see M. Massimi, ‘Exclusion Principleand the Identity of Indiscernibles: a Response to Margenau’s Argument’, British Journal for thePhilosophy of Science, (), pp. –, and fn. below.

10 As example, take a pure state of a pair of identical fermions, an equal superposition oftwo different states, the anti-symmetric tensor product state (/√)[(φψ – ψφ)], where φ, ψ areorthogonal spin states. If we ask whether a state can be ascribed to any one of the fermionsinvolved, the answer is ‘Yes’, by ‘reduction of the density matrix’. The reduction assigns toeach particle the mixed state ½P[φ] + ½P[ψ], where P[ ] is the projection on the indicatedone-dimensional subspace. See further §II. below.

11 The rationale for the calculation is this: the prediction probabilities based on this assign-ment, for observables pertaining to a single particle, will be the same as if calculated on thebasis of the total state of the ensemble – as obviously it should be. We do not accept Massimi’scritique of Margenau; but her conclusion about violation of the PII is the same.

Page 7: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

. There exist distinct particles x1, ..., xn whose ensemble is in a super-position of the states resulting from permutations of the state in whichparticle x1 is in state φ1, ..., particle xn is in φn.

In the case of a fermion ensemble, unlike the case of bosons, these individualstates φi must all be distinct. The first existential quantifier can be deleted,and then this can be read with ‘particle x1’ as subject term as follows:

Particle x1 is a member of an ensemble in which there are n– otherparticles such that ... [here insert the rest of ()].

The predicate applied to this subject term applies equally well if instead wedelete the j th existential quantifier, and let xj be the subject; so no differenti-ating feature appears. But as Saunders notes, the relation involved is irre-flexive – you could not delete both the first and the jth existential quantifier,write y for both x1 and xj, and get something that could be true. Why not?Because y would appear in components in which it bears two states at once.

This is precisely similar to the above diagnosis of the multiplicity of pointsin absolute space, and applies also to Max Black’s spheres. But once again itdoes not vindicate the PII. Rather, it is an explanation of how we can assertindiscernible entities to be distinct – indicating a condition that impliesnumerical multiplicity.

When Hans Reichenbach turns to the issue of identity over time heintroduces the relation of genidentity.12 Genidentity includes the material gen-identity of, e.g., a water droplet, and the functional genidentity of the wave ofwhich this droplet is a part. For a macroscopic physical object, material

genidentity is characterized in terms of continuity of change, spatial exclusionand the verifiability of spatial position interchange. In the case of waves,there is continuity ‘usually’, but the other two criteria are not satisfied:waves have only functional genidentity. He does not offer an explicit definitionfor either.

The atomic hypothesis in classical form would ensure that cases offunctional genidentity always supervene on a pattern in the materially gen-identical atomic constituents. But in recent physics atoms too have internalstructure, and the elementary particles of which they are composed appearto have none of the three characteristics criterial for material genidentity.The problem of individuation reappears.

Fermions and bosons display distinctive statistical behaviour. Bosons obeyBose–Einstein statistics, in contrast with the ‘normal’ or classical Maxwell–Boltzmann statistics applied to classically conceived atoms in gas theory.

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

12 H. Reichenbach, The Direction of Time (California UP, ), p. .

Page 8: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

Fermions, to which Pauli’s exclusion principle applies, obey a third statistics,the Fermi–Dirac statistics. Tossing two dice offers a fanciful illustration.What is the probability that the results will add up to ? The answers fromthe three, taken in the same order, are /, /, /. Intuitively speaking,fermions favour combinations of distinct numbers, and bosons favour‘doubles’. The question of how to account for this difference in statisticalbehaviour, and the suggestion that it has to do with identity and individu-ation, has been recurrent since the beginning.

Reichenbach suggests that the clue lies in the criterion of verifiability ofspatial position interchange. This is satisfied for classical particles but not forbosons. Hence he concludes that at first blush, particles satisfying Bose–Einstein statistics do not have material genidentity. But then he notes thatlogically speaking, distinct possible arrangements could just have unequalprobability. This would mean that the particles are materially genidentical,but subject to a causal anomaly – statistical correlation without causalexplanation. He regards this as a choice for us: there is no empirical ques-tion involved – ‘Neither interpretation is “more true” than the other; thetwo are equivalent descriptions’ (p. ). For Fermi–Dirac statistics, he firstsuggests that there is no similar problem, since all admissible arrangementsare equiprobable. But again if we take the particles to be materiallygenidentical we have a statistical correlation without causal explanation.Reichenbach did not live to finish this book, and we can only speculate onwhat precisely he had in mind. Can we complete Reichenbach’s discussionso as to find, contrary to Margenau’s claims, an interpretation of quantumtheory in which Leibniz’s principle is not violated?

The answer is ‘Yes’, but only through an addition of ‘empirically super-fluous’ hidden variables.13 Suppose first that we regard fermions such aselectrons as not enduring in time: the ‘histories’ of such particles are really

sequences of events not connected by a genidentity relation. Yet when, at agiven time in a given region or situation, there are n such events, then we say

that n such particles are present. The weak discernibility pointed out bySaunders for a state of the ensemble at any given time suffices now to allow fora consistent addition of hidden characteristics to make these events mutuallydiscernible.

For bosons, this will not work, since the state of a boson ensemble at aparticular time does not satisfy the weak discernibility condition. Yet theretoo scientists speak intuitively of the presence of n particles. Reichenbach’sdiscussion of genidentity provides the option of discernibility over time. Couldnot the required hidden parameter then be the relation of genidentity to

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

13 Cf. B. van Fraassen, Quantum Mechanics: an Empiricist View (Oxford UP, ), ch. ,§§–.

Page 9: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

previous states? That would precisely echo Aquinas’ solution for theindividuation of souls.

So, logically speaking, the issue is once again unsettled. One option im-plies that pace Margenau the fermions are particles only in a ‘conventional’or Pickwickian sense (there is no genidentity), but they do not violateLeibniz’s principle. Pace Reichenbach, however, the PII can be saved forbosons also by postulating that they are really genidentical, though thecriteria for neither material nor functional genidentity are satisfied. But itis crucial to such choices that empirically superfluous parameters areintroduced, whether for the sake simply of interpretation, or as actual highmetaphysics.

I.. Logical arguments for the PII

If the PII were a logical truth, then the possibility of distinct but indis-cernible entities, which we have taken so seriously, would make no sense atall.14 But there are arguments to that effect.15

Argument . A set s with two indiscernible but distinct elements has foursubsets, including two that have just one member each. But the elements areindiscernible, so cannot belong to different sets. Hence the only subsets of s are sitself and the empty set ∅. This is a contradiction: it is a theorem of settheory that sets have more subsets than members (Cantor). Should wechange set theory, or admit that PII is a logical truth?

This argument can be countered by saying that unit sets of indiscerniblebut distinct elements are themselves distinct but indiscernible.

Argument . A set s has two members if and only if there exists a function fwhich maps s one–one onto the set {,}. But then there is one member ins which has the property of being f–1(), and another member which doesnot. So the two members of s are discernible after all.

One change in set theory which has been suggested is to allow sets whoseelements are indiscernible to have a cardinality but no ordinal. But given thedefinition of equicardinality by one–one mapping, it follows that if there isany well ordered set of cardinality n, then all sets of that cardinality admit awell ordering, and hence a differentiation of the above sort. So this argu-ment is not so easily countered.

Argument . If two entities are indiscernible, then any predicate that appliesto the one will also apply to the other. But to say that they are distinct, wehave to use the identity symbol ‘=’ (since ‘distinct’ means ‘not identical’).Therefore we can make up a predicate using ‘=’ which will apply to the one

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

14 Thanks to Charles Daniels, who suggested the arguments for the PII in this section.15 As Jauernig points out, Leibniz himself did not take the PII to be a logical truth, but

allowed violation by abstract entities.

Page 10: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

and not to the other. If there are distinct indiscernible entities, it must betrue for any and every definable predicate F that (∃x)(∃y)(x ≠ y & [Fx ≡ Fy]).Taking the predicate ‘x = ...’ for F, we obtain (∃x)(∃y)(x ≠ y & [x=x ≡ x=y]),which is a self-contradiction.

Argument . In second-order logic we can quantify over predicates, and sodefine identity: ‘x=y’ is short for ‘(∀F)(Fx ≡ Fy)’, thus establishing the PII atonce. To stop that move we can object that if the predicate variable rangesover a restricted set of properties only, then the defined relation is anequivalence relation that could assimilate distinct objects. Even without thisobjection, we have a right to reject the definition. However, we still have aproblem: given that we still need a way to say that there are distinct entities,we then require ‘=’ as a primitive symbol. From here on, the argumentcontinues like the preceding.

Can we offer a diagnosis of these arguments which will save standardlogic and set theory while rejecting the PII? There is just one option, itseems – to deny that every verbally definable predicate stands for a discern-ible difference. Kant’s reaction to ‘real’ and ‘exists’ in the ontological proofof the existence of God was to argue that there is no difference betweena hundred thalers and a hundred real thalers. No use saying that there is adifference because you can see only the real ones – as if there were unrealones that are invisible!

Without a rationale, this reaction would render the PII effectively vacu-ous. Any rationale would have to specify plausibly what is and what is not tobe taken seriously as a discernible difference. But where the problem arisesin practice, as in quantum mechanics, we can clearly see what is and is nottaken seriously in this regard. The electrons in the same atomic orbit areindiscernible because there is no observable (i.e., no measurable quantity)which will differentiate them individually. Any difference postulated be-tween them would have to involve empirically superfluous parameters, andthere is no compelling reason to believe in these. The classification as empir-ically superfluous, however, is in epistemic terms: they make no difference toprobabilities in empirical predictions.

We do need a rationale for a distinction between genuine discernibledifferences and merely verbal differences. The only clue we have at thispoint, but a very noticeable one, is the way in which physics is distinguishedfrom pure mathematics, namely, through its bearing on experience andexperimentation. Hence this dialectic concerning the conditions of thepossibility of being leads us inexorably into the conditions of the possibility of

knowledge.

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 11: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

II. CONDITIONS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF KNOWLEDGE

Kant wrote that we precipitate ourselves ‘into darkness and contradictions’by seemingly unobjectionable steps that ‘transcend the limits of experi-ence, [and so] are no longer subject to any empirical test’.16 The form ofmetaphysics he thus criticized can be avoided by turning instead to atranscendental enquiry, an enquiry into the conditions of the possibility ofknowledge in a given subject area, with reference to both experience andunderstanding.

II.. The transcendental turn and logical empiricism

For the sciences, this enquiry focuses on conditions for measurement and forobtaining given kinds of information from measurement, especially in orderto bring hidden theoretical presuppositions to light. The neo-KantianMarburg school concentrated on this, but in certain respects their enterprisewas continued by the Vienna and Berlin Circles, despite the controversiesbetween these two philosophical camps. When Reichenbach departed fromthe neo-Kantian tradition to forge his distinctive version of logical empir-icism, he retained the conviction that nothing is meaningful unless it can beclearly co-ordinated with conditions of knowledge rooted in experience.

We have pointed out an example of this in his discussion (p. ) ofmaterial genidentity, a relation which, though not defined by them, carriesthe hallmarks of the possibility of such co-ordination. When denying thatelementary particles have material genidentity, he concentrates in his argu-ment on what can be manifest in an experiment. Thus the conditions ofpossibility for knowledge, the characteristic focus of the Kantian tradition,remain crucial to meaning in Reichenbach’s thought, even when he greatlymodifies and weakens the infamous verification criterion for meaningfulnessin his Experience and Prediction. It is in this spirit, without subscribing to afixed or inflexible dogma concerning meaningfulness, that we shall now re-examine the issues pertaining to identity, individuation, and indiscernibility.

II.. Conception of knowledge: Leibniz to Kant

Gilles Deleuze presents the PII as the key to a profound and indeedirreconcilable opposition between Leibniz and Kant.17 What distinguishes

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

16 Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, tr. N. Kemp Smith (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, ),Preface to the st edn.

17 G. Deleuze, Courses Given at Vincennes , http://www.webdeleuze.com/php/sommaire.html.

Page 12: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

Kant from Leibniz here, he says, is a difference in how they conceive ofwhat it is to know. For Leibniz, knowledge is gained by analysis: to knowis to discover what is included in a concept. But for Kant, all analysispresupposes a synthesis. To affirm, as Kant does, the irreducibility of thespace-time determination to the conceptual determination is, according toDeleuze, to introduce a new conception of space and time, no longer as anorder of existence and of succession, reducible to what co-exists or followsone after another, but as a priori forms of exteriority and interiority.

Leibniz’s principle implies that if a distinction is known, it must be knownthrough a difference, and hence through a difference detectable throughanalysis of concepts. But for Kant, there is besides conceptual determinationalso spatiotemporal determination, which is a form of intuition, irreducibleto the conceptual order. What we must seek now in the history of thisproblem of articulation between identity and indiscernibility are, first of all,the differences on the level of the conception of knowledge, and secondly,what it means to regard spatiotemporal determination as irreducible toconceptual determination.

Kant’s first Critique begins with the famous ‘There can be no doubt thatall our knowledge begins with experience’. This rules out neither knowledgea priori nor empirical knowledge, which has its sources ‘a posteriori, that is, inexperience’. But he introduces a further divergence: temporal determinationis irreducible to conceptual determination: the space of physics is not orientated,but perceptual space is. Thus enters the indexical, as we can already clearly seein his early pre-Critical essay ‘Von dem ersten Grunde des Unterschiedesder Gegenden ...’:

(a) the map: ‘a map of the heavens, if the direction were not specified relativeto my hands, would not enable me ... to infer [where] to expect thesun to rise’

(b) the compass: ‘No matter how well I may know the order of the compasspoints, I can only determine directions by reference to them if I knowwhether this order runs from right to left, or from left to right’

(c) the two hands (as later elaborated in Prolegomena, §): ‘the difference be-tween similar and equal things, which are yet not congruent, cannotbe made intelligible by any concept, but only by the relation to the rightand the left hands which immediately refers to intuition’.

This last example is related to the other two through the surprising diagnosisKant provides of it. The case of these hands contrasts with that of twoarrows of the same shape and size. Even if the arrows are currently pointingin opposite directions, they can be considered geometrically alike in allrespects, and either can be made to occupy the exact place of the other by

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 13: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

means of a rigid motion (translation and rotation). The right hand and lefthand are not superimposable in this way, although they are, as objects inEuclidean space, geometrically alike as well. They are what Kant called‘incongruent counterparts’. Contrary to how Leibniz conceived it, the noteddifference between the pair of hands and the pair of differently orientatedarrows need not, merely because it is knowable, be founded in ‘intrinsic’,that is conceptual, differences.

The symmetries which deprive the arrows of any individuality, of anyspecificity with respect to each other, are lacking in the case of the twohands. There are two sorts of Euclidean symmetries: ‘rigid motions’ and‘reflections’. In current geometric terms, mirror reflections are indeed sym-metries of Euclidean -space, but they are not symmetries of the space inwhich we ‘see’ the objects of experience. For us, though they are locatedin the same Euclidean space, the absence of a rigid motion that turns onehand into the other signals a differentiation of a different kind. A descriptionof a hand-shaped region in Euclidean space, given entirely in geometricterms, does not distinguish between left and right hands, precisely becausethat space is not an orientated space. Related by any symmetry, two spatialregions are geometrically, and hence conceptually, the same. But for us, forobservers, there is a difference, which does not stem, as Kant claimed butLeibniz denied, from conceptual differences.

If the space in which they are represented had an extra dimension, a righthand and a left hand could be superposed, just as two two-dimensionalarrows represented in a three-dimensional space can be. But in a four-dimensional space there would also be examples of regions which arerelated by reflections and not by any rigid motion. So, even in general, the‘for us’ is crucial here. Just as in the case of the map of the heavens, the in-formation captured in geometric description must be supplemented by theact of relating the description to our own situation, that is, it must beinstantiated perspectivally. The space-time determinations which completethe conceptual determinations of the hand or the chart, so as to make themobjects of knowledge for us, are indexical.

So there is a difference between the non-orientated object of knowledgerepresented in a chart, geometric model or physical theory, and theorientated object of knowledge by which we can steer ourselves. How does itshow up in the domain of scientific knowledge? To what could we todayeither oppose or assimilate the claim that space-time determinations areirreducible to conceptual determinations? Space-time determinations whichcan be called upon today by a neo-Kantian conception of knowledge are notlimited, as they were for Kant, to ‘natural’ or individual forms of sensibility.What are they, then? How does the way in which we envisage the epistemic

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 14: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

function of space-time determinations in knowledge affect the articulationbetween identity and indiscernibility?

Kant’s way of accounting for incongruent counterparts changed from anappeal to absolute space to a transcendentalist perspective. Laying out thedifferent options for accounting for incongruence, Oliver Pooley regardsKant’s earlier position as externalist and substantivalist, where the incon-gruence is explained not in terms of an intrinsic difference but by appealingto something external, for instance an absolute, independent space.18 Hesays that the later (transcendental idealist) Kant rejected this substantivalistinterpretation, and claimed the incongruence to be not conceptually com-prehensible but graspable only in perception. Pooley suggests (p. , fn. )that Kant must then have opted for explaining the incongruence in terms ofintrinsic differences between left and right which ‘cannot be made intel-ligible through concepts’. Yet Pooley recalls too that Kant called themcounterparts because he thought they were ‘perfectly identical in terms ofthe distances between their corresponding parts’. So what kind of intrinsic

differences would be compatible with their being ‘perfectly identical’?Pooley does not tell us, and his suggestion could be read as harking back tothe metaphysics which Kant criticized, where any difference at all is reified.However one understands the evolution in Kant’s position with respect toincongruence, it was always, in a critical perspective, using the case of in-congruent counterparts as an argument against the necessary conceptualfoundation of distinctness. What could be meant by intrinsic differenceswhich are not conceptual, not a matter of instantiating different concepts?If one insists on seeing all accounts of incongruence as divided betweensubstantivalism and relationalism, there is simply no room for the transcend-entalist approach.

Moreover, to reject, as Kant did, the idea that any distinctness isnecessarily founded in conceptual differences is not to say that people canhave no conceptual understanding whatsoever of a distinction not foundedin conceptual differences. We have a conceptual understanding of the non-conceptual foundation of the distinctness of incongruent counterparts,namely, that the distinction between left and right can only be made byostension, that is, by an indexical judgement.

Pooley himself (p. ) advocates the relationalist option according towhich ‘the difference between incongruent counterparts is grounded in theirrelations to each other and to other material objects’. Contrary to whatPooley sometimes suggests, transcendentalism does share with relationalismthe idea that incongruence of counterparts is not to be accounted for by

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

18 O. Pooley, ‘Handedness, Parity Violation, and the Reality of Space’, in Brading andCastellani (eds), Symmetries in Physics, pp. –, at pp. –.

Page 15: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

intrinsic differences. But in other respects it is as far from relationalism asfrom substantivalism. Both the substantivalist and the relationalist look for afoundation of the distinction in things which have been distinguished whichis indifferent to how they have been distinguished; this is where these theoriesdiffer from the transcendentalist approach.

The transcendentalist starts from the mere fact that in certain conditionspeople find themselves making a distinction, and asks for the conditions ofthe possibility of doing so. How do we come to make this distinction, underwhat sorts of circumstances, and what is involved in the making of thisdistinction? Can we imagine other circumstances in which this distinctioncould not have been made, and if so, are they conditions we could imagineourselves living in? Is it contingent that we are not in these circumstances, oris the idea of being in such conditions incompatible with how we think ofourselves ?

The distinction between the left and right hand is understood, both bythe relationalist and the transcendentalist, in terms of relations. But thetranscendentalist does not begin with relations between things that can beconceptually formulated. For the transcendentalist, it is a matter of relationsinvolved in the act of distinguishing, a matter of attending to how making acertain distinction depends on the conditions under which this distinctioncan actually be made.

The distinction which we make with the hands but do not make with thearrows has to be related to the fact that the hands are three-dimensionalobjects embedded in a three-dimensional orientated space. Geometrically,the incongruence of the hands is contingent on the dimensionality of thespace in which they are embedded. But the dimension and orientation ofperceptual space are a necessary condition of our perception of anything.We cannot conceive of a perceptual distinction independently of the fulfil-ment of these conditions; it is therefore an a priori condition of perception.This is overlooked if the distinctness is explained in terms of conceptualdifferences, or in terms of some relation between items distinguished, whileno mention is made of the cognitive relation through which this distinctioncan be made. To postulate some conceptualizable ‘intrinsic’ differencegraspable only in direct perception places the ground of the distinctionbetween regions of space once again in the objects, and the restriction toperceptual access only serves to make it mysterious.

The need for such a postulate will be felt only by those who adhere,tacitly or explicitly, to some doctrine, along the lines of Leibniz’s conceptionof knowledge, to the effect that any act of distinguishing requires some pre-existent difference conceptualizable without recourse to ostension or toindexical judgement. This is all the more regrettable because such recourse

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 16: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

might be a key to how anyone can conceive of identity and individuation inthe context of quantum mechanics.

II.. The world of physics

As did the Marburg school of neo-Kantians, we aim to generalize on thesereflections so as to arrive at an understanding of the physical sciences. Speci-fically, we aim to generalize from perception to measurement. Just as thenon-orientated space of Newtonian physics must in practice be co-ordinatedwith the orientated perceptual space, so the general ‘view from nowhere’ inany scientific model needs in practice to be particularized to a situationrelative to a measurement set-up. The significance and meaningfulness of(combinations of ) factual judgements requires as a condition that they can inprinciple enter as conclusions in the context of a measurement of ‘what theyare about’. In quantum physics, the natural form of prediction is assignmentof probabilities of outcomes conditional on measurement of an appropriatekind. (In some interpretations of QM these conditional probabilities arederived from absolute probabilities; but we take an orthodox line here.)That it is incumbent on observers to apply concepts only in ways that makesense experimentally and experientially does not, however, require themnever to apply those concepts to situations in which there is no measure-ment. It requires only that conditions of possibility can be specified for theseconcepts, that is, that it can be shown how their application could be part of ajudgement properly based in a well defined measurement context.

There is an analogy between incongruent counterparts and entangledstates of identical particles. The state vector associated with the result of apreparation may have to be taken from the tensor product of two Hilbertspaces, so that the ‘global system’ is visualized as a thoroughly entangledpair of subsystems. This entanglement expresses a correlation betweenthe possible outcomes of measurements of pairs of local observables. But thecharacterizations of these two subsystems within the entangled state are nodifferent from each other, any more than were the concepts of the incongru-ent counterparts. So it becomes necessary to make a numerical distinction,with respect to the correlation, just as with respect to the incongruence; butit is impossible to state a difference in concepts pertaining to the disting-uished entities or parts.

How can anyone make sense of correlation, which implies a numericaldistinction, without being able to state an intrinsic difference, that is, adifference in the concepts of what are distinguished?

One option is to say that there are intrinsic differences, but they do notshow up in the concepts of quantum theory, nor appear in the quantumstate. Why not? Tellingly, a typical answer is that these differences make no

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 17: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

empirical difference whatsoever: there is no means of grasping them empir-ically, and for that reason no way to describe them within the resources ofthe quantum theory. But these empirically superfluous ‘hidden’ variables areintroduced to ‘explain’ an empirically attestable difference in the results ofmeasurements which can be made. The explanation and its rationale do seemto imply that there is one kind of empirical evidence serving for numericaldistinction and another kind for conceptual discernibility. There are here allthe reasons needed to attend to the empirical conditions in which the ten-sion between distinction and discernibility arises.

Another option is one we mentioned above, Saunders’ contention thatthere is here not a case of distinction without discernibility, but rather aweak discernibility, to be stated in terms of a relation. This relation, sym-metric but irreflexive, can be formulated in logical terms without any regardfor empirical conditions. Can it, really?

Under the heading of weak discernibility come both the case of twoidentical spheres located at a certain distance from each other and the caseof two identical particles in a superposition of pairs of opposite spincomponents. This assimilation overlooks an important difference, as hasbeen carefully highlighted by Michel Bitbol (in an unpublished MS, ).The conditions of measurement under which (a) the two spheres are indi-vidually and differently located, or (b) found to be at a distance d from eachother, are compatible. But in the case of a system of two electrons orphotons, measurements which localize them individually are not compatiblewith a measurement which reveals a global property such as being in anentangled state. The required kind of compatibility is no longer available. Inthe context where an entangled state is attributed, there is no basis for thedistinction other than the [anti-]correlation itself. Labels such as ‘x1’ and ‘x2’used in describing the state seem misleadingly to stand for an ascription ofindividuality, but can actually do no more than express the blind, merelynumerical, distinction.

Suppose we have a situation described in quantum-mechanical terms aspreparation of systems in the symmetric tensor product state (/√)[(φψ + ψφ)],where φ, ψ are orthogonal spin states – informally, spins ‘up’ and ‘down’ in acertain direction. If we calculate the predictions for the counting observables

corresponding to spin-up, spin-down, and spin-up or spin-down (the latter beingthe observable with constant value , the ‘identity’ I) then we get the answers, , with certainty, for the state is an eigenstate of each of these threeobservables. The measurements can be made without disturbance: the stateis left intact. There are other such ‘global’ observables, of which the totalsystem state is an eigenstate, for example, the sum of the two spins, which isa way to check whether this is a case of combining opposite spins.

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 18: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

Together, these judgements, which can thus be combined meaningfullywith respect to measurement conditions, certainly yield a judgement of distinct-

ness. In whatever way we want to phrase the facts about what we can predictwith certainty here, we shall have to use the number .

The state described above can be ascribed to a boson pair, and is in-formally described as a system consisting of two bosons of the same typewith opposite spins. But just as with Pauli’s exclusion principle, as Margenaupointed out, such an informal description calls up a ‘classical’ picture: itwould be just right only if the situation were not one of entanglement. Thevery conclusion that this is a system consisting of two distinct individuals isnot one which can be satisfactorily linked to any similar non-disturbingmeasurement procedure which could bring it to light. Measurements whichcan be designed to support such a conclusion are necessarily ones which doperturb the state. Even the talk of ‘disturbing’ and ‘perturbing’ is unhappilyladen with ‘classical’ imagery, and may be misleading. What we can sayquite definitely is that such measurements cannot be regarded as doing any-thing to reveal (except relative to contentious interpretative principles addedto the basic theory) what the situation was like before the measurement wasmade.

Suppose we try to design a measurement that would pertain to one part-icle rather than the other. There is a standard mathematical design for this.We can designate the system as x+y, with distinct labels x and y. To measureobservable a that pertains to x is the same as measuring a ⊗ I on this com-posite system, where I is the identity. (In quantum mechanics, states can beattributed to the components x, y individually, but the assignment is definedby the constraint assign to x the state such that the expectation value of any pertinent

observable a in that state is the same as the expectation value of a ⊗ I in the state of the

whole.) Even if a pertains also to the other, the expectation value of a ⊗ I willin general not be the same as that of I ⊗ a. This is how the assertion that thesystem is composed of two different individuals is satisfactorily linked tofeasible measurement possibilities.

If we now try to do the same with the permutation invariant state of apair of particles, we cannot get a difference in measurement predictions orexpectation values for I ⊗ a and a ⊗ I. We can illustrate this starting withAspect’s famous experiment to detect violations of the Bell inequalities.Intuitively, a pair of entangled photons are travelling in opposite directionsaway from a source. If the pair is in the boson state (/√)[(φφ + ψψ)], theirstates are perfectly correlated. Results of polarization measurements withthe two polarizers aligned in parallel are % correlated. That is, eachphoton may be found randomly either in channel + or – of the corre-sponding polarizer, but in this case, when one photon is found positively

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 19: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

polarized, then so is its twin companion.19 (Light polarization and photonspin are not the same, though they are intimately related. The photon’s spinaxis is parallel to the direction of travel, whereas the polarization axis of awave of light is perpendicular to the direction of travel. But the effect ofpolarization on the behaviour of photons is formally similar to the effectof spin on the behaviour of massive particles, and the difference does notaffect our arguments here.)

We can write the state in this more illustrative form: it is a superpositionof |vert>⊗ |vert> and |horiz>⊗ |horiz>. If we do assign a state to the individ-ual subsystems by the previously mentioned calculation (‘reduction of thedensity matrix’), what we get is that each of the two component photons isin a / mixture of |horiz> and |vert>. That is why on each side we seethe filter being passed % of the time. The pure state of the pair taken as awhole, however, is what accounts for the perfect correlation observed.

Especially important here is that the local measurements cannot be takenas revealing polarization before the measurements are made. Indeed, if weassume that the photons were already definitely polarized beforehand, theBell inequalities can be deduced, in contradiction with the results obtainedby Aspect. Therefore the measurement outcomes do not reveal that therewas already a discernible difference between parts of the total system.

There certainly are ways to ‘disentangle’ such an entanglement, but they

are violent. To begin with, on the basis that such an entangled state wasprepared, we have a prediction of perfect correlation in the outcomes of twoseparated local measurements, and hence a conditional certainty for pre-diction. Finding an outcome on the left, we can predict with certainty theoutcome that will be found, afterwards, on the right if the same angle is chosen

for the polarizer there. Once the measurements are made, however, thesituation is very different: the total system is no longer in an entangled state.If we contemplate subsequent measurements on the two photons, the resulton one side will no longer be, independently of any knowledge of what wasdone or has happened on the other side, symptomatic of what will happenthere whenever the same orientations are chosen.

Therefore judgements of distinctness do not bring with them any implica-tion of discernibility. For judgements in which we discern two localizedparticles or events require a measurement set-up incompatible with main-taining a certain kind of state, entanglement, for which judgements ofdistinctness are perfectly possible and meaningful.

We conclude that judgements of numerical distinctness are perfectly poss-ible and meaningful in certain states which cannot be maintained in the

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

19 See A. Aspect, ‘Bell’s Inequality Test: More Ideal than Ever’, Nature, (),pp. –, for a schematic account of his own and later experiments.

Page 20: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

measurement set-up required for judgements in which two localized part-icles are discerned. Judgements of distinctness do not bring discernibility along with

them.

In the case of incongruent counterparts, we mentioned Kant as calling forspatial determination in terms of the a priori conditions of perception. Trans-cendental attention to the conditions of possibility of any distinction mustrethink its target: we need now to take into account the pragmatic readingof scientific knowledge which has become current in epistemology sinceKant’s time. We need to enlarge the idea of ‘sensibility’ to embrace condi-tions of experimental measurement.

To see an experimental set-up such as the above as discerning the twoparticles by ascription of different individual characteristics, related to thespin component, is to be oblivious to the experimental conditions of eitherasserting a correlation or ascribing a spin component. The correlationassociated with the entanglement of the state vectors is tied to a certainexperimental set-up. ‘The entanglement of state vectors, far from denoting asubstantial relation, expresses but a potentiality of a correlation if a certainkind of experimentation is performed in the following of a first measurementwhich stands then as the preparation for it’, that is, for this second measure-ment (Bitbol). The correlation is just in the probabilities for outcomes ofmeasurements that could be made or will be made. Moreover, as Bitbol says, theexperimental set-up in which the correlation statement makes sense is notcompatible with the experimental set-up in which measurement related tolocal observables, such as the spin component, are performed:

the experimental set-up which defines a correlation and allows the obtaining ofinformation about it is generally exclusive of an experimental set-up defining localobservables and allowing the obtaining of maximal information about them.

In transition from the first kind of set-up to the second, no continuitycondition for identity is satisfied which would enable us to say that what hasthis or that spin component now is what the correlation was about before.The now and the before refer to different preparations, and there is then noexperimental basis for saying that the correlation concerns two distinctentities.

It is important to see how the Kantian case of the incongruent counter-parts and the quantum case of the correlated particles diverge from eachother, as well as how they are similar. In both we have a relation (incon-gruence, correlation) which is not founded in attributes of the relata, and forwhich the conditions of possibility of knowledge are tied to specific experi-mental contexts. But in the case of the counterparts, the compatibility betweenthe two experimental contexts – that in which one hand is individuated as

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN AND ISABELLE PESCHARD

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

Page 21: IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELYipeschard.free.fr/Identity.pdf · 2008-09-19 · The possibility of rejecting the principle of the identity of indiscernibles has certain

right or left, and that in which the relation of incongruence holds – makes itpossible for the hands to be the relata of the relation. In the case of quantumparticles, the incompatibility of the corresponding experimental contextsmakes this impossible, and highlights, by contrast, the non-givenness of anyroute which could relate numerical distinction to discernibility. Thus con-ceptual discernibility cannot, even logically, be a foundation for knowledgeof numerical distinctness, but is a further stage of knowledge which has toinvolve a cognitive procedure, of individuation, which requires particularconditions of possibility. This procedure is so ‘naturally’ conducted in ordin-ary contexts that one is oblivious to it and to the conditions it requires – butof these one is then forcefully reminded by their absence in the quantumcontext. The very fact that one calls this an absence betrays the reference-role still given to situations in which the possibility of this procedure ispresent. The transcendental perspective leads therefore to a more uniform,less preferential consideration of the different experimental and experientialconditions of knowledge.20

Princeton University & University of Twente, Enschede

IDENTITY OVER TIME: OBJECTIVELY, SUBJECTIVELY

© The Authors Journal compilation © The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly

20 Appendices to this paper are available from the authors. We thank Michel Bitbol, AnjaJauernig, Fred Muller, Simon Saunders and Paul Teller for helpful conversation and cor-respondence. Our conclusions, though reached differently, are similar to those of Teller’s ‘TheIns and Outs of Counterfactual Switching’, Noûs, (), pp. –.