385

General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach
Page 2: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

GENERAL SYSTEMS THEORYA MATHEMATICAL APPROACH

Page 3: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

International Federation for Systems ResearchInternational Series on Systems Science and Engineering

Series Editor: George J. KlirState University of New York at Binghamton

Editorial BoardGerrit BroekstraErasmus University, Rotterdam,

The NetherlandsJohn L. CastiSanta Fe Institute, New Mexico

Brian GainesUniversity of Calgary, Canada

Ivan M. HavelCharles University, Prague,

Czech Republic

Manfred PeschelAcademy of Sciences, Berlin, Germany

Franz PichlerUniversity of Linz, Austria

Volume 8 THE ALTERNATIVE MATHEMATICAL MODEL OFLINGUISTIC SEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICSVilém Novák

Volume 9 CHAOTIC LOGIC: Language, Thought, and Reality from thePerspective of Complex Systems ScienceBen Goertzel

Volume 10 THE FOUNDATIONS OF FUZZY CONTROLHarold W. Lewis, III

Volume 11 FROM COMPLEXITY TO CREATIVITY: Explorations inEvolutionary, Autopoietic, and Cognitive DynamicsBen Goertzel

Volume 12 GENERAL SYSTEMS THEORY: A Mathematical ApproachYi Lin

Volume 13 PRINCIPLES OF QUANTITATIVE LIVING SYSTEMSSCIENCEJames R. Simms

Volume 14 INTELLIGENT ROBOTIC SYSTEMS: Design, Planning,and ControlWitold Jacak

IFSR was established “to stimulate all activities associated with the scientific study of systems andto coordinate such activities at international level.” The aim of this series is to stimulate publicationof high-quality monographs and textbooks on various topics of systems science and engineering. Thisseries complements the Federation’s other publications.

A Continuation Order Plan is available for this series. A continuation order will bring delivery of each new volumeimmediately upon publication. Volumes are billed only upon actual shipment. For further information please contactthe publisher.

Volumes 1–6 were published by Pergamon Press.

Page 4: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

GENERAL SYSTEMS THEORYA MATHEMATICAL APPROACH

YI LINSlippery Rock University

Slippery Rock, Pennsylvania

KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERSNEW YORK, BOSTON , DORDRECHT, LONDON, MOSCOW

Page 5: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

0-306- 46962-60-306-45944-2

©2002 Kluwer Academic PublishersNew York, Boston, Dordrecht, London, Moscow

All rights reserved

No part of this eBook may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic,mechanical, recording, or otherwise, without written consent from the Publisher

Created in the United States of America

Visit Kluwer Online at: http://www.kluweronline.comand Kluwer's eBookstore at: http://www.ebooks.kluweronline.com

Print ISBN

eBook ISBN

Page 6: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Preface

As suggested by the title of this book, I will present a collection of coherentlyrelated applications and a theoretical development of a general systems theory.Hopefully, this book will invite all readers to sample an exciting and challenging(even fun!) piece of interdisciplinary research, that has characterized the scientificand technological achievements of the twentieth century. And, I hope that manyof them will be motivated to do additional reading and to contribute to topics alongthe lines described in the following pages.

Since the applications in this volume range through many scientific disciplines,from sociology to atomic physics, from Einstein’s relativity theory to Dirac’s quan-tum mechanics, from optimization theory to unreasonable effectiveness of mathe-matics to foundations of mathematical modeling, from general systems theory toSchwartz’s distributions, special care has been given to write each application in alanguage appropriate to that field. That is, mathematical symbols and abstractionsare used at different levels so that readers in various fields will find it possibleto read. Also, because of the wide range of applications, each chapter has beenwritten so that, in general, there is no need to reference a different chapter in orderto understand a specific application. At the same time, if a reader has the desire togo through the entire book without skipping any chapter, it is strongly suggestedto refer back to Chapters 2 and 3 as often as possible.

The motivation to write this book came from the strong influence of historicalworks by L. von Bertalanffy, George Klir, and M. D. Mesarovic, and the bookOn Systems Analysis, by David Berlinski (MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts,1976). Berlinski’s book and challenges from several scholars really made medecide to write such a book with strong applications in different scientific fieldsin order to justify the very meaning of existence for a general systems theory. Atthe same time, one of the important lessons we have learned from the several-decade-old global systems movement, started and supported by many of the mostpowerful minds of our modern time, is that senseless transfer of statements (morespecifically, theoretical conclusions or results) from one discipline to anothermakes people feel that general systems theory is a doubtful subject. To keep suchunnecessary situations from occurring, we develop each application with rigorous

vii

Page 7: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

viii Preface

logical reasoning. Whenever a bold conclusion is deduced, some relevant gaps inthe reasoning process will be pointed out right on the spot or in the final chapter(“Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory”). On the other hand,doubtful people will be as doubtful as they can no matter what facts or evidenceare out there to show them their doubt is unfounded. For example, more than 100years ago, when naive set theory was first introduced and studied, many first-classmathematicians did not treat it as a serious theory at all. Furthermore, Cantor, thefounder, was personally attacked by these scholars. As a consequence, he washospitalized and eventually died in a psychiatric hospital. Today, set theory hassucceeded in a great many areas of modern science, including the entire spectrumof mathematics, when the central idea of infinity is employed in systems science,we can still hear doubters saying things like: Infinity? One can be sure that in aninfinitely long period of time, a monkey will produce the great Beethoven’s music!(A note: according to results in set theory, this statement is not true!)

The structure of my theoretical development in this book is the “top-down”— formalization — approach, launched in 1960 by Mesarovic. This approachis characterized by the following: (1) All concepts are introduced with mini-mal mathematical structures. (2) Additional mathematical conditions are addedwhen necessary to display the richness of systems properties. At the same time,applicability is always used to test the mathematical conditions added.

Calculus is all that is needed to comprehend this book, since all other mathe-matical techniques are presented at appropriate levels.

Finally, I would to express my sincere appreciation to many individuals, toomany to list. My thanks go to President Robert Aebersold and Vice President andProvost Charles Foust, Deans Charles Zuzak and Jay Harper of Slippery RockUniversity, Pennsylvania, whose academic support for the past several years wasessential to finishing this book. I thank Dr. Ben Fitzpatrick, my Ph.D. supervisor,for his years’ teaching and academic influence, Professor Lotfi Zadeh, the fatherof fuzzy mathematics, for his keen encouragement, Professor Xavier J. R. Avula,President of the International Association for Mathematical and Computer Mod-eling, for his personal influence and education on professional perfection for thepast several years.

I hope you enjoy using and referencing this book, and your comments andsuggestions are welcome! Please let me hear from you — my e-mail address [email protected].

Yi Lin

Page 8: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Acknowledgments

This book contains many research results previously published in various sources,and I am grateful to the copyright owners for permitting me to use the material.They are International Association for Cybernetics (Namur, Belgium), Gordon andBreach Science Publishers (Yverdon, Switzerland, and New York), Hemisphere(New York), International Federation for Systems Research (Vienna, Austria),Kluwer Academic Publishers (Dordrecht, Netherlands), MCB University Press(Bradford, U.K.), Pergamon Journals, Ltd. (Oxford, England), Principia Scientia(St. Louis), Springer-Verlag (London), Taylor and Francis, Ltd. (London), WorldScientific Press (Singapore and New Jersey), and Wroclaw Technical UniversityPress (Wroclaw, Poland).

ix

Page 9: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Contents

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1

1.1. Historical Background . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2

1.2. Several Aspects of Systems Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6

1.3. A Few Thoughts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14

2. Naive Set Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15

2.1. A Set and Its Classification . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15

2.2. Operations of Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19

2.3. Arithmetic of Cardinal Numbers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23

2.4. Ordered Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32

2.5. Well-Ordered Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42

2.6. Crises of Naive Set Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56

3. Axiomatic Set Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59

3.1. Some Philosophical Issues . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59

3.2. Constructions of Ordinal and Cardinal Number Systems . . . . . . 65

3.3. Families of Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77

3.4. Well-Founded Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 90

3.5. References for Further Study . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96

4. Centralizability and Tests of Applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 97

4.1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 97

4.2. Centralized Systems and Centralizability . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99

4.3. Several Tests of Applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 100

4.4. Growth of the Polish School of Mathematics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 104

4.5. The Appearance of Nicolas Bourbaki . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 106

4.6. Some Related Problems and a Few Final Words . . . . . . . . . . . . 108

xi

Page 10: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

xii Contents

5. A Theoretical Foundation for the Laws of Conservation . . . . . . . . . 1115.1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1115.2. Brief History of Atoms, Elements, and Laws of Conservation . . . 1125.3. A Mathematical Foundation for the Laws of Conservation . . . . . . 1155.4. A Few Final Words . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 119

6. A Mathematics of Computability that Speaks the Language of. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121

6.1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1216.2. Multilevel Structure of Nature . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1226.3. Some Hypotheses in Modern Physics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1246.4. A Non-Archimedean Number Field . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1256.5. Applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1296.6. Some Final Words . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 134

7. Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations . . . . . . . . . 1357.1. A Brief Historical Note . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1357.2. Hu’s Counterexample and Analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1367.3. Generalized Principle of Optimality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1387.4. Some Partial Answers and a Conjecture . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1407.5. Generalization of Fundamental Equations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1437.6. Operation Epitome Principle . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1477.7. Fundamental Equations of Generalized Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . 1507.8. Applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1577.9. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 161

8. Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour . . . . . . . . . 163

8.1. What Is Mathematics? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 163

8.2. The Construction of Mathematics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1668.3. Mathematics from the Viewpoint of Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 171

8.4. A Description of the State of Materials . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1748.5. Some Epistemological Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1768.6. The Vase Puzzle and Its Contradictory Mathematical

Modelings . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 177

8.7. Final Comments and Further Questions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 188

9. General Systems: A Multirelation Approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1919.1. The Concept of General Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1919.2. Mappings from Systems into Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2009.3. Constructions of Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2049.4. Structures of Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2149.5. Hierarchies of Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2249.6. Controllabilities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 235

Levels

Page 11: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Contents xiii

9.7. Limit Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2459.8. References for Further Study . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 254

10. Systems of Single Relations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25510.1. Chaos and Attractors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25510.2. Feedback Transformations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26310.3. Feedback-Invariant Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27110.4. Decoupling of Single-Relation Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28010.5. Decomposability Conditions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29110.6. Some References for Further Study. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 309

11. Calculus of Generalized Numbers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31111.l.Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31111.2. Continuity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31711.3. Differential Calculus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32111.4. Integral Calculus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32511.5. Schwartz Distribution and GNS . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33511.6. A Bit of History . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34411.7. Some Leads for Further Research . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 345

12. Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory . . . . . . . . . . . 34712.1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34712.2. The Concept of Systems. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34812.3. Mathematical Modeling and the Origin of the Universe . . . . . . . 35112.4. Laws of Conservation and the Multilevel Structure of Nature . . . 35612.5. Set-Theoretic General Systems Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35812.6. Analytic Foundation for an Applicable General Systems

Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36312.7. A Few Final Words . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 367

References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 369

Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 379

Page 12: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 1

Introduction

Although people often talk about “modern science” and “modern technology,”what really are their characteristics? The most important and most obvious char-acteristic is that the forest of specialized and interdisciplinary disciplines can beeasily seen, yet the boundaries of disciplines become blurred. That is, the “overall”trend of modern science and technology is to synthesize all areas of knowledge intoa few major blocks, as evidenced by the survey of an American national committeeon scientific research in 1985 (Mathematical Sciences, 1985). Another character-istic, which is not obvious but dominates the development of modern science andtechnology, is that the esthetic standard of scientific workers has been changingconstantly. Because of the rapid progress of science and technology, researchersand administrators of scientific research have been faced with unprecedented prob-lems: How can they equip themselves with the newest knowledge? How can theyhandle new knowledge, the amount of which has been increasing in a geomet-ric series? If traditional research methods and esthetic standards are employedwithout modification, then today’s unpublished scientific results could becomeoutdated tomorrow. In this new environment, a new scientific theory — scienceof sciences — was born (Tian and Wang, 1980). In particular, administrators ofscientific research are interested in whether science itself can be studied as a socialphenomenon.

Parallel with the science of sciences some natural questions arise. Can theconcept of wholeness or connection be used to study similar problems in differentscientific fields? Can the point of view of interconnections be employed to observethe world in which we live? In the second decade of this century, von Bertalanffy(1934) wrote: since the fundamental character of living things is its organization,the customary investigation of the single parts and processes cannot provide acomplete explanation of the vital phenomena. This investigation gives us noinformation about the coordination of parts and processes. Thus the chief taskof biology must be to discover the laws of biological systems (at all levels oforganization). We believe that the attempts to find a foundation for the theoreticalpoint at a fundamental change in the world picture. This view, considered as amethod of investigation, we call “organismic biology” and, as an attempt at anexplanation, “the system theory of the organism.” From this statement it can

1

Page 13: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

2 Chapter 1

be seen that parallel to the challenge of modern science and technology, a newconcept of “systems” had been proposed formally. Tested in the last seventy someyears, this concept has been widely accepted by the entire spectrum of science andtechnology [for details, see (Blauberg et al., 1977)].

In this chapter we analyze the historical background for systems theory andseveral important research directions. For a detailed treatment on the history ofsystems theory, please refer to (von Bertalanffy, 1972; von Bertalanffy, 1968).

1.1. Historical Background

Before discussing the historical background of systems theory, let us first talkabout what systems methodology is. Scholars in the field understand it in differentways. However, their fundamental points are the same, loosely speaking. Inthe following, let us first look at typical opinions of the two important figures inmodem science: H. Quastler and L. Zadeh.

Quastler (1965) wrote: generally speaking, systems methodology is essen-tially the establishment of a structural foundation for four kinds of theories oforganization: cybernetics, game theory, decision theory, and information theory.It employs the concepts of a black box and a white box (a white box is a knownobject, which is formed in certain way, reflecting the efficiency of the system’sgiven input and output), showing that research problems, appearing in the afore-mentioned theories on organizations, can be represented as white boxes, and theirenvironments as black boxes. The objects of systems are classified into severalcategories: motivators, objects needed by the system to produce, sensors, andeffectors. Sensors are the elements of the system that receive information, and ef-fectors are the elements of the system that produce real reactions. Through a set ofrules, policies, and regulations, sensors and effectors do what they are supposed todo. By using these objects, Quastler proved that the common structure of the fourtheories of organization can be described by the following laws: (1) Interactionsare between systems and between systems and their environments. (2) A system’sefficiency is stimulated by its internal movements and the reception of informationabout its environment.

Zadeh (1962) listed some important problems in systems theory as follows:systems characteristics, systems classification, systems identification, signal rep-resentation, signal classification, systems analysis, systems synthesis, systemscontrol and programming, systems optimization, learning and adaptation, systemsliability, stability, and controllability. The characteristics of his opinion are that themain task of systems theory is the study of general properties of systems withoutconsidering their physical specifics. Systems methodology in Zadeh’s viewpointis that systems theory is an independent scientific discipline whose job is to de-velop an abstract foundation with concepts and frames in order to study various

Page 14: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Introduction 3

behaviors of different kinds of systems. Therefore, systems theory is a theory ofmathematical structures of systems with the purpose of studying the foundation oforganizations and systems structures.

Even though the concept of systems has been a hot spot for discussion in almostall areas of modern science and technology, and was first introduced formally inthe second decade of this century in biology (von Bertalanffy, 1924), as all newconcepts in science, the ideas and thinking logic of systems have a long history.For example, Chinese traditional medicine, treating each human body as a whole,can be traced to the time of Yellow Emperor about 2800 years ago; and Aristotle’sstatement “the whole is greater than the sum of its parts” has been a fundamentalproblem in systems theory. That is, over the centuries, mankind has been studyingand exploring nature by using the thinking logic of systems. Only in modern timeshave some new contents been added to the ancient systems thinking. The method-ology of studying systems as wholes adequately agrees with the development trendof modern science, namely to divide the object of consideration into parts as smallas possible and studying all of them, seek interactions and connections betweenphenomena, and to observe and comprehend more and bigger pictures of nature.

In the history of science, although the word “system” was never emphasized,we can still find many explanatory terms concerning the concept of systems. Forexample, Nicholas of Cusa, that profound thinker of the fifteenth century, linkingMedieval mysticism with the first beginning of modern science, introduced thenotion of coincidentia oppositorum, the opposition or indeed fight among the partswithin a whole which nevertheless forms a unity of higher order. Leibniz’s hier-archy of monads looks quite like that of modern systems; his mathesis universalispresages an expanded mathematics which is not limited to quantitative or numeri-cal expressions and is able to formulate much conceptual thought. Hegel and Marxemphasized the dialectic structure of thought and of the universe it produces: thedeep insight that no proposition can exhaust reality but only approaches its coin-cidence of opposites by the dialectic process of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis.Gustav Fechner, known as the author of the psychophysical law, elaborated, in theway of the natural philosophers of the nineteenth century, supraindividual organi-zations of higher order than the usual objects of observation — for example, lifecommunities and the entire earth, thus romantically anticipating the ecosystems ofmodern parlance. Here, only a few names are listed. For a more comprehensivestudy, see (von Bertalanffy, 1972).

Even though Aristotelian teleology was eliminated in the development ofmodern science, problems contained in it, such as “the whole is greater than thesum of its parts,” the order and goal directedness of living things, etc., are stillamong the problems of today’s systems theory research. For example, what is a“whole”? What does “the sum of its parts” mean? All these problems have notbeen studied in all classical branches of science, since these branches have beenestablished on Descartes’ second principle and Galileo’s method, where Descartes’second principle says: divide each problem into parts as small as possible, and

Page 15: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

4 Chapter 1

In (von Bertalanffy, 1972), von Bertalanffy described the scientific revolutionin the sixteenth century as follows: “(The Scientific Revolution of the sixteenthto seventeenth centuries) replaced the descriptive-metaphysical conception of theuniverse epitomized in Aristotle’s doctrine by the mathematical—positivistic orGalilean conception. That is, the vision of the world as a teleological cosmoswas replaced by the description of events in causal, mathematical laws.” Basedon this description, can we describe the change in today’s science and technologyas follows? At the same time of continuously using Descartes’ second principleand Galileo’s method, systems methodology was introduced in order to deal withproblems of order or organization.

Galileo’s method implies simplifying a complicated process as basic portions andprocesses [for details see (Kuhn, 1962)].

From this superficial discussion, it can be seen that the concept of systems weare studying today is not simply a product of yesterday. It is a reappearance ofsome ancient thought and a modern form of an ancient quest. This quest has beenrecognized in the human struggle for survival with nature, and has been studied atvarious points in time by using the languages of different historical moments.

Ackoff (1959) commented that during the past two decades, we witnessed theappearance of the key concept “systems” in scientific research. However, with theappearance of the concept, what changes have occurred in modern science? Underthe name “systems research”, many branches of modern science have shown thetrend of synthetic development; research methods and results in various disciplineshave been intertwined to influence overall research progress, so one feels the ten-dency of synthetic development in scientific activities. This synthetic developmentrequires the introduction of new concepts and new thoughts in the entire spectrumof science. In a certain sense, all of this can be considered as the center of theconcept of “systems .” One Soviet expert described the progress of modern scienceas follows (Hahn, 1967, p. 185): refining specific methods of systems researchis a widespread tendency in the exploration of modern scientific knowledge, justas science in the nineteenth century with forming natural theoretical systems andprocesses of science as its characteristics.

Should we continue to use Descartes’ second principle and Galileo’s method?Yes, for two reasons. First, they have been extremely effective in scientific researchand administration, where all problems and phenomena could be decomposed intocausal chains, which could be treated individually. That has been the foundationfor all basic theoretical research and modern laboratory activities. In addition, theywon victories for physics and led to several technological revolutions. Second,modern science and technology are not Utopian projects as described by Popper(1945), reknitting every corner for a new world, but based on the known knowledgebase, they are progressing in all directions with more depth, more applicability,and a higher level of difficulty.

On the other hand, the world is not a pile of infinitely many isolated objects,where not every problem or phenomenon can be simply described by a single

Page 16: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Introduction 5

causal relation. The fundamental characteristics of this world are its organizationalstructure and connections of interior and exterior relations of different matters.The study of either an isolated part or a single causality of problems can hardlyexplain completely or relatively globally our surrounding world. At this junction,the research progress of the three-body problem in mechanics is an adequateexample. So, as human race advances, studying problems with multicausality ormultirelation will become more and more significant.

In the history of scientific development, the exploration of nature has alwaysmoved back and forth between specific matters or phenomena and generalities.Scientific theories need foundations rooted deep inside practice while theoriesare used to explain natural phenomena so that our understanding can be greatlyenhanced. In the following, we discuss the technological background for systemstheory — that is, the need which arose in the development of technology andrequirement for higher level production.

There have had been many advances in technology: energies produced by vari-ous devices, such as steam engines, motors, computers, and automatic controllers;self-controlled equipment from domestic temperature controllers to self-directedmissiles; and the information highway, which has resulted in increased communi-cation of new scientific results. On the other hand, increased speed of communi-cation furthers scientific development to a different level. Also, societal changeshave brought more pressing demands for new construction materials. From theseexamples, it can be seen that the development of technology forces mankind toconsider not only a single machine or matter or phenomenon, but also “systems”of machines and/or “systems” of matter and phenomena. The design of steamengines, automobiles, cordless equipment, etc., can all be handled by speciallytrained engineers, but when dealing with the designs of missiles, aircraft, or newconstruction materials, for example, a collective effort, combining many differ-ent aspects of knowledge, has to be in place, which includes the combination ofvarious techniques, machines, electronic technology, chemical reactions, people,etc. Here the relation between people and machines becomes more obvious, anduncountable financial, economic, social, and political problems are intertwined toform a giant, complicated system, consisting of men, machines, and many othercomponents. It was the great political, technical and personnel arrangement suc-cess of the American Apollo project, landing humans on the moon, that hinted thathistory has reached a point where all aspects of science and technology have beenmaturely developed so that each rational combination of information or knowledgecould result in unexpected consumable products.

A great many problems in production require locating the optimal point ofthe maximum economic effect and minimum cost in an extremely complicatednetwork. This kind problem not only appears in industry, agriculture, militaryaffairs, and business, but politicians are also using similar (systems) methods toseek answers to problems like air and water pollution, transportation blockages,decline of inner cities, and crimes committed by teenage gangs.

Page 17: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

6 Chapter 1

In production, there exists a tendency that bigger or more accurate productswith more profits are designed and produced. In fact, under different interpreta-tions, all areas of learning have been faced with complexity, totality, and “systemal-ity.” This tendency betokens a sharp change in scientific thinking. By comparingDescartes’ second principle and Galileo’s method with systems methodology andconsidering the development tendency, as described previously, appearing in theworld of learning and production, it is not hard to see that because of systemsconcepts, another new scientific and technological revolution will soon arrive. Tothis end, for example, each application of systems theory points out the fact that therelevant classical theory needs to be modified somehow [see (Klir, 1970; Berlin-ski, 1976; Lilienfeld, 1978)]. However, not all scientific workers have this kind ofoptimistic opinion. Some scholars believe that it is an omen that systems theoryitself is facing a crisis [see (Wood-Harper and Fitzgerald, 1982) for details]. Onlytime and history will have the right to tell who is right and who is wrong.

1.2. Several Aspects of Systems Theory

In the past half century or so, since the concept of systems was first introducedby von Bertalanffy, systems thinking and methodology have seeped into all cornersof science and technology. Because of such a wide range of applications, scholarsin systems science have been divided into two big groups. One group followsthe direction pointed out by Quastler and Zedah, and the other contains scholarswith the desire to discover general principles while solving practical and specificproblems. Thus, under the name “systems methodology,” many problem-orientedsystems approaches have appeared. Here we look at the taxonomy of differentapproaches, made available by Wood-Harper and Fitzgerald based on the fieldof application of each approach. For the original work, see (Wood-Harper andFitzgerald, 1982).

1.2.1. General Systems Methodology

General systems methodology is a theoretical methodology whose purpose isto realize the ideal model of a systems theory described by von Bertalanffy (1968),Quastler (1965) and Zadeh (1962) — that is, establish a general theory applicableto explain phenomena in various specific systems. Based on the idea and logic ofestablishing such a general systems theory, many scholars have tried to employknown results in general systems theory to solve practical problems (Klir, 1970).However, Berlinski (1976) and Lilienfeld (1978) thought that all these attemptswere extremely unsuccessful, since if a conclusion were obtained by applyingresults from general systems theory, it would require modification of the relevant

Page 18: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Introduction 7

theory. However, from the previous discussion, it can be seen that it is naturalfor the application of results from general systems theory to bring about such aphenomenon, because we are using a different methodology than our forefathersused. On the other hand, if an application of results of general systems theoryrequires a complete rebuilding of the structure and rules of the relevant theory, wesurely need to study the correctness of the application of the results from generalsystems theory. Also, because of this phenomenon, some systems analysts believethat considering applications of general systems theory is not practical. At thesame time, many scholars hope to locate the reason why this phenomenon everappeared and to fix the problem so that the resulting general systems theory willbe more like what von Bertalanffy, Quastler, and Zadeh dreamed about, and mucheasier to use to solve practical problems.

1.2.2. Human Activity Systems Approach

Checkland (1975) tried to establish a systems theory in order to solve problemswith unclear meanings and incomplete definition of structures. He believes thatthis kind of system appears in environmental protection, administration of orga-nizations, and business. He also attempted to look for a specific solution amongmany candidates of solutions so his approach would be more meaningful in thesense of application, because when practical problems are being solved often theeffort is difficult to define and causes controversy.

Checkland established his methodology based on general systems theory andmodified some aspects of systems theory so that the results would be more ap-plicable in the real world. This methodology has been applied to many differentproblems and obtained some obvious consequences. It can be classified intogeneral systems methodology, with its emphasis on problems without definitestructures, and complicated environments. Before solving a problem, this methodrequires effort to explore and test the problem structure.

1.2.3. The Participant Approach

The participant approach emphasizes the importance of the researcher(s) insystems analysis (Mumford et al., 1978). Mumford believes that men must beconsidered as a part of the system under consideration, either as participants of theactivities of the system or as designers of the system.

1.2.4. The Traditional Approach

The traditional approach was introduced by the American National ComputerCenter. To a certain degree, this method is accepted by many systems analysts.

Page 19: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

8 Chapter 1

Its basis is that certain problems are solvable with computers. Each application isconsidered individually; and problems are usually solved by finding and designingthe optimal subsystems. Based on research on the properties of systems of interest,the condition of optimality is determined. According to the desired output, theinput is designed. This process is employed to complete the systems design. See(1978–1979) for details.

1.2.5. Data Analysis Approach

Data analysis is established on the principle that the fundamental structureof systems is data [see (1978) for details]. The hypothesis is that if we can,under certain conditions, classify the data, then we will be able to comprehend theessential properties of the system under consideration. For the same set of data,different mathematical models can be established. However, all these models mustpossess some common properties. This implies that the given set of data can bethe initial point for studying properties of the underlying structure, and there isno need to define various models for different applications. Also, if the relationsbetween the data have been established, then the essential structure of the system,represented by the set of data, will appear naturally. Therefore, data analysis canbe considered as the “median” steps leading to the ultimate understanding of thestructure of organization.

1.2.6. Structured Systems Analysis Approach

The structured systems analysis approach was described individually byde Marco (1980) and Gane and Sarsons (1979). It has been attracting the attentionof more and more businesses and organizations. This method was developed tosolve problems contained in classical research methodologies. For example, howcan the concept of subsystems be used to coordinate a large group of analysts andto solve complicated problems concerning big machines and large systems? Thismethod offers new tools for analysis and literature editing. For instance, conceptssuch as data flow diagrams, data dictionary, and constructed English have beenintroduced. These concepts have allowed the literature of known systems to beedited more clearly; consequently discoveries of new structures of the systems canbe expected.

From the aforementioned classification of systems approaches due to Wood-Harper and Fitzgerald, it can be seen that the basic assumptions of various systemsmethodologies can be considered as axioms or as results of general systems theory.In a certain sense, all the systems approaches listed are applications of generalsystems theory. At the same time, the first three approaches emphasize under-standing of systems structures and theoretical analysis of systems, while the otherthree approaches concentrate on problem solving with the hope that the results will

Page 20: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Introduction 9

allow us to understand these systems on a theoretical level. Therefore, the firstthree approaches can be termed theoretical systems methods, while the others canbe called applied systems techniques. For detailed discussion on various systemsapproaches, see (Klir, 1970).

To conclude this chapter, we discuss the foundations of various systems ap-proaches and some research directions in general systems theory.

1.2.7. Some Research Directions in General Systems Theory

Among the main tasks of general systems theory are (1) define the meaning of“systems” and related concepts; (2) classify systems and find their properties in themost general sense; (3) model systems behaviors; (4) study special systems modelslogically and methodologically. The first three tasks constitute the theoreticalbasics for the concepts of special systems, such as control systems theory, automata,and information systems theory. That is, the goal of general systems theory is toestablish a higher-level abstract theory without touching on any specific physicalproperties. That was why von Bertalanffy believed that general systems theorydeals with formal characteristics of systems structures so that its results can beapplied to research topics in various scientific fields, and that it can be used notonly in physical systems but in any “whole” consisting of interacting “parts”(von Bertalanffy, 1967, pp. 125–126).

Even though it follows from the previous discussion that systems have a longhistory and that many problems discussed in modern systems theory have hadbeen considered by many great thinkers from different angles in the past severalcenturies with different languages, as a theory, especially, as a methodology ofgeneral systems, it is still relative new. In (von Bertalanffy, 1972), von Bertalarnffyasked how we can define a system. That is, even though the idea of systems haspermeated all of modern science, we still have not obtained an ideal definition forthe concept of systems!

As a matter of fact, as stated in (Department of Business Administration, 1983),“system” is a generalization of the concept of “structure” in physics but differsfrom a structure. A system possesses three important features: (i) order or levels;(ii) structure of a set; that is, each system consists of at least two subsystems;(iii) relativity and wholeness; that is, the existence of subsystems is relative anddependent on each other and conditioning each other.

Tarski (1954–1955) defined the concept of a system with relations as anonempty set, called the domain of the system with relations, and a finite se-quence of relations defined on the domain. Hall and Fagen (1956) discussed thedefinition of systems. They believed that a system consisted of a set of objects,some relations between the objects, and some relations between the attributes ofthe objects. In (Systems, 1969–1976), Uyomov proved that the attributes con-necting the objects of a system can be considered as new objects of the system.

Page 21: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

10 Chapter 1

In this way, Hall and Fagen’s definition of systems can be simplified as follows:A system is a set of objects and some relations between the objects. Mesarovic(1964) used the language of set theory to define a system as a relation. Therefore,general systems theory becomes a theory of relations. However, ten years later,Mesarovic and Takahara (Mesarovic and Takahara, 1975) pointed out that generalsystems theory, produced with this definition of systems, does not contain any re-sults. Does this imply that the definition of systems, given by Mesarovic, containssomething inappropriate? The authors also pointed out that there is no need tobe concerned because the entire research literature of systems theory contains noresults. If that is a fact, does it imply that it is still too early to establish sucha theory? Yi Lin and Yonghao Ma (Lin, 1987; Lin and Ma, 1987) studied theattempts at defining systems, synthesized all opinions into one with a consider-ation of future development, and introduced a definition of (general) systems asfollows: S is a (general) system if, and only if, S is an ordered pair (M,R ) ofsets, where M is the set of all objects of S and R is a set of relations defined onM. Here a relation r belongs to R means that there exists an ordinal number n(nonzero) such that r is a subset of the Cartesian product Mn. The referee(s) of(Ma and Lin, 1987) claimed that the definition introduced by Lin and Ma willproduce a good quantity of results, which has been evidenced by results containedin (Lin, 1987; Lin and Ma, 1987; Ma and Lin, 1987; Lin, 1989d). In this book,the reader will be led to some of these results. Here, uncertainty, contained in theconcept of “sets,” makes application of systems theory, developed on the definitionof systems by Lin and Ma, contain many uncertain factors. For example, for agiven experimental material, is the totality of molecules constituting the materiala set? Is the collection of all relations between molecules in the material a set?To deal with these uncertainties, Yi Lin introduced the following epistemologicalaxiom: The existence of an object is determined by the existence of some particlesof a certain level and of some relations between the particles, which constitute theobject; for details [see (Lin, 1989d)].

We now briefly introduce several research directions in general systems theory.

1.2.7.1. Classical systems theory. Classical systems theory is a mathematicaltheory, based on calculus, to study the general principles of structures and structureswith specific properties, and has been used for research and description. Its resultshave also been used to solve concrete problems. Because of the generality ofthe problems studied, even with special features, parts, and relations between theparts of a structure, one can still obtain some formal properties of the structureunder concern. For instance, generalized principles of dynamics can be applied tothe totality of molecules or biological objects. That is, these principles can findapplications in chemistry and biology. There are many references here, one ofwhich is (Wonham, 1979).

1.2.7.2. Catastrophe theory. Catastrophe theory, initiated by Newton andLeibniz three centuries ago, is a different way of thinking and reasoning about

Page 22: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Introduction 11

“discrete,” “jump” or “discontinuous” changes in a course of events, in an object’sshape, change in a system’s behavior, and change in ideas themselves. As sug-gested by its name, this study has been applied to research of literal catastrophes(e.g., collapse of a bridge, downfall of an empire) and to quiet changes, (e.g.,dancing of sunlight on the bottom of a pool, transition from wakefulness to sleep).For more details, see (Poston and Steward, 1978).

1.2.7.3. Compartment theory. In (Rescigno and Segre, 1966), Rescigno andSegre first studied compartment theory. The basic idea is that the problem orstructure under consideration can be described as a whole consisting of partssatisfying certain boundary conditions, between which there appear processes oftransportation, such as “chains” or “nipples.” That is, the parts can be chainedtogether by transportation, or transportation appears between a central part andits surrounding parts. The mathematical difficulty in dealing with structures withthree or more parts becomes obvious. In this area, Laplace transformation andnetworks and graph theory have been successfully used.

1.2.7.4. Cybernetics. Cybernetics is a theory on systems and their environ-ments, internal information transportation of systems, and impacts on the environ-ment of controlled systems. This theory has found many applications. Becauseof its usefulness, many scholars do not see it as a part of systems theory. Cy-bernetics has often been used to describe the formal structure of some “actionprocesses.” Even though the structure of the system under concern is not clearlygiven, and the system is an input—output “black” box, cybernetics can still offersome understanding about that structure. Therefore, cybernetics has been appliedin many areas, including hydraulics, electricity, ecology, markets, etc. For moreinformation, see (Bayliss, 1966; Milsum, 1966).

1.2.7.5. Fuzzy mathematics. Fuzzy mathematics is a theory dealing with therapprochement between the precision of classical mathematics and the pervasiveimprecision of the real world. The fundamental concept here is fuzzy sets, whichare classes with boundaries that are not sharp in which the transition from mem-bership to nonmembership is gradual rather than abrupt. At present, we are unableto design machines that can compete with humans in the performance of tasks suchas recognition of speech, translation of languages, comprehension of meanings,abstraction and generalization, decision making with uncertainty, and, above all,summarization of information. This stems from a fundamental difference betweenhuman intelligence, containing fuzziness, and machine intelligence, based on pre-cision. Consisting of a body of new concepts and techniques, this theory acceptsfuzziness as an all-pervasive reality of human existence, which has opened manynew frontiers in psychology, sociology, political science, philosophy, physiology,economics, linguistics, operations research, management science, and other fields.The literature in this research area is plentiful, and I will not list any here.

Page 23: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

12 Chapter 1

1.2.7.6. Game theory. According to Quastler, game theory is a systems theory,since it deals with the behaviors of (n) ideal players with the ability to reason andmake decisions, whose goal is to win more than to lose. One goal of this researchis how to apply optimal strategies to confront other players (or the environment).That is, game theory is about the study of systems with special reaction forces. Agood reference is (Shubik, 1983).

1.2.7.7. Genetic algorithms. Genetic algorithms (GAs) have been appliedin many areas, including economics, political science, psychology, linguistics,biology, computer science, etc. GAS are search procedures based on the mechanicsof natural selection and natural genetics. They combine survival of the fittestamong string structures with a structured yet randomized information exchangeto form a search algorithm with some of the innovative flair of human search.The goals of this research are twofold: (1) to abstract and rigorously explain theadaptive processes of natural systems, and (2) to design artificial systems softwarethat retains the important mechanisms of natural systems. This approach has ledto important discoveries in both natural and artificial science. The central themeof research here has been robustness, the balance between efficiency and efficacynecessary for survival in many different environments. A good introductory bookon this subject matter is (Goldberg, 1989), and the classic is (Holland, 1975).

1.2.7.8. Graph theory. Besides the quantitative study of structures, manyproblems deal with the organization and topological structures of the systemsof interest. There exist many methods useful to this research. Graph analysis,especially directed graph theory, describes in detail the construction of relationsbetween systems. This method has been successfully applied in many differentareas, including biology [see, for example, (Rashevsky, 1956)]. Combined withmatrix theory in mathematics, the characteristics of the models, developed in graphtheory are similar to those of compartment theory, so it establishes relations withthe theory of open systems.

1.2.7.9. Information theory. Based on the opinion of Shannon and Weaver(1949), information theory is established on the concept of information, which isdefined by an expression similar to one with negative entropy in thermodynamics.Quastler (1955) believes that information can be considered as a measure of thestructure of organization. Although information theory is very important in theengineering of communication, research results in other areas of application havenot yielded any convincing consequences.

1.2.7.10. Navier–Stokes equation and chaos. Even though the Navier–Stokesequation has been successfully applied in weather forecasting (short term only), itsstudy has recently given some new understanding, which has led to the new sciencecalled Chaos. On one hand, the concept of chaos, which has several differentmeanings, has created a burst of research in almost all areas of science. Peopleare trying to find and understand chaos. On the other hand, some scholars have

Page 24: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Introduction 13

shown that the original chaos, introduced by Lorenz in the study of simplifyingNavier–Stokes equation, has nothing to do with modem chaos. In fact, it is eitheran illusion of a concept of a higher dimensional space or a misunderstanding incomputer-aided calculation. Here I list only two references (Cohen and Steward,1994; Gleick, 1987).

1.2.7.11. Networks. Network theory can be considered as part of set theory,or graph theory, or compartment theory. The main structure dealt with is netstructures of systems. It has been applied to neural networks; for details, see(Rapoport, 1949).

1.2.7.12. Set theory. All the general definitions and properties of structureshave been given in terms of set theory. For example, open and closed systemscan be described by axioms using the language of set theory. All research alongthis line was originated by Mesarovic (1964, pp. 1–24). Most of this research,carried out since 1964, is related to the concept of systems and related topics, not tosolving practical problems, at least until recently [see (Lin and Ma, 1987; Ma andLin, 1987; Lin, 1989d; Lin and Qiu, 1987)]. Because of the use of the languageof set theory, the language and methodology of category theory can be employedto classify structures. On the other hand, algebraic methods can be introduced sothat concepts, such as linear and nonlinear structures, have been introduced. Forrelated references, see (Mesarovic and Takahara, 1975).

1.2.7.13. Simulation. If the structures, described by differential equations,contain nonlinear equations, in general, there is no way to solve the systems.Because of this reason, computer simulation becomes an important method. Thismethod not only saves time and human labor, but also opens up research areas inwhich, mathematically, we do not know if the solution exists. This kind of systemcannot be solved by known mathematics. On the other hand, specific experimentsin laboratories can be replaced by computer simulations. For example, computer-aided design uses computer simulation as a substitute for laboratory experiments.At the same time, the mathematical structure or model obtained by computersimulation can be evaluated by experimental data. For example, Hess (1969)employed this method to compute a 14-th step chemical reaction in human cells,which was described by a system of more than 100 nonlinear differential equations.As a matter of fact, this method has often been used in the study of markets andpopulations.

1.2.7.14. Statistics. Einstein said (1922, p. 60):

The belief in an external world independent of the perceiving subject is the basisof all natural science. Since, however, sense perception only gives information ofthis external world or of “physical reality” indirectly, we can only grasp the latterby speculative means. It follows from this that our notion of physical reality cannever be final.

Page 25: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Chapter 114

Based on this understanding, statistics is a mathematical theory of how topredict and comprehend “reality” according to a small sample, collected withreference to some prior mathematical analysis. This theory is not of what eventcauses another event (i.e., causality) but about what event will imply that anotherwill occur. Successful applications of statistics can be found in almost all appliedareas of human endeavors. One of the best references here is Box, Hunter, andHunter’s classic (Box et al., 1978).

1.2.7.1.5. Theory of automata. The theory of automata concerns an idealautomaton with input and output, and its ability to be corrected and learn(Minsky, 1967). One such example is the Turing machine (Turing, 1936). Inordinary language, the Turing machine is an ideal machine which can print “1”and “0” on an infinitely long tape. It can be shown that, no matter how compli-cated a process can be, if it can be expressed by finite steps of logic rules andcalculations, then this process can be simulated by a machine. From this fact, thefuture of this theory can be seen.

1.3. A Few Thoughts

It can be seen that systems theory is very young. Researchers are trying tofind more practical examples and general properties, and are testing and rethinkingthe theory. That is why new ideas have been appearing quickly, and consequentdiscussions have been intensive. It can be foreseen that the development ofmodern science and technology will be the effective motivation and method totest the duration and significance of ideas and thoughts in general systems theory.Based on the thoughts of general systems theory, some scientific workers havesimplified the question in which administrators of scientific research are interestedto the following: Can science be studied as a system? This is an important andpractical problem since if this question can be studied deeply with reasonableoutcome, the human exploration of nature might be able to go to a higher level(Yablonsky, 1984).

Page 26: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 2

Naive Set Theory

Set theory, created by Georg Cantor (1845–1918), is one of the greatest creationsof the human mind. Everyone who studies it is fascinated by it. More important,however, is that the theory has become of the greatest importance for the entirespectrum of mathematics. It has given rise to new branches of mathematics, or atleast first rendered the possibility for their further development, such as the theoryof point sets, theory of real functions, and topology. Finally, the theory of setshas had influence on the investigation of the foundation of mathematics, as well asthrough the generality of its concepts, as a connecting link between mathematicsand philosophy.

We will present the basic features of Cantor’s naive set theory. The basicconcepts and methods of proofs will be used in the development of general systemstheory.

2.1. A Set and Its Classification

According to Cantor a set M is “a collection into a whole, of finite, well-distinguished objects (called the ‘elements’ of M) of our perception or of ourthoughts.” For example, the 38 students in a classroom constitute a set of 38elements; the totality of even numbers, a set of infinitely many elements; thevertices of a die, a set of 8 elements; the points on a circle, a set of infinitely manyelements.

Two sets M and N are equal, in symbols M = N , if they contain the sameelements. For example, if M = {1,2,3} and N = {2,1,3}, then M = N . (Sets,in general, are designated by enclosing their elements in braces or by a symbollike {x : Φ(x)}, which means that the set consists of all the elements satisfying theproposition Φ .)

The notation M ≠ N means that the sets M and N are different. Further, m ∈ Mmeans that m is an element of the set M , whereas m ∉ M denotes that m is notan element in M. M ⊆ N denotes inclusion; that is, M is a subset of N , or allelements of M also belong to N.

15

Page 27: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

16

ƒ(x) ≠ ƒ(y)

0, 1, 2, 3, . . .

–1, –2, –3, . . .

(2.2)

(2.3)

Chapter 2

Proposition 2.1.1. M = N iff M ⊆ ⊆ N and N ⊆ ⊆ M.

A mapping (or a function) from a set M into a set N is a rule under which eachelement in M is assigned to an element in N . Generally, lower case letters, say,ƒ, g , and h, will be used to indicate mappings. Let ƒ be a mapping from the setM into the set N , denoted by ƒ : M → N . Then for each element m ∈ M , ƒ(m )indicates the element in N which is assigned to the element m .

The mapping ƒ : M → N is onto (or surjective), if for each element n ∈ N ,there exists an element m ∈ M such that ƒ(m) = n . The mapping ƒ : M → N is1–1 (or one-to-one, or injective) if for arbitrary distinct elements x and y ∈ M,

(2.1)

The mapping ƒ : M → N is a bijection (or a bijective mapping) if ƒ is both surjectiveand injective.

Sets M and N are equipollent if there exists a bijection of M onto N . Theequipollence relation between sets classifies the collection of all sets into classessuch that each class contains all the equipollent sets. Another coarse classificationof sets distinguishes the collection of all sets into finite, denumerable and uncount-able sets according to whether the sets contain a finite number of elements, or areequipollent to the set of all natural numbers N, or do not satisfy the previous twoconditions; i.e., they contain infinitely many elements and are not equipollent toN .

Proposition 2.1.2. A set X is denumerable iff it can be written as a sequence{x0 , x1 , x2 , x3 , ...}.

This fact implies that an infinite set X is denumerable iff to every element x ofthe set, precisely one natural number corresponds to it and vice versa.

Theorem 2.1.1. The set of all integers is denumerable.

Proof: Let us write the integers as follows:

Then the set of all integers can be written as the sequence

{0, 1 –1, 2, –2, 3, –3, ..., n , –n, ...}

Theorem 2.1.2. The set of all rational numbers is denumerable.

Page 28: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 17

r

Proof: Let us first deal with the set of all positive rational numbers. We canwrite all whole numbers in order of magnitude (i.e., all numbers with denominator1), then all fractions with denominator 2, then all fractions with denominator 3,etc. Thus, we have the rows of numbers

(2.4)

If we write the numbers in the order indicated by the arrows (leaving out numberswhich have already appeared), then every positive rational number certainly ap-pears, and only once. The collection of these rational numbers is thus written as asequence

(2.5)

If we denote this sequence by {r1 ,r 2 ,r3 , ... }, then obviously

{0, r1, – r1, r 2 ,–r2, 3 , – r3 , . . . }

is the set of all rational numbers, and the denumerability of this set is established.�

The following theorem shows that not every set of real numbers is denumerable.

Theorem 2.1.3. The set of all points in the closed interval [0, 1] is uncountable.

Proof: We prove the theorem by a diagonal method, called the second, orCantor, diagonal method. Suppose that the closed interval [0, 1] is denumerable;then the open internal (0, 1) is also denumerable. From Proposition 2.1.2 it followsthat the points in (0, 1) can be written as the sequence

b0 ,b1,b2 ,b3, . . . (2.6)

We now write each of them as infinite decimal numbers by putting in enough zeros

Page 29: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

18 Chapter 2

whenever necessary. Then

(2.7)

Now we construct a number b ∈ (0, 1), defined by

b = 0.b0b1 b2 b3 . . . (2.8)

such that Then b is not contained in thesequence {b0,b1 ,b2 , . . . } , contradiction. This contradiction implies that the set ofall points in the interval (0, 1) is uncountable. �

The sets X and Y are of the same cardinality if they are equipollent. Generally,to every set X the cardinality of X is assigned and is denoted by X. The equality X = Y holds iff X and Y are equipollent. For a finite set X the cardinalityof X is equal to the number of elements of X. The cardinality assigned to eachdenumerable set is denoted by ℵ 0 (read aleph zero), and the cardinality assignedto the set of all real numbers is denoted by c (called the continuum ).

Let m and n be two cardinalities, and let X = m and Y = n. We say that mis not larger than n, or that n is not smaller than m, and we write m ≤ n or n ≥ m,if there exists a one-to-one mapping of X into Y. We say that m is smaller than n,or that n is larger than m, and we write m < n or n > m, if m ≤ n and X and Y arenot equipollent.

Corollary 2.1.1. ℵ 0 < c.

The following fact says that for any fixed cardinality m there exists a set whosecardinality is larger than m.

Theorem 2.1.4. Let X be a set and 2X the set of all subsets of X, which is calledthe power set of X. Then

X < 2 X (2.9)

Proof: Define a mapping ƒ: X → 2X by letting ƒ(x) = {x} for each x ∈ X.Then ƒ is one-to-one, so X ≤ 2X . We must now show that X and 2X arenot equipollent. We prove this by contradiction. Suppose that X and 2X are

Page 30: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 19

equipollent. There then exists a bijection h from X onto 2X . Define a subset of Xas follows:

Since h is onto, it follows that there exists an element y ∈ X such that

(2.10)

h (y) = A (2.11)

There now exist two possibilities: (1) y ∈ A or (2) y ∉ A. If case (1) holds, theny ∈ A = h (y ). This implies that y ∉ A, contradiction. If case (2) is true, theny ∉ h ( y ) = A. So y ∈ A, another contradiction. Therefore, the bijection h cannotexist, and X < 2 X . �

2.2. Operations of Sets

Let X be a set. A set Y is called a proper subset of X, denoted Y ⊂ X, if Yis a subset of X and X ≠ Y. A set Z of those elements of X which do not belongat the same time to the subset Y is called the complement of Y with respect to X;in symbols, Z = X – Y. When Y is not a proper subset of X, Z may not containany element. In this case, we introduce an ideal set, called the empty set, Ø. Theempty set is classed with the finite sets. It is a subset of every set and, in particular,of itself.

Theorem 2.2.1. Every subset of a denumerable set is at most denumerable.

Proof: Let X = {x 0,x1 ,x 2, ... } be a denumerable set and Y ⊂ X. Then in Xthere exists a first element xk . This is followed1 which belongs to Y ; let y1 = x k1

again by a first element, denoted by xk2 , in X, which belongs to Y ; let y2 = xk2 , etc.The process does or does not terminate, according to whether Y is finite. Since Xcontains all the elements of Y, the possibly terminating sequence { 1 , kk 2 , k 3, ... }comprises precisely the elements of Y. Therefore, Y is finite or denumerable. �

The union of finitely or infinitely many sets is defined to be the set of thoseelements which belong to at least one of the sets. The union U of an at mostdenumerable number of sets X0 , X1 , X2 , ... is written in the form

(2.12)

Page 31: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

20 Chapter 2

The intersection of arbitrarily many sets is defined to be the set of thoseelements which belong to each of the aforesaid sets. For the intersection D of twosets X1 and X2 , we write

and

(2.13)

and for the intersection of at most denumerably many sets,

(2.14)

Let I be a collection of sets. The union U and the intersection D of the sets in I iswritten

(2.15)

(2.16)

Theorem 2.2.2 [De Morgan’s Laws]. Suppose that A, B, and C are sets. Then

(2.17)

(2.18)

Proof: We prove only the first equality. For any element x, x ∈ A – (B ∩C)iff x ∈ A and x ∉ B ∩C, iff x ∈ A and either x ∉ B or x ∉ C, iff either x ∈ A andx ∉ B or x ∈ A and x ∉ C, iff x ∈ ( A – B) ∪ (A – C). �

Proposition 2.2.1 [Commutative Laws]. Let A and B be two sets. Then

(2.19)

The proof follows immediately from the definitions of union and intersection.

Proposition 2.2.2 [Associative Laws]. Let A, B, and C be sets. Then

(2.20)

The proof follows immediately from the definitions of union and intersection.

Proposition 2.2.3 [Distributive Laws]. Let A, B, and C be sets. Then,

(2.21)

(2.22)

Page 32: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 21

The proof is left to the reader.

Proposition 2.2.4 [Laws of Tautology]. For any set A,

The proof is straightforward and is omitted.The following identities are given without proof.

Proposition 2.2.5. Let A, B and C be sets. Then

The following formulas illustrate the analogy between the inclusion relationand the “less than or equal to” relation in arithmetic:

(2.23)

Proposition 2.2.6. For arbitrary sets A, B, C, and D, the following are true:

where → means “imply.”

For the union and intersection of a collection I of sets, we have the followingresults.

Proposition 2.2.7 [De Morgan’s Laws]. Let A be an arbitrary set. Then

Proof:

(1) For any element x, iff x ∈ A and iff x ∈ A andthere exists an X ∈ I such that x ∉ X, iff there exists X ∈ I such that

iff

Page 33: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

22 Chapter 2

(2) For any element x, x ∈ A – ∪ X ∈ I X iff x ∈ A and for each set X ∈ I , x ∉ X ,iff for each set X ∈ I , x ∈ A–X , iff x ∈ (A – X). �

Let x and y be two elements. The ordered pair (x , y) is the set {{x}, {x,y}}. Wecall x the first term (or coordinate) of ( x , y) and y the second term (or coordinate)of (x,y).

Theorem 2.2.3. In order that ( a,b ) = (c,d ), it is necessary and sufficient thata = c and b = d.

Proof: The sufficiency part is clear. To prove necessity, suppose that (a,b) =(c,d ). From the definition of ordered pairs, it follows that { c} ∈ ( a,b ) and{c,d} ∈ (a,b); that is, (i) {c} = {a} or (ii) {c} = {a,b}, and (iii) {c,d} = {a} or(iv) { c,d } = {a,b}.

Equality (ii) holds if a = b = c. Equalities (iii) and (iv) are then equivalentand it follows that c = d = a. Hence, we obtain a = c = b = d , in which case thetheorem holds. Similarly, one can check that the theorem holds for case (iii). Itremains to show that the theorem holds for cases (i) and (iv). We then have c = aand either c = b or d = b . If c = b , then (ii) holds and this case has already beenconsidered. If d = b, then a = c and b = d, which proves the theorem. �

The Cartesian product of two sets X and Y is defined to be the set of all orderedpairs (x,y) such that x ∈ X and y ∈ Y. This product is denoted by X × Y . If X =or Y = , then obviously X × Y = . Certain properties of Cartesian products aresimilar to the properties of multiplication of numbers. For example, we have thefollowing results:

Proposition 2.2.8 [Distributive Laws]. Let X1, X2 , and Y be sets. Then

(1) (X1 ∪ X2 ) × Y = (X1 × Y) ∪ (X2 × Y),

(2) Y × (X1 ∪ X2 ) = (Y × X1) ∪ (Y × X2 ),

(3) (X1 ∩ X2) × Y = (X 1 × Y) ∩ (X2 × Y ),

(4) Y × (X1 ∩ X2 ) = (Y × X1) ∩ (Y × X2 ),

(5) (X1 – X2 ) × Y = ( X1 × Y ) – ( X2 × Y),

(6) Y × (X1 – X2) = ( Y × X1 ) – ( Y × X2).

Proof: We prove only the first equation. For an ordered pair (x,y), (x,y) ∈(X1 ∪ X2) × Y iff x ∈ X1 ∪ X2 and y ∈ Y, iff either x ∈ X 1 or x ∈ X2 and y ∈ Y,

Page 34: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 23

iff either x ∈ X1 and y ∈ Y or x ∈ X 2 and y ∈ Y, iff either ( x ,y) ∈ X 1 × Y or(x , y ) ∈ X 2 × Y, iff ( x,y ) ∈ (X1 × Y ) ∪ (X2 × Y). �

A subset f ⊂ X × Y is called a function or mapping from X into Y if for anyx ∈ X and any y1 and y2 ∈ Y, (x ,y1), (x,y 2) ∈ f implies that y 1 = y 2 = y. In thiscase, the element y is denoted f(x ). The function f is written f : X → Y. Wheneach x ∈ X belongs to a pair in f , the function f is defined on X. Otherwise, f iscalled a partial function from X to Y.

Theorem 2.2.4. If f : X → Y is a function, then f – 1 = {( x,y ) : ( y,x ) ∈ f } is apartial function from Y into X iff f is one-to-one; that is, if (x1 ,y ) and ( x2 ,y ) ∈ fthen x 1 = x2.

Proof: By definition, the subset ƒ –1 is a partial function from Y into X ifffor any y, x1 and x2 , (y,x1 ) and (y,x2) ∈ f –1 implies that x1 = x 2. That is, iff (x1) = y = f ( x2 ), then x1 = x2 . Thus, f is one-to-one. �

2.3. Arithmetic of Cardinal Numbers

Let X and Y be two sets. The notation X ~ Y indicates that the sets areequipollent. The following result says that the equipollence relation is reflexive,symmetric, and transitive.

Theorem 2.3.1. For arbitrary sets A, B, and C the following holds:

(1) Reflexive property: A ~ A.

(2) Symmetric property: A ~ B implies B ~ A.

(3) Transitive property: (A ~ B) and (B ~ C) imply A ~ C.

The proof is straightforward and is omitted.

Example 2.3.1. Since the concept of equipollence is of fundamental importance,we illustrate it by some examples.

(a) The sets of the points of the intervals [0, 1], [0, 1), (0, 1], and (0, 1) areequipollent to each other.

Page 35: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

24 Chapter 2

Figure 2.1. A half-line obtained by central projection.

First, let us prove that (0, 1] ~ (0, 1). We denote the points of the first intervalby x and those of the second by y, and set up the following correspondence:

It is evident that we have already set up a 1–1 correspondence between the twointervals. This proves our assertion.

We can show analogously that [0, 1) ~ (0, 1). From this it follows finally that[0, 1) ~ [0, 1].

(b) A half-line and an entire line are equipollent to an interval.A half-line can be obtained by central projection from an interval erected at

right angles to it and open above (Fig. 2.1). A full line can be obtained similarlyfrom a bent, open interval (Fig. 2.2).

(c) Two finite sets are equipollent if, and only if, they contain equally manyelements.

(d) An infinite set can be equipollent to one of its proper subsets. This isshown by the equipollence of the sets {1,2,3, . . . } and {2, 4, 6, . . . }. Infinite sets

Figure 2.2. A full line obtained from a bent open interval.

Page 36: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 25

thus exhibit in this respect an entirely different behavior from that of finite sets[see example (c)]. This property can therefore be used to distinguish finite andinfinite sets independently of any enumeration.

(e) The set of all real functions defined on the interval [0, 1] is neither denu-merable nor equipollent to the continuum.

The proof of this fact is obtained by a procedure which is again essentiallythe second diagonal method. It is clear not only that there are infinitely manydistinct functions on [0, 1] but also that there exist uncountably many. For, at thepoint x = 0 alone, the functions can already assume the uncountably many valuesbetween 0 and 1. Thus, there remains to be proved only that the set of functionsis not equipollent to the continuum.

Suppose that the set of functions were equipollent to the continuum. Then itwould be possible to make the function f (x) and the points z of [0, 1] correspondin a 1–1 manner. Denote by fz (x) the function thus assigned to the point z. Now,construct a function g(z) defined on the interval 0 ≤ z ≤ 1 with the property that,at every point z, g(z ) ≠ fz (z). Since g ( z) is also a function defined on [0, 1], itmust coincide with an fu(x ); hence, in particular, g( u) = fu (u ). This, however, isexcluded by the definition of g(z). The assumption that the set of our functions isequipollent to the continuum has thus led to a contradiction.

When two sets X and Y are given, precisely one of the following cases canoccur:

(a) X is equipollent to a subset of Y.

(b) X is equipollent to no subsets of Y.

Likewise, exactly one of the following possibilities can take place:

(1) Y is equipollent to a subset of X,

(2) Y is equipollent to no subsets of X.

There are four combinations of these two pairs of cases, vis., (a)(1), (a)(2),(b)(1), (b)(2). In the two middle cases X < Y and Y < X . Case (b)(2) meansthat X and Y are not comparable. We will show that this case never occurs. Case(a)(1) is discussed next.

Theorem 2.3.2 [Bernstein’s Equipollence Theorem]. If each of two sets X andY is equipollent to a subset of the other, then X ~ Y.

Proof: Assume that f : X → Y and g : Y → X are both 1–1 functions. LetA0 = X – g (Y ), B0 = Y – f (X ), and define inductively

Page 37: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

26 Chapter 2

where = {0,1,2,. . . }. Then by induction on n we have

(2.24)

If A n ∩ Am = , then B n+ 1 ∩ B m +1 = since ƒ is 1–1 and if B n ∩ Bm = , thenAn +1 ∩ Am+1 = since g is 1–1. So, since A 0 ∩ An = and B0 ∩ Bn = , byinduction, for each n ≠ 0, Eq. (2.24) follows. Now, define A = An andB = Bn and define a 1–1 function h from A onto B by

if z ∈ Am and m is evenif z ∈ Am and m is odd

(2.25)

Then if t ∈ Bm and m is even, h –1 (t) = g (t ), and if m is odd then h – 1( t ) = ƒ – 1 (t).So, h is from A onto B.

In addition, ƒ is 1–1 onto between X – A and Y – B since if z ∈ X – A, thenƒ(z) ∉ B (since ƒ (z) ∈ Bm implies that m ≠ 0 and z ∈ A m– 1 ); similarly, if t ∈ Y – B,then t = ƒ(z) for some z ∈ X (otherwise t ∈ B 0 ), and z ∈ A implies t ∈ B. Now,we extend h as follows:

(2.26)

Then h is 1–1 from X onto Y, which establishes the equipollence between X andY . �

We know from Section 2.1 that to each set X a cardinality (or cardinal number)is assigned. Corollary 2.1.1 says that besides the finite cardinal numbers, thenumber ℵ 0 , and the continuum c, there exist infinitely many other cardinal numbers.In the sequel, we use p(X) to indicate the power set of the set X.

Theorem 2.3.3. Let A be an arbitrary set. Then no two of the sets

(2.27)

are equipollent.

Proof: Let p κ be the κ th set in the sequence (2.27) and suppose that thereexist κ and ι such that κ > ι and p κ is equipollent to a subset of p ι . The set pκ – 1

is clearly equipollent to a subset of pκ , namely to the subset of singletons {x},where x ∈ p κ –1 . Thus, the set pκ –1 is equipollent to a subset of p ι . Repeating thisargument, we conclude that each of the sets p κ ,p κ –1 , . . . , p ι +1 is equipollent tosome subset of pι , but this contradicts Corollary 2.1.1 and Theorem 2.3.2 becausepι + 1 = p(pι ). �

Page 38: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 27

Theorem 2.3.4. Let the family A have the property that for every X ∈ A thereexists a set Y ∈ A which is not equipollent to any subset of X. Then the union

∪ X ∈ A X is not equipollent to any X ∈ A nor to any subset of X ∈ A.

Proof: Assume that there exists an X ∈ A such that Itfollows that there exists a 1–1 function ƒ such that By assumptionof the theorem there is a set Y ∈ A which is not equipollent to any subset of X. Since

we have that is, ƒ(Y ) ⊂ X 1 and consequentlyY ~ ƒ(Y ) ⊂ X. The contradiction thus shows that �

Theorems 2.3.3 and 2.3.4 give us some ideas about how many distinct infinitecardinal numbers exist. Starting with the set of nonnegative integers which haspower ℵ 0 , we can construct the sets

(2.28)

no two of which are equipollent by Theorem 2.3.3. In this way we obtain infinitelymany distinct cardinal numbers. Theorem 2.3.4 says the unionwhere for each n ∈ , has a cardinal numberdifferent from each of the sets in sequence (2.28) and from each of their subsets.Again applying Theorem 2.3.3 we obtain the sequence of sets

S , p(S), p (p(S)), p (p(p(S) ) ) , . . . (2.29)

no two of which are equipollent and none of which is equipollent to any of thesets in sequence (2.28). We obtain in this way a new infinite number of distinctcardinalities.

We may still obtain other cardinal numbers by constructing the family B =(S) and a new sequence

B , p(B), p (p(B)), p (p(p(B) ) ) , . . . (2.30)

This procedure continues infinitely. We see that the hierarchy of distinct infinitecardinal numbers is comparably richer than the hierarchy of finite cardinalities,which coincides with

We now begin to define the operations of addition, multiplication, and expo-nentiation for cardinal numbers. Let m and n be cardinal numbers and X and Ytwo disjoint sets such that X = m and Y = n. Then define

m + n = X ∪ Y (2.31)

For the definition to have a meaning, it is necessary to show that the sum m + ndoes not depend on the choice of the sets X and Y. Therefore, let X* and Y* betwo disjoint sets with X* = X and |Y* | = |Y |. Then it is not hard to see thatX* ∪ Y * ~ X ∪ Y .

Page 39: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

28 Chapter 2

Theorem 2.3.5. The addition of cardinal numbers is commutative and associa-tive; that is, for arbitrary cardinal numbers n1 , n2 , and n3 ,

(2.32)

(2.33)

The proof follows from the definition of addition of cardinal numbers.

Theorem 2.3.6. Let mi and ni be cardinal numbers, i = 1, 2, such that m i ≤ n i .Then

Proof: Let Xi and Yi , i = 1, 2, be four pairwise disjoint sets such thatand . Then by hypothesis there exist 1–1 functionsDefine a new function g : by

(2.35)

(2.34)

We then check that g is a one-to-one function from X ∪ X into1 2 Y 1 ∪ Y2 . This givesm 1 + m 2 ≤ n1 + n2 . �

We cannot, however, always infer from m1 < n 1 and m2 ≤ n2 that m 1 + m 2 <n but1 + n n < ℵ 0 and ℵ 0 ≤ ℵ 0 n + ℵ 02 . For example, for every n ∈ we have =ℵ 0 = ℵ 0 + ℵ 0 .

The cardinal number m is the product of n1 and n2 , denoted m = n1 ⋅ n2 , if everyset of power m is equipollent to the Cartesian product A1 × A2 , wherei = 1,2. Thus,

Theorem 2.3.7. The multiplication of cardinal numbers is commutative, associa-tive, and distributive over addition:

(2.36)

(2.37)

(2.38)

Proof: Equation (2.36) is an immediate consequence of the relation

A × B ~ B × A

Equation (2.37) follows from

[A × (B × C)] ~ [(A × B) × C]

Page 40: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 29

Equation (2.38) is shown by the following:

Denote the n-fold product m ⋅ m ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ m by m n . Then m n is the power of the setof all sequences of n-elements (a1 , a2 , . . . ,an ), where a1 , . . . , an are elements of aset A of power m. In other words, A n = A

n . Generalizing this idea, let m, n,

and p be cardinal numbers. Then

(read as m equals n raised to the p th power) if every set of power m is equipollent

m = n p (2.39)

to the set AB , where A = n, B = p, and AB = {ƒ :ƒ is a function from B into A} .

Theorem 2.3.8. For arbitrary cardinal numbers n, p, and q,

(2.40)

(2.41)

(2.42)

(2.43)

(2.44)

Proof: Suppose that X, Y, and Z are pairwise disjoint sets with X = n , Y = p, and Z = q. Then, showing Eq. (2.40)–(2.44) is equivalent to showing

(2.45)

(2.46)

(2.47)

(2.48)

(2.49)

The proofs of Eqs. (2.48) and (2.49) are straightforward. We give only thearguments of the important formulas Eqs. (2.45)–(2.47).

To prove Eq. (2.45), we associate with every function ƒ ∈ XY ∪ Z the orderedpair of restricted functions (ƒ Y, ƒ Z). Then it is not difficult to show that thiscorrespondence is a bijection from the set XY ∪ Z onto the set XY × XZ .

For the proof of Eq. (2.46), notice that if ƒ ∈ (X × Y )Z , then ƒ (z) is, for everyz ∈ Z, an ordered pair (g(z), h(z)), where g(z) ∈ X and h (z) ∈ Y. Then g ∈ X Z

Page 41: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

3 0 Chapter 2

and h ∈ Y Z . It is easy to show that this correspondence of the function ƒ to thepair (g, h) determines a l–l mapping from the set (X × Y )Z onto the set XZ × Y Z .

Finally, let us prove Eq. (2.47). Let ƒ ∈ X Y ∪ Z ; hence ƒ is a function oftwo variables y and z, where y ranges through the set Y and z through the setZ and where ƒ takes values in X. For each fixed z, the function gz defined bygz (y ) = ƒ(y,z) is a function from Y into Y; i.e., gz ∈ X Y . The function F definedby F(z) = g z associates with every z ∈ Z an element of the set XY , so F ∈ (X Y)Z.

If ƒ1 and ƒ2 are distinct functions from XY∪ Z , then the corresponding functionsF 1 and F 2 are also distinct. In fact, if ƒ1 (y0, z 0) ≠ ƒ2 (y0 , z 0 ), then the elementsF1 (z 0) and F2 (z0 ) of XY are distinct. Each function F ∈ (X Y ) Z corresponds ina manner described before to some function ƒ ∈ XY ×Z , namely, ƒ(y,z) = g z (y),where gz = F(z). It follows that the correspondence of the function ƒ ∈ XY × Z t othe function F ∈ (X Y ) Z establishes the equipollence set X Y × Z with (X Y )Z , whichproves Eq. (2.47). �

Theorem 2.3.9. If A has the power m, then the power set p( A) has power 2 m; i.e.,

Proof: By definition, 2m is the power of the set {0, 1}A , consisting of allfunctions ƒ whose values are the numbers 0 and 1 and whose domain is the setA. Each such function is uniquely determined by the set Xƒ of those a ∈ A forwhich ƒ(a) = 1. To distinct functions ƒ1 and ƒ2 correspond distinct sets Xƒ1 andXƒ2 . Thus, associating with the function ƒ ∈ {0, 1}A the set Xƒ ⊂ A, we obtain abijection from the set {0, 1}A onto the set p(A). �

Theorem 2.3.10. The relation “≤ ” between cardinal numbers possesses the fol-lowing properties:

m ≤ n and n ≤ p imply m ≤ p (2.50)

m ≤ n implies m + p ≤ n + p (2.51)

m ≤ n implies mp ≤ np (2.52)

m ≤ n implies mp ≤ np (2.53)

m ≤ n implies p m ≤ p n (2.54)

Proof: Equation (2.50) expresses the transitivity of the relation ≤. Equations(2.51)–(2.54) express the monotonicity of addition, multiplication and exponenti-ation with respect to ≤. The proof is straightforward and is omitted here. �

In the arithmetic of natural numbers, the laws converse to Eqs. (2.51)–(2.54)are called the cancellation laws for the relation ≤ with respect to the operations of

Page 42: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 31

addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. These theorems hold in arithmeticprovided that p > 1. In the arithmetic of arbitrary cardinal numbers all of thecancellation laws fail to fold: it suffices to let m = 2, n = 3, and p = ℵ 0 to obtain acounterexample. On the other hand, the cancellation laws with respect to addition,multiplication, and exponentiation hold for the relation <. They follow withoutdifficulty from the law of trichotomy, which now we state without proof.

Theorem 2.3.11. For arbitrary cardinal numbers m and n, either m ≤ n or n ≤ m.

We now study a few properties of the cardinal numbers ℵ 0 a n d c .

(1) c = c + c:In fact, let X and Y be intervals (0,1) and [1,2). Then X = Y = c and

X∪ Y = c + c = (0,2) = c.

(2) For each natural number n, n < ℵ 0 < c :The inequality follows from Theorem 2.1.3.

(3) For each natural number n, n + c = ℵ 0 + c = c:In fact, c ≤ n + c ≤ ℵ 0 + c ≤ c + c = c. So, by property 1 and Bernstein’stheorem, the result follows.

(4) c = c · c :

Proof: Let X be the set of all points in (0,1]. Then X × X = {( x,y) : x,y ∈(0, 1]} has power c · c. The assertion is proved as soon as we show that thesets X and X × X are equipollent.

Let z ∈ (0,1) and (x,y) ∈ X × X . We write the numbers x, y and z bynonterminating decimal fractions. Since the representation of our numbersby means of such decimal fractions is unique, it is necessary to show thatthe set of decimal fraction pairs x, y can be mapped on the set of decimalfractions z. Let the pair of decimal fractions x and y be given. Now we writethe first x-complex, then the first y-complex, then the second x-complex,followed by the second y-complex, etc. Since neither x nor y exhibits onlyzeros from a certain point on, the process can be continued without endingand gives rise to a nonterminating decimal fraction. This decimal fractionshall be made to correspond to the number pair x,y. Every number pair x,ythus determines precisely one z; conversely, every z determines exactly onenumber pair x,y, and, in fact, precisely that pair which gave rise to z. Aone-to-one correspondence between the number pairs x,y and the numbersz is thereby established, and this completes the proof. �

Page 43: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

32

(5) For each natural number n, n ⋅ c = ℵ 0 ⋅ c = c :In fact, from Theorem 2.3.10, we have

Chapter 2

(2.55)

Thus, it follows from Bernstein’s theorem and property 4 thatn ⋅ c= ℵ 0 ⋅ c = c.

(6) For each natural number n, cn = c:By induction and property 4 we obtain the proof.

(7) Under the hypothesis that c = 2ℵ 0, this is the continuum hypothesis. Wehave the following: for each natural number n > 1,

(2.56)

In fact, from Theorem 2.3.10, it follows that

whence property 7 follows by applying Bernstein’s theorem.

2.4. Ordered Sets

Since the elements of sets need by no means be numbers or points on the realnumber line, and even if the elements are numbers, it is not at all necessary forthem to be ordered according to magnitude. The concept of ordered sets will beformulated abstractly as follows:

A set X is called an ordered set if a binary relation, called an order relation anddenoted by ≤, exists with its field X such that

(1) For all x ∈ X, x = x.

(2) For x, y ∈ X, if x ≤ y and y ≤ x, then x = y ; i.e., the relation isantisymmetric.

(3) For x,y,z ∈ X, if x ≤ y and y ≤ z, then x ≤ z ; i.e., the relation is transitive.The ordered set X will be denoted by the ordered pair (X , ≤ ).

The notation x > y means the same as y < x and is read either “y precedes x”or “x succeeds y.” The field of the order relation ≤ is often said to be orderedwithout explicitly mentioning ≤. It is necessary to remember that an ordering is

Page 44: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 33

by no means an intrinsic property of the set. The same set may be ordered bymany different order relations.

Let X be a set ordered by a relation ≤. If x and y are elements of X and eitherx ≤ y or y ≤ x, then we say that the elements x and y are comparable; otherwisethey are incomparable. If Y ⊂ X and any two elements of Y are comparable, thenwe call Y a chain in X; if any two elements of Y are incomparable, then Y is calledan antichain in X. An order relation ≤ of a set X is called a linear order relation ifX ordered by ≤ becomes a chain.

Example 2.4.1.

(1) Every family of sets is ordered by the inclusion relation.

(2) The set of natural numbers is ordered by the relation of divisibility.

(3) The set of natural numbers in the order indicated by {0,2,4, . . . , 1,3,5, . . . }is a linearly ordered set; i.e., first come the even nonnegative integersordered according to increasing magnitude, and then the odd integers.

(4) The set {0, 2, 4, 6, . . . ,7, 5, 3, 1}, as written, is linearly ordered; that is, firstcome the even nonnegative integers ordered according to increasingmagnitude, then the odd integers ordered according to decreasingmagnitude.

The next result is obvious.

Proposition 2.4.1. Let X be an ordered set with ordering ≤. Then every subset ofX is also ordered by ≤. Hence, the subsets of ordered sets can always be regardedas ordered.

Two ordered sets (X, ≤ X ) and (Y, ≤Y ) are equal,

(2.57)

if X = Y and for any x, y ∈ X, x ≤ X y is equivalent to x ≤ Y y . Without confusion,we write X = Y instead. Thus, the sets in Examples 2.4.1(3) and 2.4.1(4) are tobe considered distinct in the sense of ordered sets. Without regard to an order,however, the two sets are identical.

Let (X, ≤ ) be an ordered set and a ∈ X. The element a is called a maximal(respectively, minimal) element in the ordered set X provided that no elementx ∈ X satisfies x > a (respectively, x < a ). The element a is called the maxi-mum (respectively, minimum) element of X provided that for every x ∈ X, x ≤ a(respectively, a ≤ x).

Proposition 2.4.2. An ordered set contains at most one maximum element and atmost one minimum element.

Page 45: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

34

(1) i.e., every ordered set is similar to itself.

(2) implies

(3) If and then

(4) implies X ~ Y.

Chapter 2

Proof: Let a and a* be two maximum elements of a set ordered by an ordering≤. Then a* ≤ a and a ≤ a* , which implies that a = a* . The same argument showsthat an ordered set contains at most one minimum element.

An ordered set, however, need have neither a maximum nor a minimum ele-ment.

An ordered set A is cofinal with its subset B if for every x ∈ A there existsy ∈ B such that x ≤ y. The subset B is a cofinal subset in A. Analogously, we candefine coinitial sets and subsets.

Example 2.4.2. The set of all real numbers is cofinal and coinitial with the set ofall integers.

An ordered set (X, ≤ X ) is similar to an ordered set (Y, ≤ Y ),

(2.58)

if there exists a bijection h : X → Y such that for any x1 , x 2 ∈ X, x1 ≤ X x2 impliesh(x1) ≤ Y h (x 2 ). Without causing confusion, we write X Y instead of Eq. (2.58).The bijection h is called a similarity mapping from the ordered set (X, ≤ X ) ontothe ordered set (Y, ≤Y ) .

The following four fundamental properties result immediately from the defi-nition:

Theorem 2.4.1. If a set X is equipollent to an ordered set (Y , ≤Y ), then X can beordered in such a way that X (Y ,≤ Y ).

Proof: Let h be a bijection from X onto Y. We define an order relation ≤X onX as follows: For any if and only if

Theorem 2.4.2. If two ordered sets are similar, then both possess maximum (min-imum) elements or neither set has such an element.

Proof: Let (X, ≤X ) and (Y, ≤ Y ) be two similar ordered sets with a similaritymapping h : X → Y. If x 0 is a minimum element from X, then for every x ∈ X,

Page 46: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 35

This implies that for everyalso has a minimum element.

The family of all ordered sets is divided, by similarity relation, into pairwisedisjoint groups, each of which contains all sets similar to each other. Two orderedsets (X, ≤ X ) and (Y, ≤Y ) are of the same order type if they are similar. Each ordertype will be denoted by a small Greek letter, and the order type of (X, ≤ X ) willalso be denoted by without confusion.

The order type of the set of natural numbers, ordered according to increasingmagnitude, is denoted by ω. If, on the other hand, these numbers are orderedaccording to decreasing magnitude, then the order type of the set is denoted by*ω. Generally, *µ denotes that order type which results from µ when the order ofsuccession of the elements is reversed; i.e., when a new order relation is derivedfrom the relation < defined for the original set, by setting * < equal to >.

Let ( X, ≤ X ) and (Y , ≤ Y ) be two disjoint ordered sets. An order relation ≤ onthe union X ∪ Y is defined as follows: For any s1 and s 2 ∈ X ∪ Y, if s 1 and s2 ∈ X,we let s1 ≤ s2 if and only if s1 ≤X s 2; if s1 and s2 ∈ Y, we let s1 ≤ s 2 if and onlyif s1 ≤ Y s2 ; if s1 ∈ X and s 2 ∈ Y, then we let s1 ≤ s 2. The order relation ≤ thusdefined on the union is obviously transitive, and it therefore orders X ∪ Y. Theordered sum X + Y of the ordered sets (X, ≤ X ) and (Y, ≤ Y ) is now understood tobe the ordered set (X ∪ Y, ≤ ).

Let µ and γ be two order types and ( X,≤ X ) and (Y , ≤ Y) be two disjointordered sets such that = µ and = γ. The sum of the order types µ and γ isdefined by

(2.59)

It is again easy to see that the sum µ + γ is independent of the choice of theordered sets (X ,≤ X ) and (Y, ≤ Y ).

The addition of order types need not be commutative. For example, if

X= {1, 2, 3, . . . } and Y = {0} (2.60)

then

X + Y = {1, 2, 3, . . . ,0} and Y + X = {0, 1, 2, 3, . . . } (2.61)

so that 1 + ω = ω, but ω + 1 ≠ ω, where 1 is the order type of Y.The associative law of order types µ , γ, and π is valid:

(2.62)

The concept of addition of order types can be defined for arbitrary manyorder types. In fact, let an ordered set (I , ≤ I ) be given, and to each k ∈ I there

Page 47: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

36 Chapter 2

corresponds an ordered set (Xk , ≤ k ), where the sets Xk are pairwise disjoint. Thenthe ordered sum

(2.63)

is ordered in the following manner: If two elements s1 and s2 of belongto the same Xk , then we let s1 ≤ s2 if and only if s 1 ≤k s2 ; if, however, s1 and s2

belong to different Xk’s, say and then we let s1 < s2 if and onlyif k 1 < k 2.

Let µ k be an order type for each k ∈ I and ( Xk , ≤ k ) an ordered set such thatµ k = where {Xk : k ∈ I ) consists of pairwise disjoint sets. The sum of theorder types µk is defined by

(2.64)

It is easy to see once more that this sum is independent of the choice of the orderedsets (Xk , ≤ k ) .

In the previous definition, if µk = µ for each k ∈ I and = γ, then theproduct of the order types µ ⋅ γ will equal the sum thus determined; i.e.,

(2.65)

For γ = 0 we let µ ⋅ γ = 0. The concept of product of order types can also bedefined as follows: Let K and µ be two ordered types of nonempty sets (X, ≤ X )and ( Y, ≤ Y ) such that = K and = µ . Define an ordered set (X × Y, ≤ ) byletting (x1, y1 ) < (x2, y2 ) if and only if x1 < x 2 , or when x1 = x 2 then y l < y 2 .Then the product µ ⋅ K = The order relation defined here is called alexicographical order.

This second definition follows immediately from the first. It is also evidentfrom the second definition that the product of order types is independent of theirparticular set representatives.

For multiplication there is no commutative law either. For if we choose K = ωand µ = 2, where 2 is the order type of { 0, 1 } ordered by 0 < 1, then 2 ⋅ ω = ωand ω ⋅ 2 is the order type of the ordered set

{1, 3, 5, . . . ; 2, 4, 6, . . . } (2.66)

This set is not certainly similar to any ordered set of type w. Hence, 2 ⋅ ω ≠ ω ⋅ 2.We do have, however, for multiplication, as for addition, the associative law,

which is so important for calculation:

(2.67)

Page 48: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 37

In fact, let (X , ≤ X ), (Y, ≤ Y ), and (Z , ≤ Z ) be ordered sets such that = µ ,= γ , and = π . Then, according to the second definition, the order type

( µ · γ) · π is the order type of the ordered set (Z × (Y × X ), ≤ 1 ), where for any(zi ,( yi ,xi )) ∈ Z × (Y × X ), i = 1,2,

(2.68)

if z1 < z2, or z1 = z2 , y1 < y2, or z1 = z2 and y 1 = y2 and x1 < x2 . Likewise,µ · (γ · π) is the order type of the ordered set ((Z × Y ) × X, ≤ 2 ), where for any((zi ,yi), xi ) ∈ ( Z ×Y ) × X, i = 1,2,

(2.69)

if z1 < z2, or z1 = z2 , y1 < y2, or z1 = z2, y1 = y2, x1 < x2 . If we now associate, forthe same elements x, y , and z, the element (z, (y, x)) with the element ((z,y),x),we define a similarity correspondence between (Z × (Y × X) , ≤ 1 ) and (( Z × Y ) ×X, ≤ 2 ). This proves the assertion.

The right distributive law does not hold. Namely,

(2.70)

For example,

and this differs from

(2.71)

(2.72)

The left distributive law, however, is valid; that is,

(2.73)

In fact, let (X, ≤ X ), (Y , ≤ Y ), and (Z, ≤ Z ) be disjoint ordered sets such that= µ, = γ , and = π. Then π · (µ + γ) is the order type of the ordered set

where for any (qi, zi)

(2.74)

Page 49: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

38 Chapter 2

Now it is evident that the same ordered set is obtained with order type π · µ +π · γ . This completes the proof of the statement.

It does not yet follow from the results derived thus far that to every cardinalnumber there corresponds at least one order type µ with µ = where µmeans the cardinality of any of those ordered sets with type µ. In other words, itdoes not follow from the results derived that every set can be ordered. Let bethe set of all order types which belong to a given cardinal number and call thisset the type class belonging to

Theorem 2.4.3. For any cardinal number the type class satisfies

(2.75)

Proof: Let X be a set with cardinality Let µ be any order type in Thenit is always possible to order X so that = µ. The set of all order types of class

is equipollent to the set of all possible orderings of our set X. For each orderrelation < on the set X, let S < = {(x1 , x2 ) ∈ X ² : x1 < x2 }. Then it can be seenthat different order relations <1 and <2 on X correspond to different subsets S< 1

and S< 2 of X². Therefore,

(2.76)

Theorem 2.4.4. For the class of all order types of denumerable sets,

Proof: The previous theorem implies that

(2.77)

It remains to show that ≥ 2 . Let γ = * ω + ω. With any sequence of naturalnumbers

(2.78)

we form the order type

(2.79)

Then distinct sequences (2.78) always give rise to distinct order types (2.79). Infact, let

(2.80)

Page 50: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 3 9

also be a sequence of natural numbers, and with it we form the order type

Suppose that α = β . Then we are to show that the sequences (2.78) and (2.80)coincide. This follows by induction from the following auxiliary consideration:

Let Xi and Yi be distinct ordered sets, i = 1,2. Then the relations

(2.81)

follow from

(a) have no first element, and Xi, i = 1,2, arefinite sets,

(b)

In fact, for the case (a), under a similarity mapping of X1 + Y 1 onto X 2 + Y 2 ,no element of Y2 can correspond to an element of X1 because every element of X1

is preceded by only a finite number of elements in X1 + Y l , whereas every elementof Y2 is preceded by infinitely many elements in X2 + Y 2 . It follows, likewise, thatno element of Y1 can correspond to an element of X2 . Consequently, X1 is mappedon X2 and Y1 is mapped on Y2 . In (b) under a similarity mapping of Yl + X1 ontoY2 + X2 , an element x1 of X1 cannot correspond to an element y2 of Y 2; otherwisethe subset Y1 preceding x1 in Y1 + X1 would have to be mapped on a part ofthe elements of Y2 , which is impossible, because Y1 does not have a last element,whereas does. In like manner we see that no element of Y1 can correspond toan element of X2 . Hence, also in this case, X1 is mapped on X2 and Y1 is mappedon Y2 .

If we now apply (a) to the equal sums α = β , we get

and

so that, by (b),

and hence, by (a),

etc. Thus, by induction it follows that the sequences (2.78) and (2.80) coincide.

Page 51: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

40 Chapter 2

Since the totality of distinct sequences (2.78) gives rise to distinct order types(2.79), and since (2.79) implies that any set with order type (2.79) has cardinality

has at least the power of the set of all sequences (2.78). The

power of these sequences of numbers is

A set A is densely ordered by an order relation < if < is linear and for any twoelements x and y ∈ A there exists an element z ∈ A between x and y. We say alsothat A is dense. In a densely ordered set no element has either a direct successoror a direct predecessor. An ordered set is called unbordered if it is not empty andhas no maximal or minimal elements.

All one-element sets, as well as the empty set, are densely ordered. All otherdensely ordered sets contain infinitely many elements.

Theorem 2.4.5 [G. Cantor]. All unbordered, dense, denumerable sets are similarto one another.

Proof: Let (X , ≤ X ) and (Y , ≤ Y ) be two sets of the kind mentioned in thetheorem. Since they are denumerable, they can be written as sequences

(2.82)

and

(2.83)

We now show that X and Y with their orders ≤X and ≤ Y can be mapped ontoeach other. To this end, let x0 correspond to any element n0 of Y, say n0 = y0 .We then look for the element in Y – {n0} with the smallest index, denoted by n1 ,such that n0 < Y n1 when x0 < X x1 , or n0 Y > n1 when x0 X > x1 . This is possiblebecause Y is unbordered. We associate x1 with n1 .

Now x2 may appear before, after, or between x0 and x1 under ≤ X . In each case,since (Y , ≤ Y ) is unbordered and dense, there is an element n2 with the smallestindex in sequence (2.83) which has the same position relative to n0 and n1 as x2

has relative to x0 and x1.In this way, a mapping h from X into Y is defined. In fact, h is onto. Suppose

that h is not onto; then Let yn be the first element in (2.83) suchthat yn ∈ Y – h (X). Then there are three possibilities:

(1)

(2)

(3) there are i , j < n such that and no other yk , for k < n , isbetween yi and yj .

yn < Y yi , for all i < n .

y n Y > yi , for all i < n.

Page 52: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 41

If (1) is true, and since (X, ≤ X ) is unbordered, it follows that there exists x ∈ Xsuch that x <X h – 1 (yi), i < n. Let x m be the first element in sequence (2.82)such that xm <X h–1 (yi), i < n. Then the definition of h implies that h (xm ) = yn ,contradiction. A similar argument shows that (2) and (3) do not hold. Therefore,h is a similarity mapping from (X, ≤ X ) onto (Y , ≤ Y ) .

The proof of Theorem 2.4.5 yields the following result, the proof of which isleft for the reader.

Theorem 2.4.6. Given any dense set with at least two elements and any linearlyordered denumerable set, there is always a subset of the former which is similarto the latter:

Let (A, ≤ A ) be a linearly ordered set. A pair (X, Y ) is a cut in the ordered setA, if Y = {a ∈ A : x ≤A a , for all x ∈ X } and X = {a ∈ A : y A ≥ a , for all y ∈ Y}.The set X is called the lower section, and Y the upper section, of the cut.

Proposition 2.4.3. Let (X, Y ) be a cut in a linearly ordered set A. Then X ∩ Ycontains at most one element.

Proof: If there are x and y ∈ X ∩ Y , then it must be both x ≤ y and y ≤ x.Thus, x = y.

A set A is continuously ordered if A is linearly ordered and each proper cut(X, Y ) in A (i.e., X ≠ ≠ Y) has a nonempty intersection X ∩ Y. We also say thatA is continuous.

Theorem 2.4.7. Every continuous set (A, ≤ A ) contains a subset which is similarto the set of all real numbers in their natural order.

Proof: According to Theorem 2.4.6, (A, ≤A ) contains a subset Q which issimilar to the set of all rational numbers. The set Q ordered by ≤A has gaps. Inother words, there is at least one proper cut (X, Y ) in (Q, ≤Q), where ≤ Q is therestriction of ≤ A on the set Q, defined by ≤Q = ≤A ∩ Q², such that X ∩ Y = Let

Q = X + Y (2.84)

be a decomposition of Q where the cut (X, Y ) determines a gap in Q Then(A, ≤ A ) contains an element a which succeeds all elements of X while precedingall elements in Y. In fact, let X* be the totality of elements of A which belong to Xor precede an element of X, and let Y* be the totality of elements of A which belongto Y or succeed an element of Y. If (X*, Y*) is a cut with a gap, the set (A , ≤ A)would have a gap, contrary to the assumption that (A, ≤ A ) is continuous. Hence,X* + Y * lacks at least one element a of A , and, according to the construction of

Page 53: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

42 Chapter 2

X * + Y *, this element succeeds X * and precedes Y *, so it also succeeds X andprecedes Y.

Every cut (2.84) thus determines at least one element a of A. For every gap(2.84), we choose one of these elements a(X,Y ) and keep it fixed. Let

is a proper cut in with a gap}

This set is also ordered by ≤A and is similar to the set of all rational numberstogether with their gap elements in the domain of real numbers. In other words,according to Dedekind’s introduction of the real numbers, R * is similar preciselyto the set of all real numbers, which proves the theorem.

Theorem 2.4.8. Let (A, ≤ A ) be an ordered set with the following properties:

(1) ( A, ≤ A ) is unbordered.

(2) (A, ≤ A) is continuous.

(3) (A, ≤ A) contains a denumerable set U such that between every pair ofelements of A there exists at least one element of U.

Then (A, ≤ A) is similar to the naturally ordered set of all real numbers.

Proof: The set U is unbordered, because before and after every element of Uthere are still elements of A, and hence, due to (3), elements of U. Likewise, itfollows from (2) and (3) that U is dense also. Consequently, U is similar to the setof all rational numbers ordered naturally. Every gap in U determines, accordingto the proof of Theorem 2.4.7, at least one element a of A and, because of (3), notmore than one element of A. This, however, implies the assertion. For the set ofall rational numbers can be mapped on U, whereby with every gap in the domainof rational numbers there is associated precisely one gap of U and, consequently,precisely one element of A. We have thus obtained a similarity mapping of the setof all real numbers on the set A.

2.5. Well-Ordered Sets

An ordered set ( X, ≤ X ) is well-ordered if it is linearly ordered and everynonempty subset of X contains a first element with respect to the relation ≤X .

Page 54: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 43

Example 2.5.1. Every finite linearly ordered set is well-ordered and so is the set= {0,1,2,3,...}. The set {...,3,2,1,0} is not well-ordered because it does

not have a first element. The set of all real numbers in the interval [0,1], in theirnatural order, is not well-ordered because the subset (0, 1] does not have a firstelement.

The following two theorems are simple consequences of the definition.

Theorem 2.5.1. In every well-ordered set there exists a first element. Everyelement except the last element (if such exists) has a direct successor.

Theorem 2.5.2. No subset of a well-ordered set is of type* ω.

Theorem 2.5.3. If a linearly ordered set A is not well-ordered, it contains a subsetof type * ω.

Proof: Let P be a nonempty subset of A which contains no first element. Let

(2.85)

We have for every x ∈ P. Let p 0 be any element in P. We define byinduction a sequence by letting Sincep n < pn –1 , for n > 1, this sequence is of type *ω.

Theorems 2.5.2 and 2.5.3 imply the next results.

Theorem 2.5.4. In order that a linearly ordered set be well-ordered, it is necessaryand sufficient that it contain no subset of type * ω.

Theorem 2.5.5 [Principle of transfinite induction]. If a set A is well-ordered,B ⊂ A, and if for every x ∈ A the set B satisfies the condition

(2.86)

then B = A.

Proof: Suppose that Then there exists a first element in A – B.This means that if y < x, then y ∈ B. This shows that {y ∈ A : y < x } ⊂ B. Nowit follows from (2.86) that x ∈ B, which contradicts the hypothesis that x ∉ B.

Let ( A, ≤ ) be a linearly ordered set. A function f : A → A is an increasingfunction if f satisfies the condition

(2.87)

Page 55: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

44 Chapter 2

Theorem 2.5.6. If a function f : A → A is increasing, where (A, ≤ A) is a well-ordered set, then for every x ∈ A we have x ≤ A f (x ) .

Proof: Let Wenow show that x ∈ B. In fact, let y ∈ O (x); that is, y < A x. By (2.87) it follows that

Since y ∈ B, we have y ≤ A f (y) and thus y <A f (x ). This means thatthe element f (x) occurs after every element y of O(x ), that is, f (x ) ∈ A – O ( x ).Since x is the first element of A – O(x ), we have x ≤ A f (x ) and finally x ∈ B.Hence, from Theorem 2.5.4 the set B equals A.

Corollary 2.5.1. If the well-ordered sets A and B are similar, then there existsonly one similarity mapping from A onto B.

Proof: Suppose that the sets A and B are well ordered by ≤A and ≤ B and thatthere exist two functions f and g establishing similarity from A onto B.

The function is clearly increasing in A. By Theorem 2.5.5 we thushave for every x ∈ A. Hence, g (x ) ≤ B f (x ). Consequently,

instead of By the same argument f (x ) ≤ B g(x ). This implies

Corollary 2.5.2. No well-ordered set is similar to any of its initial segments.

Proof: Let x ∈ A, where ( A, ≤ A ) is a well-ordered set. The initial segmentis the set defined by

(2.88)

Suppose that A and are similar. Then the function f establishing thesimilarity from A onto would be increasing and would satisfy f (x ) ∈

that is, f (x) < A x. But this contradicts Theorem 2.5.5.

Theorem 2.5.7. Let A and B be two well-ordered sets. Then,

(i) A and B are similar, or

(ii) A is similar to a segment of B, or

(iii) B is similar to a segment of A.

Page 56: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 45

Proof: Let ≤ A and ≤ B be relations which well-order A and B, respectively,and let

(2.89)

By Corollary 2.5.2, for given x ∈ Z there exists only one segment suchthat Let a function f : A → B be defined by f (x) = y for eachx ∈ A, such that

First we show that either Z = A or Z is a segment of A that is, there exists ana ∈ A such that In fact, let Since is a segmentof the function f also maps onto a segment of B. Hence, x ∈ Z.

Similarly, either f ( Z) = B or else f(Z ) is a segment of B : Toshow this it suffices to observe that

(2.90)

Finally, we observe that f establishes the similarity between Z and f(Z ) .Indeed, we have just shown that x < x' ∈ Z implies that is a segmentof therefore, f (x ) < f (x ).

Therefore, we have one of the following four possibilities:

The first three possibilities correspond to those stated in the theorem. Case (4)is impossible, because then and, thus, by definition of Z, a ∈ Z ;that is, which contradicts the definition of a segment.

Corollary 2.5.3. If A and B are well-ordered, then |A |≤ | B | or | B | ≤ | A | .

By ordinal numbers (or ordinals or ordinalities) we understand the order typesof well-ordered sets. Theorem 2.5.7 implies that we can define a “less than”relation for ordinals. We say that an ordinal α is less than an ordinal β if any setof type α is similar to a segment of a set of type β. This relation will be denotedα < β or β > α. We write α ≤ β instead of α < β or α = β.

Theorem 2.5.8. For any ordinals α and β one and only one of the followingformulas holds:

(2.91)

Page 57: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

46

This theorem is a direct consequence of Theorem 2.5.7.

Theorem 2.5.9. If α, β, and γ are ordinals such that α < β and β < γ, thenα < γ.

Proof: Let A, B, and C be well-ordered sets of types α, β, γ, respectively.By assumption, A is similar to a segment of B and B is similar to a segment of C.Thus, A is similar to a segment of C.

The following formulas can be proved without difficulty:

Theorem 2.5.10. If the well-ordered sets A and B are of types α and β and if A issimilar to a subset of B, then α ≤ β.

Proof: Let h : A → B be a mapping such that h establishes the similaritybetween A and h(A). If the theorem were not true, then we would have β < α andthen B would be similar to a segment of h(A). This contradicts Theorem 2.5.5.

Theorem 2.5.11. The set W (α) consisting of all ordinals less than α is well-ordered by the relation ≤. Moreover, the type of W (α ) is α.

Proof: Let A be a well-ordered set of type α. Associating the type of thesegment O(a) with the element a ∈ A, we obtain a one-to-one mapping of A ontoW (α). It is easily seen that the following conditions are equivalent:

(1) a1 precedes a2 or a 1 = a 2 .

(2) O(a1) is a segment of O(a2 ) or O (a1 ) = O (a2).

(3) The type of O(a1 ) is not greater than the type of O(a2 ).

This shows that the relation ≤ indeed orders W (α) in type α.

Theorem 2.5.12. Every nonempty set of ordinals has a first element under therelation ≤.

Proof: Let A be a nonempty set of ordinals and α ∈ A. If α is not the smallestordinal of A, then A ∩ W ( α) ≠ Then in the set A ∩ W (α) there exists a smallestnumber β because W(α ) is well-ordered. At the same time, β is the smallestordinal in A.

Chapter 2

Page 58: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 47

An ordinal number is a limit ordinal if it has no direct predecessor. All ordertypes of finite well-ordered sets are denoted by the corresponding natural numbers.For example, {0} = 1, {0,1} = 2, {0,1,2,} = 3,.... Then the order type 0 of theempty set is a limit ordinal.

Theorem 2.5.13. Each ordinal can be represented in the form λ + n, where λ is alimit ordinal and n is finite ordinal (natural number).

Proof: Let α be an ordinal and A a set of type α. Every set of the formA – O (a) is a remainder of A. Clearly,

A – O(a 1) ⊂ A – O(a2) if and only if (a1 ≥ a2 ) (2.92)

This implies that there exists no infinite increasing sequence of distinct remainders.So there exists only a finite number of m ∈ such that there exists a remainder ofpower m. If n is the greatest such number and if A – O (a) is a remainder of powern, then the segment O(a) has no last element. Thus O(a) is a limit ordinal λ. Thisimplies that α = λ + n.

Let α be an ordinal number. A transfinite sequence of type α (or an α-sequence)is a function ϕ whose domain is W(α). If the values of ϕ are ordinals, the sequenceis also called a sequence of ordinal numbers. In particular, an α-sequence ϕ o fordinals will be called an increasing sequence if for any µ , γ ∈ W ( α), µ < γalways implies ϕ(µ ) < ϕ (γ); it is a decreasing sequence, if µ < γ invariablyimplies ϕ(µ ) > ϕ ( γ) .

Theorem 2.5.14. Every set of ordinal numbers can be written as an increasingsequence.

This is a consequence of Theorem 2.5.12.

Theorem 2.5.15. Every decreasing sequence of ordinal numbers contains only afinite number of ordinal numbers.

This result follows from Theorem 2.5.12.

Theorem 2.5.16. To every set M of ordinal numbers µ, there is an ordinal numberwhich is greater than every ordinal number µ in M.

Proof: By Theorem 2.5.14, we can assume that M is an increasing sequence.Let M* = { µ + 1 : µ ∈ M} and σ = U{W ( µ + 2) : µ ∈ M}. Then every µ +1 ≤σ; hence, µ < σ, for every µ ∈ M.

Let ϕ be a λ-sequence of ordinals where λ is a limit ordinal. By Theorem2.5.16 there exist ordinals greater than all ordinals ϕ(γ) where γ < λ. The smallest

Page 59: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

48 Chapter 2

such ordinal (see Theorem 2.5.12) is called the limit of the λ-sequence ϕ(γ) forγ < λ and is denoted by lim γ < λ ϕ (γ).

We say that an ordinal λ is cofinal with a limit ordinal α if λ is the limit of anincreasing α-sequence

(2.93)

Theorem 2.5.17. An ordinal λ is cofinal with the limit ordinal α if and only ifW(λ) contains a subset of type α cofinal with W(λ) .

Proof: Let A be a subset of W(λ) cofinal with W(λ ) and such that A = α. Forevery ordinal ξ < α there exists an ordinal ϕ (ξ) in A such that the set {η ∈ A :η < ϕ (ξ)} is of type ξ. The sequence ϕ(ξ) is clearly increasing and ϕ (ξ) < λ forξ < α because ϕ (ξ) ∈ A ⊂ W (λ ) . If µ < λ , there exists an ordinal ξ < λ such thatµ < ξ because the sets A and W (λ) are cofinal. Thus, µ < ξ ≤ ϕ(η) for someη < α . This shows that λ is the least ordinal greater than all ordinals ϕ (ξ ), ξ < α ,which proves Eq. (2.93).

Suppose, in turn, that Eq. (2.93) holds. Let A be the set of all values of ϕ.We have η < λ for all η ∈ A and, consequently, since λ is a limit ordinal, thereexists ξ ∈ W(λ) such that η < ξ. Conversely, if ξ ∈ W (λ) then ξ < λ , and by thedefinition of limit there exists ξ′ < α such that ξ < ϕ (ξ′ ). This means that someordinal in A is greater than ξ. Hence, the sets A and W(λ) are cofinal.

We now consider the arithmetic of ordinal numbers.

Theorem 2.5.18. The sum and product of two ordinal numbers are ordinal num-bers.

Theorem 2.5.19. The ordered sum of ordinal numbers, where the index set is alsowell-ordered, is an ordinal number.

These theorems are consequences of the definitions in the previous section.

Theorem 2.5.20 [The First Monotonic Law for Addition].

( α < β ) →( γ + α < γ + β ) (2.94)

Proof: Let B and C be disjoint sets such that B = β and C = γ. Since α < β,B contains a segment A of type α. The ordered sum C + A , which is of type γ + α,is a segment of C + B, which is of type γ + β. Thus, γ + α < γ + β.

Theorem 2.5.21 [The Second Monotonic Law for Addition].

( α ≤ β ) →( α + γ ≤ β + γ) (2.95)

Page 60: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 49

Proof: Let A, B , and C be the sets defined in the proof of Theorem 2.5.20.Then by applying Theorem 2.5.10 to the ordered sums A + C and B + C we obtain(2.95).

Theorem 2.5.22. Let α and β be ordinals. If α ≥ β , then there exists exactly oneordinal γ such that α = β + γ.

Proof: Let A = α , B be a segment of A of type β , and γ = A – B. Clearly,α = β + γ. To prove the uniqueness of γ suppose that β + γ1 = β + γ2 . By (2.94)this implies that γ1 ≥ γ2 and γ2 ≥ γ1 . Thus, γ1 = γ2 by Theorem 2.5.8.

Theorem 2.5.23 [The First Monotonic Law for Multiplication].

(α < β ) → ( γ α < γβ), for γ > 0 (2.96)

Proof: In fact, γβ is the type of the Cartesian product B × C ordered lexico-graphically, where B = β and C = γ. Let A = α , and let A be a segment of B. TheCartesian product A × C ordered lexicographically is a segment of B × C.

Theorem 2.5.24 [The Second Monotonic Law for Multiplication].

(α ≤ β) → (αγ ≤ βγ) (2.97)

Proof: Let A, B , and C be well-ordered sets of type α , β , and γ, respectively,and we assume that A ⊂ B. Thus, C × A ⊂ C × B , which proves Eq. (2.97).

It follows from the identity 1 · ω = 2 · ω that ≤ in Eq. (2.97) cannot be replacedby < .

The operation of ordinal exponentiation is defined by transfinite induction asfollows:

(2.98)

(2.99)

(2.100)

where λ is a limit ordinal. We say that γα is the power of γ, γ is the base, and αthe exponent.

Page 61: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

50 Chapter 2

(2.101)

(2.102)

Theorem 2.5.25. For any ordinals α , β , and γ with γ > 1,

α < β → γα < γβ

This follows from the definition.

Theorem 2.5.26. For any ordinals ξ , η , and γ , we have

γξ + η = γξ · γη

Proof: Given an ordinal ξ , let B denote the set of those ς ∈ W (η + 1) forwhich We shall show that if ς ≤ η, then

W (ς) ⊂ B → ς ∈ B (2.103)

In fact, the following three cases are possible: (i) ς = 0; (ii) ς is not a limit ordinal;(iii) ς is a limit ordinal > 0. In case (i), ς ∈ B , becauseIn case (ii), ς= ς1 + 1 where ς1 ∈ W (ς); thus, by assumption, ς1 ∈ B. Hence.

and therefore

which shows that ς ∈ B. Finally, in case (iii), ξ + ς is a limit ordinal; thus,

(2.104)

Because the sequence γα , α < ξ + ς , is increasing when γ > 1,

(2.105)

Since for α < ς we have α ∈ W (ς ), it follows that α ∈ B; i.e.,Thus,

which implies that ς ∈ B. Hence, implication (2.103) is proved. By induction itfollows that B = W(η + l). Thus, η ∈ B. This proves Eq. (2.102).

Theorem 2.5.27. For any ordinals ξ, η , and γ,

( γξ )η = γξη (2.106)

Page 62: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 51

which shows that ς ∈ B. Finally, if ς is a limit ordinal > 0, then

we have ς ∈ B. Hence Eq. (2.106) is proved.

Proof: This argument is analogous to that of the previous theorem. Let Bdenote the set of those ς ∈ W ( ς

that implication (2.103) holds. As before we consider cases (i)–(iii). In case (i),ς ∈ B , because (γξ)0 = 1 = γ 0 = γξ ·0 . In case (ii) we have ς = ς1 + 1, where ς1

satisfies the condition that (γξ)ς1 = γξς1 . This formula in turn implies

η + 1) for which (γξ) = γ ξη . It suffices to show

Theorem 2.5.28. For any given ordinal γ > 1, every ordinal number α can beuniquely represented in the form

where n is a natural number, and ηi and βi , i = 1, 2, … , n, are ordinals such thatη1 > η2 > … > ηn , and 0 ≤ β i < γ, for i = 1, 2 , … ,n.

Proof: By transfinite induction it can be shown that for any ordinal α,

We now let ς be the smallest ordinal such that α < γς . If ς were a limit ordinal,then and γλ ≤ α for λ < ς , which implies γς ≤ α. This contradictsthe definition of ς. Thus, ς = η1 + 1, where

Notice that there exists an ordinal pair (β1 , σ1 ) ∈ W(γ ) ×W(γη1) such that O ((β1, σ1)) = α, w h e r e{β1 } × O (σ1). Therefore,

where β1 < γ and σ1 < γη1 . For the same reason, there exist ordinals η2 < η1 ,β2 < γ, and σ2 < γη2 such that

Page 63: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

52 Chapter 2

{η1, η2 , . . .}This procedure must stop within a finite steps because, otherwise,would be a sequence of type * ω of ordinals numbers, and this contradicts Theorem2.5.12. Therefore, there exists a natural number n such that

with the property thatNow we show the uniqueness of the expression. If

η1 = ξ 1, β1 = θ 1, andwhere n, andj = 1 ,2 , . . . , p. By the definition of η1 and ξ1, we must have

Repeating this procedure, we have n = p, ηk = ξ k, and βk = θk for k ≤ n.

Well-ordered sets owe their importance mainly to the fact that for each set thereexists a relation which well-orders the set. This theorem is also of the greatestimportance for the theory of cardinal numbers because it shows that all cardinalnumbers are comparable with each other.

Theorem 2.5.29 [Well-Ordering Theorem]. Every set can be well-ordered.

Proof: Let f be a function defined on p (A) – where A is a nonempty set,such that for each nonempty subset B ⊂ A, f (B) ∈ B. We can extend this functionto the whole power set p (A) by letting = p, where p is any fixed elementwhich does not belong to A.

Now let C denote the set of all relations R ⊂ A × A well-ordering their field.Then there exists a set of all ordinals β, where β = the order type of some R ∈ C.Let α be the smallest ordinal greater than every ordinal β in this set.

We now define a transfinite sequence of type α by transfinite induction suchthat

(2.107)

(2.108)

for each Iffor all ξ < α we had then there would exist a transfinite sequence of typeα with distinct values belonging to A. This implies that there exists a relation onA well-ordering a subset of A into type α. But this contradicts the definition of α.Therefore, there exists a smallest ordinal β such that ϕβ = p. This implies that

thus, A is the set of all terms of a transfinite sequence of typeβ whose terms are all distinct. Consequently, there exists a relation well-orderingA into type β.

Page 64: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 53

Theorem 2.5.30. If A and B are two arbitrary sets, precisely one of the followingholds:

i.e., any two cardinal numbers are comparable with each other.

The proof follows from the well-ordering theorem and Theorem 2.5.8.By Theorem 2.5.30, every set of cardinal numbers can be ordered according

to the increasing magnitude of its elements. This ordered set will prove to beactually well-ordered. For this and similar considerations concerning cardinalnumbers, it is practical to represent the cardinal numbers by means of ordinalnumbers. According to the well-ordering theorem, every cardinal number can berepresented by a well-ordered set; briefly, every cardinal number can be representedby an ordinal number. The totality of ordinal numbers which represents the samecardinal number ℵ is designated the number class Q(ℵ ), where Q (ℵ ) contains asmallest ordinal, which is called the initial number of Q(ℵ ) or the initial numberbelonging to ℵ.

Theorem 2.5.31. Every transfinite initial number is a limit number.

Proof: If some transfinite initial number were not a limit number, it would beimmediately preceded by an ordinal number γ, and the initial number would beγ + 1. But then γ and γ + 1 would have the same cardinal number; i.e., γ + 1would not be the smallest ordinal number in its number class, contradiction.

Theorem 2.5.32. Every set of cardinal numbers, ordered according to increasingmagnitude, is well-ordered. There exists a cardinal number which is greater thanevery cardinal number in the set.

Proof: For the first part of the assertion we have to show that every nonemptysubset of cardinal numbers contains a smallest cardinal number. This is, however,clear if every cardinal number is represented by the initial number belonging toit. Among these initial numbers then there is, as in every nonempty set of ordinalnumbers, a smallest one, and the corresponding cardinal number is the smallestcardinal number in the set.

The second part of the assertion follows from Theorems 2.5.11 and 2.1.4.

If the family of all transfinite cardinal numbers is ordered according to increas-ing magnitude, then we denote the smallest transfinite cardinal number by ℵ 0, thenext by ℵ 1 , etc. In general, every transfinite cardinal number receives as index

Page 65: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

54 Chapter 2

the ordinal number of the set of transfinite cardinal numbers which precede thecardinal number in question. Therefore,

(2.109)

The initial number which belongs to ℵ µ is denoted by ωµ . Then ω0 is the smallesttransfinite limit number and is therefore the same as the ω introduced before.

Theorem 2.5.33. For any ordinal µ > 0,

(2.110)

Proof: The set W (ωµ) has order type ωµ and is therefore a set of powerConsequently, the cardinal number is the power of the setWe now show that this set has at most the cardinal number

Let Then by Theorem 2.5.28 and adding whatevernecessary terms with coefficient 0, we can represent ξ and η uniquely in the form

(2.111)

where γ1 > γ2 > . . . > γk and for all i ≤ k either m i > 0 or n i > 0. Define apolynomial

Since only a finite number of nonzero terms appear, it follows that

and the proof of Theorem 2.5.28 implies that

Consequently,

We therefore certainly obtain all number pairs ξ, η by solving the equationBut for every this equation has only

a finite number of solutions. Therefore, the cardinal number of the set of all solu-tions for all is at most We now need only show that

Theorem 2.5.28 implies that for any ordinal α,

(2.112)

Page 66: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 55

where σ < ω. Therefore, when α is a limit number, we have α = ωβ. This impliesthat ωµ = ωβ for some fixed ordinal β. Therefore,

Thus, �

Theorem 2.5.34. For ; in particular,

Proof: and�

Theorem 2.5.35. For

Proof: Without loss of generality, let . Then

Theorem 2.5.36. (1) , and (2) if µ is a limit number,

Proof: We have invariably

If µ is a limit number, then, on the one hand,

and, on the other hand, for every γ < µ we also have γ + 1 < µ, so; i.e., the sum is greater than every cardinal number which is less than

. These two results then yield the assertion in this case, too. �

Page 67: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

56 Chapter 2

Theorem 2.5.37. For ordinals γ and µ with µ ≤ γ + 1,

Proof: According to Theorem 2.3.9 and the hypothesis

and hence

Theorem 2.5.38. The number class Q ordered according to increasing mag-nitude of its elements, has order type ωµ +1 and therefore has cardinality

Proof: The elements of Q are the ordinal numbers γ with

(2.113)

Hence, in the sense of addition of well-ordered sets, we have

This implies that

From this we have But Theorem 2.5.35 implies that we cannothave

Let be the order type of Q Then Eq. (2.113) implies thatand implies that . Hence, �

2.6. Crises of Naive Set Theory

Careful readers may have already found some inconsistencies in the develop-ment of naive set theory. These contradictions are connected with the followingconcepts.

Page 68: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Naive Set Theory 57

(a) The set of all cardinal numbers. For example, let A be the set of all cardinalnumbers. Then Theorem 2.5.16 implies that there exists a cardinal number

greater than all numbers in A. That is, This contradicts Theorem2.5.33.

(b) The set of all ordinal numbers. For example, Theorem 2.5.16 implies thatto every set of ordinal numbers there exists a still greater ordinal number.Accordingly, the concept of “set of all ordinal numbers” is a meaninglessconcept. This is the so-called Burali-Forti paradox.

(c) The set of all sets which do not contain themselves as elements(Zermelo–Russell paradox or simply Russell’s paradox). For this set X, asfor every set, only the following two cases are conceivable: either Xcontains itself as an element, or it does not. The first case cannot occurbecause otherwise X would have an element, namely, X, which containeditself as an element. The second assumption, however, also leads to acontradiction. For in this case, X would be a set which did not containitself as an element, and for this very reason X would be contained in thetotality of all such sets, i.e., in X.

(d) The set of all sets. For if X is such a set, it would have to contain the set ofall its subsets. The set of all subsets of X, however, has a greater powerthan X , according to Theorem 2.1.4.

From the list of paradoxes above, we can see that two concepts, or words,appear in each of them. One of the two words is “set” and the other is “all.” Theconcept “set” was introduced by Cantor as “a collection into a whole of definite,well-distinguished objects.” The meaning of this definition might be too wide forus to avoid these paradoxes. The concept “all” actually was never introduced inthe context, and the meaning of “all” we have been using contradicts some resultswe get in set theory. Our analysis on the appearance of the paradoxes shows thatif we can narrow the meaning of the concept of “set” and if we can avoid using theword “all,” we may be in good shape to establish a set theory without contradictorypropositions. In the next chapter, we will try along this line to study properties ofabstract sets and to set up a new theory of sets, called the axiomatic set theory onZFC.

For further study of naive set theory, the reader is advised to consult(Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976).

Page 69: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 3

Axiomatic Set Theory

This chapter investigates how naive set theory can be rebuilt so that the resultingset theory will not contain the paradoxes in Section 2.6. Axiomatic set theory,based on the ZFC axiom system (i.e., Zermelo–Fränkel axioms and the Axiom ofChoice) is introduced.

In Section 3.1 we introduce the language of axiomatic set theory, list theaxioms of ZFC, and discuss some related philosophical problems. Section 3.2sketches the development of the ordinal and cardinal number systems, based onthe axioms of ZFC, excluding regularity. Section 3.3 covers some special topicsin combinatorial set theory. Martin’s axiom (MA) is introduced to study somerelated problems. Section 3.4 develops the class WF of all well-founded sets andshows that all mathematics takes place within WF.

3.1. Some Philosophical Issues

Most scientific workers have little need for a precise codification of the conceptsof set theory. It is generally understood that some principles are correct and someare questionable. In this chapter, we establish a set theory which makes moreprecise the basic principles of naive set theory. To accomplish this, we build thetheory on a few axioms.

The idea of establishing a theory upon a set of axioms harks back to thetime of Euclid. Usually, in science, axioms, principles, and laws are stated in aninformal language, i.e., a language with many grammatical inconsistencies, suchas English. A major disadvantage of using an informal language is the possiblemisunderstanding of a sentence or word. For example, in the past few decades,the word “system” has been understood in many different ways (see Chapter 4for a detailed discussion). In order to establish a rigorous set theory, we state ouraxioms in a formal, or artificial, language, called first-order predicate calculus.The characteristic of a formal language is that there are precise rules of formationfor linguistic objects.

59

Page 70: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

60 Chapter 3

The basic symbols of our formal language include , =, and vj

for each natural number j. Their grammatical meanings are as follows:

• means “and.”

• ¬ means “not.”

• ∃ means “there exists.”

• ∈ means membership.

• = means equality.

• vj , for each natural number j, are variables.

The parentheses are used for phrasing. An expression is any finite sequence of basicsymbols. The intuitive interpretation of the symbols indicates which expressionsare meaningful; these are called formulas. Precisely, a formula is defined to beany expression constructed by the rules:

(a) are formulas for any natural numbers i, j.

(b) If φ and ψ are formulas, so are for any i.To save ourselves the work of always writing long expressions, we will usethe following abbreviations.

(c)

(d)

(e)

(f)

(g)

(h)

Other letters from English, Greek, and Hebrew are used for variables. In thischapter, we follow standard mathematical usage of writing expressions mostly inEnglish, augmented by logical symbols when this seems necessary. For example,we may say “there are sets x, y, z such that ,” rather than

(3.1)

A subformula of a formula φ is a constructive sequence of symbols of φ whichforms a formula. The scope of an occurrence of a quantifier ∃ vi is the uniquesubformula beginning with that ∃ vi. For example, the scope of the quantifier ∃ v2

in formula (3.1) is An occurrence of a variable in a

Page 71: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 61

formula is called bound if and only if it lies in the scope of a quantifier acting onthat variable, otherwise it is called free. For example, in formula (3.2),

(3.2)

the first occurrence of v1 is free, but the second is bound, whereas v0 is bound atits occurrences and v2 is free at its occurrence.

Note that since ∀ vi is an abbreviation for ¬∃ vi ¬ , it also binds its variablevi , whereas the abbreviations , →, ↔ are defined in terms of other propositionalconnections and do not bind variables.

We often write a formula as φ(x 1 , . . ., xn ) to emphasize its dependence on thevariables x1, . . , xn . Then, if y1 , . . . ,y n are different variables, we use φ(y1, . . . ,y n)to indicate the formula resulting from substituting a yi for each occurrence ofthe free variable xi . Such a substitution is called free, or legitimate, if no freeoccurrence of an xi is in the scope of a quantifier ∃ yi. The idea is that the formulaφ( y 1 , . . . , yn ) says about variables y1 , . . . , y n what the formula φ(x1 , . . . , x n ) saidabout x1 , . . . , xn, but this will not be the case if the substitution is not free and someyi gets bound by a quantifier of φ. In general, we will always assume that oursubstitutions are legitimate. The use of the notation φ(x1 , . . . , x n) does not implythat each xi actually occurs free in φ(x1 , . . . , xn ); also, φ( x1 , . . .,x n ) may haveother free variables, which in this discussion we are not emphasizing.

A sentence is a formula with no free variables. Intuitively, a sentence states anassertion which is either true or false. If S is a set of sentences and φ is a sentence,then S φ means that φ is provable from S by a purely logical argument that mayquote sentences in S as axioms but may not refer to any intended “meaning” of ∈ .

If S φ, where S is the empty set of sentences, we write φ and say that φis logically valid. If (φ ↔ ψ), we say that φ and ψ are logically equivalent.

Let φ be a formula; a universal closure of φ is a sentence obtained by univer-sally quantifying all free variables of φ. For example, let φ be the formula

(3.3)

Then ∀ x ∀ y φ and ∀ y∀ x φ are universal closures of φ. All universal closures of aformula are logically equivalent. In general, when we assert φ, we mean to assertits universal closure. Formally, if S is a set of sentences and φ is a formula, wedefine S φ to mean that the universal closure of φ is derivable from S .

We call a formula φ logically valid if its universal closure is logically valid;we say two formulas φ and ψ are logically equivalent if φ ↔ ψ is logically valid.

A set S of sentences is consistent, denoted by Con(S), if for no formula φ doesS φ and S φ. We can see easily that for any sentence φ, S φ if and only if

is inconsistent.In order to use formal deduction, we need the following important facts: (a) If

S φ, then there exists a finite S0 ⊂ S such that S 0 φ. (b) If S is inconsistent,there is a finite S 0 ⊂ S such that S 0 is inconsistent.

Page 72: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

6 2 Chapter 3

As an exercise, we now list all axioms in the ZFC axiom system.

Axiom 1. (Set Existence)

Axiom 2. (Extensionality)

Axiom 3. (Regularity)

Axiom 4. (Comprehension Scheme) For each formula φ with free variablesamong x, z, w1 , . . . , wn ,

Axiom 5. (Pairing)

Axiom 6. (Union)

Axiom 7. (Replacement Scheme) For each formula φ with free variablesamong x, y, A, w1 , . . . , wn ,

where the symbol ∃ ! means “there exists exactly one.”

Axiom 8. (Infinity)

Axiom 9. (Power Set)

Axiom 10. (Choice (Axiom of choice or AC))

∀ A ∃ R(R well orders A)

Page 73: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

63Axiomatic Set Theory

In the following, we write the meanings of the axioms in English.

Axiom 1.

Axiom 2.

Axiom 3.

Axiom 4.

Axiom 5.

Axiom 6.

Axiom 7.

Axiom 8.

Axiom 9.

Axiom 10.

(Set Existence) There exists a set.

(Extensionality) Two sets x and y are identical if they contain thesame elements.

(Regularity) Each nonempty set x has an element y such thatx ∧ y =

(Comprehension Scheme) For each given formula and each set z,there exists a set y such that y = {x ∈ z : (x )}.

(Pairing) For any sets x and y, there exists a set z such that x ∈ zand y ∈ z.

(Union) For any given set of sets there exists a set A whichconsists of all elements belonging to at least one element set in

(Replacement Scheme) For each formula and any set A, if toeach element x ∈ A there corresponds exactly one y satisfying

(x,y), then there exists a set Y consisting of all y satisfying(x,y), for some x ∈ A.

(Infinity) There exists a set x satisfying (1) ∈ x, and (2) for eachy ∈ x there exists a set S(y) ∈ x which contains all elements in yand y itself.

(Power Set) For any set x, there exists a set y, called the power setof the set x and denoted by p(x), such that all subsets of x arecontained in y.

(Choice) Any set can be well-ordered.

An interpretation of the language of set theory is defined by specifying anonempty domain of disclosure, over which the variables are intended to vary,together with a binary relation defined on that domain, which is the interpretationof the membership relation ∈. If is a sentence in the language of set theory,is either true or false under a specified interpretation.

In the intended interpretation, under which the axioms of ZFC are presumedtrue, the symbol x ∈ y is interpreted to mean that x is a member of y. Since wewish to talk only about sets and their elements in our domain of discourse, all

Page 74: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

64 Chapter 3

elements of such a set should be sets also. Repeating this, we can see that thedomain of our discourse consists of those x such that

x is a set, and

We call such an x a hereditary set.If S is a set of sentences, we may show that S is consistent by producing an

interpretation under which all sentences of S are true. Usually, ∈ will still beinterpreted as membership, but the domain of discourse will be some subdomainof the hereditary sets.

The justification for this method of producing consistency proofs is the easydirection of the Gödel completeness theorem, which says that if S holds in someinterpretation, then S is consistent. The reason this theorem is true is that the rulesof formal deduction are set up so that if S then must be true under anyinterpretation which makes all sentences in S true. If we fix an interpretation inwhich S holds, then any sentence that is false in that interpretation is not provablefrom S. Since and cannot both hold in a given interpretation, S cannot proveboth and ; thus S is consistent.

We now conclude this section with a few extremes of mathematical thought.For a more serious discussion, see (Fraenkel et al., 1973; Kleene, 1952; Kreiseland Krivine, 1967).

Platonists believe that the set-theoretic universe has an existence outside thespirit of human beings. From this point of view, the axioms in ZFC are merelycertain obvious facts in the universe, and we might have failed to list some otherobvious but basic facts in the ZFC axiom system. Platonists are still interested inlocating principles of the universe which are not provable from ZFC.

A finitist believes only in finite objects. It is meaningless to consider any sortof concept like that of “whole.” If, say, “human knowledge” does not exist, the setof all rational numbers is not a practical concept; hence, the theory of infinite sets isa piece of meaningless garbage. There is some merit in the finitist’s position, sinceall objects in known physical reality are finite, so infinite sets may be discardedas figments of the mathematician’s imagination. Unfortunately, this point of viewalso discards a big portion of modern mathematics.

The formalist can hedge his bets. The formal development of ZFC makes sensefrom a strictly finitistic point of view: the axioms of ZFC do not say anything, butare merely certain finite sequences of symbols. The assertion ZFC means thatthere is a certain kind of finite sequence of finite sequences of symbols, namely,a formal proof of Even though ZFC contains infinitely many axioms, notionslike ZFC will make sense only when a particular sentence is recognized asan axiom of ZFC. A formalist can thus do mathematics just as a platonist, but if

Page 75: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 65

challenged about the validity of handling infinite objects, he can reply that all heis really doing is juggling finite sequences of symbols.

In this chapter, we will develop ZFC from a platonistic point of view. Thus,to establish that ZFC we simply produce an argument that is true based onthe assumption that ZFC contains true principles.

3.2. Constructions of Ordinal and Cardinal NumberSystems

TheLet z be any set. Axiom 3 (comprehensive scheme) implies that

axiom on set existence says that our domain of discourse is not empty.

{x ∈ z : x ≠ x} (3. 4)

defines the existence of the empty set. By extensionality, such a set is unique.The Comprehension Axiom is intended to formalize the construction of sets

of the form {x : P (x)}, where P(x) denotes a property of x. Since the notionof property is made rigorous via formulas, it is tempting to set forth as axiomsstatements of the form

(3.5)

where is a formula. Unfortunately, such a scheme is inconsistent by the famousZermelo–Russell paradox (Section 2.6): Let be x ≠ x then this axiom gives a ysuch that

(3.6)

whence y ∈ y ↔ y ∉ y. To avoid this contradiction the Comprehension Axiom isgiven as follows: For each formula without y free, the universal closure of thefollowing is an axiom:

We can also prove, not simply to avoid this paradox, that there is no universalset.

Theorem 3.2.1.

Proof: If ∀ x(x ∈ z ), by the Comprehension Axiom we can formwhich would yield a contradiction by the Zermelo–

Russell paradox.

Page 76: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

66

prod(A,B) = {prod(A , y) : y ∈ B }

Chapter 3

We let A ⊂ B abbreviate ∀ x ( x ∈ A → x ∈ B ). So, A ⊂ A and ⊂ A.The example {x : x = x } shows that for a given formula (x ) , there need not

exist a set {x : (x)}. Generally, this collection (or class) may be too big to forma set. The Comprehension Axiom says that if the collection is a subcollection of agiven set, then it is a set. Axioms 4–8 of ZFC say that certain collections do formsets.

By the Pairing Axiom, for given x and y we may let z be any set such thatx ∈ z ∧ y ∈ z; then { v ∈ z : v = x ∨ v = y } is the unique (by extensionality)set whose elements are precisely x and y; we call this set {x,y}. Note that(x,y) = {{ x}, {x,y}} is the ordered pair of x and y.

In the Union Axiom, we think of as a family of sets and postulate theexistence of a set A such that each member Y of is a subset of A. This justifiesour defining the union of the family, denoted by , by

(3.7)

When we let

(3.8)

If then and “should be” the set of all sets, which does not exist.Finally, we let

For any sets A and B, we define the Cartesian product

(3.9)

To justify this definition, we must apply replacement twice. First for any y ∈ B,we have

so by replacement (and comprehension) we can define

Now

so by replacement we may define

Finally, we define A × B = prod'(A,B ).

Page 77: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 67

A relation H is a set all of whose elements are ordered pairs. Let

(3.10)

and

(3.11)

We define H – 1 = {(x,y) : (y,x) ∈ H }, so (H– 1)– 1 = H.A function (or mapping) is a relation ƒ such that

(3.12)

A total ordering (or strict total ordering or linear ordering) is a pair ( A,H) suchthat H totally orders A; that is, A is a set, H is a relation such that

(3.13)

(3.14)

and

(3.15)

where we write xHy for (x,y) ∈ H . Note that our notation does not assumeH ⊂ A × A, so if (A, H) is a total ordering so is (B, H) whenever B ⊂ A.

Whenever H and K are relations and A and B are sets, we say (A, H) (B,K)if there exists a bijection ƒ : A → B such that ∀ x,y ∈ A (xHy ↔ ƒ(x)Kƒ(y)). Thismapping ƒ is called an isomorphism from (A, H) to (B, K).

We say H well-orders A, or (A,H) a well-ordering, if (A,H) is a total orderingand every nonempty subset of A has an H-least element; i.e., ∀ B ⊂ A (B ≠ Ø →∃ x ∈ B ∀ y ∈ B (xHy)). If x ∈ A, let pred(A,x,H) = { y ∈ A : yHx}.

Lemma 3.2.1. If (A,H) is a well-ordering, then

(A,H) (pred(A,x,H),H) for each x ∈ A

Proof: If ƒ : A → pred (A,x,H) were an isomorphism, let z be the H -leastelement of {y ∈ A : ƒ(y) ≠ y}. Then for each y ∈ A with yHz,ƒ (y) = y. Since ƒis an isomorphism it follows that ƒ(z ) = z. This contradicts the definition of z.�

Lemma 3.2.2. If (A, H) and (B, K) are isomorphic well-orderings, then the iso-morphism between them is unique.

Page 78: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

68 Chapter 3

Proof: If f and g were different isomorphisms, let z be the H -least y ∈ A suchthat ƒ(y) ≠ g (y). Then a similar contradiction as in the proof of Lemma 3.2.1 willoccur.

Theorem 3.2.2. Let (A,H) and (B,K) be two well-orderings. Then exactly oneof the following holds:

(a) (A,H) (B,K).

(b) ∃ y ∈ B((A,H) (pred(B,y,K),K)).

(c) ∃ x ∈ A ((pred(A,x,R) (B,K)).

Proof: Let

f = { (v,w) : v ∈ A ∧ w ∈ B ∧ (pred(A,v,H),H) (pred (B,w,K ),K)}

Note that f is an isomorphism from some initial segment of A onto some initialsegment of B, and that these segments cannot both be proper.

A set x is transitive if every element of x is a subset of x. Examples oftransitive sets are Ø, {Ø} , {Ø, {Ø}},…. The set {{Ø}} is not transitive. A set xis an ordinal if x is transitive and well-ordered by the relation ∈. More formally,the assertion that x is well-ordered by ∈ means that (x, ∈ x ) is a well-ordering,where ∈ x = {(y,z) ∈ x × x : y ∈ z }. Examples of ordinals are Ø, {Ø} , {Ø, {Ø}}. Ifx = {x}, then x is not ordinal since we have defined orderings to be strict. Withoutcausing confusion, we write x (A, H) for (x, ∈ x ) (A, H) and y ∈ x, pred( x ,y)for pred(x,y, ∈ x ).

Theorem 3.2.3.

(1) If x is an ordinal and y ∈ x, then y is an ordinal and y = pred(x,y).

(2) If x and y are ordinals and x y, then x = y.

(3) If x and y are ordinals, then exactly one of the following is true: x = y,x ∈ y , y∈ x .

(4) If x, y, and z are ordinals, x ∈ y and y ∈ z implies that x ∈ z.

(5) If C is an nonempty set of ordinals, then ∃ x ∈ C ∀ y ∈ C(x ∈ y ∨ x = y ).

Page 79: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 69

Proof: For(3), we use (1), (2), and Theorem 3.2.2 to show that at least oneof the three conditions holds. That no more than one holds follows from the factthat no ordinal can be a member of itself, since x ∈ x would imply that (x, ∈ x ) isnot a strict total ordering (since x ∈ x x). For (5), we note that the conclusion is,by (3), equivalent to ∃ x ∈ C (x ∩ C = Ø). Let x ∈ C be arbitrary. If x ∩ C # Ø,then since x is well-ordered by ∈, there is an ∈ -least element x1 of x ∩ C, and thenx 1 ∩C = Ø

Theorem 3.2.3 implies that the set of all ordinals, if it existed, would be anordinal, and thus cannot exist, because if such an ordinal existed, denoted by η,then Theorem 3.2.3(5) implies that η ∩ { η } = Ø, but the definition of η impliesη ∈ η ∩ { η}, contradiction. This fact takes care of the Burali-Forti paradox (seeSection 2.6 for details).

Lemma 3.2.3. Let A be a set of ordinals and ∀ x ∈ A ∀ y ∈ x(y ∈ A) then A is anordinal.

Theorem 3.2.4. If (A,H) is a well-ordering, then there exists a unique ordinal Csuch that (A,H) C.

Proof: The uniqueness of the ordinal C follows from Theorem 3.2.3(2). toprove existence, let

B = {a ∈ A : ∃ x(x is an ordinal ∧ ( pred(A,a,H),H) x)} (3.16)

Let ƒ be the function with domain B such that for each a ∈ B, f ( a) = the uniqueordinal x such that (pred(A, a, H), H) x, and let C = R (ƒ). Now, we check thatC is an ordinal (from Lemma 3.2.3), that ƒ is an isomorphism from ( B, H) onto C,and that either B = A (in which case we are done), or B = pred( A, b, H) for someb ∈ A (in which case b ∈ B, and hence a contradiction).

Theorem 3.2.4 implies that ordinals can be used as representatives of theorder types of well-ordered sets. Thus, we have the following: If (A, H) is awell-ordering, the type (A,H) is defined to be the unique ordinal C such that(A, H) C. From now on we use Greek letters α, β, γ ,… to indicate ordinals.We may thus say, e.g., ∀ α … instead of ∀ x (x is an ordinal → … ). Since ∈ ordersthe ordinals, we write α < β for α ∈ β and use α ≥ β to indicate β ∈ α ∨ β = α.

Lemma 3.2.4.

(1) ∀ α β (, α ≤ β → α ⊂ β) .

(2) If X is a set of ordinals, then ∪ X is the least ordinal ≥ all elements in X,and, if X ≠ Ø ∩ X is the least ordinal in X.

Page 80: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

70 Chapter 3

We use natural numbers to count finite sets. The Axiom of Choice tells thatevery set can be counted by an ordinal. Therefore, we use natural numbers toindicate finite ordinals.

Let α be an arbitrary ordinal. The successor S( α) of the ordinal is defined byS (α ) =α ∪ {α}. Then S(α ) is also an ordinal, and we have

0 = Ø 1 = S (Ø) 2 = S (2 ) 3 = S (2), . . . (3.17)

Intuitively, natural numbers are those ordinals obtained by applying S to Ø a finite number of times.

An ordinal α is a successor ordinal (or isolated ordinal) if ∃ β( α = S(β)). It isa limit ordinal if α ≠ 0 and α is not a successor ordinal. For example, let ω be theset of all natural numbers and 0. Then ω is an ordinal and all smaller ordinals aresuccessor ordinals or 0. So ω is a limit ordinal, since if not it would be a naturalnumber, and hence ω is the least limit ordinal. Actually, the Axiom of Infinity isequivalent to postulating the existence of a limit ordinal.

The following theorem shows that the elements of ω are the real naturalnumbers.

Theorem 3.2.5. The Peano postulates are

(1) 0 ∈ ω.

(2)

(3)

(4) (Induction)

Proof: For (4), if X ≠ ω, let γ be the least element of ω \X, and show that γis a limit ordinal < ω, contradiction.

Let α and β be two ordinals. Define α + β = type ( α × {0} ∪ β × {1}, H),where

Theorem 3.2.6. For any α, β, γ:

(1)

(2)

(3)

Page 81: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 71

(4)

(5) If β is a limit ordinal,

Proof: The results are straightforward from the definition of addition. �

Recall that the addition of ordinals is not commutative. Let α and β be twoordinals. We define the multiplication α · β = type (β × α, H ), where H is thelexicographic order on β × α:

(3.18)

Again, we get directly from the definition the basic properties of the multiplicationof ordinals.

Theorem 3.2.7. For any α, β, γ::

(1)

(2)

(3)

(4)

(5) If β is a limit ordinal,

(6)

We, again, need to remember that the multiplication of ordinals is not commu-tative and the distributive law (6) fails for multiplication on the right.

Let A be a set. We define A n to be the set of all functions from n to A,and is the function s with domain n such

that Under these definitions, A² andA × A are not the same, but there is an obvious 1–1 correspondence between them.In general, if s is a function with domain(s) = I, we may think of I as an indexset and s as a sequence indexed by I. In this case, we write si for s (i). When D(s)is an ordinal α, we may think of s as a sequence of length α. If D (t) = β, w emay concatenate the sequences s and t to form a sequence of length α + β asfollows: the function with domain α + β is defined by for each

and for allWe have seen that there need not exist a set of the form {x : φ (x) }. But there is

nothing wrong with thinking about such collections, and they sometimes provideuseful motivation. Informally, we call any collection of the form {x : φ(x)} a

Page 82: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

7 2 Chapter 3

class. A proper class is a class which is not a set (because it is too “big”). We useV and ON to indicate the following two classes

V = {x : x = x} (3.19)

ON = {x : x is an ordinal} (3.20)

Theorem 3.2.8 [Transfinite Induction on ON]. If C ⊂ ON and C ≠ Ø, then Chas a least element.

Proof: Fix α ∈ C. If α is not the least element of C, let β be the least elementof α ∩ C. Then β is the least element of C. �

Theorem 3.2.9 [Transfinite Recursion on ON]. If F : V → V, then there existsa unique G : ON → V such that

Proof: For uniqueness, if G1 and G2 both satisfy Eq. (3.21), we can show thatby transfinite induction on α .

(3.21)

To establish existence, we call g a δ-approximation if g is a function withdomain g and

(3.22)

As in the proof of uniqueness, if g is a δ approximation and g' is a δ- ' -approximation, then Next, by transfinite induction onδ, we can show that for each δ there is a δ-approximation (which then is unique).Now, let G(α) be the value g(α), where g is the δ-approximation for some δ > α .�

A useful application of recursion is in defining ordinal exponentiation: Let αand β be two ordinals. Then αβ is defined by recursion on β by

(1)

(2)

(3) If β is a limit,

As in Chapter 2, 1–1 functions are used to compare the size of sets. Generally,if A can be well-ordered, then A α for some α (Theorem 3.2.4), and there isthen a least such α , which we will call the cardinality of the set A, denoted by A. In any statement involving A, we imply that A can be well-ordered. Underthe Axiom of Choice, A is defined for every set A. Regardless of the Axiom ofChoice, α is defined and is ≤ α for every ordinal α .

Page 83: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 73

Theorem 3.2.10. If α ≤ β ≤ α , then β = α .

Proof: β ⊂ α implies β ≤ α , and α ~ α ⊂ β , so α ≤ β . Thus, byBernstein’s equipollent theorem in the previous chapter, we have α = β . �

Theorem 3.2.11. If n ∈ ω , then

(1) n n + 1.

(2) ∀α ( α ~ n → α = n) .

Proof: Statement (1) can be proved by induction on n and (2) follows by usingTheorem 3.2.6. �

Corollary 3.2.1. ω is a cardinal and each n ∈ ω is a cardinal.

A set A is finite if A < ω and to be countable if A ≤ ω . Infinite means notfinite. Uncountable means not countable.

Cardinal multiplication and addition are defined in the following. They mustbe distinguished from ordinal multiplication and addition. Let κ and λ be twocardinals we define

Theorem 3.2.12. For

Proof: First show n + m < ω by induction on m. Then show n · m < ω byinduction on m. The rest follows from Theorem 3.2.11 (2). �

Theorem 3.2.13. Every infinite cardinal is a limit ordinal.

Proof: If κ is an infinite cardinal and κ = α + 1, then since 1 + α = α ,κ = κ = 1 + α = α .This contradicts the definition of κ . �

.Theorem 3.2.14. If κ is an infinite cardinal, κ × κ = κ

Proof: We prove the theorem by transfinite induction on κ . Assume thisholds for smaller cardinals. Then for α < κ , α × α = α ⊗ α < κ. Define awell-ordering on κ × κ by (α , β) (γ,δ) if and only if

precedes lexicographically] (3.23)

Each has no more thanpredecessors under the ordering , so type whence �

Page 84: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

7 4 Chapter 3

Corollary 3.2.2. Let κ and λ be infinite cardinals then

(1)

(2)

Proof: For (2), use the proof of Theorem 3.2.13 to define a 1–1 mappingThis gives a 1–1 mapping Therefore,

Theorem 3.2.15. ∀α∃κ (κ α and κ is a cardinal).

Proof: Assume α ≥ ω. Let W = {H : H ∈ P( α × α) and H well-orders α } .Let S = {type(H) : H ∈ W }. Then ∪ S is a cardinal > α . �

Let α be an ordinal and α + the least cardinal > α . A cardinal number κ is asuccessor cardinal if there exists some ordinal α such that κ = α+ . The cardinalκ is a limit cardinal if κ > ω and is not a successor cardinal. Now, the sequenceof transfinite cardinals ℵ α = ωα is defined by transfinite recursion on α by

(1) ω0 = ω.

(2) ωα +1 = (ωα)+ .

(3) For any limit ordinal

Theorem 3.2.16.

(1) Every infinite cardinal is equal to ωα for some α .

(2) α < β →ωα < ωβ.

(3) ωα is a limit cardinal if and only if α is a limit ordinal.

(4) ωα is a successor cardinal if and only if α is a successor ordinal.

We now turn to cardinal exponentiation. Let AB = BA = {ƒ : ƒ is a function ∧D(ƒ) = B ∧ R (ƒ) ⊂ A}. We define

Theorem 3.2.17. If λ ≥ ω and 2 ≤ κ ≤ λ , then

Proof: λ 2 ~ P( λ ) follows by identifying sets with their characteristic func-tions. Then

where X Y implies that there exists a 1–1 function from X into Y.

(3.24)

Cardinal exponentiation is not the same as ordinal exponentiation. For exam-ple, the ordinal 2ω is ω, but the cardinal 2ω = P( ω) > ω .

Page 85: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 7 5

Theorem 3.2.18. If κ , λ , and σ are any cardinals, then and

Proof: We can check that

and

The Continuum Hypothesis (CH) is the conjecture that 2ω = ω1 . The Gener-alized Continuum Hypothesis is the conjecture that

If α and β are ordinals and ƒ : α → β is a mapping. The mapping ƒ maps αcofinally if D(ƒ) is unbounded in β ; i.e., ∀ b ∈ β∃ a ∈ D(ƒ)( b ≤ a ). The cofinalityof β, denoted by cf(β), is the least α such that there is a mapping from α cofinallyinto β. Therefore, cf(β) ≤ β; if β is a successor, cf(β ) = 1.

Theorem 3.2.19. There is a cofinal mapping ƒ : cf(β) → β which is strictly in-

creasing

Proof: Let g : cf(β) → β be any cofinal mapping, and define a mapping ƒrecursively by

Theorem 3.2.20. If α is a limit ordinal and ƒ : α → β is a strictly increasingcofinal mapping, then cf(α) = cf(β).

Proof: cf(β ) ≤ c f (α) follows by composing a cofinal mapping from cf(α)into α with the mapping ƒ. To show cf(α) ≤ cf( β), let g : cf(β) → β be a cofinalmapping, and let h(ξ ) be the least η such that ƒ(η) > g (ξ ); then h : cf(β) → α isa cofinal mapping. �

Corollary 3.2.3. cf(cf( β)) = cf(β).

An ordinal β is regular if β is a limit ordinal and cf(β ) = β . Thus, Corollary3.2.3 implies that cf(β) is regular for all limit ordinals β.

Page 86: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

76 Chapter 3

Theorem 3.2.21. If an ordinal β is regular, then β is a cardinal.

Theorem 3.2.22. κ+ is regular.

Proof: If ƒ mapped α cofinally into κ+ for some α < κ + , then

(3.25)

but the union of ≤ κ sets each of cardinality ≤ κ must have cardinality ≤ κ ⊗ κ = κby Theorem 3.2.14. �

Theorem 3.2.23 [König’s Theorem]. If κ is infinite and cf(κ ) ≤ λ , then κλ > κ .

Proof: Fix a cofinal mapping ƒ : λ → κ . Let G :κ → λ κ . We show that Gcannot be an onto mapping. Define h : λ → κ so that h(α) is the least element of

(3.26)

Then h ∉ R (G). �

Theorem 3.2.24. Assume AC and GCH. Let κ and λ ≥ 2 and at least one of thembe infinite. Then

(1)

(2)

(3)

Proof: (1) follows from Theorem 3.2.17. For (2), κλ > κ by Theorem 3.2.23,but κ λ ≤ κ κ =2κ = κ + . For (3), λ < cf(κ ) implies thateach

and�

We conclude this section by showing that all of classical mathematics can bebuilt upon ZFC.

Let be the ring of integers, the field of rational numbers, the field of realnumbers, and the field of complex numbers. It suffices to show that there is away, based on ZFC, to construct the sets of and Any reasonable wayof defining these sets from the natural numbers will do, but for definiteness wetake = ω × ω/ ~, where (n , m) is intended to represent n – m the equivalencerelation ~ is defined by the following: (a,b) ~ (c,d) if and only if a + d = c + b.

Page 87: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 77

is the set of equivalence classes of the relation ~, and operations + and · aredefined as follows:

(3.27)

(3.28)

where [( a, b)] is the equivalence class of the relation ~ containing (a , b ).Let y where (x , ) is intended to represent x / y, and

So is theset of left sides of all Dedekind cuts. with field operations defined inthe usual way.

We will need the following definitions.

(a)

(b)

3.3. Families of Sets

For an infinite cardinal κ we say that two sets X and Y are k -disjoint if

Theorem 3.3.1. If κ ≥ ω0 and A0 = κ, then there exists S0 ⊂ p (A0) of power κ +

consisting of m-disjoint sets and such that A0 = S0.

Proof: It will be sufficient to find just one set A which can be decomposed asin the theorem and has power κ. A 1–1 mapping of A onto A0 will then enable usto obtain the desired decomposition of A0 .

Let κ = ℵ α and . Two functions ƒ, g in F (conceived as sets of orderedpairs) are ℵ α -disjoint if

We will construct a sequence of type ωα+1 of ℵ α disjoint functions. To carry out this construction we need the following lemma.

Lemma 3.3.1. If ϕ is a transfinite sequence of type γ < ωα+1 with range containedin F, then there exists a function ƒ ∈ F which is ℵ α -disjoint from each term ϕξ ofthe sequence.

Proof of lemma: To see this we notice that the range of ϕ has power≤ ℵ α and thus can be represented as the range of a function Φ : ωα → F. If ξ <

Let ƒ (ξ) be the first ordinal inThen ƒ ∈ F which is ℵ α -disjoint from every Φη , because can holdonly if η ≥ ξ. �

Page 88: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

78 Chapter 3

Let Γ : p (F) → F ∪ {ρ}, where ρ ∉ F, such thatFor each transfinite sequence ϕ denote by B(ϕ) the

set of all functions in F which are ℵ α -disjoint from all terms of ϕ. By transfiniteinduction, we obtain a function g : satisfying the equation

(3.29)

for each ξ < ωα+ 1.Thus, and is ℵ α -disjoint from all gη, η < ξ, which belong

to F, provided that such functions exist; otherwise gξ = ρ.We claim that gξ ≠ ρ for each ρ < ωα + 1. Otherwise there would be a smallest

γ < ω α+ 1 (g γ = ρ ) and g γ would be a sequence satisfying the assumptions ofLemma 3.3.1. This contradicts the assumption that ρ ∉ F. Thus, R (g) = ωα +1.

Let A = R (g). Since each element of A is an ordered pair of ordinals < ωα , weinfer that A ≤ ωα; on the other hand, Thus, A = ωα . �

For an infinite cardinal κ two sets x, y ⊂ κ are almost disjoint if x ∩ y < κ.An almost disjoint family ⊂ p(κ )such that and any two distinctelements of are almost disjoint. A maximal almost disjoint family is an almostdisjoint family with no almost disjoint family properly containing it.

Theorem 3.3.2. Let κ ≥ ω 0 then

(a) If ⊂ p (κ ) is an almost disjoint family and = κ , then is notmaximal.

(b) There is a maximal almost disjoint family ⊂ p(κ ) of cardinality ≥ κ + .

The proof follows from that of Theorem 3.3.1.

Theorem 3.3.3. If κ ≥ ω and 2 <κ0 = κ, then there exists an almost disjoint family

⊂ p (κ ) with = 2 κ .

Proof: Let I = { x ⊂ κ : x < κ } . Since If X ⊂ κ, letIf X = κ, then Ax = κ also. If X ≠ Y, then

since if we fix β such that then

(3.30)

Let then = 2 κ and is an almost disjoint familyof subsets of I. If we let ƒ be a 1–1 function from I onto κ , { ƒ (A ): A ∈ } is analmost disjoint family of 2κ subsets of κ.

A family of sets is called a ∆-system, or a quasi-disjoint family, if there is afixed set r, called the root of the ∆-system, such that a b = r whenever a and bare disjoint members of

Page 89: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 79

Theorem 3.3.4. (∆-System Lemma). Let κ be an infinite cardinal. Let θ > κ b eregular and satisfy ∀α < θ (α <κ < θ ). Assume ≥ θ and ∀ x ∈ ( x < κ ) thenthere is a ⊂ such that = θ and forms a ∆-system.

Proof: By shrinking if necessary, we may assume = θ. ThenSince what the elements of are as individuals is irrelevant, we may assume

Then each x ∈ has some order type < κ as a subset of θ. Since θ isregular and θ > κ, there is some ρ < κ such that = {x ∈ : x has type ρ} hascardinality θ. We now fix such a ρ and deal with

For each α < θ, α <κ < θ implies that fewer than θ elements of are subsetsof α. Thus, is unbounded in θ. If x ∈ and ξ < ρ, let x (ξ ) be the ξ thelement of x. Since θ is regular, there is some ξ such that isunbounded in θ. Now fix ξ0 to be the least such ξ ( ξ 0 may be 0). Let

(3.31)

Then α0 < θ and x (η) < α 0 for all x ∈ and all η < ξ 0.By transfinite recursion on µ < θ, pick x µ ∈ so that xµ (ξ 0 ) > α0 and x µ (ξ0)

is above all elements of earlier xγ ; i.e.,

(3.32)

Let = {xµ : µ < θ}. Then = θ and x ∩ y ⊂ α 0 whenever x and y aredistinct elements in Since there is an r ⊂ α 0 and ⊂ with

= θ and whence forms a ∆-system with root r. �

Under the assumption of CH or GCH, we calculated many exponentiations ofcardinals in Section 3.2. If we now assume that CH fails, questions arise about thevarious infinite cardinals κ < 2ω. For example, we have

Question 3.3.1. If κ < 2ω , does 2κ = 2 ω?

Question 3.3.2. If κ < 2ω , does every almost disjoint family A ⊂ p ( ω) of size κfail to be maximal?

Since the answer to these questions is clearly “yes” when κ = ω, they are onlyof interest for ω < κ < 2ω. For such κ, it is known by the method of forcing thatneither question can be settled under the axioms ZFC + ¬ CH. In the following weshow how these questions can be settled by using a new axiom, called Martin’saxiom. Martin’s axiom is known to have numerous important consequences incombinatorics, set-theoretic topology, algebra, and analysis. For examples otherthan those given here, please consult (Martin and Solovay, 1970; Rudin, 1977;Shoenfield, 1975).

Page 90: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

80 Chapter 3

A partial order is a pair (P, ≤) such that P ≠ Ø and ≤ is a relation on P whichis transitive and reflexive (∀ ρ ∈ P (ρ ≤ ρ)) . p ≤ q is read “p extends q.” Elementsof p are called conditions. A partial order (P, ≤) is a partial order in the strictsense, if it, in addition, satisfies

(3.33)

We often abuse notation by referring to “the partial order P” or “the partial order≤” if ≤ or P is clear from context.

If (P, ≤) is a partial order, p and q ∈ P are compatible if

(3.34)

They are compatible, denoted by p⊥ q if ¬∃ r ∈ P (r ≤ p ∧ r ≤ q ). An antichain inP is a subset A ⊂ P such that ∀ p, q ∈ A (p ≠ q → p ⊥ q ). A partial order (P, ≤) hasthe countable chain condition (ccc) if every antichain in P is countable.

A subset G ⊂ P is called a filter in P if

Axiom 3.3.1 [Martin’s Axiom]. MA(κ) is the statement: Whenever (P, ≤) is anonempty ccc partial order and is a family of at most κ many coinitial subsets ofP, then there is a filter G in P such that MA is the statement

Example 3.3.1. Let P be the set of all finite partial functions from ω to 2; i.e.

(3.35)

Define p ≤ q by q ⊂ p; i.e., the function p extends the function q. Now p and qare compatible if and only if they have the same values on the set D(p) ∩ D(q), inwhich case p ∪ q is a common extension of both p and q.

The partial order (P, ≤) has ccc. In fact, let D ⊂ P be an antichain in P then D ≤ P = ω. If G is a filter in P, the elements of G are pairwise compatible.Hence, if we let ƒ = ƒG = G then ƒG is a function with D(ƒG ) ⊂ ω In thisexample, we are more interested in ƒ than G. If p ∈ P, we think of p as a finiteapproximation to ƒ, and we say intuitively that p forces “p ⊂ ƒ” in the sense thatif p ∈ G, then p ⊂ ƒ G . So p says what f is restricted to D(p). If q ≤ p, then q saysmore about ƒ than p does.

D(ƒG ) could be a very small subset of ω; for example, Ø is a filter and Ø = Øthe empty function. However, by requiring that G intersect many coinitial sets,we can make ƒG representative of typical functions. For example, let

(3.36)

Page 91: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 81

for each n ∈ ω. Since each p ∈ P can be extended to a condition with n in itsdomain, D n is coinitial in P. If ∀ n ∈ ω ( G ∩ D n ≠ Ø), then ƒG has a domain equal toω. Let E = {p ∈ P : ∃ n ∈ D (p)(p(n) = 1)}. E is coinitial in P; and if G ∩ E ≠ Ø,then ƒG takes the value 1 somewhere.

Let h : ω → 2 be a fixed mapping. Define

(3.37)

Then Eh is coinitial in P; and if G ∩ E h ≠ Ø, then ƒ G ≠ h. Let = {D n : n ∈ ω} ∪ {Eh : h ∈ ω2 }; then = 2 ω . If G is a filter in P and G ∩ D ≠ Ø ∀ D ∈ ,then ƒG is a function from ω to 2, which is impossible.

This fact shows the next result.

Theorem 3.3.5. MA(2ω ) is false.

Theorem 3.3.6.

(a) If κ < κ ', then MA(κ') → MA (κ ).

(b) MA(ω) is true.

Proof: (a) is clear. For (b), let = {Dn : n ∈ ω } and define, by inductionon n, P n ∈ P so that P0 is an arbitrary element of P (since P ≠ Ø) and P n +1 i sany extension of P n such that Pn + 1 ∈ D n . This is possible since D n is dense.So P 0 ≥ P1 ≥ P2 ≥ … . Let G be the filter generated by {P n : n ∈ ω}; i.e.,G = {q ∈ P : ∃ n(q ≥ P n )}. Then G is a filter in P and G ∪ D n ≠ Ø for eachn ∈ ω . �

Theorem 3.3.6(b) implies that MA follows from CH, because we can view MAas saying that all infinite cardinals < 2ω have properties similar to ω.

Since the proof of Theorem 3.3.6(b) did not need the fact that P was ccc, wemight attempt to strengthen MA(k) by dropping this requirement, but for k > ωthis strengthening becomes inconsistent by the next example.

Example 3.3.2. Let

(3.38)

If G is a filter in P, then, as in Example 3.3.1, G is a function with D( G ) ⊂ ωand R ( ∪ G) ⊂ ω 1. If α < ω1 , let

(3.39)

Then D α is coinitial in P. We claim that no filter G in P could intersect each Dα ,α < ω 1, since that would mean that R( G ) = ω 1, contradiction. Of course, Phere is not ccc since the conditions {(0, α ) : α ∈ ω 1} are pairwise incompatible.

Page 92: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

82 Chapter 3

We now proceed to show how MA is applied to answer Questions 3.3.1 and3.3.2.

Theorem 3.3.7. Assume MA( k ). Le t where and as-sume that for all and all finite Then there is d ⊂ ωsuch that

Proof: Define a partial order P by

(3.40)

where (s 1 ,F 1 ) ≤ ( s,F ) if and only if

(3.41)

Then the partial order has the ccc. In fact, for (s1 , F 1 ) and (s2 , F 2 ) ∈ P ,they are compatible if and only if

(3.42)

Suppose that were pairwise incompatible. By Eq. (3.42),the sets s would all be distinct, which is impossible.

For each x ∈ , define

(3.43)

Then Dx is coinitial in P . In fact, for eachFor any

(3.44)

E n,y is coinitial in P , since for each If we pickwith m > n, then F ) is an extension of (s, F ) in En,y .

By MA(k ), there is a filter G in P intersecting all sets in

(3.45)

Let ThenIn fact, If

then (s', F' ) and ( s, F ) are compatible. Eq. (3.42) implies that

(3.46)

This implies that If is infinite.

Question 3.3.2 now can be answered by the following corollary.

Page 93: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 83

Corollary 3.3.1. Let ⊂ P (ω) be an almost disjoint family of power κ, whereAssume MA(κ ). Then is not maximal.

Proof: Let Then since is almost disjoint it follows thatω for all finite F ⊂ Thus, Theorem 3.3.7 implies that there is an infinitealmost disjoint from each member of

Theorem 3.3.8. Let ⊂ P(ω) be an almost disjoint family of size κ, where ω ≤κ < 2 ω. Let ⊂ If MA( κ ), then there is a d ⊂ ω such thatand

Proof: Apply Theorem 3.3.7 with

Corollary 3.3.2. MA( κ ) → 2κ = 2ω.

Proof: Fix any almost disjoint family of size κ ( exists by Theorem 3.3.3).Define Theorem 3.3.8 saysthat Φ is onto, so

Corollary 3.3.3. Iƒ MA, then 2ω is regular.

Proof: If κ < 2 ω, then 2 κ = 2ω, so by König’s theorem, cf(2 ω) > κ.

Corollary 3.3.4. MA( )κ is equivalent to MA(κ) restricted to partial orders ofcardinality κ.

Proof: Assume the restricted form of MA( κ), and let (Q, be a ccc partialorder of arbitrary cardinality, and a family of at most κ many coinitial subsets ofQ. We shall find a filter H in Q intersecting each by applying the restrictedform of MA( κ) to a suitable suborder P ⊂ Q with

We first show that we can find P ⊂ Q such that

(1)

(2) D P is coinitial in P for each

(3) If p, q ∈ P, p and q are compatible in P if and only if they are compatiblein Q.

Page 94: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

8 4 Chapter 3

For let fD : Q → Q be such that

(3.47)

and let g : Q × Q → Q be such that

(3.48)

Let P ⊂ Q be such that and P is closed under g and each fD ; i.e.,g (P × P) ⊂ P and f D(P ) ⊂ P, for all D ∈ P satisfies (3) by closure under gand (2) by closure under fD.

Statement (3) implies that P has the ccc, so by applying the restricted MA(k )to P, let G be a filter in P such that

(3.49)

If H is the filter in Q generated by G, i.e.,

(3.50)

then H is a filter in Q intersecting each

A tree is a partial order in the strict sense (T, ≤ ) such that, for each x ∈ T,is well-ordered by ≤ . As usual, we abuse notation and refer to T

when we meanLet T be a tree. If x ∈ T, the height of x in T, denoted by ht(x, T ), is type

For each ordinal α, the αth level of T, denoted by Levα ( T ),is Then ht( T ) is the least α such that Levα Asubtree of T is a subset T ' ⊂ T with the induced order such that

(3.51)

Proposition 3.3.1.

(a) ht

(b) If T' is a subtree of T, then for each x ∈ T', ht(x, T ) = ht(x, T' ).

The proof is immediate from the definitions involved.

Example 3.3.3.

(a) Let a partial order be defined by Thenht(x, T ) = 0 for all x ∈ T and ht( T ) = 1.

Page 95: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 85

(b) Let I be any set and δ an ordinal. A tree is defined as follows:and s ≤ t if and only if s ⊂ t. This tree is called the

complete I -ary tree of height δ. We think of elements of αI as sequences ofelements of I of length α. If α < δ, then Lev and htWhen I = 2, we refer to as the complete binary tree of height δ.

For any infinite cardinal κ, a κ-Suslin tree is a tree T such that T = κ andevery chain and every antichain of T have cardinality < κ. Suslin trees wereintroduced by Kurepa (1936c). We first continue with a general discussion ofκ -Suslin trees and related concepts. We confine our attention to the case when κis regular. When κ is singular, κ -Suslin trees exist but are of little interest.

For any regular κ, a κ-tree is a tree T of height κ such thatκ ).

Theorem 3.3.9. For any regular κ, every κ-Suslin tree is a κ-tree.

Proof: since if would be a chain ofcardinality κ. Thus, ht(T ) ≤ κ. Since each Levα ( T ) is an antichain,κ. Since T = κ and regularity of κ implies thatht(T ) = κ.

Theorem 3.3.10 [König’s Theorem]. If T is an ω-tree, then T has an infinitechain.

Proof: Pick such that is infinite. This is possiblesince Lev0 (T) is finite, T is infinite, and every element of T is ≥ some element ofLev0 (T ). By a similar argument, we may inductively pick so thatfor each and is infinite. Then is aninfinite chain in T.

For any regular κ, a κ -Aronszajn tree is a κ-tree such that every chain in T isof cardinality < κ. Thus, each κ -Suslin tree is a κ -Aronszajn tree, but Theorem3.3.10 says that there are no ω-Aronszajn trees. At ω1 the situation is different.The existence of an ω -Suslin tree is independent of ZFC, but there is always an1

ω1-Aronszajn tree.

Theorem 3.3.11. There is an ω1 -Aronszajn tree.

Proof: Let

(3.52)

Page 96: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

86 Chaper 3

Thus, T is a subtree of The ht(T) = ω1 , since for every α < ω1 , there is a 1–1function from α into ω. If C were an uncountable chain in T, then C would be a1–1 function from ω1 into ω; thus, every chain in T is countable. Unfortunately, Tis not Aronszajn since T is not an ω1-tree; Levα (T ) is uncountable forHowever, we can define a subtree of T which is Aronszajn.

If s, t ∈ α ω, define s ~ t if and only if the set is finite.We will find sα for each α < ω1 such that

Assuming such s α may be found, let

(3.53)

By (ii), T* is a subtree of T. By (i), each sα ∈ T* so Lev α for each α < ω1.Unlike T, T* is an ωl -tree since is countable. Thus, T* is anω1-Aronszajn tree.

We now see how to construct the sequence {sα } by induction. Given sα , takeany and let it is here (iii) is used. Now supposethat we have s α for α < γ , where γ is a limit ordinal. Fix so that

and and inductively defineso that and Let

Then and t is 1—1; if we set then (i) would hold forand Then so(iii) holds as well.

A well-pruned κ -tree is a κ -tree T such that and

(3.54)

Theorem 3.3.12. If κ is regular and T is a κ -tree, then T has a well-prunedκ -subtree.

Proof: Let T 1 be the set of x ∈ T such that

(3.55)

Then T 1 is clearly a subtree of T. To verify Eq. (3.54) for T 1, let us fix x ∈ T 1 andα such that ht( x, T ) < α < κ. Let By definition of T1

and the fact that each has cardinality

Page 97: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 87

κ, and each element of this set is above some element of Y. Since Y < κ , thereis y ∈ Y such that and this y is in T ¹ . A similar argumentshows that

Now for every is a well-pruned subtree of T.

Theorem 3.3.13. If κ is regular, T is a well-pruned κ-Aronszajn tree, and x ∈ T,then

(3.56)

Proof: For n = 2, this follows from the fact that {y : y > x} meets all levelsabove x and cannot form a chain. For n > 2, we proceed by induction. If thetheorem holds for n, fix α > ht(x,T)and distinct y1 , y2 , . . . , yn ∈ Levα (T ) witheach yi > x. Now let β > α be such that there are distinct zn , zn +1 ∈ Lev β (T ) withzn, z n +1 > yn . For i < n, there are z i ∈ Lev β(T ) with zi > y i. Then {z1, z2 , . . . , z n + 1}establishes the theorem for n+1.

A topological space (Engelking, 1975) is a pair (X, T ) consisting of a set Xand a family T of subsets of X satisfying the following conditions:

(i) ø ∈ T and X ∈ T.

(ii) If U ∈ T and V ∈ T , then U ∩ V ∈ T.

(iii) If ⊂ T , then ∪ ∈ T.

The set X is called a space, the elements of X are called points of the space,and the subsets of X belonging to T are called open in the space. The family T isalso called a topology on X.

Let ( X, ≤) be a total ordering. The order topology T, or the topology inducedby the ordering ≤, on the set X is the topology generated by the following sets,called intervals: For a , b ∈ X satisfying a < b , let

(3.57)

(3.58)

and

(3.59)

That is, each element in T is either a union on a finite intersection of some sets ofthe forms in (3.57)–(3.59).

Page 98: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

88 Chapter 3

A topological space has ccc, if each collection of pairwise disjoint open sets ofthe space is countable; it is separable if it has a countable subset A such that eachnonempty open set intersects A.

A Suslin line is a total ordering (X, ≤ ) such that in the order topology X is cccbut not separable. Suslin’s hypothesis (SH) states that “there are no Suslin lines.”SH arose in an attempt to characterize the order type of the real numbers (R, <) .It was well known that any total ordering (X, ≤ ) satisfying

(a) X has no first and no last elements,

(b) X is continuous, and

(c) X is separable in the order topology

is isomorphic to (R, <) (see Theorems 3.4.5 and 3.4.7). Suslin (1920) askedwhether (c) may be replaced by

(c') X is ccc in the order topology.

Clearly, under SH, (c) and (c’) are equivalent, and one can show that if there is aSuslin line, then there is one satisfying (a) and (b). Thus, SH is equivalent to thestatement that (a), (b), and (c’) characterize the ordering (R, <).

Theorem 3.3.14. There is an ω1 -Suslin tree if and only if there is a Suslin line.

Proof: First, let T be an ω1-Suslin tree. By Theorem 3.3.12, we can assumethat T is well-pruned. Let

L = {C ⊂ T : C is a maximal chain in T } (3.60)

If C ∈ L, there is an ordinal h (C ) such that C contains exactly one element fromLev α(T ) for α < h ( C ) and no elements from Levα (T ) for α ≥ h (C ). Since T isAronszajn, h(C) < ω1 . Since T is well-pruned, a maximal chain cannot have alargest element, so each h(C ) is a limit ordinal. For α < h( C), let C (α) be theelement of C on level α.

We order L as follows: Fix an arbitrary total order < of T. If C, D ∈ L, C ≠ D,let d (C,D ) be the least α such that C (α ) ≠ D (α). Observe that d ( C,D ) <min{h(C), h( D )}. Let C D if and only if C(d (C,D )) < D (d( C,D )). We havethus defined an order on L. It is easily verified that it is indeed a total order of L.We now show that (L, ) is a Suslin line.

First, we show that L has the ccc. Suppose that is a familyof disjoint nonempty open intervals. Pick and α ξ so that

(3.61)

Page 99: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 89

then {Eξ( αξ ) : ξ < ω1} forms an antichain in T, contradicting that T is a Suslintree.

To show that L is not separable, it is sufficient to see that for each δ < ω1,{C : h (C) < δ} is not dense in L. Fix x ∈ Lev s( T ). By Theorem 3.3.13, thereexists an α > δ with three distinct elements, y, z, w ∈ Levα( T) above x. Let D, E, Fbe elements of L containing y, z, w, respectively. Say they are ordered D E Fthen (D, F) is a nonempty interval, but since x ∈ D ∩ F, (D, F) contains no C ∈ Lwith h(C) < δ.

On the other hand, suppose that we are given a Suslin line ( L , ). We mayassume that L is densely ordered by putting gaps in the set and no nonempty opensubset of L is separable. Let be the set of all nonempty open intervals of L; thus,elements of are of the form (a, b), where a b. Then is partially ordered byreverse inclusion: I ≤ J if and only if I ⊃ J. We will define a subset T ⊂ s othat ≤ is a Suslin tree ordering on T.

To find T, we first find for each β < ω1 so that for each β,

(1) the elements of are pairwise disjoint,

(2) is a dense subset in L, and

(3) if α < β , I ∈ and ∈ then either

( a ) I ∪ = or

(b) ⊂ I and I \cl ≠

where cl( ) stands for the closure of , which is the smallest subset Y whosecomplement belongs to .

Assuming that this can be done, we let T = By (1)–(3), T is a tree andeach β = Levβ (T ). If A ⊂ T is an antichain, then the elements of A are pairwisedisjoint, so |A | ≤ ω. T can have no uncountable chains, since if {Iξ : ξ < ω1}were such a chain, with ξ < η → Iξ ≤ I η, then by (3)(b)

(3.62)

so would contradict the ccc of L. Finally, |T| = ω1 , since(2) implies in particular that each β ≠ . Thus, T is a Suslin tree.

We now construct the sets β by induction. is any maximal disjointsubfamily of maximality implies is dense. Given α , we define α+1 asfollows: For I ∈ , let I be a maximal disjoint subfamily of

(3.63)

Let

Page 100: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

9 0 Chapter 3

Finally, we assume γ is a limit ordinal and have defined the for each α < γsatisfying (1)–(3) for α < β < γ. Let

and let be a maximal disjoint subfamily of Then (1) and (3) now hold forall α < β < γ. For β = γ, (2) says that no J ∈ is disjoint from all membersof ; this will follow by maximality of ιφ we can show that for each J∈ ∃ K ∈ (K ⊂ J ). Let E be the set of all left and right endpoints of all intervalsin E is countable and J is not separable, so fix K1 ∈ with K1 ⊂ Jand K1 ∩ E = If I ∈ ∪ α < γ α, then K1 does not contain the endpoints of I, soI ∩K1 = or K1 ⊂ I. Now take K ∈ with K ⊂ K1 and K1 \cl(K ) ≠ thenK ⊂ and K ∈

(3.64)

Theorem 3.3.15. MA (ω1 ) implies that there are no ω1-Suslin trees.

Proof: Let (T, ≤ ) be an ω 1-Suslin tree, and let P = (T , ≥), the reverse orderof T. Since T has no uncountable antichains, P has ccc. By Theorem 3.3.12, wemay assume that T is well-pruned, in which case Dα = {x ∈ T : ht(x, T) > α } isdense in P. By Μ Α (ω1 ), there is a filter G intersecting each D α . Then G is anuncountable chain, contradicting the fact that T is a Suslin tree.

First question: Is there anything which is not a set? We have declared thatour axioms of set theory deal with sets — in fact, hereditary sets (Section 3.1).Furthermore, the Axiom of Extensionality has embodied in it the assertion that allthings in our domain of discourse are sets. It seems likely that we have not left anyinteresting mathematics behind by so restricting our universe, since mathematicalobjects like the set of all real numbers, and the set of all complex numbers,are hereditary sets and have been defined explicitly within this domain in Section3.2.

Second question: Is there an “object” x such that x = {x}? This question isindependent of the existence of physical reality, and such a set x would clearly be anhereditary set. Such an object x did not occur in the construction of mathematicalobjects like and This is also an important question in systems theory (seeChapters 8 and 12).

Some questions about sets are relevant to applications of mathematics. Wegive two of the most important questions. A detailed discussion on the relevancebetween the questions and applications of mathematics will be given in Chapter 8.

3.4. Well-Founded Sets

Page 101: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 91

In this section, we study the position of the Axiom of Regularity relative tothe axioms in axiomatic set theory. We work in the axiom system of all axioms inZFC except Regularity and define the class WF of well-founded sets by startingwith and iterating the power set operation. Then we show that WF is closedunder the other set-theoretic operations as well.

Let us define R (α) for each α ∈ ON by transfinite recursion as follows:

(a) R(0) =

(b)

( c ) when α is a limit ordinal.

A set A is well-founded if there is an α ∈ ON such that A ∈ R (α). Let WF be theclass of all well-founded sets, i.e., WF = ∪ {R(α) : α ∈ O N}.

Theorem 3.4.1. For each ordinal α:

(a) R(α) is transitive.

(b)

Proof: We use transfinite induction on α: We assume that the result holds forall β < α and prove it for α .

Case 1. α = 0. the result is trivial.

Case 2. α is a limit. Statement (b) is immediate from the definition; (a)follows from the fact that the union of transitive sets is transitive.

Case 3. α = β +1. Since R (β) is transitive, p (R(β)) = R (α) is transitive andR(β) ⊂ R (α). This establishes (a) and (b) for all ordinals α.

Let x ∈ WF , the least ordinal α with x ∈ R (α) must be a successor ordinal.The rank of x, denoted by rank(x), is the least β such that x ∈ R (β + 1). Hence,if β = rank(x), then x ⊂ R (b), and x ∉ R (β), and x ∉ R (α) for all α > β .

Theorem 3.4.2. For each ordinal α,

R (α) = {x ∈ WF : rank (x ) < α}

Proof: For x ∈ WF , rank(x) < α if and only if ∃β < α (x ∈ R (β + 1)) if andonly if x ∈ R(α).

Page 102: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

92 Chapter 3

Theorem 3.4.3. If y ∈ WF , then

(b) rank( y ) = ∪ {rank(x ) + 1 : x ∈ y}.

(a) ∀ x ∈ y(x ∈ WF ∧ rank(x) < rank(y)).

Proof: For (a), let α = rank(y), then y ∈ R (α + 1) = p (R(α)). If x ∈ y ,x ∈ R (α ), so rank( x) < α .

For (b), let α = ∪ {rank(x ) + 1 : x ∈ y}. By (a) α ≤ rank( y). Furthermore,each x ∈ y has rank < α , so y ⊂ R( α). Thus, y ∈ R( α +l), so rank(y ) ≤ α .

Theorem 3.4.3 says that the class WF is transitive and that we may think of theelements y ∈ WF as being constructed, by transfinite recursion, from well-foundedsets of smaller rank. Therefore, the class WF excludes sets which are built up fromthemselves. More formally, there is no x ∈ WF such that x ∈ x , since from thiswe would have rank(x ) < rank(x). Likewise, the class WF excludes circularitieslike x ∈ y ∧ y ∈ x , since this would yield rank(x) < rank(y ) < rank(x). It is clearthat the following result holds.

Theorem 3.4.4. Each ordinal is in WF and its rank is itself.

Proof: What we need to show is that ∀α ∈ ON(α ∈ WF ∧ rank(α) = α ). Weprove this by transfinite induction on α . Assume that the theorem holds for allβ < α . Then, for β < α , β ∈ R ( β + 1) ⊂ R (α), so α ⊂ R (α), so α ∈ R (α +1) .By Theorem 3.4.3(b), rank(α) = ∪ { β + 1 : β < α} = α . Thus the theorem holdsfor all ordinals α .

Theorem 3.4.5. ∀α ∈ ON (R(α ) ∩ ON = α ).

The proof follows from Theorems 3.4.4 and 3.4.2.

Theorem 3.4.6.

(a)

If x , y ∈ WF, then x × y, x ∪ y, x ∩ y, { x, y}, and y are all in WF, and therank of each of these sets is less than max{rank(x), rank(y )} + ω.

If x ∈ WF, then ∪ x, p(x ), and {x} ∈ WF , and the rank of these sets is lessthan rank( x) + ω.

(b) x

Proof: For (a), let α = rank( x ). Then x ⊂ R (α ), so p (x ) ⊂ p (R( α )) =R ( α + l), so p (x) ∈ R(α + 2). Similarly, {x } ∈ R(α + 2) and ∪ x ∈ R( α + 1).

For (b), let α = max{rank(x), rank(y )}. As in (a), we show, e.g., {x , y} ∈R ( α +2),( x , y) ∈ R (α +3). Any ordered pair of elements of x ∪ y is in R (α+ 3),so yx ⊂ R (α + 3), so yx ∈ R (α + 4). We leave the rest of the details for the reader.

Page 103: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 93

Theorem 3.4.7. The sets and are all in R(ω + ω).

The proof follows from Theorem 3.4.6 and the definitions of these sets inSection 3.2.

Theorem 3.4.8.

(a) ∀ n ∈ ω (|R(n )| < ω).

(b) | R (ω) | = ω.

Proof: (a) is easy by induction on n. For (b), since ω ⊂ R (ω), it is sufficient tosee that R( ω) is countable. To show this by induction, for each n we may identifyR (n + 1) with R (n)2 and order it lexicographically. Then the ordered sum of thesets R(n ), n ∈ ω , has order type ω.

The cardinalities of the sets R(α) increase exponentially: |R( ω)| = ω,|R(ω+ 1)| = 2ω, |R( ω+ 2)| = 22ω

, etc. Generally, let a α be defined by trans-finite recursion on α as follows:

(1) a 0 = ω.

(2) a α +1 = 2aα .

(3) For a limit γ, a γ = ∪ { aα : α < γ}.

Then we have the following theorem.

Theorem 3.4.9. |R(ω + 2)| = a α.

The proof follows from transfinite induction on α .The following theorem is an example of showing that all mathematics takes

place in the class WF.

Theorem 3.4.10.

(1) Every group is isomorphic to a group in WF.

(2) Every topological space is homeomorphic to a topological space in WF.

Proof: A group is an ordered pair (G, × ) where × : G × G → G. Theorem3.4.6 therefore implies that

(3.65)

If (G, × ) is any group, let α = |G| and let ƒ be a 1–1 mapping from α onto G.Define an operation ξon α by η = ƒ – 1(ƒ( ξ ) × ƒ(η )). Then (α, ) is a group

Page 104: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

94 Chapter 3

isomorphic to ( G, × ). The same idea can be used to prove (b). We leave the proofof (b) to the reader.

Generalizing the notion of well-orderings, we have the following: A relationH is well-founded on a set A if and only if

(3.66)

The element y in Eq. (3.66) is called H -minimal in X. Thus, a relation H iswell-founded on A if and only if every nonempty subset of A has an H-minimalelement.

Theorem 3.4.11. If A ∈ WF, ∈ is well-founded on A.

Proof: Let X be a nonempty subset of A. Let α = min{rank( y) : Y ∈ X }, andpick a y ∈ X with rank( y) = α . Then y is ∈ -minimal in X by Theorem 3.4.3(a).

Theorem 3.4.12. If A is transitive and ∈ is well-founded on A, then A ∈ WF .

Proof: It is sufficient to show A ⊂ W F , because if A ⊂ W F, let α =∪ {rank( y) + 1 : y ∈ x }; then x ∈ R (α ), so x ∈ R(α + 1) ⊂ WF . If A ⊄ W F ,let X = A \WF ≠ φ and let y be the ∈ -minimal in X. If z ∈ y, then z ∉ X , but z ∈ Asince A is transitive; so z ∈ WF . Thus, y ⊂ WF, so y ∈ WF . This contradicts thedefinition that y ∈ A\ WF.

Let A be a set. By recursion on n , we define

(1) ∪ 0 A = A.

(2) ∪ n + 1 A= ∪ ( ∪ n A ).

(3) tr cl( A) = ∪ {∪ n A : n ∈ ω }.

Here tr cl is the “transitive closure,” which is the least transitive set containing Aas a subset.

Theorem 3.4.13.

(a) A ⊂ tr cl(A).

(b) tr cl( A) is transitive.

(c) If A ⊂ T and T is transitive, then tr cl(A) ⊂ T.

(d) If A is transitive, then tr cl(A ) = A.

Page 105: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Axiomatic Set Theory 95

(e) If x ∈ A, then tr cl(x ) ⊂ tr cl(A ).

(f) tr cl(A ) = A {tr cl(x ) : x ∈ A}.

The proof is straightforward from the definition of transitive closure.

Theorem 3.4.14. For any set A the following are equivalent:

(a) A ∈ WF .

(b) tr cl(A ) ∈ WF.

(c) ∈ is well-founded on tr cl(A ).

Proof: (a) → (b). If A ∈ WF , then by induction on n, ∪ n A ∈ WF since WFis closed under the union operation (Theorem 3.4.6). Thus, each ∪ n A ⊂ WF , sotr cl(A) ⊂ WF, so tr cl(A ) ∈ WF .

The proof of (b) → (c) is Theorem 3.4.11.(c) → (a). By (c) and Theorem 3.4.12, tr cl( A) ∈ WF, so A ⊂ tr cl(A) ⊂ WF ,

so A ∈ WF .

Let V be the class defined by

(3.67)

In other words, V is the class of all sets. If we are convinced by the previoustheorems that all mathematics takes place in WF, it is reasonable to adopt as anaxiom the statement that V = WF. This does not mean that the two classes V andWF are really identical, but only that we restrict our domain of discourse to be justWF. In the following, we discuss some of the consequences of adding the axiomV = WF to the axiom system of ZFC axioms except Regularity.

Theorem 3.4.15. The following are equivalent:

(a) The axiom of regularity.

(b) ∀ A ( ∈ is well-founded on A).

(c) V = W F.

Proof: (a) ↔ (b) is immediate from the definition of well-founded relations.For (b) → (c), (b) implies that for any A , ∈ is well-founded on tr cl(A), so A ∈ WF .For (c) → (b), apply Theorem 3.4.11.

Unlike the other axioms of ZFC, Regularity has no application in ordinarymathematics, since accepting it is equivalent to restricting our attention to WF,

Page 106: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

96 Chapter 3

where all mathematics takes place. In Chapters 5 and Chapter 9, we will see howthe Axiom of Regularity can be used to study level structures of general systems.

Since Regularity is equivalent to V = WF = ∪ {R( α) : α ∈ ON}, it gives us apicture of all sets being created by an iterative process, starting from nothing.

Theorem 3.4.16. A is an ordinal if and only if A is transitive and totally orderedby ∈ .

Proof: To see that ∈ well-orders A, let X be any nonempty subset of A. ThenRegularity implies there exists an ∈ -minimal element in X.

3.5. References for Further Study

There are many good books in the area of axiomatic set theory, such as (Drake,1974; Engelking, 1975; Fraenkel et al., 1973; Jech, 1978; Kleene, 1952; Kreisel andKrivine, 1967; Kunen, 1980; Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976; Kurepa, 1936c;Martin and Solovay, 1970; Quigley, 1970; Rudin, 1977; Shoenfield, 1975; Suslin,1920).

Page 107: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 4

97

Centralizability and Tests ofApplications

The concept of centralized systems is written in the language of set theory inorder to take advantage of the rigorous mathematical reasoning. The concept ofcentralizable systems is introduced. Applications of the concept in sociology,concerning the existence of factions in human society, public issues of contention,and importance level of problems versus media, are listed. Two real-life examplesare given to illustrate the results obtained in this chapter. At the end some openquestions are posed.

4.1. Introduction

Hall and Fagen (1956) introduced the concept of centralized systems, where acentralized system is a system in which one object or a subsystem plays a dominantrole in the system operation. The leading part can be thought of as the center ofthe system, since a small change in it would affect the entire system, causingconsiderable changes. Lin (1988a) applied the concept of centralized systemsto the study of some phenomena in sociology. Several interesting results wereobtained, including the argument on why there must be a few people in eachcommunity who dominate others. In this chapter we look at the overall study ofthe concept of centralized systems, related concepts, and some applications.

n = n ( r ), a function of r, called the length of the relation r, such that r ⊆ M n ,

In the rest of this section, all necessary concepts of systems theory and termi-nology of set theory will be listed in order for the reader to follow the discussions.

A system is an ordered pair of sets, S = (M , R), such that M is the set of allobjects of S, and R is a set of some relations defined on M. The sets M and Rare called the object set and the relation set of S , respectively. Here, let r ∈ Rbe a relation of S . Then r is defined as follows: There exists an ordinal number

Page 108: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

98 Chapter 4

where

is the Cartesian product of n copies of M.A system S = (M,R) is trivial (resp., discrete) if M = R = Ø (resp., M ≠ Ø

and either R = Ø or R = {Ø}). Given two systems Si = (Mi ,Ri), i = 1,2,S1 isa partial system of S2 if either (1) M 1 = M 2 and R 1 ⊆ R 2 or (2) M1 ⊆ M2 and

≠there exists a subset R' ⊆ R2 such that R1 = R ' M1 ≡ {ƒ : ƒ is a relation on M1

and there exists g ∈ R' such that ƒ is the restriction of g on M1 }. In symbols,

R' M1 = {ƒ : g ∈ R'(ƒ = g M1 }, where . The system S1 is asubsystem of S2 if M 1 ⊆ M2 and for each relation r1 ∈ R1 there exists a relationr2 ∈ R2 such that r1 ⊆ r2 M1.

A system S = (M,R) has n levels, where n is a fixed whole number, if (1)each object S1 = (M1 ,R1 ) in M is a system, called the first-level object system;(2) if is an (n – 1)th-level object system, then each object

is a system, called the nth-level object system of S.Let Si = ( Mi, Ri), i = 1,2, be two systems and h : M 1→ M2 a mapping. By

transfinite induction, two classes , i = 1, 2, and a class mappingcan be defined with the properties

and for each x =

where Ord is the class of all ordinals. For each relationis a relation on M2 with length n(r). Without confusion, h will be used to indicatethe class mapping and h is a mapping from the system S1 into the system S2 ,denoted by h : S1 → S2. When h : M 1 → M 2 is surjective, injective, or bijective,the mapping h : S1 → S2 is also surjective, injective, or bijective, respectively.

The systems S i are similar if there exists a bijection h : S1 → S2 such thatThe mapping h is called a similarity mapping from

S 1 onto S2 . Evidently, if h is a similarity mapping from S1 onto S 2 , the inverseh – 1 is a similarity mapping from S2 onto S1. A mapping h : S 1 → S2 is termed ahomomorphism from S1 into S 2 , if h (R1 ) ⊆ R2 .

Note that a theorem followed by (ZFC) means that the theorem is true onlyunder the assumption that the ZFC axioms are true, where ZFC stands for theZermelo–Fränkel system with the axiom of choice. For set X, X denotes the

Page 109: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Centralizability and Tests of Applications 99

cardinality of X. A cardinal number α = ℵ λ is called regular if for any sequence ofordinal numbers {αβ < ℵ λ : β < λ} , the limit of the sequence is less than ℵ λ . Fordetails and other terminology of set theory, see (Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976).

4.2. Centralized Systems and Centralizability

To use the mathematical reasoning to study centralized systems, Lin(submitted) redefined the concept in the language of set theory as follows.

Definition 4.2.1. A system S = (M , R) is called a centralized system if each objectin S is a system and there exists a nontrivial system C = (M C, RC) such that forany distinct elements x and y ∈ M , say x = (Mx ,Rx ) and y = (My ,Ry ), thenMC = M x ∩ M y and the system C is called a center of S.

Theorem 4.2.1 [ZFC (Lin and Ma, 1993)]. Let κ be an arbitrary infinite car-dinality and θ > κ a regular cardinality such that for any ordinal number

Assume that S = (M,R) is a system sat-isfying M ≥ θ and each object m ∈ M is a system with m = ( Mm ,Rm ) and Mm < κ . If there exists an object contained in at least θ objects in M, there thenexists a partial system S' = (M',R') of S such that S' forms a centralized systemand M' ≥ θ .

This result is a restatement of the well-known ∆-lemma in axiomatic set theory(Kunen, 1980). The following question, posed by Dr. Robert Beaudoin, is stillopen.

Question 4.2.1. A system S = (M,R) is strongly centralized if each object in S isa system and there is a nondiscrete system C = (MC , RC) such that for any distinctelements x and y ∈ M , say x = (Mx ,Rx ) and y = and

Give conditions under which a given system has a partialsystem which is strongly centralized.

A system S 0 is n-level homomorphic to a system A, where n is a fixed naturalnumber, if there exists a mapping h S : S0 0 → A , called an n -level homomorphism,satisfying the following:

(1) The systems S0 and A have no nonsystem kth-level objects, for each k < n.

(2) For each object S 1 in S 0 , there exists a homomorphism hS1 from the objectsystem S1 into the object system hS0 (S1 ).

(3) For each i < n and each ith-level object Si of S 0, there exist level objectsystems Sk , for k = 0, 1, ... , i – 1, and homomorphisms hS , k = 1, 2, ... , i,k

such that S k is an object of the object system S k –1 and hSk is ahomomorphism from S k into hSk– 1 (Sk ) , for k = 1, 2, ... , i.

Page 110: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

100 Chapter 4

Definition 4.2.2 [Lin et al. (1998)]. A system S is centralizable if it is l-levelhomomorphic to a centralized system SC under a homomorphism h : S → S C suchthat for each object m in S the object systems m and h(m) are similar. Each centerof S C is also called a center of S.

Theorem 4.2.2 [Lin et al. (1998)]. A system S = (M,R) with two levels is cen-tralizable if and only if there exists a nontrivial system C = ( MC ,R C ) such that Cis embeddable in each object of S — that is, C is similar to a partial system of S1.

Similar to the existence theorem of centralized systems (i.e., Theorem 4.2.1),we have the following result.

Theorem 4.2.3 [Lin et al. (1998)]. Let κ and θ be cardinalities satisfying theconditions in Theorem 4.2.1. Assume that S is a system with an object set ofcardinality ≥ θ and each object in S is a nontrivial system with object set ofcardinality < κ . There then exists a partial system S' of S such that the object setof S' is of cardinality ≥ θ and S' forms a centralizable system.

For detailed proofs of these theorems, please refer to Chapter 9.

4.3. Several Tests of Applications

In this section we show how the concept of centralizability has been appliedin several research areas.

4.3.1. A Societal Phenomenon

Sociology concerns the environment in which we live and the problems en-countered in human society. In (Lin, 1988a) the following social phenomenonwas studied in the light of centralizability: the dominance of one person or a smallgroup of persons over their family or neighbors. For example, in a relationshipbetween two individuals, one of them must dominate the other. This is true inrelationships between husband and wife, brothers, sisters, or even friends. Tomake any progress, let us first write a special case of Theorem 4.2.1.

Theorem 4.3.1 [ZFC]. Suppose that S = (M,R) is a system such that M ≥ c,where c is the cardinality of the set of all real numbers and that each object in Sis a system with finite object set. If there exists such an element that belongs to atleast c objects in M, there then exists a partial system B of S with an object set ofcardinality ≥ c, and B forms a centralized system.

Suppose that A is a collection of people and [A]< ω is the collection of all finitesubcollections of people in A. Then for any finite subcollection x ∈ [A]< ω , threepossibilities exist:

Page 111: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Centralizability and Tests of Applications 101

(1) There exists exactly one relation among the people in x.

(2) There exists more than one relation among the people in x.

(3) There does not exist any relation among the people in x.

If situation 1 occurs, we construct a system Sx = ( x ,Rx ) as follows: in therelation set Rx there exists only one element which describes the relation amongthe people in the finite set x. If situation 2 occurs, we construct a collectionof systems {Si

x : i ∈ Ix}, where Ix is an index set that may depend on the finitesubcollection x such that for any i ∈ I x the relation set of the system Si

x hascardinality 1 and for any fixed relation ƒ among the people in x there exists exactlyone i ∈ I x such that S i

x = (x,{ƒ}). Finally, if situation 3 occurs, we construct asystem Sx = (x, Ø ), where the relation set is empty.

We now consider the system (M, Ø) with empty relation set, where M = {Sx :x ∈ [A] < ω , there exists at most one relation among the people in[A]< ω , there exists more than one relation among the people in x }. Theorem 4.3.1says that if (1) the cardinality M is greater than or equal to c and (2) there existsat least one person who is an object in at least c elements in M, then there exists asubcollection M* ⊆ M such that (M*, Ø) forms a centralized system and M* ≥ c.

Based upon the construction of the system (M, Ø), it follows that condition (1)means that there exists a complicated network of relations among the people in A.Condition (2) implies that there exists at least one person in A who has enoughrelations with the other people in A. However, when we study problems withpeople, how can we enumerate the relations that exist among these people? Thedifficulty comes from the notion of relation. To apply Theorem 4.3.1 correctly, wemust rewrite each relation between people in the language of set theory. That is,each relation must be written in such a way that it consists of the following basicblocks only: “x is a set,” “x ∈ y,” “x = y ,” “and,” “or,” “if … then,” “if and onlyif.” For details see (Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976). For the time being, thequestion is still open.

However, no matter how complicated the relations among the people in a realcommunity can be, Theorem 4.3.1 says that a person or a subcollection of peoplex ∈ [A ] <ω who want to be a center in the collection A must possess the followingbackground: (3) the people in x have many transverse and longitudinal relationswith the others in A. Thus, if we suppose that in any social society there areuncountably many relations in the sense of set theory among the people, then fromthe point of view of centralizability, we can understand why there always existfactions in human society, namely because there is more than one center.

4.3.2. Public Issues of Contention

If history is seen as a moving picture, each moment of the moving picture showsa few public issues attracting major public attention. To prove this point, Vierthaler

Page 112: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

102 Chapter 4

(1993) used the Reader’s Guide to investigate shifts and changes in Americanpublic concern for social problems. The research uses data available in the seriesof 52 volumes (1990–92) to consider historic variations in the series of volumes.Then Dr. Vierthaler looked at the topics identified as special “social problems” inthe 92-year series to analyze the degree and types of “connectiveness” that existamong the specific social problems as a way to study changes in “American socialproblems consciousness.” Besides the data supporting the observation that at anymoment in history some public issues seem to attract more attention than others,in (Lin and Vierthaler, 1998) a systems theoretical evidence was given to showthat this observation is a historical truth. In this subsection we briefly describehow the systems theoretical evidence was developed.

In the discussion of the previous subsection, we replace possibilities in 1–3 bythe following:

(1′) There exists exactly one social issue connnecting the people in x.

(2′) There exists more than one social issue connnecting the people in x.

(3′) There does not exist any social issue connnecting the people in x.

where a social issue connecting the people in x means that the people in x are eitheraffected by or attracted to a social issue. Now we consider the system (M, )accordingly, and Theorem 4.3.1 will be applied. Note that when we study thecollection of all social issues connecting the people at a fixed historical moment,there is no straightforward method to enumerate all social issues, both minorand major, because there are so many that we do not know how to enumeratethem. As a result, social scientists use several methods to obtain indicators.Most recognized are social survey polls that repeat the question from 1935–1971,asking respondents: “What is the most important problem facing our country?”Other researchers use documents, such as the Readers’ Guide, a record of popularmagazine articles about “social problems” from 1900–1991, or further originalsources (Krippendorff, 1980) such as front page newspaper stories and the studyof other texts over time to identify public issues of importance. So, a consequenceof Theorem 4.3.1 is that because there always exist opposite central social issues,which divide the public, there will always exist opposite political parties in humansociety. In addition, different “positions” are possible on the same issue. hence, thebasis to unify or divide depends on peoples’ interest and their ideas or positionstoward how to best resolve a social issue. Thus, a public issue is a matter ofimportance to the public precisely because it addresses a matter of concern that iscontroversial — whether over the goals or the means considered plausible to attainthe goal.

Page 113: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Centralizability and Tests of Applications 103

4.3.3. Public Issues: Importance Level of Problems versus Media

One school’s opinion says that there are “real” social issues at any given timein history which derive from major problems in the social structure that affectspeople, thus attracting public attention, and that the media just reports to the publictruthfully about all aspects of these social issues. A different school’s opinion saysthat there is no such thing as major social issues at each given moment in historywhich attract public attention, because the mass media manufactures issues byexaggerated propaganda or by accentuating extreme ideological positions. Fordetails, see (Lauer, 1976; Spector and Kitsuse, 1977).

In (Lin and Vierthaler, 1998), the concept of systems was used to show thatthese two opposite theories are actually the two opposite sides of reality. They areunified in the name of systems. Let us see how to achieve this end.

If reality is considered as truth, we then need to understand the meaning of truthfirst. In general, “truth” is a fuzzy concept. For example, the laws of nature are thetruths about the world. A mathematical truth is a true statement in mathematics.Then what should be the general meaning of truth? Klir (1985) introduced aphilosophical definition of systems. He says that a system is what is distinguishedas a system. Based upon this understanding, it can be seen that for any systemS = (M,R) and each relation r ∈ R , r is a true relation in S connecting someobjects in the set M. So, r can be an S -truth. From Russell’s paradox (Kuratowskiand Mostowski, 1976), we have the following theorem.

Theorem 4.3.2 [Lin and Ma (1993)]. There is no system whose object set consistsof all systems.

This result means that we cannot consider a relation which is true with respectto all systems as its objects, and that for each given statement, if it is a truth, itthen implies that there exists a system in which the given statement describes arelation. One interesting consequence of this understanding explains why therealways exist different and opposite interpretations about each social issue. Thereason is because for a given social issue, there always exist systems S1 and S2

such that the social issue is looked at differently in S1 than in S2 . That is, theconcept of “reality” is relative. The concept of truth was first studied in the nameof systems in (Lin, 1990b).

Let (M,R) be a system such that the object set M is defined as in Section4.3.2 and R is a set of relations between the object systems in M. It is thenreasonable to believe that this system describes all aspects or all “realities” aboutthe collection of all social issues existing at a fixed moment of time. Then the factthat (M,R) is a system implies that M is a pile of isolated social issues and therelation set R describes how the historical moment (M,R) can be studied as anentity of continuity, connection, and movement. As pointed out in (Lin, 1990b),Klir’s definition of systems means the following.

Page 114: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

104 Chapter 4

Axiom 4.3.1. That a system A possesses a property B means that there existsa system C , different from system A, such that C recognizes that A possessesproperty B.

This axiom implies that consciousness and matter coexist. That is, the impor-tance level of social issues catches the media’s interest; in turn, the media makesthe issues more accessible to the public and so more public attention is created.Another interesting consequence of this axiom is that the media could do whateverpossible to promote the importance level of a social issue. However, if the issuedoes not have many transverse and longitudinal connections with other social is-sues, no matter how hard the media tries, there will be a “plateau” over whichthe importance level or the level of public attention will never go. This mightbe the reason why during the 1992 U.S. presidential campaign, the percentage ofsupporters for then-president George Bush rose dramatically during the final daysand then began to stall. Consequently, public support for Bush never reached ahigh level nor went beyond the observed level, which was lower than desired bythat side of campaign.

In the next two sections, two examples are used to elucidate the results obtainedin this chapter.

4.4. Growth of the Polish School of Mathematics

A good book about the developing history of the Polish School of Mathematicsis Kuratowski (1980), which is the source of the story used here. Briefly, in 1911there were four distinguished professors of mathematics in the only two Polishuniversities: J. Puzyna, W. Sierpinski, S. Zaremba, and K. Zorawski. They hadno common interests in the field of mathematics, since each worked in a differentfield: Puzyna in analytic functions, Sierpinski in number theory and set theory,Zaremba in differential equations, and Zorawski in differential geometry. Asa consequence of the discussion in the preceding sections, they could not havestudents in common because there did not exist enough relations between them;this means that there was no possibility of organizing a mathematical school.

For that to happen, there had to be a common set of problems on which anumber of people were engaged so that the people would be working as a wholecommunity. At the same time, no matter how small the group of people was atthe beginning, it had to contain sufficiently bright and active people to attract theinterest of other mathematical adepts by its topics; that is, the people in the groupshould be active enough to set up relations with other mathematicians outside.

A few years later, two exceptionally talented and creative young mathemati-cians, Z. Janiszewski and S. Mazurkiewicz, were working in almost the same field,topology. Janiszewski received his doctor’s degree in Paris in 1912, Mazurkiewiczin Lwow in the same year.

Page 115: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Centralizability and Tests of Applications 105

In early 1918, some people spoke about a fairly strong Warsaw center of set the-ory, topology, and their applications under the direction of Professors Janiszewski,Mazurkiewicz, and Sierpinski. Since the arrival of Janiszewski and Mazurkiewicz,a community of the three mathematicians with common interests had been formed.The development of the hard-working community of mathematicians linked bycommon scientific interests was one of the essential factors leading to the creationof the Polish School of Mathematics. In the next two years the school was createdand developed exactly as described by Janiszewski in the keynote address of theschool.

In 1918, in the first volume of a publication titles Polish Science, Its Needs,Organization and Development, Janiszewski published the article, “On the needs ofmathematics in Poland.” He began with the assumption that Polish mathematicianscould not afford “to be just the recipients or customers of foreign centers” but “towin an individual position for Polish mathematics.” One of the principal meanssuggested by him for attaining that end was the concentration of scientific staff ina relatively narrow field of mathematics but one in which Polish mathematicianshad common interests and — what was more important — one in which theyhad achievements that counted on a world scale. Though mathematicians needno laboratories or expensive and sophisticated auxiliary equipment for their work,they do need a proper atmosphere; this proper atmosphere can be created only bythe cultivation of common topics. For research workers, collaborators are almostindispensable, for in isolation they will in most cases be lost. The causes are notonly psychological, such as lack of incentive, but an isolated researcher knowsmuch less than those who work as a team. Only the results of research, the finishedripe ideas can reach an isolated researcher and then only when they appear in print,often several years after their conception. The isolated researcher does not knowhow and when they have been obtained, is far from those forges or melting potswhere mathematics is produced, comes late, and must inevitably lag behind.

Because of the concentration of scientific staff, Janiszewski suggested theestablishment of a periodical devoted exclusively to the fields of mathematicsconnected with set theory and foundations of mathematics. Such a periodical,if published in a language known abroad, would serve a double goal: It wouldpresent the achievements of Polish mathematicians to the world of learning, whileattracting foreign authors with similar interests.

Such a journal, entitled Fundamenta Mathematicae, was founded, and thefirst volume appeared in 1920. That day was thought to be the inauguration ofthe Polish School of Mathematics. Although Fundamenta was conceived as aninternational journal, the first volume deliberately contained papers only by Polishauthors. It was something of an introduction to the world of the newly risen schoolof mathematics.

Fundamenta was a journal limited to just one field of mathematics. Publicationin languages known abroad made the accomplishments of Polish mathematiciansaccessible to the scientific world on a large scale, and it was an indispensable

Page 116: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

106 Chapter 4

condition for attracting the works of foreign mathematicians for publication in thejournal and thus giving it an international character. In contrast to the prevalentpractice today, where there exist strictly specialized mathematical journals, inthose days it was a novelty and met with undisguised skepticism on the part ofmany mathematicians.

The part played by Fundamenta in the development of fields represented init is not limited to the publication of papers. A considerable role has also beenplayed by the problems sections, which have been maintained since the firstvolume. Some problems became classics; others resulted in the appearance ofmany valuable papers. Proof of this may be found by inspecting the new editionof the first volume, which appeared in 1937. The editors had hit upon the veryhappy idea of presenting in a new edition the actual state of problems discussedin the first edition of that volume (i.e., 17 years earlier), both in individual papersand in the problem section. The purpose of recalling the original problems wasused to show the world of learning that Fundamenta was a journal that publishedimportant problems.

In 1935, Fundamenta celebrated its twenty-fifth volume. A jubilee volume oftwice the normal size was published, and the most distinguished scholars workingin the fields represented in the journal were invited to publish their works in it.Thus, the papers in the jubilee volume showed the world that Fundamenta was aprestigious journal of the fields represented in it and showed the position of thePolish School of Mathematics.

According to Tamarkin (Tamarkin, 1936), under the masterful guidance of itseditors, Fundamenta Mathematicae immediately developed into a unique peri-odical that attracted international recognition and cooperation and whose historybecame the history of development of the modem theory of functions and pointsets. From this brief description, we can see how the idea of centralized systemswas used extremely successfully in the establishment of a scientific center.

4.5. The Appearance of Nicolas Bourbaki

We can read about Nicolas Bourbaki, a French School of Mathematics, inmany articles, such as (Cartan, 1980; Halmos, 1957). In this section we describesome stories useful to systems analysis.

Nicolas Bourbaki is the author of a wide-ranging textbook on mathematicswritten in French. Although the first volume appeared in 1939, the work is by nomeans complete; 21 volumes totaling more than 3000 pages have been publishedto date. Bourbaki has also written articles for mathematical journals, amongthem the Archiv der Mathematik. In addition, he runs a seminar (the SéminaireBourbaki) in Paris at which noted professors and researchers from all over Franceand from neighboring countries come together three times a year for a three-day

Page 117: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Centralizability and Tests of Applications 107

mathematical conference held in the Institut Henri Poincaré. Nearly 150 paperscovering a broad range of mathematical topics have been delivered in this seminarand then to mathematical circles around the world.

Since the first notes, reviews, and papers with Nicolas Bourbaki’s name ap-peared in some journals in the middle 1930s, his courage and resourcefulness inusing the axiomatic method to develop the whole of mathematics, the especiallyingenious terminology, and the clean and economical organization of ideas andstyle of presentation have fascinated many mathematicians. They had been asking:Who is Nicolas Bourbaki? How was the scientific research group formed? Howare they working? Why did they choose this name? In short, Nicolas Bourbakiappeared in the world as if he came from a dim mist.

In about 1946, in an article for the Encyclopedia Britannica, R. P. Boas, then-executive editor of Mathematical Reviews, printed his opinion that Bourbaki wassimply the pseudonym for a group of French mathematicians. The publishers ofBritannica soon found themselves in an acutely embarrassing position, for theyreceived a scathing letter signed by Nicolas Bourbaki in which he declared that hewas not about to allow anyone to question his right to exist. And to avenge himselfon Boas, Bourbaki began to circulate the rumor that the mathematician Boas didnot exist and that the initials B.O.A.S. were simply a pseudonym for a group ofeditors of Mathematical Reviews.

In his work, Bourbaki introduced many new and important concepts. Becausethere do not exist general rules in mathematics by which to judge what kindsof problems are important and what others are not of interest, mathematiciansare extremely interested in the criteria on which Bourbaki decided what to do.Bourbaki divided the class of all mathematical problems into several categories(Dieudonne, 1982, p. 2):

(I) Stillborn problems (e.g., the determination of Fermat primes or theirrationality of Euler’s constant)

(II) Problems without issue

(III) Problems that beget a method

(IV) Problems that belong to an active and fertile general theory

(V) Theories in decline for the time being

(VI) Theories in a state of dilution

The majority of Bourbaki’s topics belong to categories IV and III. The study ofproblems in category IV ultimately (and perhaps only after a long time) reveals theexistence of unexpected underlying structures that not only illuminate the originalquestions but also provide powerful general methods for elucidating a host ofproblems in other areas of mathematics. For the problems in category III, an

Page 118: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

108 Chapter 4

examination of the techniques used to solve the original problems enables one toapply them (perhaps by making them considerably more complicated) to similaror more difficult problems without necessarily feeling that one really understandswhy they work.

Mathematics has changed radically in the past 20 years (a development inwhich Bourbaki may have had a hand). There may be some concepts among thefundamentals in Bourbaki’s textbook that have already become outdated. AfterBourbaki finishes the first part of his work, he may feel obligated to start all overagain. Now people are watching Bourbaki’s behavior with some further questions:What is the working direction of Bourbaki with newcomers? Will he still restricthimself to the mathematical foundation? What are his plans now?

In comparing the appearance of Nicolas Bourbaki and the growth of the PolishSchool of Mathematics, we can observe some similarities and differences. Inthe present situation, where there are uncountably many schools of thought in theworld of learning, how can scientists in the coming generations choose appropriatemethods that will enable them to tower above the forest of scientific schools? Thisis an actual problem. But no matter how many thousands of methods exist toachieve superiority in science, according to the study in this chapter, one point willnever change—that is, that the establishment of a network of relations is essentialto achieving the desired superiority successfully.

4.6. Some Related Problems and a Few Final Words

All applications of the concept of centralizability, discussed in this chapter,depend on the assumption that all axioms in ZFC are true. Furthermore, thequestion of how to enumerate human relations in terms of the basic blocks of settheory is still unknown. The assumption and the question need to be addressedin order to make this piece of research more reliable. The study of the feasibilityof the assumption will have impact on the entire research of applied mathematics,since in applications of mathematics no one in the known literature has ever triedto address whether the setting of an application really makes the axioms in ZFCtrue. As is well known, if some of the axioms were not true in an applicationsetting, then the truthfulness of the mathematical theorems applied would be indoubt. So, the study for the feasibility of this assumption will no doubt lead to anactive research area in applied mathematics.

As for the question, it has been open in sociology for years. So far, no oneseems to have developed a convincing method to enumerate human relations.

Compared with applications of systems theory in sociology, done earlier bymany scholars, the study in this chapter is different in the following ways: First,each application is based on rigorous logical reasoning. Because of this feature, theproblems mentioned appeared. Second, any cap appearing in the logical reasoning

Page 119: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Centralizability and Tests of Applications 109

is pointed out so that the applicability of the current approach of systems theorycan be checked; at the same time, the concept of feedback can play an importantrole here. That is, if for some reason the approach needs to be modified, systemstheory will accordingly be enriched. Consequently, more and deeper insights inrelated areas can be obtained.

Page 120: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 5

A Theoretical Foundation for the Lawsof Conservation

Finite divisibility of general systems is shown. Based upon this result, Lavoisier’sAxiom, introduced in 1789, is verified by using the concept of fundamental par-ticles, where a fundamental particle is one which can no longer be divided intosmaller ones. The conservation principle of ancient atomists is recast and provedmathematically, based on which the law of conservation of matter–energy canbe seen clearly. A brief history of atoms, elements, and laws of conservation isgiven, and some important open questions are posed. This chapter is based on(Lin, 1996).

5. 1. Introduction

In the rest of this section, we briefly list some basic terminology and conceptsto fully understand the discussion in Section 5.2.

According to Cantor, the creator of set theory, the word “set” means a collectionof objects (or elements). However, such a view is untenable, as in certain cases theintuitive concept has been proved to be unreliable. So, in axiomatic set theory thetheory is based on a system of axioms (usually on the system of ZFC axioms), fromwhich all theorems are obtained by deduction. “Set” is one of the two primitivenotions of the theory and is not examined directly about its meaning.

The law of conservation of matter–energy, one of the greatest achievementsof all time, and systems, a current fashionable concept in modern science andtechnology, are joined under the name of general systems theory. Research in thefoundation of mathematics, named set theory, has found its way through generalsystems theory into the realm of scientific activities related to the search for orderof the natural world in which we live. The goal of this chapter is to establish arigorous theoretical frame-work for the part of the world of learning on the lawsof conservation. Hopefully, this study will provide an early casting of a stone toattract many beautiful and useful gems in future research along the line describedhere.

111

Page 121: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

112 Chapter 5

The ZFC axiom system is the Zermelo–Fränkel system with the axiom ofchoice. For details, refer to (Kunen, 1980; Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976). Forconvenience, we state the Axiom of Regularity, one of the ZFC axioms: If A is anonempty set of sets, then there exists a set X in A such that

5.2. Brief History of Atoms, Elements, and Laws ofConservation

All mathematical results, introduced in Section 5.2, are based on the assump-tion that the system of ZFC axioms is consistent, denoted by Theorem (ZFC). Thatis, the theory derived from ZFC axioms does not contain contradictory statements.

Let x and y be two sets. The set {{x}, {x,y}} is called an ordered pair, denotedby (x , y ). The first term of (x,y ) is x, and the second term is y. For details, see(Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976).

The concept of systems, used in the following discussion, was first introducedin (Lin, 1987). It generalizes those concepts introduced by Whitehead (1978),Tarski (1954–1955), Hall and Fagen (1956), Mesarovic and Takahara (1975), andBunge (1979). The definition reads as follows: S is a (general) system, if S equalsan ordered pair ( M , R ) of sets, where M is the set of objects and R is a set of somerelations on M. The sets M and R are called the object set and the relation set ofS, respectively. (For those readers who are sophisticated enough in mathematics,a relation r in R implies that there exists an ordinal number n = n(r ), a functionof r, such that r is a subset of the Cartesian product of n copies of the set M.)

The countless ideas in thousands of volumes in a library are arrangements of26 letters of the alphabet, 10 numerals, and a few punctuation marks. Becauseof this and similar observations, the great thinkers throughout the history havebeen wondering whether the rich profusion from objects around us are formed ofa basic alphabet of nature itself in various combinations? If so, what would be thecharacteristics of nature’s “building blocks”?

The ancient Greeks were intrigued by the diverse, changing, temporary char-acter of objects around them. But they were confident that the universe is one, andthey looked for something unifying and eternal in the variety and flux of things.In the search for order, the one-element Ionians (624–500 B.C.) had a naturalis-tic and materialistic bent. They sought causes and explanations in terms of theeternal working of things themselves rather than in any divine, mythological, orsupernatural intervention. Looking for a single basic reality, each Ionian believedthat all things have their origin in a single knowable element: water, air, fire, orsome indeterminate, nebulous substance.

Page 122: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Theoretical Foundation for the Laws of Conservation 113

The four-element philosophers, including Empedocles (490–435 B.C.),Pythagoras and his followers (from 5th century B.C. on), Philolaus (480 B.C.–?), Plato (427–347 B.C.) and Aristotle (384–322 B.C.), claimed that there is notone basic element but four: earth, water, air, and fire. The Egyptians had longrecognized four elements with qualities of male or female. For example, earth ismale when it has the form of boulders and crags; female when it is cultivable land.When air is windy, it is male; when cloudy or sluggish, female. The Chinese,as early as the 12th century B.C., had five elements, the previous four and wood,together with five virtues, tastes, colors, tones, and seasons.

Among his physical ideas of matter, Aristotle introduced a fifth element. Thiselement cannot be “generated, corrupted, or transformed.” This pure, eternal, ethe-real substance makes up the heavens and all their unchangeable objects. Beneaththe lunar sphere, the many products of the terrestrial four elements ceaselesslytransform. He pointed out that, although all substances of the four elements areindividually “generated, corrupted, and transformed, the universe as a whole isungenerated and indestructible.” Thus, in him a conservation of matter conceptcan be found.

Anaxagoras (510–428 B.C.) in his “seeds” idea was unwilling to submergethe tremendous varieties in things into any common denominator. He preferredto accept the immediate diversity of things as is. With his philosophy, everyobject is infinitely divisible. No matter how far an object is divided, what is leftwould have characteristics of the original substance. That brings us to the veryinteresting question of the transformation of matter. If all substances are derivedfrom unique seeds of themselves, how can one substance develop into another?The contribution of Anaxagoras’ concept of seeds was its refinement, its ideaof taking substances as they are and breaking them down minutely in order toknow more about them. One main weakness of the concept is passing down thecomplexities of a large-scale object to unseen miniatures of itself. Since theseminiatures were infinitely divisible, a fundamental unit was lacking.

The Leucippus–Democritus atom (500–55 B.C.) combined features of theIonian single element, Anaxagoras’ seeds, and Empedocles’ four elements and yetwas an improvement over all of them. “Atom” means “not divisible” in Greek.This term was intentionally chosen by Democritus to emphasize a particle so smallthat it could no longer be divided. To Leucippus and Democritus, the universeoriginally and basically consisted entirely of atoms and a “void” in which atomsmoved. Eternally, the atom is indestructible and unchanging. Atoms are all of thesame substance, but by their various sizes and shapes, they can be used to explainthe large variety of objects they compose. Individual atoms, solid, eternal, andindestructible, always maintain their identity in uniting or separating. It is the unionand separation of atoms that is temporary and that results in the transformation ofobjects. The result is the principle of conservation of matter: Matter is neithercreated nor destroyed but is transformed. However, after the atomists, the ideaof Plato and Aristotle on the nature of matter might seem almost an anticlimax.

Page 123: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

114 Chapter 5

Without the introduction of experimentation or the refinements of measurement,the Greek atomic theory, as it turned out, did not have a chance against the authorityof Plato and particularly that of Aristotle. However, experimental techniques andknowledge had not yet reached the point where they could prevent the atomistsfrom being eclipsed by Aristotle — and experimental techniques and knowledgeare social accumulations. That is why we need to develop the fundamental theoryand understanding about the existence and feasibility of the modern concept ofelements and particles.

Men search for order through a few unifying principles, but nature has a wayof seeping through categories set for it. Meanwhile, men gain detailed knowledgeof their surroundings and develop more sophisticated concepts, techniques, andunifying principles. Experiments, becoming respectable in the Scientific Revolu-tion, eventually showed that earth, water, air, and fire can be resolved into simplersubstances and that the Aristotelian elements are not elements after all, or that theyare more appropriate as states of matter that apply to every substance.

Bacon and Galileo had accepted the Greek idea of atoms. D. Sennert, a Germanphysician, had applied atomic theory to specific natural processes. P. Gassendi,influential French mathematician and philosopher, developed an extensive non-mathematical atomic theory. Boyle, a founder of the British Royal Society, wasamong the first serious experimenters of the Scientific Revolution to use atomsto explain specific experiments. His contemporary Newton used a corpusculartheory to explain his investigations of light.

To ancient atomists, the total count of atoms in the universe was constant. Thetotal amount of matter, therefore, remained the same regardless of changes. Theatomists had a conservation principle of matter. In 1789, Lavoisier abstracted fromhis laboratory observations a law of conservation of matter: All matter existingwithin any closed system constitutes the universe for a specific experiment, wherea “closed” system is one in which outside matter does not enter and inside matterdoes not leave. According to William Dampier, in 1929, “Because of its practicaluse, and for its own intrinsic interest, the principle of conservation of energy maybe regarded as one of the great achievements of the human mind.” Let us now takea brief look at the development of the conservation law of energy.

Heat of friction was the Achilles’ heel of the caloric theory. Rubbing twoblocks of wood together, makes the surfaces warmer. Why? From where doesthis heat of friction come? The calorists theorized that heat fluid is squeezed outfrom the interior of the blocks. That is, caloric is neither created nor destroyed; itis merely forced to the surface by friction.

Count Rumford (1753–1814) denied the calorists’ theory, as he supervisedthe boring of cannon. Sir Humphrey Davy (1778–1829) corroborated Rumfordby rubbing two pieces of ice together. Ship’s Surgeon J. R. Mayer (1814–1878)speculated that the calorists were wrong while observing venous blood color indifferent climates. And J. P. Joule (1818–1889) argued against it as his paddlesvigorously stirred water in calorimeters. All these men claimed evidence that heat

Page 124: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Theoretical Foundation for the Laws of Conservation 115

of friction is heat produced by motion, that heat is a form of motion (energy), not aform of matter. Conversely, Watt’s steam engines, invented in 1763, transformedheat into mechanical energy. The ancient Chinese invented gunpowder and used itin rockets. Europeans of the Middle Ages used the powder to propel musket shotand cannonballs. Actually, a gun is an engine that converts the heat and expansiveforce of an explosion into mechanical motion. So, by Joule’s time, conservationof energy as a broad principle was in the air.

Some limited aspects of the broad principle appeared as follows: Newton’slaw of action and reaction led to conservation of momentum. Huygens proposeda conservation of kinetic energy for elastic collisions. Work concepts and swing-ing pendulums led to a principle of conservation of mechanical energy and toefforts toward perpetual-motion machines. Black took seven-league steps withhis conservation of heat principle. Experiments by Rumford and Davy pointed toheat as a form of energy, and Joule established a quantitative connection betweenmechanical energy and heat through persistent, precise techniques.

What remained was for someone with enough insight, interest, and imaginationto put the pieces together and present the whole picture. This was what the Germanphysician J. R. Mayer (1814–1878) did, later reinforced by the technical language,mathematical rigor, and pointed applications of his countryman H. von Helmholtz(1821–1894), a famous biophysicist.

Chemistry was based on the law of conservation of matter. Physics was basedon the law of conservation of energy. It has been shown however that mattertransforms into energy, and energy into matter. Now hen what? Where is theconstancy of matter or energy? What happens to the indispensable “=” signs inthe equations of physicist and chemist? What happens to physics and chemistryas “exact” sciences? Einstein combined the two conservation laws into one, a lawof the conservation of matter–energy: The total amount of both matter and energyis always the same.

For a more detailed and comprehensive history, please refer to Perlman’s work(Perlman, 1970).

5.3. A Mathematical Foundation for the Laws ofConservation

From the discussion in the previous section, it can be seen that all these lawsof conservation were established based on experiments or intuitive interpretationsof some related experimental results or simple observations. In this section somemathematical results of general systems theory are introduced and used to establisha theoretical foundation for the laws of conservation. The models or understandingof the laws of conservation used in this section may not be those currently acceptedby research physicists or chemists, but they are surely some of the major steps

Page 125: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

116 Chapter 5

(5.1)

along the path leading to the current ones. By doing so purposely, I hope that agreater audience can be reached.

A system S n = (M n , Rn ) is an n th-level object system (Lin and Ma, 1987) ofa system S0 = (M0 ,R0 ) if there exist systems S i = (Mi , Ri ), for i = 1, 2, . . . , n – 1,such that the system Si is an object in M i - 1 , 0 < i < n + 1. Each element in Mn

is called an n th-level object of S0 . A chain of object systems of a system S is asequence { Si : i < α}, for some ordinal number α, of different-level object systemsof S , such that for each pair i, j < α with i < j , there exists an integer n = n (i, j ) ,which depends on the ordinal numbers i and j , satisfying that the system Sj is annth-level object system of Si . Then we can prove the following result.

Theorem 5.3.1 [ZFC]. Suppose that S is a system. Then each chain of objectsystems of S must be finite.

Proof: For the sake of completeness of this chapter, a proof of this result isgiven. It is not intended for general audiences but for a few readers who have theadequate mathematical background. The theorem will be proven by contradiction.

Suppose that there exists a chain of object systems of infinite length, suchas {Si = ( Mi , Ri ) : i = 1, 2, 3, . . . }, satisfying that Si is an object of the systemS i –1, i= 1, 2, 3 , . . . . Now define a set X as follows:

From the Axiom of Regularity (Kunen, 1980), it follows that there exists a set Yin X such that

There are now three possibilities: (1) Y = Mi , for some i = 1, 2, . . . ; (ii) Y = S i ,for some i = 1, 2, . . . ; and (iii) Y = {Mi }, for some i = 1, 2, . . . . If (i) holds,

This contradicts Eq. (5.1). So, the possibility (i) cannot be true.If (ii) holds, Y = S i = (Mi ,R i ) = {{Mi }, {Mi ,Ri }}. That is,This contradicts Eq. (5.1). Hence, (ii) cannot be correct. If (iii) holds, Mi ∈

, again a contradiction of Eq. (5.1). Therefore, (iii) cannot be true.These contradictions show that the assumption of a chain of object systems ofinfinite length cannot be correct.

As introduced by Klir (1985), a system is what is distinguished as a system.We then can do the following general systems modeling: For each chosen matter,real situation problem, or environment, such as a chemical reaction process, asystem, describing the matter of interest, can always be defined. For example,let S = ( M,R) be a systems representation of a chemical reaction process, suchthat M stands for the set of all substances used in the reaction and R is the set

Page 126: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Theoretical Foundation for the Laws of Conservation 117

of all relations between the substances in M. It can be seen that S represents thechemical reaction of interest. Changes of S represents changes of the objects inM and changes of relations in R. Based upon this understanding and by virtueof Theorem 5.3.1, it follows that we have proven theoretically Lavoisier’s Axiom,given in 1789.

Axiom 5.3.1 [Lavoisier’s Axiom (Perlman, 1970, p. 414)].

In all the operations of art and nature, nothing is created! An equal quantity ofmatter exists both before and after the experiment . . . and nothing takes placebeyond changes and modifications in the combination of the elements. Upon thisprinciple, the whole art of performing chemical experiments depends.

In brief, this conservation law says that all matter existing within any closedsystem constitutes the universe for a specific experiment. That is, if S = (M,R) isthe systems representation of a chemical reaction defined as before, then a chemicalreaction between the substances in M is just simply a change and modification ofsome relations between the fundamental particles. Here, a fundamental particleis a particle which can no longer be divided into smaller ones. The existence offundamental particles is shown by Theorem 5.3.1, since if a particle A can still bedivided into smaller particles, A then can be studied as a system, based upon Klir’sdefinition of systems. Theorem 5.3.1 says that each chain of object systems muststop; i.e., each particle must be finitely divisible.

Based upon this understanding, the conservation principle of ancient atomists(Perlman, 1970, p. 414), which states that the total count of atoms in the universeis constant; therefore, the total amount of matter remains the same regardless ofchanges, can be restated as follows:

Law [Conservation of Fundamental Particles]. The total count of basic parti-cles in the universe is constant; therefore, the total amount of matter remains thesame regardless of changes and modifications.

A brief reasoning for the feasibility of this law is the following: There are threebasic known changes in the universe: physical, chemical, and nuclear. A changein which a substance entirely retains its original composition is a physical change.A change in which a substance loses its original composition and one or more newsubstances are formed is a chemical change. A change where nuclei, which areunstable, shoot out “chunks” of mass and energy, and other changes, while takeplace in the nucleus of an atom, are called nuclear reactions. None of these changesis a change at the fundamental particle level. Rather each is a recombination ofsome higher level systems of the fundamental particles. At the same time, thefollowing theorem guarantees that for each given system S = (M,R), the set offundamental particles is uniquely determined. Hence, if the physical universeis studied as a system, the set of basic particles is eternal, indestructible, andunchangeable. It, in turn, proves the feasibility of the Law of Conservation ofFundamental Particles.

Page 127: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

118 Chapter 5

Theorem 5.3.2 [ZFC]. For each system S = (M,R), the set of all fundamentalobjects are unique.

Proof: Again, the proof given here is for completeness of this chapter. Let

M1 = {m ∈ M : m is not a system}

and

By mathematical induction, assume that all sets Mi and M*i have been defined for

each i < n + 1 for a natural number n satisfying

Mi = {m ∈ M*i – 1 : m is not a system}

and

Then Mn + 1 and Mn + 1* can be defined as follows:

Mn + 1 = {m ∈ M*n : m is not a system}

and

Theorem 5.3.1 guarantees that there is a natural number n such that Mj and M*j

equal φ, for all j > n + 1. Thus, the set

consists of all fundamental objects of the system S and is unique, since each setMi is uniquely defined.

Let us discuss some impacts of what has been done on the Law of Conservationof Matter–Energy. The law states that the total amount of matter and energyis always the same. Historically, this law was developed based upon the newdevelopment of science and technology: Energy and matter are two differentforms of the same thing. That is, matter can be transformed into energy, andenergy into matter. Each matter consists of fundamental particles, and so doesenergy. Since energy can be in different forms, such as light, it confirms that eachfundamental particle has no volume or size. Actually, Theorem 5.3.1 also provesthis fact, because if a particle has certain a volume, it would be possible to chop itup into smaller pieces. That is, the particle can be considered a system; it is nota fundamental particle. As a consequence of the Law of Conservation of BasicParticles, the Law of Conservation of Matter–Energy becomes clear and obvious.

Page 128: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Theoretical Foundation for the Laws of Conservation 119

5.4. A Few Final Words

In the previous mathematical analysis of the laws of conservation, many impor-tant questions are left open. For example, it is necessary to develop conservationequations in terms of fundamental particles and to write them in modern symbolicform. Only with the indispensable “=” signs in the equation can the theory, devel-oped on the law of conservation of fundamental particles, be made into one “exactscience” with the capacity of prediction.

It took several thousand years to develop the Law of Conservation of Matter–Energy. The law has been considered as one of the greatest syntheses of alltime, comparable to those of Ptolemy and Newton. Without the “=” signs ofthe conservation laws, certainly modern physics, chemistry, and technology couldhardly exist. Not only this, the great idea, contained in the conservation law,contradicts the common notion that all things must change. This idea is stilldeveloping. The full range of its implications is not yet clear, but surely theconsequence will be revolutionary.

Page 129: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 6

A Mathematics of Computability thatSpeaks the Language of Levels

In this chapter we use the modern systems theory to retrace the history ofimportant and interesting philosophical problems. Based on the discussion, weshow that the multilevel structure of nature can be approached by using thegeneral systems theory approach initiated by Mesarovic in the early 1960s.Two difficulties appearing in modern physics are listed and studied in termsof a new mathematical theory. This theory reflects the characteristic of themultilevel nature. Some elementary properties of the new theory are listed.Some important and fruitful leads for future research are posed in the finalsection.

6.1. Introduction

Since the concept of systems was first formally introduced by von Berta-lanffy in the 1920s, the meaning of system has been getting wider and wider.As the application of the systems concept has become more widespread, theneed to establish the theoretical foundation of all systems theories becomesevident. To meet the challenge of forming a unified foundation of the theoryof systems, Mesarovic and Takahara introduced a concept of general systems,based on Cantor’s set theory, in the 1960s. Since the theory of general systemshas been established on set theory, one shortfall of this “theoretical foundation”is that it is difficult or impossible to quantify any subject matter of research.In this chapter recent results in general systems theory are used to show theneed for a mathematical theory of multilevels, and, based on Wang’s work(1985; 1991), one is introduced. This theory is used to study two problemsin modern physics. Hopefully, this work will make up the computationaldeficiency of the current theory of general systems.

121

Page 130: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

122 Chapter 6

6.2. Multilevel Structure of Nature

Even though the major part of classical and modern mathematics deals withsubject matters of one level, such as problems on the real number line, the plane,the n -dimensional Euclidean spaces, etc., human minds have been searching forthe organic structure of multilevels of the universe since at least the time of theone-element Ionians (624–500 B.C.). For example, in the search for order, Ionianshad a naturalistic and materialistic bent. They sought causes and explanationsin terms of the eternal working of things themselves rather than in any divine,mythological, or supernatural intervention. Looking for a single basic reality,each Ionian believed that all things have their origin in a single knowable element:water, air, fire, or some indeterminate, nebulous substance. For more on this,see (Perlman, 1970). This section shows that general systems theory, based onCantor’s set theory, first introduced formally by Mesarovic in the early 1960s, canbe seen as a new research approach to the multilevel structure of nature.

Mesarovic’s definition of a general system is as follows (Mesarovic and Taka-hara, 1975):

A system S is a relation on nonempty sets Vi :

where I is an index set.

This structure of general systems is multilevel, since elements in the nonemptysets Vi could be systems also. Using this idea inductively, we see that an elementS1 of the system S could be a system, an element S2 of system S1 could be asystem, . . . Can this process go on forever? If the answer to the question is “yes,”then “the world would be infinitely divisible”?! If the answer to the question is“no,” does that mean the world is made up of fundamental elements?

The idea that the world is infinitely divisible can be found in Anaxagoras’“seeds” philosophy (510–428 B.C.). He was unwilling to submerge the tremen-dous varieties of things into any common denominator, and preferred to accept theimmediate diversity of things as is. With his philosophy, every object is infinitelydivisible. No matter how far an object is divided, what is left would have char-acteristics of the original substance. The opposite idea — that the world is madeup of fundamental particles — appeared from 500 to 55 B.C. The Leucippus–Democritus atom combined features of the Ionians’ single element, Anaxagoras’“seeds,” and some thoughts of other schools, and yet was an improvement overall of them. “Atom” means “not divisible” in Greek. This term was intentionallychosen by Democritus to emphasize a particle so small that it could no longerbe divided. To Leucippus and Democritus, the universe originally and basicallyconsisted entirely of “atoms” and a “void” in which atoms move.

Page 131: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Mathematics of Computability that Speaks the Language of Levels 123

In the search for an answer as to which of the two opposite ideas could beright, Ma and Lin (1987), introduced the following definition of general systems:S is a (general) system, if S is an ordered pair (M,R ) of sets, where R is a set ofsome relations defined on M. Each element in M is called an object of S, and Mand R are called the object set and the relation set of S, respectively. For eachrelation r ∈ R, r is defined as follows: there exists an ordinal number n = n (r) ,depending on r, such that r ⊆ M n, that can be either finite or infinite, and calledthe length of r. Assume the length of the empty relation is 0; i.e., n( ) = 0. Thisnew definition of general systems generalizes that of Mesarovic. Many importantstructures of systems can now be studied that otherwise could not have been withthe one-relation approach. We note that the concept of general systems was definedin more general terms by many other authors as well. For example, Wu and Klirindependently defined the concepts of pansystems and systems at a much higherlevel. For more details see (Wu, 1994; Klir, 1985).

Two systems Si = (Mi ,Ri ), i = 1, 2, are identical, if M1 = M 2 and R1 = R 2.System S1 is a partial system of system S2 if M1 ⊆ M2 and for each relation r1 ∈ R 1

there exists a relation r2 ∈ R2 such that r1 = r 2 M1 = r2 ∩ ( M1)n(r2) . System S1 isa subsystem of S2, if M1 ⊆ M2 and for each relation r1 ∈ R1 there exists a relationr2 ∈ R 2 such that r1 ⊆ r 2 M1. A system Sn = ( Mn, Rn ) is an nth-level object systemof a system S0 = (M0 ,R0) if there exist systems Si = (Mi ,Ri ), i = 1, 2, . . . , n – 1,such that Si is an object in Mi – 1 , 1 ≤ i ≤ n. Each element in Mn is called ann th-level object of S0.

Based on these notations, the following mathematical results (Lin and Ma,1993) can be proved, where (ZFC) means that we assume all the axioms in theZFC axiom system (Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976) are true.

Theorem 6.2.1 [Russell’s paradox].of the system consists of all systems.

There is no system such that the object set

Theorem 6.2.2 [ZFC]. Let S0 = (M0, R 0 ) be a system and Sn = (Mn , Rn ) an nth-level object system of S0. Then it is impossible for S0 to be a subsystem of Sn fo reach integer n > 0.

A chain of object systems of a system S is a sequence {Si : i < α } for someordinal number α , of different-level object systems of the system S, such that foreach pair i,j < α with i < j , there exists an integer n = n(i , j ) such that the systemSj is an nth-level object system of the system Si.

Theorem 6.2.3 [ZFC]. Suppose that S is a system. Then each chain of objectsystems of S must be finite.

Theorem 6.2.4 [ZFC]. For each system S there exists exactly one set M(S) ,consisting of all basic objects in S, where a basic object in S is a level object of Swhich is no longer a system.

Page 132: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

124 Chapter 6

For detailed treatment of these theorems, please refer to Chapter 9.As introduced by Klir (Klir, 1985), a system is what is distinguished as a

system. We can then do the following general systems modeling: For each chosenmatter, real situation problem, or environment, such as a chemical reaction process,a system, describing the matter of interest, can always be defined. For example,let S = (M,R ) be a systems representation of a chemical reaction process, suchthat M stands for the set of all substances used in the reaction and R is the setof all relations between the substances in M. It can be seen that S representsthe chemical reaction of interest. Based upon this modeling and Theorems 6.2.3and 6.2.4, it follows that we have argued theoretically that the world is finitelydivisible.

In (Lin, 1996) or in Chapter 5 the same methodology was used to show that atheoretical foundation can be established for the Law of Conservation of Matter–Energy.

6.3. Some Hypotheses in Modern Physics

Without using a mathematics of multilevels, some hypotheses in modern sci-ence seem to be contradictory. However, the theories, established on the hy-potheses, have been winning victories one after another. Einstein’s relativity andDirac’s quantum mechanics, for example, are two of these theories. In this sectiontwo such hypotheses are listed to further support the need for a mathematics ofmultilevels.

6.3.1. The Rest Mass of a Photon

rest mass mAccording to Einstein, the inertial mass m of a moving particle is related to its

0 as follows:

(6.1)

where c stands for the speed of light and v is the particle speed. As for thephoton, since its speed is v = c, the rest mass m0 should be zero, or from Eq. (6.1)m = ∞ , contradicting observations. However, even it is assumed that m0 = 0, thefallacy involved in the calculation still remains in Eq. (6.1) because in classicalmathematics on the real number line, 0 ÷ 0 is undetermined.

6.3.2. Dirac’s δ δ Function

In Dirac’s well-known work (1958), a function, later named Dirac’s δ function,was introduced as follows: δ : , where is the set of all real numbers,

Page 133: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Mathematics of Computability that Speaks the Language of Levels 125

satisfies the conditions:

δ(x ) = 0 whenever x ≠ 0δ(0) = ∞

(6.2)

where ƒ (x ) is a function on with compact support and is infinitely differentiable.This function has played an important role in quantum mechanics. However,

in classical mathematics, including modem measure theory, it is impossible tohave such a function, since each function ƒ(x ) satisfying the first condition mustpossess the property that

Because of the magnificent role that Dirac’s δ function had played in thesuccess of quantum mechanics, the international mathematics community becamedesperate to come up with a feasible explanation for the strange δ function. In1950, Schwartz introduced the concept of distributions, based on which the δfunction was understood as a linear functional defined on the “elementary space”consisting of real-valued functions with some special mathematical properties.For details, see (Richards and Youn, 1990).

6.4. A Non-Archimedean Number Field

In this section a number field, called a generalized number system (GNS), isintroduced. The concept of the GNS is based upon (Wang, 1964), which suc-cessfully solved an open problem in general topology. Independently, Laugwitz(1961; 1962; 1968) studied the concept of generalized power series. The conceptof the GNS was first introduced in the early 1980s by Wang (1985; 1991) withoutreference to Laugwitz’s work and Robinson’s nonstandard analysis. The GNSis really a non-Archimedean number field and has found many successful appli-cations in modern physics. Algebraically, the GNS is a subfield of Laugwitz’sgeneralized power series.

Historically speaking, nonstandard analysis, established in the early 1960sby Robinson (Davis, 1977), first introduced the infinitesimal and infinitely largenumbers formally and legally, based on mathematical logic. This theory brokethrough the limitation of the classical concept of real numbers, where infinitiesare usually considered ideal objects. With nonstandard analysis, many classicaltheories, such as mathematical analysis, algebra, norm spaces, some classicalmechanics problems, etc., can be greatly simplified and become more intuitive.However, the shortfall of Robinson’s nonstandard analysis is that infinitesimalsand infinities can only be shown to exist and have no concrete expressions ofany tangible form. Based on the argument of the existence of infinitesimals and

Page 134: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

126 Chapter 6

infinities given in Robinson’s theory, the GNS has the computational advantage,since each number here, whether ordinary real, infinitesimal, or an infinity, has anexact expression in terms of the real numbers in the classical sense.

A generalized number x is a function from to where is the set ofall integers and is the set of all real numbers, such that there exists a number

called the level index of x, satisfying

x ( t ) = 0 for all t < k, and x (k (x )) ≠ 0 (6.3)

Then x can be expressed as a generalized power series as follows:

(6.4)

where 1 (t) stands for the function from to such that 1 (t ) (s) = 0 if s ≠ t, and1(t) (t ) = 1 and x (t ) ≡ xt . Intuitively, the right-hand side of Eq. (6.4) is the “graph”of the function x : . The set of all generalized numbers will be written asGNS.

We now define operations of generalized numbers as follows:

(1) Addition and subtraction.:Let x,y be arbitrary from GNS. Define

(6.5)

(2) Ordering.:The order relation between x and y ∈ GNS is the lexicographical ordering;i.e., x < y iff there is an integer k0 such that x (t ) = y (t) if t < k0 andx (k0) < y (k0).

(3) Scalar multiplication.:Let c ∈ and x ∈ GNS define

(6.6)

Because of the ordering relation defined in 2, we can now think of GNS asa system of numbers of different level; and the function 1(t) will be calledthe “unit element” of the tth level.

Page 135: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Mathematics of Computability that Speaks the Language of Levels 127

(4) Multiplication.:Let x,y ∈ GNS. Then the product x × y or xy is defined by

(6.7)

Specifically, 1(t) × 1(s) = 1 (t+s ) .

(5) Division.:For x,y ∈ GNS, if there exists a z ∈ GNS such that

y × z = x (6.8)

then the generalized number z is called the quotient of x divided by y,denoted by x ÷ y or x /y.

Theorem 6.4.1. If y ≠ 0 ≡ ∑ t 0 × 1( t) , the zero function from to then thequotient x ÷ y always uniquely exists.

Proof: Assume that the known and the unknown generalized numbers X, y,and z are

and

We need to find z such that

(6.9)

with k (y ) ≤ u ≤ s – k (z) and k (z) ≤ v ≤ s – k (y). This second inequality impliesthat we can define k (z ) = k (x ) – k(y ). Hence, replacing s by k(x ) in Eq. (6.9), wehave

That is,

Page 136: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

128 Chapter 6

Therefore, When s is replaced by k(x) + 1 in Eq. (6.9),we have

Therefore,

By induction, we can continue this process and define each z(m), for m ≥ k (z) =Thus, the generalized number z is defined based on the given x and

y.The uniqueness of z can be shown by observing that the level index of z cannot

be less than To this end, assume that for somenonzero whole number n. Then replacing s by k (x) – n , in Eq. (6.9), we obtain

contradiction. Therefore, the whole number n must be zero. That is, the general-ized number z must be unique.

Theorem 6.4.2. For each x ∈ GNS such that x(k(x)) ≥ 0 and k(x) is an evennumber, there exists a unique y ∈ GNS such that y² = y × y = x. This generalizednumber y is called the square root of x, denoted

Proof: Assume the unknown generalized number y is

Then the equation y × y = x is equivalent to that for any integer s,

(6.10)

where That is, We can then defineWhen s = k (x), Eq. (6.10) becomes

Since . When s = k(x) + 1, Eq. (6.10) becomes

Page 137: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Mathematics of Computability that Speaks the Language of Levels

To show the uniqueness of y, it suffices to see that k(y) cannot be less thank(x)/2, as defined. To this end, assume for some nonzerowhole number n. Replacing s by k (x) – 2n, changes Eq. (6.10) to

By applying induction on the index k(y) + i , the generalized number y can bewell defined.

129

contradiction. That is, the definition of the generalized number y is unique.

The proof of Theorem 6.4.2 can be generalized to obtain 6.4.3.

Theorem 6.4.3. For each natural number n ≥ 2 and each x ∈ GNS such that k (x )is a multiple of n, then

(1) If n is even and x(k(x)) ≥ 0, there exists a unique y ∈ GNS such that

(2) If n is odd, there exists a unique y ∈ GNS such that yn = x.

The generalized number y in (1) or (2) will be called the nth root of x and denotedby

Since y × y = In general, k(yn) =nk(y), where xi ∈ G N S, i =1,2, ... , n , and That is, if k(x) is not a multiple ofn, there is no y ∈ GNS such that y n = x. In this sense, then Theorem 6.4.3 is thebest we can get.

To conclude this section, let us observe the following facts.

Theorem 6.4.4. (GNS, +, ×, <) forms an ordered non-Archimedean field. Ifand k and h are integers satisfying k < h, then

the generalized numbers contained in I(h ) are infinitesimals, compared with thosecontained in I(k ) ; conversely, nonzero generalized numbers in I(k ) are infinitiescompared with those contained in I(h ) .

6.5. Applications

In history, “laws” of the nature have been frequently expressed and treated withthe rigor and beauty of mathematical symbols. For the most part, this applicationhas been very successful. However, in the past 40 some years, theoretical physicists

Page 138: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

130 Chapter 6

have been faced with difficulties in mathematical calculation. According to Wang(1991), such difficulties arise mainly because the modem world of physics ismultilevel in character, whereas applicable mathematics still remains at the stage ofsingle level where the only infinities are denoted by –∞ or +∞ , and are consideredin our macroscopic world as ideal objects and treated with a different set of rules,compared with those of ordinary real numbers. Now, in GNS , the field i sisomorphic to I (0) , which represents measurable quantities within the macroscopicworld. Also, all numbers in GNS , whether infinities or infinitesimals, are treatedwith the same set of rules. In this section we show how the difficulties listed inSection 6.3 can be resolved with GNS.

6.5.1. The Hypothesis on the Rest Mass of a Photon

The difficulty in the calculation of m = 0 ÷ 0, discussed in Section 6.3, can beovercome as follows. Suppose that the rest mass m0 of a photon is

and that the inertial mass m in Eq. (6.1) is a finite real number; that is, m ∈ I(0)

has the representation

Now the velocity of a photon is

where v 2 < 0, since c is assumed by Einstein to be the maximum speed in theuniverse. Equation (6.1) can then be written as

where c is understood in the same way as m ∈ I (0) . By substituting the GNS valuesof m, m0 , 1(0) , v , and c, into this equation, and by comparing the leading nonzeroterms (i.e., the coefficients of 1(2) ), we obtain That gives therelation between v2 and m1 .

Page 139: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Mathematics of Computability that Speaks the Language of Levels 131

In this argument, the existence of the square root can be seenas follows:

and

So

and

From Theorem 6.4.2, it follows that exists.

6.5.2. A New Look at Dirac’s d Function

We show that, as a real-valued function is a function from a subset of I (0) to asubset of I (0) , Dirac’s δ function can be considered as a function from GNS intoGNS. Therefore, it is a more natural representation. At the same time, the integralsign in Eq. (6.2) is no longer a symbol without much mathematical meaning. Forconvenience, boldfaced letters will be used for GNS-related concepts and lightfaceletters for real-valued concepts. For example, f(x) is a real-valued function, andf(x) is a function from a subset of GNS to a subset of GNS .

Without loss of generality, let y = f(x) be a function from GNS to GNS. Wedefine the integral of the function inductively as follows.

Let E = {x ∈ GNS : f(x) ≠ 0}.Case 1: Suppose that for each x ∈ E , x –m = 0 for all m ∈ the set of all

natural numbers, and that y = (… , y–m , … ,y0 , … ,yn , … ), where, in general,yk = y k(x) is a function of all xm , m ∈ {0}.

Step 1: Define a subset H (0) ⊆ as follows: x0 ∈ H (0) iff

y – n = 0 if n > 0 and y0 = y 0(x0 ) a function of x0 (6.11)

Page 140: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

132 Chapter 6

and let

(6.12)

If the real-valued function f (0) is Lebesgue integrable on then – H (0) hasLebesgue measure zero, denoted

Step n: Assume the real numbers have all been defined.For fixed define a subset H ( n ) ⊆ as follows: xn ∈ H ( n ) iff

y– m = 0 if m > n and y– n = y –n (xn ) a function of xn (6.13)

and let

(6.14)

If the real-valued function is Lebesgue integrable on denote the

integral on by is meaningful— that is, if there are only up to countably many nonzero summands and thesummation is absolutely convergent—then the sum is denoted a( n ) .

Definition 6.5.1 [Wang (1985)]. Iffunction f(

is convergent and equals a, then thex) is GNL-integrable and we write

Case 2: Partition the set E as follows: whereEk = {x ∈ GNS : k(x) = – k}. Consider the right-shifting of

, and the left-shifting of f(x):

Using the method developed in Case 1, denote

Definition 6.5.2 [Wang (1985)]. If ∑k ak is convergent, then the function f(x) isGNL-integrable and we write

Page 141: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

A Mathematics of Computability that Speaks the Language of Levels 133

We are now ready to look at Dirac’s δ function. Let ƒ: be infinitelydifferentiable and define f : GNS → GNS as follows:

This function is called the GNS function induced by ƒ(x). Then it can be shownthat 6.5.1 holds.

Theorem 6.5.1 [Wang (1985)]. Let ƒ and f be defined as before. Then there is aGNL-integrable function g: GNS → GNS such that

In particular, let g: be arbitrary and infinitely differentiable with boundedsupport: that is, Sup(g ) = {x ∈ g(x) ≠ 0} is bounded in and g(x ) dx = 1.Then the GNL-integrable function g: GNS → GNS can be defined

1, x2 , . . . )otherwiseif x = (... , 0, x

That is, g(x) is a Dirac δ function according to Eq. (6.2).

Proof: Pick a real-valued function g: such that g is infinitely differ-entiable with bounded support and satisfies

Define

for x = ( . . . , 0,x 1, x2 , ...)otherwise

Then

for x = (..., 0, x1 ,x2 , ...)otherwise

Page 142: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

134 Chapter 6

Since (f)(x)g(x))– n = 0, for each n = 0,1,2, ..., and g (t)dt = 1, it followsthat

This completes the proof. �

For a more rigorous treatment of GNS, please refer to Chapter 11

6.6. Some Final Words

If the ordered field GNS is substituted for we can see that the theory andapplications of GNS will have a great future, since has been applied in almostall areas of human knowledge and been challenged numerous times. As shownin (Wang, 1985; Wang, 1991), many studies can be carried out along the linesof classical research, such as mathematical analysis, distribution theory, quantummechanics, etc., on GNS. Not only this, we also expect that when one is studyingtopics from various disciplines with GNS, some open problems in relevant fieldsmight be answered, and some new fields of research might be opened up. Mostimportantly, we hope that the study of GNS will furnish a convenient tool for acomputational general systems theory.

Page 143: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 7

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality andIts Generalizations

In dynamic programming Bellman’s principle of optimality is extremely important.The principle says (Bellman, 1957) that each subpolicy of an optimum policy mustitself be an optimum policy with regard to the initial and the terminal states of thesubpolicy. Here, the terms “policy,” “subpolicy,” “optimum policy,” and “state”are are primitive and are not given specific meanings. In each application, theseterms are understood in certain ways comparable to the situation of interest. Forexample, in a weighted graph, an optimum path from a vertex v1 to vertex v2 i sthe one with the smallest sum of weights of the edges along the path. In this case,a “policy” means a path, a “subpolicy” a subpath, an “optimum policy” standsfor a path with the smallest weight, and “the initial and terminal states” for thebeginning and ending vertices v1 and v 2, respectively. The principle implies thatfor each chosen optimum path from v1 to v2, each subpath must be an optimumpath connecting the initial and terminal vertices of the subpath.

7.1. A Brief Historical Note

During the last half century or so, Bellman’s principle has become the cor-nerstone in the study of the shortest-path problem, inventory problem, traveling-salesman problem, equipment-replacement models, the resource allocation prob-lems, etc. For details see Dreyfus and Law (1977). However, since the early1970s, a number of practical optimization problems have been put forward inmanagement science, economics, and many other fields. One feature commonto all these problems is that the performance criteria are not real numbers, andconsequently, the optimum options are no longer maxima or minima of someset of real numbers. Many dynamic programming models with nonscalar-valuedperformance criteria have been established. See (Bellman and Zadeh, 1970; Mit-ten, 1974; Wu, 1980; Wu, 1981a; Furukawa, 1980; Henig, 1983; Baldwin andPilsworth, 1982).

135

Page 144: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

136 Chapter 7

Figure 7.1. A subpolicy of the optimum policy is no longer optimum.

Since the application of Bellman’s principle is no longer restricted to classicalcases, scholars began to question how far the validity of the principle can becarried. Hu (1982) constructed an example to show that the principle does nothold in general. In fact, it was shown by Qin (1991), that if the goal set is strongantisymmetric, then the sum of local optimization orders is less than or equal tothe global optimization order. Therefore, the following natural question arises.

Question 7.1.1 [Hu (1982)]. Under what characterizations can a given problembe solved by dynamic programming?

At the same time, as many scholars have realized, it is the fundamental equationapproach, not the principle of optimality, that makes up the theoretical foundationof dynamic programming. The optimum principle gives one a property of theoptimum policy, while the fundamental equation approach offers one an effectivemethod to obtain the desired optimal policy. Since the validity of Bellman’sprinciple is limited, is the fundamental equation approach also limited? Again,Hu’s counterexample shows that the fundamental equation approach does notalways work. Thus, the following questions are natural:

Question 7.1.2 [Wu and Wu (1986)]. In what range does the fundamental equa-tion approach hold? How can its validity be proved? What relations are there,if any, between the fundamental equation approach and Bellman’s Principle ofOptimality?

To seek the answer to these questions, several approaches of systems analysispresented.are

7.2. Hu’s Counterexample and Analysis

Let us first look at Hu’s counterexample.

Page 145: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 137

Example 7.2.1. Consider the network in Fig. 7.1. Define an optimum path asone where the sum of all arc lengths (mod4) is the minimum. Then the policyA → B2 → C → D2 → E is optimum, but its subpolicy B2 → C → D 2 → E is notoptimum, since B2 → C → D 1 → E is, which has weight 0.

Now let W ={0,1,2,3 ,... } be the set of all possible weights, θ1 = minimum: p(W) → W be the optimum option, which is a mapping from the power set p( W )of W, the set of all subsets of W, into W such that

(7.1)

and let θ2 = {+} ° (mod4) : W² → W be the binary relation on W such that

(7.2)

where ° stands for the ordinary composition of mappings.If G is a nonempty set, representing the set of all vertices, then each network

or graph or weighted graph is simply an element g ∈ W ↑ G , ² where W ↑ G² is the set of all mappings from G² = G × G into W. For any a0 , an ∈ G, define

whereThen Bellman’s principle of optimality can be written as follows.

Theorem 7.2.1 [Bellman’s Principle of Optimality]. For any natural numbern, elements

(7.3)

where z is the zero in W, then for any 0 ≤ i ≤ j ≤ n ,

For any g ∈ W ↑ G², a natural number n, and a, b ∈ G, the fundamentalequation on (g; n , a, b) is given by the following functional equations:

where 2 ≤ m ≤ n. Applying these equations to Hu’s counterexample, one obtains:ƒ 4⟨ ⟩ ( A,E ) =1, with A → B → C → D → E being its policy. However, it can be1 1easily seen that g ⟨ 4⟩ (A E ) = 0 and A → B2 → C → D 2 → E is the global optimumpolicy with weight 0. That is, in this example, ƒ 4⟨ ⟩ (A,E ) ≠ g ⟨ 4 (⟩ A,E). Hence, we ask when will the weight obtained from the fundamental equation approach be thesame as the global optimum weight?

Page 146: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

138 Chapter 7

7.3. Generalized Principle of Optimality

By formalizing the discussion in the previous section, Wu and Wu (1984a)obtained one sufficient and three necessary conditions for Bellman’s principle tohold. In this section, all results are based on (Wu and Wu, 1984a).

In general, let W and G represent two nonempty sets, θ1 : p (W ) → W be theoptimum option satisfying Eq. (7.1), and θ2 be a mapping from W 2 into W. Forany element g ∈ W ↑ G2 and any a0 , a n ∈ G, define

whereAn element z ∈ W is called a zero element, or simply zero if

for each w ∈ W

and

for each

The optimum option θ1 is X-optimum-preserving for X ∈ p (W ) if

for any

The option θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law if θ1 is X-optimum-preservingfor all

The relation θ2 is distributive over θ1 if

for all ≠ X ∈ p (W ) and any x ∈ W, and

for all ≠ X ∈ p (W ) and x ∈ W . The relation θ2 is associative if for anyw l , w , w3 ∈ W,2

The relation θ2 satisfies the cancellation law if for any w1 , w 2 , w3 ∈ W,

implies w2 = w3

and

implies w2 = w3

whenever w1 is not the zero element in W.

Page 147: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 139

Theorem 7.3.1 [Generalized Principle of Optimality (Wu and Wu, 1984a)].Assume that θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law and that θ2 is associative,

cancellative and distributive over θ1. Then in the system ( W, G; θ1, θ2), Bellman's Principle of Optimality (Theorem 7.2.1) holds.

Proof: Suppose that g ∈ W ↑ G 2, n is a natural number,and For any 0 ≤ i ≤ j ≤ n, since

and

and

then by the optimum-preserving law of θ1 , it follows that

By the associative law and the distributive law over θ1 of θ2, one has

Since one has that ω(a0a1 ... ai ) ≠ z and ω(ajaj +1 . . . an ) ≠ z.Therefore, by the cancellation law of θ2,

That is,

The generalized principle of optimality is a sufficient condition of the con-servation from a global optimization to local ones. In the following section, it isshown that the conditions in the generalized optimality principle are also necessaryexcept for the condition of associativity.

Page 148: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

140 Chapter 7

7.4. Some Partial Answers and a Conjecture

Theorem 7.4.1 [Wu and Wu (1984a)]. Assume that θ2 is associative, n a natu-ral number, and a0 , a1 , . . . , an ∈ G satisfy Eq. (7.3). If the Generalized Principleof Optimality (Theorem 7.3.1) holds for a chosen g ∈ W ↑ G2, then θ2 pos-sesses the following property of cancellation: for any 0 ≤ i < j < k ≤ n and any

(7.4)

implies

and

implies

Proof: Since and from the assumptionthat the Generalized Principle of Optimality holds, it follows that

(7.5)

By Eq. (7.4) and the associative law of θ2 , it follows that

That is,

From the assumption that the Generalized Principle of Optimality holds, itfollows that

(7.6)

Page 149: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 141

By Eqs. (7.5) and (7.6), it follows that

The proof of the other equation is similar and is omitted.

Theorem 7.4.2 [Wu and Wu (1984a)]. Assume that θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law, θ2 is associative, n os a natural number, and a0 , a1 , . . . , an ∈ Gsatisfy Eq. (7.3). If the Generalized Principle of Optimality (Theorem 7.3.1) holds,then θ2 possesses the following distributivity over θ1 : for 1 ≤ i ≤ n – 1,

and

Proof: Since it is assumed that the Generalized Principle of Optimality holds,it follows that

(7.7)

The assumption that θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law implies that

(7.8)

Then, from Eqs. (7.7) and (7.8) and the associative law of θ2 , it follows that

just what is desired. The proof of the other identity is similar and is omitted.

Page 150: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

142 Chapter 7

Theorem 7.4.3 [Wu and Wu (1984a)]. Assume that θ2is associative and distribu-tive over θ1 and n is a natural number, and a0 , a1 , . . . , an ∈ G satisfy Eq. (7.3). Ifthe Generalized Principle of Optimality (Theorem 7.3.1) holds, then θ1 possessesthe following optimum-preserving property: for each 1 ≤ i ≤ n – 1,

Proof: Since the Generalized Principle of Optimality is assumed to be true,

Therefore, by associativity and the distributive law over θ1 of θ2, it follows that

The proof of the other identity is similar and is omitted.

We conclude with the following conjecture.

Conjecture 7.4.1. In the system (W, G; θ1, θ2), the Generalized Principle of Op-timality holds iff there is an ordering relation ≤ on W such that

(i) for any x, y ∈ W, one and only one of the following must be true:

(ii) the optimum option θ1 is defined by θ1 = superior or θ1 = inferior underthe ordering relation ≤

(iii) the ordering relation ≤ and the relation θ2 are consistent. That is, x ≤ y iffxθ2w ≤ y θ2w and w θ2x ≤ w θ2y for any w ∈ W.

Page 151: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 143

7.5. Generalization of Fundamental Equations

In the previous two sections, Bellman’s Principle of Optimality has beengeneralized and three necessary conditions given. However, one should keep inmind that the optimum principle only states a property of the optimum policy, whilethe fundamental equation approach offers an effective method for one to obtainthe desired optimal policy. In this section, a sufficient condition and two necessaryconditions are established under which the fundamental equation approach holds.That is, under the conditions, the weight computed from the fundamental equationequals that of a global optimum. The presentation here is based on Shouzhi Wuand Xuemou Wu (1986).

For a given system (W, G; θ1 , θ2), defined in the same way as in the previoussection, for any g ∈ W ↑ G2 , a natural number n, and a , b ∈ G , the followingfunctional equations are called a fundamental equation on (g; n , a , b ), or simply afundamental equation:

(7.9)

for 2 ≤ m ≤ n. Here, the mappings θ1 and θ2 express the recursiveness of operation,which in turn shows that Eq. (7.9) is a generalization of the fundamental equationsin dynamic programming (Bellman, 1957).

Theorem 7.5.1 [Wu and Wu (1986)]. In the system (W, G ; θ1 , θ2), if θ1 satisfiesthe optimum-preserving law, and θ2 the associative and distributive laws over θ1,then for any and a, b ∈ G , the following is true:

Proof: For any and a, b ∈ G , mathematical induction willbe used on the index m to show that

When m = 1, it is obvious that

Suppose that for some and any a and b ∈ G. Itis now sufficient to show that Since θ2 satisfies theassociative and distributive laws, for any x ∈ G, one has

Page 152: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

144 Chapter 7

Therefore,

Claim. If θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law, then for anyand a and b ∈ G, the following equation holds:

1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law and the ClaimNow the assumption that θguarantee that

Thus,

which is what we desired.To finish the proof of the theorem, let us see why the claim is true.Proof of claim: First note that for any x1 ∈ G , the following is true:

Therefore, for any x1 ∈ G, one has

Hence, it follows that

(7.10)

Assume that for some c1 , c2 , . . . ,cn–1 ∈ G. Since

and

Page 153: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 145

and θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law, it follows that

This equation implies at once that

(7.11)

Now, Eqs. (7.10) and (7.11) and the assumption that θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law imply that

This ends the proof of the theorem.

The following results show that the conditions in Theorem 7.5.1 are alsonecessary.

Theorem 7.5.2 [Wu and Wu (1986)]. In the system (W, G ; θ1 , θ2) with θ1 satis-fying the optimum-preserving law and θ2 satisfying the associative law, if for any

and a, b ∈ G, it is true that

then θ2 possesses the following distribution over θ1 : for any gand a, b ∈ G,

Proof: For any and a, b ∈ G, and since θ1 satisfies theoptimum-preserving law, from the Claim it follows that

From the assumption that θ2 satisfies the associative law, it follows that

Therefore,

(7.12)

Page 154: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

146 Chapter 7

Now, from the assumption that for any and a, b ∈ G , thefollowing is true: Thus,

(7.13)

By Eqs. (7.12) and (7.13), it finally follows that

This ends the proof of the theorem.

Theorem 7.5.3 [Wu and Wu (1986)]. In the system (W, G ; θ1 , θ2) with θ2 satis-fying the associative law and the distributive law over θ1 , if for any g ∈ W ↑ G2,

and a, b ∈ G, it is true that

then θ1 possesses the following optimum-preserving property: for any g ∈ W ↑and a and b ∈ G , the following is true:

Proof: Since for any and a, b ∈ G , it is true that and θ2 satisfies the associative law and the distributive law over θ1 , it

then follows that

as desired.

Page 155: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 147

7.6. Operation Epitome Principle

Define a mapping so that the following conditions are satis-fied:

This section presents a different approach to systems analysis, which is due toQin (1991). With this approach, Bellman’s Principle of Optimality once again isgeneralized. The generalized result is called the “operation epitome principle.”

For an N -stage sequential decision process, let Xi be the set of all states ofthe ith stage, i = 0, 1, 2, . . . , N , where X0 , X1 , . . . , XN are some fixed sets. Let

and definea binary relation g ⊆ W 2 by the following: for any x, y ∈ W 2, (x,y) ∈ g iff x ≤ y.Further, hi j : E i × Xj → W is the gain (function) of decisions. Intuitively speaking,the set E consists of all available policies, and the set W is made up of all the criteriaused in the decision-making process. The binary relation g ⊆ W 2 establishes thecomparison between criteria.

(1) F (w) = w for each w ∈ W.

(2) For each (w1 , w2 , . . . ,wi ) ∈ W i , i ≤ N , and 1 ≤ k ≤ i,

(3) For each fixed w ∈ W, the mappings F ( · , w) and F(w, · ) : W → W arestrictly order-preserving. That is, for any x , y ∈ W, x < y iffF (x, w) < F (y, w), and x < y iff F (w, x) < F (w , y).

For example, it can be shown that the addition operation of real numbers canbe the mapping F. In addition, if W contains all positive real numbers, then themultiplication operation can also be the mapping F.

The gain of the policy e1 – N = (e1 , e2 , . . . , eN ) ∈ E is measured by the functionƒ : E → W, defined by

For a subpolicy of with initial statexi ∈ Xi and terminal state xj ∈ Xj , the gain of ei –j is defined as follows:

and

Page 156: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

148 Chapter 7

Now, for each policy e ∈ E , the stationary set (of the policy e) is defined

Theorem 7.6.1 [Bellman’s Principle of Optimality]. For any policy e1 – N =(e1 , e2, . . . , eN ) ∈ E, if the equation STY(e1– N) = holds in the system (W,E;ƒ,g),then for any natural numbers i and j satisfying 0 ≤ i ≤ j ≤ N, the subpolicyei–j = (ei , ei +1 , . . . , ej) of the policy e1 – N satisfies the condition that the equationSTY(ei – j ) = holds in the system (W, Ei – j ;ƒ, g).

If STY(e) = , then ƒ(e) is called a generalized extreme value of ƒ(E). Then,Bellman’s Principle of Optimality can be written as follows.

To prove this new version of Bellman’s principle, we first formalize the previousdiscussion.

Consider the system (W , E;ƒ, g) such that E and W are nonempty sets, ƒ :E → W is a mapping and g ⊆ W 2 is a binary relation. This system is called theoptimization model of the general systems. The set W consists of all the criteriaused in an optimization problem of interest, and E is the set of all possible policies.These sets are called the criteria set and the policy set of (W, E : ƒ , g), respectively.Intuitively speaking, for each chosen criterion e ∈ E, there exists exactly one policyw ∈ W and the rule matching the criterion e with the policy w is described by thefunction ƒ : E → W. The binary relation g ⊆ W 2 defines how to compare criteriaused.

For any subset X ⊆ W , define

If X = ƒ (E) and w ∈ X – g * X , then there exists at least one x ∈ X = ƒ (E) suchthat x ≠ w and (w, x) ∈ g. Let e ∈ E be such that w = ƒ (e) ∈ ƒ (E) – g * ƒ(E) .Then the element w ∈ W is called a generalized extreme value of the set X = ƒ(E),and the element e ∈ E is a generalized optimal solution (or policy) of the model(W , E ;ƒ , g).

g * X = {w ∈ X : for anyx ∈ X , x ≠ w implies (w, x) ∉ g}

Lemma 7.6.1 [Qin (1991)]. If X ⊆ W is a nonempty subset, then

where I is the diagonal of the Cartesian product X2, defined by I = {(x, x) : x ∈ X }.

Proof: For each element w ∈ g * X, by the definition of g * X it follows that,for any x ∈ X , if x ≠ w , then (w, x) ∉ g. That is, w ∈ X and w ∈ (g I )(w ) =

(7.14)

Page 157: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 149

and x ≠ w, then x ∈ g (w). That is, (W , x) ∈ g ,contradiction. So, This proves that

Conversely, if for then for any x ∈ X , x ≠ w mustimply (w,x) ∉ g , since otherwise, which is impossib1e.

Now, for each policy e ∈ E the stationary set (of the policy e) is defined

If STY(e) = , then ƒ(e) is called a generalized extreme value of ƒ(E); that is,

ƒ(e) ∈ g * ƒ (E).A mapping F : X → W , where X ⊂ W, is called strictly order-preserving if the

following property holds: for any x,y ∈ X ,

F(x) ≠ F (y), (F(x),F(y)) ∈ g if and only if x ≠ y , (x,y) ∈ g

Theorem 7.6.2 [Operation Epitome Principle (Qin, 1991)]. Let W and E =E 1 × E2 be nonempty sets, g ⊆ E2 a binary relation, and hi : E i → W , i = 1,2,mappings. If a mapping satisfies

(i) F(w) = w, for each w ∈ W.

(ii) For each fixed w, the mappings F(w,·) and F(·, w) : W → W are strictlyorder-preserving, then a mapping can be defined by

and i = 1, 2

for each e = (e1 , e2 ) ∈ E such that

where X is the cardinality of the set X.

Proof: For any e' ∈ E 2, define the mapping p1 : E 1 → E , which depends onfixed e', by

p1 (e1 ) = (e1 ,e' ) for each e1 ∈ E1

For any e' ∈ E1 define the mapping p 2 : E 2 → E, which depends on fixed e', by

p2 (e2 ) = (e',e2 ) for each e2 ∈ E2

Page 158: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

150 Chapter 7

Now the desired mapping is induced by

and

Since the mapping is strictly order-preserving, one has that, foreach

(7.15)

On the other hand, it is easy to see that

(7.16)

Equations (7.15) and (7.16) imply the desired inequality.

Now, Bellman’s Principle of Optimality (Theorem 7.6.1) is clear.

7.7. Fundamental Equations of Generalized Systems

For an optimization model (W, E;ƒ, g) of general systems and a natural numbern ∈ N , the relation gn ⊆ W 2 is defined

A binary relation g ⊆ W 2 is strongly antisymmetric (Qin, 1991), if for anynatural numbers m, n ∈ there do not exist distinct elements x,y ∈ W such thatthe conditions (x ,y) ∈ g m and (y,x) ∈ gn hold simultaneously. A binary relationg ⊆ W 2 is strictly strongly antisymmetric (Qin, 1991), if there is no infinitesequence such that i i +1w ≠ w and (wi , wi+ 1) ∈ g for each i = 0, 1, 2, . . .

It can be seen that the concept of strong antisymmetry is a generalization ofthe concept of partial ordering relations. To this end, recall that a relation g ⊆ W 2

is called a partial ordering (Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976), if the followingconditions are satisfied:

(i) (Antireflexivity) (x,x) ∉ g for any x ∈ W.

(ii) (Antisymmetry) If (x,y) ∈ g and x ≠ y , then (y, x) ∉ g for x ,y ∈ W.

(iii) (Transitivity) If (x,y) and (y,z) ∈ g , then (x, z) ∈ g for x ,y,z ∈ g.

Page 159: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 151

First, if a relation g ⊆ W 2 is a partial ordering, g must be strongly antisymmetric.Suppose that this statement is not true. That is, the relation g ⊆ W 2 is a partialordering but not a strongly antisymmetric relation. Hence, there exist w1 , w2 ∈ Wsuch that w1 ≠ w 2, and natural numbers m, n ∈ such that and

From the transitivity of g, it follows thatand w1 ≠ w 2 . This last condition contradicts the antisymmetry of g. Second, thefollowing example shows that a strongly antisymmetric relation g ⊆ W2 may notbe a partial ordering relation.

Example 7.7.1. Let W = and for any a, b ∈ W , (a, b) ∈ g ⊆ W 2, iff b + 1 >a > b. It can be shown that (a, b) ∈ gm, for m ∈ iff b + m ≥ b + 1 > a > b ;and that (b,a ) ∈ gn , for n ∈ iff a + m ≥ a + 1 > b > a. Therefore, g is stronglyantisymmetric. However, it is not a partial ordering relation on W , since thetransitivity relation is not satisfied.

Theorem 7.7.1 [Qin (1991)]. If a set W is finite, then a binary relation g ⊆ W2

is strictly strongly antisymmetric iff the relation g is strongly antisymmetric.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose that g ⊆ W 2 is strictly strongly antisymmetric butnot strongly antisymmetric. From the definition of strong antisymmetry it followsthat there exist w1 , w 2 ∈ W and m , n ∈ such thatand Thus, there exist elements w1i , i = 1, . . . , m – 1, and w 2j ,

j = 1, 2 , . . . , n – 1, such that

and

That is, there exists a finite sequence such thatxi ≠ xi + 1, for i = 1, 2 , . . . , m + n–1 and (xi ,xi + 1) ∈ g, for i =1, 2, . . . , m + n–1Now an infinite sequence can be defined as follows:

and

It is easy to observe that yi ≠ y i +1 and (yi,y i + 1) ∈ g for each i ∈ whichcontradicts the assumption that g is strictly strongly antisymmetric.

Sufficiency. Suppose W is finite and g ⊆ W 2 is strongly antisymmetric. As-sume that g ⊆ W 2 is not strictly strongly antisymmetric. There then exists aninfinite sequence such that yi -1 ≠ yi and (yi –1 , yi ) ∈ g for each i ∈

Page 160: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

152 Chapter 7

It is true that the sequence satisfies the condition that if(y q , y p) ∈ g , then p > q. If not, then q ≥ p. Hence, there exists a subsequence

such that

Now take the finite sequence w0 , w1 , w 2 , . . . , w n , for n = q – p + 1, such thatwk = y k + p, if 0 < k < n – 1 and wn = y p . It can be seen that (wi– 1, w i ) ∈ g,for i = 1, 2 , . . . , n , and w0 = wn , which contradicts the fact that g is stronglyantisymmetric. Therefore, p > q.

To complete the proof, we show that the elements differ fromone another, contradicting that W is finite. The contradiction thus implies thatg ⊆ W 2 must be strictly strongly antisymmetric. To this end, suppose that theelements of do not differ. There then exist p, q ∈ such that p < q ,yp = y q , and (yp , yp +1 ) ∈ g. Hence, ( yq, yp+1) ∈ g so that q < p + 1; i.e., q ≤ p,contradicting the fact that p < q. Therefore, is an infinite set, whichcontradicts the assumption. This ends the proof of the theorem.

The proof of the previous theorem actually says that strictly strong antisym-metry implies strong antisymmetry, and that when the set W is finite the converseimplication is also true.

Question 7.7.1. Construct an example to show that the concept of strong antisym-metry is different from that of strictly strong symmetry.

For any subset X ⊆ E, define

and

W* = g * W

(7.17)

(7.18)

Lemma 7.7.1 [Qin (1991)]. For any

Proof: For any there exists such that w = ƒ(e). Equation(7.17) implies that based on which Eq. (7.14) implies thatw = ƒ (e) ∈ ƒ (E1 ) and that for any x ∈ ƒ (E1 ), x ≠ w implies (w,x) ∉ g. Thelast condition means that Therefore, we have shown that

Conversely, for any Eq.(7.14) implies that forsome e ∈ E l, and that for any implies (w,x) ∉ g. This conditionimplies that That is, we have shown that

Page 161: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 153

Lemma 7.7.2 [Qin (1991)]. For any element x ∈ W and subset X ⊆ W, define asubset X(x) ⊆ W by

Then

where I is the diagonal of the Cartesian product X², defined by I = {(x, x) : x ∈ X }.

Proof: For each w ∈ g *X(x), w ∈ (g ∪ I) (x) and for any w' ∈ X (x), w' ≠ w,(w, w') ∉ g. To show that w ∈ ( g * X ) ∩ (g ∪ I)(x), one need only prove thatw ∈ g * X. If w ∉ g * X, there exists w" ∈ X such that w ≠ w" and ( w, w") ∈ g ;i.e., w" ∈ X (x). Therefore, there exists w" ∈ X (x) such that (w, w") ∈ g, whichcontradicts w ∈ g *X (x), so w ∈ g * X. Thus, we have obtained that

Conversely, for an element w ∈ (g * X ) ∩ ((g ∪ I) (x)), w ∈ g * X and w ∈(g ∪ I)(x). It follows that w ∈ X, w ∈ (g ∪ I)(x), and that for any y ∈ (g ∪ I) (x ),w ≠ y implies y ∉ X. It is clear that

Therefore, for any y ∈ (g ∪ I)(x), y ≠ w implies y ∉ X. Hence, w =X ∩ (g ∪ I) (w );i.e., w ∈ g * X (x). The following inclusion relation is thus true:

Lemma 7.7.3 [Qin (1991)]. If g is a strictly strongly antisymmetric relation onthe set W, and Ø ≠ X ⊆ W, then

g * X ≠ Ø

Proof: The proof is by contradiction. Assume that there exists a subsetØ ≠ X ⊆ W such that g * X = Ø, and let x ∈ X, then x ∉ g * X = Ø. From Eq. (7.14)it follows that there exists x1 ∈ X such that x ≠ x 1 , (x, x1) ∈ g, and x 1 ∉ g *X ,that there exists x2 ∈ X such that x1 ≠ x2 , (x1, x2 ) ∈ g, and x 2 ∉ g * X, and soon. Therefore, an infinite sequence x1 , x2, x 3, . . . has been obtained, satisfying(xi , xi + 1 ) ∈ g, for each i = 1, 2, 3, . . . This condition contradicts the assumption gis strictly strong antisymmetric. Thus, the proof is complete. �

Page 162: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

154 Chapter 7

Theorem 7.7.2 [Qin (1991)]. Let g be a strictly strongly antisymmetric relationon the set W, and G ⊆ p(W), the power set of W. Then

Proof: For an element it follows from Lemma 7.6.1 that

Partition the subset such that andsatisfying, for any X ∈ G1 and Y ∈ G 2 ,

and

Therefore, for any X ∈ G1, w ∈ g * X, and for any w ≠ y ∈ g (w), one has thaty ∈ X. Hence y ∉ g * X. That is,

On the other hand, for any it can be seen that for anyand so y ∉ g * Y. That is, for any Y ∈ G 2 ,

Thus,

which implies that It has thus been shown that

(7.19)

Conversely, for an element

Partition the set such that and satisfying,for any X ∈ G1, and Y ∈ G 2,

and

Page 163: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 155

Hence, for any X ∈ G l , w ∈ g * X ; i.e., It follows fromLemmas 7.7.1 and 7.7.3 that for any Y ∈ G2 ,

Then one obtains that which in turn implies thatThat is,

(7.20)

Combining Eqs. (7.19) and (7.20), proved the theorem. �

Theorem 7.7.3 [Qin (1991)]. In the optimization model (W, E; ƒ, g ) of generalsystems, if F : W → W is a strictly order-preserving mapping and X is a subset ofW, then

Proof: For an element w ∈ F(g * X), there exists y ∈ g * X such that w =F(y) ∈ F(X) and such that for any z ≠ y, (y, Z ) ∈ g, so z ∉ X. It suffices to showthat there is no F(w2 ) ∉ F (X) satisfying w = F(w2 ) and F (w2 ) ≠ F (y), suchthat (F(y), F (w2 )) ∈ g. Suppose there is such an element F( w2 ) ∈ F (X). It thenfollows that (y, w) ∈ g and y ≠ w2, which contradicts the assumption that y ∈ g* Xand implies that w ∈ g * F(X). From the arbitrariness of the element w, it followsthat

Conversely, for any element w ∈ g * F(X), there exists an element y ∈ X suchthat w = F (y). It suffices to show that there is no z ∈ X such that z ≠ y and(y, z) ∈ g. Suppose this condition is not satisfied. Then from the strictly order-preserving properties of F, it follows that F(y) ≠ F (z) and (F(y), F (z)) ∈ g. Thiscontradicts the assumption that w ∈ g * F(X). Hence, y ∈ g * X ; i.e., w ∈ F (g *X ) .Again, the arbitrariness of the element w guarantees

Let W, X, and T be nonempty sets with g ⊆ W ² given. Define

A mapping ƒ : E → W is called p -resolving, if there exists a mapping F : W ∪ W² →W satisfying

Page 164: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

156 Chapter 7

(i) F (w ) = w for each w ∈ W.

(ii) For any

(iii) For any w ∈ W, the mappings F(w, ·) and F(·, w) : W → W are strictlyorder-preserving.

Theorem 7.7.4 [Qin (1991)]. If the optimization model (W,E;ƒ ,g ) of generalsystems satisfies

(i) for some given nonempty sets X and T,

(ii) ƒ : E → W is p-resolving,

(iii) and

then

(7.2 1)

Proof: It follows from Theorem 7.7.2 that

For fixed e1 ∈ E1 , it follows from Theorem 7.7.3 that

Therefore, Eq. (7.21) is valid. �

By Theorem 7.7.1 it follows that Theorem 7.7.4 holds with W strongly anti-symmetric if W is finite.

Let (W, E;ƒ ,g) be a given optimization model of general systems with the setsW and E nonempty. The optimal solutions of (W,E ;ƒ ,g) are called the zeroth-order optimization solutions of the system (W, E ;ƒ, g) . The first-order optimizationsolutions of the system (W, E;ƒ ,g) are the optimal solutions of the subsystem of(W,E;ƒ,g ) obtained by removing all zeroth-order optimization solutions fromthe original system (W,E ;ƒ ,g). Inductively, the nth-order optimization solutions

Page 165: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 157

of (W , E;ƒ,g) are the optimal solutions of the subsystem obtained by removingall zeroth-order, first-order, . . . , (n – 1)st-order optimization solutions from theoriginal system (W , E;ƒ,g). If e ∈ E is an n th-order optimization solution of( W,E ; ƒ ,g), the number n, which is a function of the optimization solution e andis denoted by n = Oo (e), is called the optimization order of the solution e.

Define

W0 = W and Wi = W i – 1 – W * for each i ∈i – 1

Each element e ∈ W *i is called an ith-order generalized extreme value of W.

Theorem 7.7.5 [Qin (1988)]. If the optimization model (W,E;ƒ,g) of generalsystems satisfies the conditions

(i) W and E are nonempty,

(ii) ƒ : E → W is p-resolving; and

(iii) g ⊆ W 2 is strongly antisymmetric,

then the sum of the optimization orders of all subpolicies is less than or equal tothe optimization order of the policy itself.

The proof is left to the reader.

7.8. Applications

(i) In Hu’s counterexample it can be shown that θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law, and that θ2 is associative but not distributive over θ1. Therefore,Theorem 7.4.2 says that Bellman’s Principle of Optimality does not hold. At thesame time, by Theorem 7.5.2, it follows that the fundamental equations will notgive the global optimum solution. For details one has that

with A → B 1 → C → D1 → E its policy, and

with A → B 2 → C → D2 → E the global optimum policy. Here,

(ii) Consider the network in Fig. 7.2. Let θ1 = maximum and θ2 = ∧ . That is,for any x,y ∈ W, θ2 (x,y ) = min{x ,y}. Then A → B1 → C 2 → D is an optimum

Page 166: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

158 Chapter 7

Figure 7.2. The principle of optimality does not hold.

path with weight 2, but its subpath B1 → C2 → D is not optimum, since its weightis 3 and the weight of B1 → C 1 → D is 2. It can be shown that θ2 is associativebut does not satisfy a cancellation property. From Theorem 7.4.1 it follows thatthe Generalized Principle does not hold in this case.

(iii) Consider the network in Fig. 7.2 again with θ1 = subminimum and θ2 = +.That is, θ2 is the regular addition, and θ1 is defined as

θ1 (X ) = min{ X – {min{ X}}}

= the second minimum in X

for each X ∈ p (W) with X > 1. Then A → B1 → C l → D is the optimum pathwith weight 6, while its subpolicy B1 → C1 → D with weight 4 is not optimum. Itcan be seen that θ2 is associative and distributive over θ1 , but θ1 does not possessan optimum-preserving property. For example,

(iv) For a sequential decision process, the system (W,G; θ1, θ2 ) can be definedas follows:

W = set of all possible weights

θ1 = optimum choice rule

θ2 = operation between weights

G = the set of all states of the process

Define a network g ∈ W ↑ G 2 such that, for any x, y ∈ G, g (x,y ) = w iff the cost(or profit) from the state x to the state y is w. If a state y is not accessible from astate x, then define g(x,y) = the zero element in W. If the process has n stages,a0 is the initial state and an is the terminal state. Then g ⟨n ⟩ (a 0 , a n ) is simply thecost (or profit) of a global optimum decision. If

Page 167: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 159

then a0 ,a 1, . . . , a n is the optimum sequential decision required. For a subpolicyai , ai + 1 , . . . , a j , where 0 ≤ i < j ≤ n, the Generalized Principle of Optimality saysthat if θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law and θ2 satisfies the associative,cancellation, and distributive laws over θ1 , then a i , a i + 1 , . . . , a j must be optimumwith regard to the initial state ai and the terminal state aj .

In the shortest-path, inventory, and traveling-salesman problems (Dreyfusand Law, 1977), the system considered is ( min, +). In the equipment-replacement models and the resource allocation problems (Dreyfus and Law, 1977),the system of interest is ( max, +). It can be shown that ( min, +) and( max, +) satisfy the Generalized Principle of Optimality (Theorem 7.3.1).Thus, Bellman’s Principle of Optimality holds in these optimization problems,and can be solved by dynamic programming. At the same time, it can be shownthat “min” and “max” satisfy the optimum-preserving law and that “+” satisfiesthe cancellation, associative, and distributive laws (over “min” or “max”). Thus,Theorem 7.5.1 says that in ( min, +) and ( max, +) the desired optimumsolutions can be obtained by applying fundamental equations.

The following propositions and theorem reveal the relation between the fun-damental equation approach and the generalized principle of optimality.

For convenience, a system (W,G;θ1 , θ 2 ), as defined in Section 7.3, is re-cursive if for any g ∈ W ↑ G 2 , n ∈ , andThat is, being recursive is equivalent to having the fundamental equation ap-proach hold. The system (W,G ; θ1 , θ2) satisfies the optimum-preserving law iffor any g ∈ W ↑ G 2 , n ∈ , and a0 , a 1 , . . . , a n ∈ G, the following is true: if

the zero element of W, then for any 0 ≤ i ≤ j ≤ n,Intuitively speaking, (W, G; θ1 , θ2 ) satisfies the

optimum-preserving law means that the generalized principle of optimality holds.

Proposition 7.8.1 [Wu and Wu (1986)]. The recursiveness of the system(W, G ; θ1 , θ2) does not imply that it satisfies the optimum-preserving law.

Proof: It suffices to construct an example to show that a recursive system( W, G; θ1, θ2 ) does not satisfy the optimum-preserving law. Let W is the set of allnonnegative real numbers, G be a subset of real numbers, θ1 is the maximum, andθ2 is the minimum. It is evident that θ1 satisfies the optimum-preserving law andθ2 satisfies the associative and distributive laws over θ1 . So, according to Theorem7.5.1, (W, G ; θ1,θ2 ) is recursive, but it does not satisfy the optimum-preservinglaw. See the network in Fig. 7.2. �

Proposition 7.8.2 [Wu and Wu (1986)]. The optimum-preserving property of thesystem (W,G ; θ1, θ2 ) does not imply the recursiveness of the system.

Page 168: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

160 Chapter 7

Figure 7.3. Optimum-preserving law does not imply recursiveness.

Proof: Again, it suffices to show the proposition by constructing a counterex-ample. Consider the system (W,G ; θ1, θ2 ), (Fig. 7.3), where

W = the set of all nonnegative real numbers

θ1(X ) = { subminimum of X if X > 1 if X = {w}w

θ2 = + (regular addition)

Then it can be seen that the element g ∈ W ↑ G 2 (Fig. 7.3) satisfies g ⟨3⟩ (A,D ) = 4and A → B 1 → C 1 → D and is the optimum policy, of which all subpoliciesare optimum. That is, the system possesses a (g ;3,A,D ) optimum-preservingproperty. However, from the fundamental equation [Eq. (7.9)], it can be computedthat

ƒ ⟨3⟩ (A,D ) = 5

with A → B2 → C2 → D its corresponding policy. Since

the system does not possess (g ;3, A,D )-recursiveness. �

Theorem 7.8.1 [Wu and Wu (1986)]. In the system (W,G; θ1, θ2) with θ1 satis-fying the optimum-preserving law and θ2 satisfying the cancellation, associative,and distributive laws over θ1 both the optimum-preserving law and the recursivelaw hold. That is, in this special system the fundamental equation will give aglobal optimum solution, and the generalized principle of optimality holds.

The result is a consequence of Theorems 7.5.1 and 7.3.1.

Page 169: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality and Its Generalizations 161

7.9. Conclusion

This chapter generalizes the fundamental idea of dynamic programming to thewidest sense available today in the research of systems science and pansystemsanalysis. For example, the first approach generalized the ideas of Bellman’sPrinciple of Optimality and of the fundamental equations in dynamic programmingto generalized weighted networks, where for any nonempty sets W and G eachelement g ∈ W ↑ G 2 is called a generalized weighted network with weights in Wand nodes in G. The second approach will surely open up a new era of research tostudy the idea of optimization in the theory of general systems.

In addition to the set of real numbers being used as the criteria set, gen-eralized dynamic programming assume all other possible sets as criteria sets,such as vectors, matrices, tensors, and so on. Actually, there have appearedsome studies and applications of vector-valued dynamic programming (Brownand Strauch, 1965; Furukawa, 1980; Denardo, 1967; Henig, 1983). In theseworks, Bellman’s Principle of Optimality in the dynamic vector-valued modelshas also been discussed and similar results obtained. These facts are helpful inshowing the universal significance of the approaches presented in this chapter.

Bellman’s Principle of Optimality has been generalized to the GeneralizedPrinciple of Optimality and the Operation Epitome Principle. It may be expectedthat in dealing with optimization problems of the most general sense, especiallywith those out of the ordinary, the Generalized Principle of Optimality and theOperation Epitome Principle will play important roles.

Practically, the main point of dynamic programming is to use the fundamentalequations to compute a desired optimal solution. However, in many practical op-timization problems, especially those with nonscalar-valued performance criteria,their underlying structure of systems is much more complicated than ( min, +)and ( max, +). In those cases, the method of classical dynamic programmingmay not apply. In this chapter, a criterion has been established to decide whetherthe approach of fundamental equations can still be employed.

Page 170: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 8

Unreasonable Effectiveness ofMathematics: A New Tour

It is well known that the spectacular success of modern science and technology isdue in large measure to the use of mathematics in the establishment and analysisof models for the various phenomena of interest. The application of mathematicsbrings life to all scientific theories, dealing with real and practical problems. It ismathematics that makes us better understand the phenomena under consideration.Mickens (1990) asked why this is the case. In fact, many great thinkers hadthought of this question, when studying natural systems (Graniner, 1988). Inthis chapter, some problems related to the structure of mathematics, applicationsof mathematics and the origin of the universe are discussed. More specifically,in the first section, mathematics is compared with music, painting, and poetry.The structure of mathematics is studied in the second section. Then the structureof mathematics is written as a formal system in the third section. This newunderstanding is used to model and to analyze the states of materials and someepistemological problems in the fourth and fifth sections. In the sixth section avase puzzle is given to show that mathematical modeling can lead to contradictoryconclusions. Based on this fact, some impacts of the puzzle are mentioned. In theconcluding section, problems concerning the material structure of human thoughtand the origin of the universe are posed.

8.1. What Is Mathematics?

Mathematics is not only a rigorously developed scientific theory, but it is alsothe fashion center of modern science. The reason is that a theory is not considereda real scientific theory if it has not been written in the language and symbols ofmathematics, since such a theory does not have the capacity to predict the future.Indeed, no matter where we direct our vision — whether to the depths of outerspace, where we are looking for our “brothers,” to slides beneath microscopes,where we are trying to isolate the fundamental bricks of the world, or to the realm

163

Page 171: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

164 Chapter 8

of imagination where much human ignorance is comforted, etc., we can alwaysfind the track and language of mathematics.

All through history, many diligent plowers of the great scientific garden havecultivated today’s magnificent mathematical foliage. Mathematics is not like anyother theories in history, which have faded as time goes on and for which newfoundations and new fashions have had to be designed by coming generations inorder to study new problems. History and reality have repeatedly showed thatmathematical foliage is always young and flourishing.

Although mathematical abstraction has frightened many people, many unrec-ognized truths in mathematics have astonished truth pursuers by its sagacity. Infact, mathematics is a splendid abstractionism with the capacity to describe, in-vestigate and predict the world. First, let us see how some of the greatest thinkersin history have enjoyed the beauty of mathematics.

Philosopher Bertrand Russell (Moritz, 1942):

Mathematics, rightly viewed, possesses not only truth, but supreme beauty — abeauty cold and austere, like that of sculpture, without appeal to any part of ourweaker nature, without the gorgeous trappings of painting and music, yet sublimelypure, and capable of a true perfection such as only the greatest art can show. Thetrue spirit of delight, the exaltation, the sense of being more than man, which is

the touchstone of the highest excellence, is to be found in mathematics as surelyas in poetry. What is best in mathematics deserves not merely to be learned as atask, but to be assimilated as a part of daily thought, and brought again and againbefore the mind with ever-renewed encouragement. Real life is, to most men, along second-best, a perpetual compromise between the real and the possible; butthe world of pure reason knows no compromise, no practical limitations, no barrierto the creative activity embodying in splendid edifices the passionate aspirationafter the perfect from which all great work springs. Remote from human passions,remote even from the pitiful facts of nature, the generations have gradually createdan ordered cosmos, where pure thought can dwell as in its natural home, and where

one, at least, of our nobler impulses can escape from the dreary exile of the naturalworld.

Mathematician Henri Poincare (Moritz, 1942):

it [mathematics] ought to incite the philosopher to search into the notions of number,space, and time; and, above all, adepts find in mathematics delights analogous tothose that painting and music give. They admire the delicate harmony of numberand forms; they are amazed when a new discovery discloses for them an unlookedfor perspective; and the joy they thus experience, has it not the esthetic characteralthough the senses take no part in it? Only the privileged few are called to enjoyit fully, it is true; but is it not the same with all the noblest arts?

Organically arranged colors show us the beautiful landscape of nature sothat we more ardently love the land on which we were brought up. Animatedcombinations of musical notes sometimes bring us to somewhere between the skywith rolling black clouds and the ocean with roaring tides, and sometimes comfort

Page 172: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 165

You might ask: Because mathematics, according to the previous description, isso universally powerful, can it be used to study human society, human relations, andcommunication and transportation between cities? The answer to this question is“yes.” Even though the motivation for studying these kinds of problems appearedlong before Aristotle’s time, research along this line began not too long ago.Systems theory, one of the theories concerning these problems, was formallynamed in the second decade of this century, and the theoretical foundation beganto be set up in the sixth decade. It is still not known whether the theory caneventually depict and answer the aforementioned problems. However, it has beenused to explore some problems man has been studying since the beginning ofhistory, such as: (1) Does there exist eternal truth in the universe? (2) Doesthe universe consist of fundamental particles? Systems theorists have eliminated

How can colors be used to display atomic structures? How can musical notesbe used to imitate the association of stars in the universe? With mathematicalsymbols and abstract logic, the relationship between the stars and the attractionbetween an atomic nucleus and its electrons are written in detail in many books.

Colors can describe figures of nature, and musical notes can express fantasiesfrom the depths of the human mind. In the previous example, every one will agreethat the symbol “2” displays a figure of nature and insinuates the marrow of humanthought. By using intuitive pictures and logical deduction, it can be shown thatthe totality of even natural numbers and the totality of odd natural numbers havethe same number of elements. That is because any even natural number can bedenoted by 2n, and any odd natural number can be described by 2n + 1, where nis a natural number. Thus, for each natural number n, 2n and 2n + 1 can be puttogether to form a pair. With the help of this kind of reasoning and abstraction,the domain of human thought is enlarged from “finitude” into “infinitude,” justas human investigation about nature goes from daily life into the microcosm andouter space.

Let us see, for example, the concept of numbers. What is “2”? Consider twobooks and two apples. The objects, book and apple, are completely different.Nevertheless, the meaning of the concept “2” is the same. Notice that the symbol“2” manifests the same inherent law in different things — quantity. We know thatthere are the same amount of books and apples, because by pairing a book andan apple together, we get two pairs. Otherwise, for example, there are two applesand three books. After forming two pairs, each of which contains exactly oneapple and one book, there must be a book left. From this fact an ordering relationbetween the concepts of “2” and “3” can be expected.

us in a fragrant bouquet of flowers with singing birds. How does mathematicsdepict the world for us? Mathematics has neither color nor sound, but with itsspecial methods — numbers and forms — mathematics has been showing us thestructure of the surrounding world. It is because mathematics is the combinationof the marrow of human thought and aesthetics that it can be developed generationafter generation.

Page 173: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

166 Chapter 8

the traditional research method — dividing the object under consideration intobasic parts and processes, and studying each of them — and have begun to utilizesystems methods to study problems with many cause—effect chains. For instance,the famous three-body problem of the sun, the moon, and the earth, the combinationof vital basic particles, and social systems of human beings are examples of suchproblems.

Mathematics is analogous neither to painting, with its awesome blazing scenesof color, nor to music, which possesses intoxicatingly melodious sounds. Itresembles poetry, which is infiltrated with exclamations and admirations aboutnature, a thirst for knowledge of the future, and the pursuit of ideals. If youhave time to taste the flavor of mathematics meticulously, you will be attractedby the delicately arranged symbols to somewhere into mathematical depths. Eventhough gentle breezes have never carried any soft mathematical songs, man hasfirmly believed that mathematics shows truth since the first day it appeared. Thefollowing two poems by Shakespeare (Moritz, 1942) will give mathematics a bettershape in your mind.

1

Music and poetry used to quicken youThe mathematics, and the metaphysicsFall to them as you find your stomach serves youNo profit grows, where is no pleasure ta’en: —In brief, sir, study what you most affect

I do present you with a man of mineCunning in music and in mathematicsTo instruct her fully in those sciencesWhereof, I know, she is not ignorant.

2

8.2. The Construction of Mathematics

Analogous to paintings, which are based on a few colors, and to music, inwhich the most beautiful symphonies in the world can be written with a few basicnotes, the mathematical world has been constructed on a few basic names, axioms,and the logical language.

The logical language K used in mathematics can be defined as follows. K isa class of formulas, where a formula is an expression (or sentence) which maycontain (free) variables. Then K is defined by induction in the following manner,for details see (Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976; Kunen, 1980).

Page 174: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 167

(a)

(b)

(c)

(d)

Expressions of the forms given below belong to K :

x is a set, x ∈ y , x = y

as well as all expressions differing from them by a choice of variables,where the concept of “set” and the relation ∈ of membership are primitivenotations, which are the only undefined primitives in the mathematicsdeveloped in this section.

If φ and ψ belong to the class K , then so do the expressions ( φ or ψ), ( φand ψ ), (if φ, then ψ), (φ and ψ are equivalent), and not φ).

If φ belongs to K and v is any variable, then the expressions (for any v , φ )and (there exists v such that φ) belong to K.

Every element of K arises by a finite application of rules (a), (b), and (c).

The formulas in (a) are called atomic formulas. A well-known set of axioms,on which the whole classical mathematics can be built and which is called the ZFCaxiom system, contains the following axioms.

Axiom 1. (Extensionality) If the sets A and B have the same elements, thenthey are equal or identical.

(Empty set) There exists a set such that no x is an element of

(Unions) Let A be a set of sets. There exists a set S such that x is anelement of S if and only if x is an element of some set belonging toA. The set S is denoted by

(Power sets) For every set A there exists a set of sets, denoted byp(A), which contains exactly all the subsets of A.

(Infinity) There exists a set of sets A satisfying the conditions:∈ A ; if X ∈ A, then there exists an element Y ∈ A such that Y

consists exactly of all the elements of X and the set X itself.

(Choice) For every set A of disjoint nonempty sets, there exists a setB which has exactly one element in common with each setbelonging to A.

(Replacement for the formula φ) If for every x there exists exactlyone y such that φ(x , y) holds, then for every set A there exists a setB which contains those, and only those, elements y for which thecondition φ(x, y ) holds for some x ∈ A.

Axiom 2.

Axiom 3.

Axiom 4.

Axiom 5.

Axiom 6.

Axiom 7.

Page 175: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

168 Chapter 8

Axiom 8. (Regularity) If A is a nonempty set of sets, then there exists a set Xsuch that X ∈ A and X ∩ A = where X ∩ A means the commonpart of the sets X and A.

The following axioms can be deduced from Axioms 1–8.

Axiom 6.

Axiom 2. (Pairs) For arbitrary a and b, there exists a set X which containsonly a and b; the set X is denoted by X = {a , b}.

(Subsets for the formula ø) For any set A there exists a set whichcontains the elements of A satisfying the formula ø and whichcontains no other elements.

From Axioms 2 and 4, we can construct a sequence of sets as follows:

Now it can be readily checked that the sequence satisfies Peano’s axioms:

P 1. 0 is a number.

P2. The successor of any number is a number.

P3. No two numbers have the same successor.

P4. 0 is not the successor of any number.

P5. If P is a property such that (a) 0 has the property P, and (b) whenever anumber n has the property P, then the successor of n also has the propertyP, then every number has the property P.

In the construction of the sequence we understand the symbol 0 inP1 as the notations of “number” in P2 as any element in the sequence

and of “successor” in P2 as the power set of the number.The entire arithmetic of natural numbers can be derived from the Peano axiom

system. Axiom P5 embodies the principle of mathematical induction and illustratesin a very obvious manner the enforcement of a mathematical “truth” by stipulation.The construction of elementary arithmetic on Peano’s axiom system begins with

Page 176: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 169

the definition of the various natural numbers — that is, the construction of thesequence Because of P3 (in combination with P5), none of the elementsin will be led back to one of the numbers previously defined, and by P4,it does not lead back to 0 either.

As the next step, a definition of addition can be established, which expressesin a precise form the idea that the addition of any natural number to some givennumber may be considered as a repeated addition of 1; the latter operation is readilyexpressible by means of the successor relation (that is, the power set relation). Thisdefinition of addition goes as follows:

(8.1)

The two stipulations of this inductive definition completely determine the sum ofany two natural numbers.

Multiplication of natural numbers may be defined by the following recursivedefinition, which expresses in rigorous form the idea that a product nk of twonatural numbers may be considered as the sum of k terms, each of which equals n

(8.2)

In terms of addition and multiplication, the inverse operations (i.e., subtractionand division) can then be defined. However they cannot always be performed; i.e.,in contradistinction to addition and multiplication, subtraction and division are notdefined for every pair of numbers; for example, 7 – 10 and 7 ÷ 10 are undefined.This incompleteness of the definitions of subtraction and division suggests anenlargement of the number system by introducing negative and rational numbers.

Within the Peano system of arithmetic, its true propositions flow not merelyfrom the definition of the concepts involved but also from the axioms that governthese various concepts. If we call the axioms and definitions of an axiomatizedtheory the “stipulations” concerning the concepts of that theory, then we may nowsay that the propositions of the arithmetic of the natural numbers are true by virtueof the stipulations which have been laid down initially for the arithmetic concepts.

Consider the Cartesian product where is thecollection of all natural numbers, defined as before, which is a set by Axiom 5,and (n, m) is the ordered pair of the natural numbers n and m, which is definedbythat for any two ordered pairs (a, b), (c , d ) (a , b ) and ( c, d) belong to

Consider a subset Z of the power set such

the same set A in Z if and only if a + d = b + c. Then it can be seen that eachordered pair in is contained in exactly one element belonging to Z and notwo elements in Z have an element in common. Now, Z is the desired set on whichthe definition of subtraction of integers can be defined for each pair of elementsfrom Z, where the set Z is called a set of all integers, and each element in Z iscalled an integer. In fact, for each ordered pair (n, m) there exists exactlyone element A ∈ Z containing the pair ( n , m ). Thus, the element A can be denoted

Page 177: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

170 Chapter 8

by Then, addition, multiplication, and subtraction can be defined asfollows:

(8.3)

(8.4)

(8.5)

Remark. A well-known result discovered by Gödel shows that the afore-describedmathematics is an incomplete theory in the following sense. Even though allthose propositions in classical mathematics can indeed be derived, in the sensejust characterized, from ZFC, other propositions can be expressed in pure ZFClanguage which are true but which cannot be derived from the ZFC axioms. Thisfact does not, however, affect the results we have outlined because the mostunreasonably effective part of mathematics in applications is a substructure of themathematics we have constructed.

for any elements and in Z. It is important to note that the subsetZ + = ∈ Z : there exists a number x ∈ such that b + x = a} of Z nowserves as the set of natural numbers, because Z+ satisfies axioms P1–P5.

It is another remarkable fact that the rational numbers can be obtained from theZFC primitives by the honest toil of constructing explicit definitions for them, with-out introducing any new postulates or assumptions. Similarly, rational numbersare defined as classes of ordered pairs of integers from Z. The various arithmeticaloperations can then be defined with reference to these new types of numbers, andthe validity of all the arithmetical laws governing these operations can be provedfrom nothing more than Peano’s axioms and the definitions of various arithmeticalconcepts involved.

The much broader system thus obtained is still incomplete in the sense that notevery number in it has a square root, cube root, . . ., and more generally, not everyalgebraic equation whose coefficients are all numbers of the system has a solution inthe system. This suggests further expansions of the number system by introducingreal and complex numbers. Again, this enormous extension can be affected byonly definitions, without posing a single new axiom. On the basis thus obtained,the various arithmetical and algebraic operations can be defined for the numbers ofthe new system, the concepts of function, of limit, of derivatives and integral can beintroduced, and the familiar theorems pertaining to these concepts can be proved;thus, finally the huge system of mathematics as here delimited rests on the narrowbasis of the ZFC axioms: Every concept of mathematics can be defined by meansof the two primitives in ZFC, and every proposition of mathematics can be deducedfrom the ZFC axioms enriched by the definitions of the nonprimitive terms. Thesedeductions can be carried out, in most cases, by means of nothing more than theprinciples of formal logic, a remarkable achievement in systematizing the contentof mathematics and clarifying the foundations of its validity.

Page 178: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 171

8.3. Mathematics from the Viewpoint of Systems

Claim. If by a formal language we mean a language which does not containsentences with grammatical mistakes, then any formal language can be describedas a system.

Proof: Assume that L is a formal language; for convenience, suppose that Lis English which does not contain sentences with grammatical mistakes, where anEnglish grammar book B is chosen and rules in B are used as the measure to seeif an English sentence is in L or not.

Each word in L consists of a finite combination of letters, that is, a finitesequence of letters. Let X be the collection of all 26 letters in L. From thefiniteness of the collection X and Axiom 7, it follows that X is a set; otherwisethe natural number 26 is not a set (from the discussion in the previous section), soinstead of the collection X we can use the set 26. Let M be the totality of all finitesequences of elements from X. Then M is the union

Mathematically speaking, S is said to be a system (Lin, 1987) if and only if S isan ordered pair (M, R) of sets, where R is a set of some relations defined on the setM. Each element in M is called an object of S , and M and R are called the objectset and the relation set of S, respectively. In this definition, each relation r ∈ Ris defined as follows: There exists an ordinal number n = n(r), called the lengthof the relation r, such that r is a subset of Mn , where M n indicates the Cartesianproduct of n copies of M. Assume that the length of the empty relation is 0; i.e.,n =n = 0. In ordinary language, a system consists of a set of objects and acollection of relations between the objects.

The concept of systems was introduced formally by von Bertalanffy in the1920s according to the following understanding about the world: The world welive in is not a pile of uncountably many isolated “parts”; and any practical problemand natural phenomenon cannot be described perfectly by only one cause–effectchain. The basic character of the world is its organization and the connectionbetween the interior and exterior of different things. Customary investigationof the isolated parts and processes cannot provide a complete explanation of thevital phenomena. This kind of investigation gives us no information about thecoordination of parts and processes. Thus, the chief task of modern science shouldbe a systematic study of the world. For details see (von Bertalanffy, 1934).

Hence, M is a set which contains all words in L.

Page 179: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

172 Chapter 8

Each sentence in L consists of a finite combination of some elements in M ,i.e., a finite sequence of elements from M. If Q be the totality of finite sequencesof elements from M, then

Thus, Q is a set. Each element in Q is called a sentence of L.Write M as a union of finitely many subsets: where

J = {0,1,2,..., n} is a finite index set. Elements in M (0) are called nouns;elements in M(1) verbs; elements in M(2) adjectives, etc., Let K ⊂ Q be thecollection of all sentences in the grammar book B. Then K must be a finitecollection, and it follows from Axiom 7 that K is a set.

If each statement in K is assumed to be true, then the ordered pair ( M, K )constitutes the English L. Here, (M, K ) can be seen as a systems description ofthe formal language L.

Generally, what is the meaning of a system with contradictory relations, e.g.,as the relation set?

Let (M,K) be the systems representation of the formal language L in thepreceding proof, and T the collection of Axioms 1–6’ in the previous section.Then (M, T K) is a systems description of mathematics.

From Klir’s (1985) definition of systems — that a system is what is distin-guished as a system — and Claim 1, it follows that if a system S = (M ,R) isgiven, then each relation r ∈ R can be understood as an S -truth; i.e., the relationr is true among the objects in the set M. Therefore, any mathematical truth isa (M, T K)-truth; i.e., it is derivable from the ZFC axioms, the principles offormal logic, and definitions of some nonprimitive terms. From this discussionabout mathematical truths the following question is natural.

Question 8.3.1. If there existed two mathematical statements derivable from ZFCaxioms with contradictory meanings, would they still be (M , T K)-truths?

The following natural epistemological problem was asked in (Lin, 1989c).

Question 8.3.2. How can we know whether there exist contradictory relations ina given system?

From Klir’s definition of systems, it follows that generally, Questions 8.3.1and 8.3.2 cannot be answered. Concerning this, a theorem of Gödel shows that itis impossible to show whether the systems description (M, T K) of mathematicsis consistent (that is, any two statements derivable from ZFC will not have con-tradictory meanings) or not in ZFC. On the other hand, we still have not foundany method outside ZFC which can be used to show that the system ( M, T K) is

Page 180: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 173

inconsistent. This means that there are systems (for example, mathematics basedon ZFC) in which we do not know whether there exist propositions with contra-dictory meanings. Therefore, this fact implies that perhaps not every system isconsistent or that not every system has no contradictory relations.

The application of mathematics has showed us that mathematics is extremelyeffective in describing, solving, and predicting practical phenomena, problems, andfuture events, respectively. That means that in practice a subsystem of ( M,T ∪ K )can always be found to match a situation under consideration. For example, ahibiscus flower has five petals. The mathematical word “five” provides a certaindescription of the flower. This description serves to distinguish it from flowerswith three, four, six, . . ., petals. When a watch chain is suspended from its ends, itassumes very nearly the shape of the mathematical curve known as the catenary.The equation of the catenary is where a is a constant. Atthe same time, this equation can be used to predict (or, say, answer) the followingproblem: Suppose someone holds his 10-inch watch chain by its ends with hisfingers at the same height and are 4 inches apart. How far below his fingers willthe chain dip? Now, the following amazing question can be asked (this questionwas not originally posed by me).

Question 8.3.3. Why is mathematics so “unreasonably effective” when appliedto the analysis of natural systems?

In order to discuss this question, we must go back to Axioms 1–6’. As aconsequence of our discussion, the whole structure of mathematics might be saidto be true by virtue of mere definitions (namely, of the nonprimitive mathematicalterms) provided that the ZFC axioms are true. However, strictly speaking, wecannot, at this juncture, refer to the ZFC axioms as propositions which are true orfalse, for they contain free primitive terms, “set” and the relation of membership“ ∈ ,” which have not been assigned any specific meanings. All we can assert so faris that any specific interpretation of the primitives which satisfies the axioms —i.e.,turns them into true statements—will also satisfy all theorems deduced from them.For detailed discussion, see (Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976; Kunen, 1980).But the partial structure of mathematics developed on the basis of Peano’s axiomshas several — indeed infinitely many — interpretations which will turn Peano’saxioms, which contain the primitives “0,” “number,” and “successor,” into truestatements, and therefore, satisfy all the theorems deduced from them. (Notethat this partial structure of mathematics constitutes the theoretical foundation foralmost all successful applications of mathematics.) For example, let us understandby 0 the origin of a half-line, by the successor of a point on that half-line thepoint 1 inch behind it, counting from the origin, and by a number any pointwhich is either the origin or can be reached from it by a finite succession of stepseach of which leads from one point to its successor. It can then be readily seenthat all Peano’s axioms as well as the ensuing theorems turn into true propositions,

Page 181: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

174 Chapter 8

although the interpretation given to the primitives is certainly not any of those givenin the previous section. More generally, it can be shown that every progressionof elements of any kind provides a true interpretation of Peano’s axiom system.This example illustrates that mathematics permits many different interpretations,in everyday life as well as in the investigation of laws of the nature and from eachdifferent interpretation, we understand something more about the nature; and atthe same time, because of this fact, we feel that mathematics is so unreasonablyeffective as applied to the study of natural problems.

We will give two examples to show how abstract mathematical structuresdeveloped on the basis of the ZFC axioms but outside Peano’s axiom system canbe used to describe and study problems in materials science and epistemology.

8.4. A Description of the State of Materials

An arbitrarily chosen experimental material X can be described as a systemS x = ( Mx ,Rx ) as follows, where Mx is the set of all molecules in the material andR x contains the relations between the molecules in Mx, which describe the spatialstructure in which the molecules in the material are arranged. If X is crystalline,then all cells in X have the same molecular spatial structure. That means that themolecules in X are aligned spatially in a periodic order, so we have the following.

Definition 8.4.1. The experimental material X is crystalline if for the systemS x = (Mx, Rx ), there exists a relation ƒ ∈ Rx such that ƒ M* ≠ ƒ, for any propersubset M* of M x , and there exists a cover for the set Mx such that for anyA and B in there exists a one-to-one correspondence h : A → B satisfying

where ƒ Y indicates the restriction of the relation ƒ on the subsetY and for any ordinalnumber β and any

For example, if X is crystalline, for any unit cell Y in X define MY as the set ofall molecules contained in Y. Then x = { MY : Y is a unit cell in X} is a cover ofM x , because each molecule in X must belong to one of the unit cells, and all unitcells look the same. It therefore follows that the main characteristics of crystallinematerials are described by Definition 8.4.1.

Given a linearly ordered set W , a time system S over W is a function from Winto a family of systems; say S (w) = S w = (Mw ,Rw ) , for each w ∈ W , where eachsystem S w is called the state of the time system S at the moment w. If, in addition,a family of mappings is given such that for any r,s, andt ∈ W satisfying and

Page 182: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 175

where is the identity mapping on Mt , then S is called a linked time systemand denoted by Each is called a linkage mapping of the linkedtime system. For details; see (Ma and Lin, 1987).

Let be the set of all real numbers, RT (= ) indicate temperature and Rt =[0, +∞) and Rp = [0, + ∞) (the interval of real numbers from 0 to positive infinity)indicate time and pressure, respectively. Define an “order” relation “<” on theCartesian product as follows: For any

if and only if either (i) (ii) and y 1 > y 2,or (ii) and x1 < x 2 . Then it can be shown that < is a linear order.

We establish a systems theory model of crystallization process of the the mate-rial X. It is assumed that the size of molecules in X will not change as temperatureand pressure change; i.e., any chemical reaction between the molecules during theprocess will be neglected.

In the state of time t, temperature T, and pressure P, the relation set, consistingof all relations describing spatial structure of the molecules in X, is Fw, wherew = ( t, T, P ). Then at the state w, X can be described as a system (M, Fw ), where Mis the set of all molecules in X so that a linked time systemwhere id M : M → M is the identity mapping on M.

If X is going to crystallize as time goes on, pressure imposed on X goes up,and temperature goes down, there then is a state such that Xis crystalline. That means that the state of S satisfies the propertyin Definition 8.4.1.

The crystallization process of X is the process that X changes from an amor-phous state to an ordered state or a crystalline state. The process is divided intotwo steps. The first step is called nucleation; i.e., when temperature is lower thanthe melting temperature of the material, the activity of the molecules decreases,which means that the attraction or interaction between molecules increases, sothere would be a tendency for the molecules to get together to form a short-rangeorder. This kind of locally ordered region is called a nucleus. The second step iscalled growth. Although at certain temperature and pressure values, many nucleican be formed at the same time they will probably disintegrate because the ratioof the surface and the volume of each nucleus is still too great and the surfaceenergy is too high. However, as soon as the nuclei grow large enough, which iscaused by the fluctuation of local energy, their energy will be lower as more andmore molecules join them. The molecules in the nearby region would prefer tojoin those nuclei so that they will grow larger and larger.

Question 8.4.1. In the previous mathematical model, does there exist a relationƒ ∈ Rx satisfying the property in Definition 8.4.1 when the material X is actuallyin a melting state, where is the systems representation of X?

We assume that the answer to Question 8.4.1 is “yes.” This assumption isbased on

Page 183: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

176 Chapter 8

(i) A view of dialectical materialism—the internal movement of contradictionsdominates the development of the matter under consideration

(ii) The beauty of the systems theory model described earlier

Under this assumption, it can be seen that under certain ideal conditions anymaterial may crystallize, because the relation ƒ will be observable under certainideal conditions. Suppose Y is a cell in the crystalline material X. The spatialgeometric relation (called the structure of Y ) of the molecules in Y is termed thebasic structure of X.

Generalizing the model in (Lin and Qiu, 1987), the following is our modelfor the arbitrarily fixed material X: no matter what state X is in (solid, liquid,or gas), there exist many pairwise disjoint groups of molecules in X such thateach molecule in X is contained in exactly one of the groups, and every groupis “topologically” isomorphic to the basic structure of X. The basic structure ofthe material determines all the physical properties that X has. The meaning oftopologically isomorphic was explained in (Lin and Qiu, 1987) with examples.With this model many phenomena about materials can be explained naturally. Fordetails, see (Lin and Qiu, 1987).

8.5. Some Epistemological Problems

In the ZFC axiom system, the following results can be shown:

(1) There is no system whose object set consists of all systems.

(2) A system is an nth-level object system of a systemS 0 = (M0 ,R0), if there exist systems Si = (Mi ,Ri ), i =1,2, . . . , n – 1, suchthat S i ∈ Mi – 1, i = 1 , 2 , . . . , n. Then for any system S, there is no nth-levelobject system Sn of S such that Sn = S for any natural number n > 0.

(3) A sequence of systems, where n is an ordinal number, is said to bea chain of object systems of a given system S if S0 is an i0th-level objectsystem of S, and for any i,j ∈ n, if i < j, there exists a natural numberij > 0 such that Sj is an ij th-level object system of Si . Then for any fixedsystem S, each chain of object systems of S must be finite.

In (Lin, 1989c) the following epistemological problems were discussed: (i)the feasibility of the definition of the theory “science of science,” (ii) the existenceof fundamental particles in the world, and (iii) the existence of absolute truths.

The theory of science of science appeared in the 1930s. Since then more andmore scientists have been involved in its research. The background in which the

Page 184: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 177

theory appeared is that, since human society entered the twentieth century, thedevelopment of different aspects of science and technology have sped up. Thedevelopment of science shows a tendency to divide science into more and moredisciplines while synthesizing results and methods in different fields to get newresults and understanding about the world. Hence, a natural problem arose: Canscience be studied as a social phenomenon so that man can develop scientificresearch with purposes and improve its recognition of the natural world? Thisproblem is very important to administrators of scientific research, because so fareach scientific achievement is obtained by either individual scientists or smallgroups of scientists, Thus, there are many scientific achievements obtained in-dependently by many different scientists. If the answer to the aforementionedquestion is “yes,” then it partially means that we can save at least some valuablescientific labor from doing the same things by arranging them to do some pretar-geted research. In this way, the development of science will be sped up greatly.Some scientists think that the research object of the theory of science of scienceis the following: The theory of science of science is such a theory that instead ofany real matter it studies science as a whole, the history and the present situationof each discipline, the relationship between disciplines, and the whole developingtendency of science.

Combining Claim 1 and result (2), we can see that the theory of science ofscience cannot exist. Because, roughly speaking, the theory has to contain a studyof itself. For detailed discussion, see (Lin, 1989c).

From Klir’s (1985) definition of systems and result (1), it follows that wecannot consider a relation which is true in a system that contains all systems as itsobjects. Does this imply that there is no universal truth? I believe so. I think thatfor any given truth, an environmental system is given in which the truth is a truerelation.

Result (3) says that any system is built upon objects which are no longersystems. Does this imply that the world consists of fundamental particles, wherea fundamental particle is a particle which cannot be divided into smaller particles?See (Lin, 1989c) for details.

8.6. The Vase Puzzle and Its Contradictory MathematicalModelings

A conceptual problem, named the vase puzzle, is used to show that math-ematical modelings can lead to contradictory inferences. Around this puzzle,some questions, concerning proof methodology in mathematics and understandingmathematical induction arise, including in general, methodology, epistemology,philosophy, and modeling time and space. Some unsettled problems are left open.

Page 185: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

178 Chapter 8

8.6.1. The Vase Puzzle and its Modelings

The concept of infinity has been bothering mankind for centuries (Moore,1991). In mathematics, different meanings are given to the concept, (Davis, 1977;Halmos, 1960; Jech, 1973). Many of the greatest thinkers in history (Moore, 199l),have been convinced that infinity is something we will never be able to understandbecause there are so many seemingly unsolvable puzzles about it.

If a person were concerned only with problems in real life, he or she wouldsay that the concept of infinity had no interest. Unfortunately, it is no longer thecase. For example, the study of quality control of the products of an automaticassembly line needs the concept. Specifically to study quality, we draw a ran-dom sample of the products and use sample statistics to make inferences on thecontinuously expanding population, which is theoretically the collection of all theproducts that have been and will be produced from the assembly line. To makethe inferences more convincing, we often treat the ever-expanding population asan infinite population.

In this section a conceptual problem is constructed to show that mathemati-cal modeling does not always work. In other words, different models can givecontradictory results. This astonishing phenomenon forces us to rethink some prin-ciples and long-lasting questions in mathematical induction, mathematical proofs,methodology, epistemology, philosophy, etc. Even though the phenomenon hasbeen studied for some time, we still hope that this presentation will cast the firstbrick in order to attract many beautiful jades.

8.6.1.1. The vase puzzle. Suppose a vase and an infinite number of pieces ofpaper are available. The pieces of paper are labeled by natural numbers 1,2,3, . . . ,so that each piece has at most one label on it. The following recursive procedureis performed:

Step 1: Put the pieces of paper, labeled from 1 through 10, into the vase; thenremove the piece labeled 1.

Step n: Put the pieces of paper, labeled from 10n – 9 through 10n into thevase; then remove the piece labeled n, where n is any natural number 1,2,3, . . .

Question 8.6.1. After the recursive procedure is finished, how many pieces ofpaper are left in the vase ?

Some comments are necessary. First, the vase need not be infinitely large— actually any size will do. Second, the total area of the infinite number ofpieces of paper can also be any chosen size. For example, Fig. 8.1 shows howan infinite number of pieces of paper can be obtained. Third, number-labelingcan be done according to the steps in the puzzle. Finally, the recursive procedurecan be finished within any chosen period of time. For convenience, we write themathematical induction procedure, which guarantees that the vase puzzle is welldefined.

Page 186: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 179

Figure 8.1. Obtain as many pieces of paper as needed out of a chosen total area of pieces of paper.

8.6.1.2. Mathematical induction. See (Smith et al., 1990). Let S be a subsetof the set N of all natural numbers. If it can be shown that

• Initial step: 1 ∈ S.

• Inductive step: If n ∈ S , then n+ 1 ∈ S .

then the subset S equals the set N.To fit the recursive procedure in the vase puzzle into the format of mathematical

induction, let us define a subset S of natural numbers as follows:

S = {n : step n can be done and all pieces of paper with labels

1 through 10n have been in the vase at least once} (8.6)

It is left to the reader to verify that S is the same as N.

8.6.1.3. An elementary modeling. To answer the question of the vase puzzle,let us define a function, based upon mathematical induction, by

ƒ(n) = 9n (8.7)

Equation (8.7) really tells how many pieces of paper are left in the vase after stepn, where n = 1,2,3 , . . . . Therefore, if the recursive procedure can be finished,the number of pieces of paper left in the vase should equal the limit of ƒ(n ) as napproaches ∞. The answer is that infinitely many pieces of paper are left in thevase.

8.6.1.4. A set-theoretical modeling. Based upon this modeling, the answer tothe question of the vase puzzle is “no paper is left in the vase.” This contradictsthe conclusion, derived in the elementary modeling.

For each natural number n, define the set Mn of pieces of paper left in the vaseas follows:

Mn = {x: x has a label between n and 10n + 1 exclusively} (8.8)

Page 187: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

180 Chapter 8

Then after the recursive procedure is finished, the set of pieces of paper left in thevase equals the intersection

That is, if x is a piece of paper left in the vase, x then has a label greater than allnatural numbers. This contradicts the assumption that each piece of paper put intothe vase has a natural number label. Thus, is empty.

Lin, Ma, and Port (1990) pointed out theoretically that there must be animpassable chasm between pure mathematics and applied mathematics. Thereason is that pure mathematics is established on a set of axioms, say, the ZFCaxioms. The theory possesses a beauty analogous to painting, music, and poetry,and the harmony between numbers and figures [for details, see (Lin, 1990d)],while in applied mathematics each object of interest is always first given somemathematical meaning, and then conclusions are drawn based on the relations ofthose to the objects involved. It is the assignment of a mathematical meaning toeach object that causes problems, because different interpretations can be given tothe same object. As described in (Lin et al., 1990), some interpretations can resultin contradictory mathematical models. In this section we chose the vase puzzleto emphasize the existence of the impassable chasm, for the following reasons:(1) The example is easy to describe. (2) The two contradictory modelings arereadily comprehensible by readers with little background in mathematics. (3) Thecontradiction has very fruitful implications.

We give two more puzzles which will be relevant to forthcoming discussions.One concerns the structure of space, and the other concerns the concept of time.

Paradox [Paradox of the Hotel, (Moore, 1991)]. Suppose a hotel has infinitelymany rooms, each occupied at a particular time. Then a newcomer can be accom-modated without anybody having to move out; for if the person in the first roommoves to the second, and the person in the second room moves to the third, and soon ad infinitum, this will release the first room for the newcomer.

Hilbert used to present this paradox in his lectures. The hotel, by the way,need only occupy a finite amount of space. For if each successive floor is half theheight of the one below it, then the entire hotel will be only twice the height of theground floor. However, this raises the following question about the nature of theconcept of space.

Question 8.6.2 [Benardete (Moore, 1991)]. If the roof of the hotel were removed,what would a person looking at the hotel from above see?

Paradox [Paradox of a Moving Particle]. Suppose a particle moves from point0 to point 1 on the real number line. If at the half-minute the particle is at point1/2, at 3/4 minute it is at point 3/4, and in general, at (2 n – 1)/2n

particle is at point (2n – 1 )/2n, where will the particle be at 1 minute?

(8.9)

minute, the

Page 188: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 181

Figure 8.2. S is the area under ƒ (x ) between a and b.

Question 8.6.3. If another particle moves from point 2 to point 0 on the same realnumber line, which point of the sequence

(8.10)

should the particles meet first ?

8.6.2. "Experts" Explanations

The vase puzzle has been presented to a number of scholars with expertisein different areas over the years. We list two of the “explanations” given for thecontradictory mathematical modelings.

Explanation. The elementary modeling is incorrect because it does not use allknown information.

Explanation. There is no way to finish the recursive procedure in the puzzle.Therefore, the question in the puzzle is invalid.

8.6.3. Mathematical Proofs, Theory of Cardinal Numbers, and theVase Puzzle

Some well-known theories and proofs of theorems in mathematics are used toargue that if explanation 2 were logically correct, then a large portion of mathe-matics would be incorrect.

Problem [The Area Problem, (Stewart, 1987)]. Find the area of the region Sunder the curve y=ƒ(x ) from a to b. This means that S (see Fig. 8.2), is boundedby the graph of a function ƒ (where ƒ(x) ≥ 0), the vertical lines x = a and x = b ,and the x-axis.

Page 189: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

182 Chapter 8

Figure 8.3. Region S under graph of y = x ² from 0 to 1.

To solve this problem, we have to answer the question: What is the meaningof the word “area”? It is easy to answer this question for regions with straightsides. For a rectangle, area is defined as the product of length and width. The areaof a triangle is half the base times the height. The area of a polygon is found bydividing it into triangles. However, it is not so easy to find the area of a region withcurved sides. Theoretically, to find the area of a region S, we first approximate itby areas of polygons and then take the limit of the areas of these polygons. Tomake the method more specific, let us briefly go through an example.

Example 8.6.1. Find the area under the parabola y = x² from x = 0 to x = 1 (seeFig. 8.3).

Solution. Divide the interval [0, 1] into subintervals of equal length and considerthe rectangles whose bases are those subintervals and whose heights are the valuesof the function y = x ² at the right-hand endpoints of these subintervals. Fig-sures 8.4–8.6 show the approximation of the parabolic segment by 4, 8, and nrectangles.

Let Sn be the sum of the areas of the n rectangles in Fig. 8.6. Therefore,

Figure 8.4. Four-rectangle approximation of the area of the region S.

Page 190: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 183

Figure 8.5. Eight-rectangle approximation of the area of the region S.

(8.11)

From Figs. 8.4 to 8.6 it appears that as n increases Sn becomes a better and betterapproximation to the area of the parabolic segment. In calculus, the area A of theregion S can be found by taking the limit:

(8.12)

Now compare the idea applied in the area problem with that in the vase puzzledo we have similar recursive procedures? In solving the area problem, we computethe area Sn for n = 1,2,3, . . . ; after all Sn ’s are computed (based on mathematicalinduction we can do this), by taking the limit of the Sn ’s we get the value for thearea A of S. If Explanation 2 were correct, how could we finish computing theSn ’s? If we are not able to, we could not take the limit of the Sn 's, either. Somereaders may get confused here and do not see the similarity because the conceptof limit is involved.

Figure 8.6. n-rectangle approximation of the area of the region S.

Page 191: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

184 Chapter 8

Example 8.6.2 [Department of Mathematics (1978)]. When studying the con-cept of convergence of a sequence, we have a well-known theorem: Each boundedsequence of numbers must have a convergent subsequence. Let us look at theproof of the theorem.

Case 1: Suppose the bounded sequence is made up of a finite set ofnumbers. Then one of the numbers, say A, must appear repeatedly infinitely manytimes. If the locations that the number A appears are the n1st term, n2 nd term, . . .,then

(8.13)

is a subsequence of satisfying lim = A. Therefore, we have provedthat has a convergent subsequence.

Case 2: Suppose is made up of infinitely many numbers. Then theset E = is a bounded infinite set. By a theorem of Weierstrass(1815–1897), the set has at least one cluster point c. We now show that there mustexist a subsequence of which converges to c.

Since c is a cluster point of E , there must be a point in the set (c – 1, c + 1) ∩(E – {c}). Pick such a point y1 in the set. This point must appear in the sequence

at least once. Hence, there is an index n1 such that

(8.14)

In general, suppose we have found such thatSince the set

(E – {c}) contains infinitely many points and the sequence x 1 , x2 , . . . , xnk has onlynk terms, we can pick a point (E –{c}) such that According to mathematical induction, a subsequence

of is obtained such that xnk

Thus,

(8.15)

When k → ∞, 1/k → 0. Thus, lim = c .

Look at the proof here. If the subsequence can be obtained by mathe-matical induction, then the recursive procedure in the vase puzzle can analogouslybe finished. That is, if “there is no way to finish the procedure,” as posited inExplanation 2, the proof given must be incorrect. Some may argue that the proofabove is not the only one for the theorem. If so, let us look at the followingwell-known argument of Cantor.

Example 8.6.3 [Halmos (1960)]. One of the greatest proofs in set theory showsthe following amazing result: The set of all real numbers that are greater than zeroand smaller than 1 has greater cardinality than the set of all natural numbers.

Page 192: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 185

Proof: Obviously, the set and the set of all real numbers between 0 and1 are infinite sets. By contradiction, suppose That is, there exists aone-to-one correspondence ƒ : For any q ∈ let a n = q if ƒ(n) = q forsome n ∈ Thus, the elements in can be written as a sequence

(8.16)

Since each q ∈ satisfies 0 < q < 1, it is possible to write the elements in as

(8.17)

where each aij is a digit in the set W = {0,1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9}. Now let b be anumber with expression

(8.18)

such that each bk ∈ W and that for each m ∈ bm ≠ amm . That is, b ∈ and b isnot in the list (8.17). This contradicts the assumption that each element of is inthe list (8.17). Hence,

Even though this proof does not mention mathematical induction, the existenceof the number b does depend on the principle. To be more specific, the number bneeds to be constructed as follows:

Initial step: Define b1 being a number ∈ A – {a11 }.Inductive step: Suppose for n ∈ the bk ’s have been defined for all k < n.

Then let bn be a number ∈ A – {a nn}.By mathematical induction, for each natural number n a number bn can be

chosen. If this inductive process “can be finished,” the desired number b can beconstructed in the form of Eq. (8.18). Once again, if “there is no way to finishthe procedure,” there is no way to finish choosing the bn ’s. Consequently, there isno way to construct b in Eq. (8.18). That is, Cantor’s diagonal method, which wehave just described, is invalid.

A seasoned mathematician can see that the principle of mathematical inductionhas been and will be “used” or “abused” in ways as we have described. Thus, oneor both of the following is true: (1) Explanation 2 is incorrect. (2) In the casesdescribed, the principle of mathematical induction has been abused.

Conjecture 8.6.1. Statement (1) is true while statement (2) is not.

Page 193: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

186 Chapter 8

Table 8. 1.

Age Age Age Sum Product1 1 72 74 721 2 36 39 721 3 24 28 721 4 18 23 721 6 12 19 722 2 18 22 722 3 12 17 722 4 9 15 722 6 6 14 721 8 9 18 723 4 6 13 723 3 8 14 72

8.6.4. Some Threatening Impacts of the Vase Puzzle

The first explanation is a great and fruitful resource of ideas that connect thevase puzzle with problems in philosophy, methodology and epistemology. In thissubsection, we discuss these connections.

8.6.4.1. Connections with methodology. In general, if known informationabout a phenomenon has not all been used, the phenomenon can either not beunderstood because of lack of knowledge or be understood at a more global leveland more information is needed to be more specific. For example [see (Billsteinet al., 1990) for details], when his students asked Mr. Factor what his children’sages were, he said, “I have three children. The product of their ages is 72, andthe sum of their ages is the number of this room.” The children then asked for thedoor to be opened to verify the room number, which is 14. Then, Sonja, the classmath whiz, told the teacher that she needed more information to solve the problem.Mr. Factor said, “My oldest child is good at chess.” Then, Sonja announced thecorrect ages of Mr. Factor’s children as: 3,3,8. Based on the given information,Sonja constructed Table 8.1. She knew the sum of the ages was 14, but could notdetermine the correct answer from the two choices (2,6,6) and (3,3,8). WhenSonja was told that the oldest child was good at chess, she knew that (2,6,6) couldnot be a possible combination because if the children were 2, 6, and 6 years old,there would not be an oldest child.

Notice that the vase puzzle does not satisfy the general methodology of recog-nition. The information about ordering really made understanding more contro-versial rather than more specific.

Page 194: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 187

Our vase puzzle does not fit into categories of problems considered by Polya(1973). The problem is neither a “perfectly stated” nor “practical.” It is concep-tual and thought-provoking. It challenges traditional mathematical reasoning. Itespecially raises questions about the idea of mathematical modeling.

8.6.4.2. Connections with epistemology. Through history, the developmentof scientific theories and the understanding of realities have been hand in hand.To know more about nature, scientists establish hypotheses and develop theo-ries. These theories further our understanding of nature and, in turn, push thedevelopment of the theories to a higher level.

Among the most common practices of modern scientific activities is the scienceand technology of data analysis. It is known in analysis that the more data that arecollected, the more misleading the conclusion that will be obtained, measuring andcollecting each datum are subject to errors or noise, and an extraordinary amountof noise can easily conceal the actual state of a phenomenon. The vase puzzleis another example showing that the more facts we know, the more confusedwe become. At the same time, the vase puzzle also questions the accuracy ofscientific predictions, because the ignorance of a fact will lead to a completelydifferent prediction. Therefore, one could question the value and the meaning ofscientific research and scientific predictions.

8.6.4.3. Connections with philosophy. Studying nature and the structure oftime and space is an ancient interest. The vase puzzle, the paradox of the hotel,and the paradox of a moving particle, once again, raise the interest of exploringthe answer to the question, because by reassigning some numbers, an infiniteprocedure can be finished within a randomly chosen time frame, an infinitely largepiece of paper can be shrunk to any desired size, and an infinitely high buildingcan be rebuilt in order to fit into a limited space. Then we ask: Are the structuresof space and time continuous? What is the meaning of volume?

Maybe the answer to the second question is that the concept of volume ismeaningless mathematically because one can prove that it is possible to chop asolid ball into small pieces and then reassemble these pieces into as many balls asone desires of the same size as the original ball (Jech, 1973).

As for the first question, about the continuity of space and time, we think thestructure of the set of all hyperreal numbers (Davis, 1977) describes and explainsthe hotel and moving particle paradoxes better than the commonly accepted one.For example, the commonly accepted model for time is the set of all real numbers,which is continuous and complete. The property of completeness of real numberswas applied to model the process of crystallization of polymers (Lin and Qiu, 1987).If the structure of hyperreal numbers is applied, the modeling for the crystallizationin (Lin and Qiu, 1987) would no longer be correct. To make things more specific,let us describe the structure of the hyperreal numbers in some detail.

The concept of hyperreal numbers is a product of nonstandard analysis. Thistheory deals with ideal elements and is a time-honored and significant mathematical

Page 195: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

188 Chapter 8

theory. These ideal elements include “numbers” that are infinitely close to thenumbers we are interested in and those that are infinitely far away from all realnumbers.

Briefly speaking, the set of all hyperreal numbers has operations +, – , × , ÷and a linear ordering relation <. Let x be the absolute value of a hyperreal numberx ∈ Then x = max{x, -x}, and is made up of three parts:

(8.19)

(8.20)

and – F, where F contains all finite hyperreal numbers, I is the set of allinfinitesimals, and – F includes all infinite hyperreal numbers.

The set of all real numbers is a dense subset of F. Geometrically, F canbe obtained as follows: For each real number r ∈ the number r in has aneighborhood

(8.21)

such that for any real numbers r, s ∈ and infinitesimals x, y ∈ I, r < s , if andonly if r + x < s + y. This neighborhood r ⊕ I is called the monad of r. It can beseen that all monads of real numbers are densely ordered.

The set – F of all infinite hyperreal numbers consists of F as the center“block,” and, in either the positive or the negative directions, an ordered set of“blocks.” These blocks are densely ordered with neither a first nor last element.Each block has the same geometric structure as F and is termed a galaxy.

If is used to model time and the Cartesian product to model space,Questions 8.6.2 and 8.6.3 can be answered as follows:

A. For (Benardete) Question 8.6.2: Suppose the hotel roof is r feet high.When the roof is removed, nothing can be seen if one looks at the hotel from abovebecause what a person sees should be in the layers r – x for each x ∈ I and x > 0,and no guests live on these levels (no floor reaches these heights).

B. For Question 8.6.3: Since a seemly smooth moving particle really jumpsforward from a monad to another, it could meet any point in the sequence (8.10)first.

8.7. Final Comments and Further Questions

From our discussion it can be seen that there are roughly two methods to intro-duce new mathematical concepts. One is that in the study of practical problems,new mathematical concepts are abstracted, and the other is that in the search forrelations between mathematical concepts, new concepts are discovered. The ap-plication of mathematics, as shown by the examples, brings life to the development

Page 196: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics: A New Tour 189

of mathematics so that when dealing with real problems, mathematics often makesus better understand the phenomena under consideration. If all well-developedmathematical theories do not fit a specific situation under consideration, a modi-fied mathematical theory will be developed to study the situation. That is to say,mathematics, just as all other scientific branches, is developed in the process ofexamining, verifying and modifying itself.

When facing practical problems, new abstract mathematical theories are de-veloped to investigate them. At the same time, predictions based on the newlydeveloped theories are so accurate that the following question appears:

Question 8.7.1. Does the human way of thinking have the same structure as thatof the material world?

On the other hand, the mathematical palace is built upon the “empty set.”History gradually shows that almost all natural phenomena can be described andstudied with mathematics. From these facts the following question arises.

Question 8.7.2. If all laws of nature can be written in the language of mathematics,can we conclude that the universe we live in rests on the empty set, just as Genesis1:1 states that “In the beginning, God created the heaven and the earth. And theearth was without form, and void”?

Page 197: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 9

General Systems: A MultirelationApproach

Based on the previous chapter, it is time to study the concept of general systemsmathematically. The concept of systems is a generalization of that of structures.Generally speaking, a system consists of a set of objects and a set of relationsbetween the objects, and has a structure of “layers.” In this chapter, a modelof general systems is introduced, based on the methods of set theory, and somebasic global properties of systems are studied in detail. The chapter containseight sections. In the first section, layer structures, the existence of fundamentalobjects, the finite chain condition, and centralized systems are studied. Thesecond section consists of properties of relations between systems, the structureof quotient systems, and a characterization of centralizable systems. Methods ofconstructing new systems, based on a set of given systems, are introduced in thethird section. These methods serve as a mathematical foundation for the analysisof “whole–parts” relations:

In the fourth section, the structure of connected systems is studied and usedto check the connectedness of newly constructed systems. This structure showswhether a system can be seen as a set of systems or a single system only. In thefifth and the seventh sections, hierarchies of systems (or, say, large-scale systems)are studied. The concepts of controllabilities of general systems are introducedand studied in the sixth section. Some references are listed in the last section.

9.1. The Concept of General Systems

Let A be a set and n an ordinal number. An n-ary relation r on A is a subset ofthe Cartesian product An . In the sequel, An means either the Cartesian product ofn copies of A or the set of all mappings from n into A. From Chapters 2 and 3 it iseasy to see that the two definitions of An are equivalent.

If r is a relation on A , there exists an ordinal n = n (r), a function of r, such

191

Page 198: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

that

192 Chapter 9

r ⊆ An

The ordinal number n = n (r) is called the length of the relation r. When r is theempty relation assume that n ( ) = 0; i.e., the length of the relation is 0.

S is a (general) system if S is an ordered pair (M, R) of sets, where R is a setof some relations on the set M. Each element in M is called an object of S , and Mand R are called the object set and the relation set of S , respectively. The systemS is discrete if R = or R = { } and M ≠ . It is trivial if M =

Two systems Si = (Mi , Ri), i = 1,2, are identical, denoted S1 = S 2, if

M1 = M2 and R 1 = R2

The system S1 is a partial system of the system S2 if M1 ⊆ M2 and for each relationr1 ∈ R1 there exists a relation r2 ∈ R2 such that r1 = r2 M1 , where r 2 M1 is therestriction of r2 on M1 , and is defined by

The system S1 is a subsystem of S2 if M1 ⊆ M 2 and for each relation r1 ∈ R1 thereexists a relation r2 ∈ R2 , satisfying r1 ⊆ r2 M1 .

Theorem 9.1.1. There is no system such that the object set of the system consistsof all systems.

This is a restatement of the Zermelo–Russel paradox.

Proof: Consider the class V of all sets. For each x ∈ V define a system by(x , ). Then a 1–1 correspondence h is defined such that h(x) = (x, ). If thereis a system S = (M, R ) whose object set contains all systems, then M is a set.Therefore, the Axiom of Comprehension shows that V is a set, contradiction.

A system Sn = (Mn , Rn ) is an nth-level object system of S0 = (M0, R0 ) if thereexist systems Si = (Mi ,Ri), for i = 1,2, … ,n–1, such that Si is an object in M i –1,1 ≤ i ≤ n. Each element in Mn is called an nth-level object of S0 .

Theorem 9.1.2 [ZFC]. Let S0 = (M0 , R0 ) be a system and Sn = (Mn , Rn) an nth-level object system of S0 . Then S0 cannot be a subsystem of Sn for each naturalnumber n ∈

Proof: The theorem will be proved by contradiction. Suppose that for a certainnatural number n, the system S0 is a subsystem of the nth-level object system S n .

Page 199: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 193

Let Si = (Mi ,Ri) be the systems, for i = 1, 2, … ,n – 1, such that Si ∈ Mi –1,i = 1, 2, . . . ,n. Define a set X by

From the Axiom of Regularity, it follows that there exists a set Y ∈ X such thatY ∩ X = There now exist three possibilities:

(i) Y = Mi for some i.

(ii) Y = Si for some i.

(iii) Y = {Mi} for some i.

If possibility (i) holds, There-fore, contradiction. If (ii) holds,and contradiction. If (iii) holds, contradiction.These contradictions show that S0 cannot be a subsystem of Sn.

A chain of object systems of a system S is a sequence for someordinal number α, of different-level object systems of S, such that for each pairi, j < α with i < j , there exists an integer n = n (i , j), a function of i and j, suchthat Sj is an nth-level object system of Si. A similar proof to that of Theorem 9.1.2gives the following.

Theorem 9.1.3 [ZFC]. Each chain of object systems of a S must be finite.

Theorem 9.1.4 [ZFC]. For any system S, there exists exactly one set M(S) con-sisting of all fundamental objects in S, where a fundamental object in S is a levelobject of the system S which is no longer a system.

Proof: Suppose that S = (M0 , R0 ). Define

*M0 = {x ∈ M0 : x is not a system}

and

Then *M0 and are sets.Suppose that for a natural number n, two sequences {*Mi : i = 0, 1, 2, … ,n}

and { : i = 0, 1, 2, … , n} have been defined such that

is not a system}

Page 200: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

194 Chapter 9

and

We then define is not a system} and

By mathematical induction a sequence can be defined. LetThen Theorem 9.1.3 guarantees that M( S) consists of

all fundamental objects in S ; and from the uniqueness of each *Mi it follows thatM (S ) is uniquely determined by S.

Theorem 9.1.5. Let S = (M,R ) be a system such that, for any r ∈ R, the lengthn(r ) = 2. Then

(9.1)

where p(X ) is the power set of X and pi+1 ( X) = p (pi( X )) for each i = 1,2, . . .

Proof: For each element (x ,y ) ∈ r, ( x ,y ) = {{x},{x ,y}} ∈ p2(M ) and r ∈p3( M ). Therefore, R ∈ p 4(M). Since { M} ∈ p (M) and (M, R )p4(M )), it follows that the inclusion in Eq. (9.1) holds.

Question 9.1.1. Give a structural representation for general systems similar tothat in Theorem 9.1.5.

A system S = ( M, R ) is called centralized if each object in S is a system andthere exists a nontrivial system C = ( MC ,RC ) such that for any distinct elementsx,y ∈ M, say x = ( Mx ,Rx ) and y = ( My , Ry ), then

where The system C iscalled a center of the centralized system S.

Theorem 9.1.6 [ZFC]. Let k be any infinite cardinality and θ > k a regularcardinality such that, for any Assume that S = (M, R) is asystem satisfying M ≥ θ and each object m ∈ M is a system with m = (Mm ,Rm )and Mm < κ. If there exists an object contained in at least θ objects in M, thenthere exists a partial system S' = ( M', R' ) of S such that S' forms a centralizedsystem and M' ≥ θ.

Page 201: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 195

Proof: Without loss of generality, we assume that M = θ and thatthere is a common element in all the object systems in M . Then

Since the specific objects in each Mx , for eachobject x = ( Mx , Rx ) ∈ M, are irrelevant, we may assume that

Then, for each x = (Mx ,Rx ) ∈ M, the object set Mx has some order type < κas a subset of θ. Since θ is regular and θ > k, there exists a ρ < k such thatM1 = {x ∈ M : Mx has order type ρ} has cardinality θ. We now fix such a ρ anddeal only with the partial system S1 = ( M1 ,R1 ) of S, where R1 is the restriction ofthe relation set R on M1 .

For each implies that less than θ objects of the partial systemS1 have object sets as subsets of α. Thus, is cofinalin θ. If x ∈ M l and ξ < ρ, let Mx (ξ) be the ξth element of Mx . Since θ is regular,there is some ξ such that {Mx (ξ ) : x ∈ M l } is cofinal in θ. Now fix ξ0 to bethe least such ξ. Then the condition that there exists a common element in eachsystem in M l implies that we can guarantee that ξ0 > 0. Let

Then α0 < θ and Mx ( η) < α0 for all x ∈ Ml and all η < ξ0 .By transfinite induction on µ < θ, pick x µ ∈ Ml so that Mxµ (ξ0 ) > α 0 and

Mxµ (ξ0 ) is above all elements of earlier xv; i.e.,

Let Then and whenever x =( Mx,Rx ) and y = ( My ,Ry ) are distinct objects in M2. Since for each α < θ,

there exists anforms a centralized system, where R B is the restriction of the relation

set R on B.

Corollary 9.1.1. If S is a system with uncountable (or nondenumerable) objectset, if each object in S is a system with a finite object set, and if there exists anobject contained in at least ℵ 1 objects in S, there exists a partial system S* of Swith an uncountable object set and S* forms a centralized system.

Proof: It suffices from Theorem 9.1.6 to show thatThis is clear because for each

(9.2)

Page 202: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

196 Chapter 9

A system S = (M ,R ) is strongly centralized if each object in S is a system andthere is a nondiscrete system C = ( MC ,RC ) such that for any distinct elementsx and y ∈ M, say x = ( Mx ,Rx ) and and

The system C is called an S-center of S.

Question 9.1.2. Give conditions under which a given system has a partial systemwhich is strongly centralized and has an object set of the same cardinality as thatof the given system.

9.1.1. A Brief Historical Remark

Roughly speaking, the idea of systems appeared as long ago as Aristotle. Forexample, Aristotle’s statement “the whole is greater than the sum of its parts”could be the first definition of a basic systems problem. Later, many great thinkersused the languages of their times to study certain systems problems. Nicholas ofCusa, for example, a profound thinker of the fifteenth century, linking medievalmysticism with the first beginnings of modern science, introduced the notion ofthe coincidentia oppositorum. Leibniz’s hierarchy of monads looks quite like thatof modem systems. Gustav Fechner, known as the author of the psychophysicallaw, elaborated in the way of the native philosophers of the nineteenth centurysupraindividual organizations of higher order than the usual objects of observation,thus romantically anticipating the ecosystems of modem parlance; for details, see(von Bertalanffy, 1972).

The concept of systems was not introduced formally until the 1920s. VonBertalanffy began to study the concept of systems formally in biology. Since then,more and more scholars have studied the concept of systems and related topics.For example, Tarski (1954–1955) defined the concept of relational systems. Halland Fagan (1956) described a system as a set of objects and some relations betweenthe objects and their attributes. They did not define mathematical meanings forobjects nor for attributes of the objects. In 1964 Mesarovic began to study themodel of general systems in the language of set theory. His final model (Mesarovicand Takahara, 1975) reads: A system S is a relation on nonempty sets:

(9.3)

After considering the interrelationship between the systems under concern andsome environments of systems, Bunge (1979) gave a model of systems as follows:Let T be a nonempty set. Then the ordered triple W = (C ,E ,S ) is a system over Tif and only if C and E are mutually disjoint subsets of T and S is a nonempty set ofrelations on C ∪ E ; the sets C and E are called the composition and an environmentof the system W, respectively. Klir (1985) introduced a philosophical concept of

Page 203: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 197

general systems. The concept of general systems discussed intensively in thischapter was first introduced by Lin and Ma (1987; 1987).

We conclude this section with three mathematical structures related to theconcept of general systems: structure, L-fuzzy system, and G-system.

9.1.2. Structures

Let A be a set and n a nonnegative integer. An n -ary operation on A is amapping f from A n into A. An n-ary relation r on the set A is a subset of An . Atype τ of structures is an ordered pair

(9.4)

where 0 ( τ) and 00 1(τ ) are fixed ordinals and nv and m v are nonnegative integers.For everyv < 0 0( τ ) there exists a symbol fv of an n v -ary operation, and for everyv < 0 1 ( τ ) there exists a symbol rv , of an mv -ary relation.

A structure U (Gratzer, 1978) is a triplet (A, F, R), where A is a nonempty set.For every v < 00 ( τ) we realize fv as an n v-ary operation (fv )U on A, for everyv < 0 1 ( τ ) we realize rv as an m v -ary relation (rv )U on A, and

(9.5)

(9.6)

If 01 (τ) = 0, U is called an algebra and if 00 (τ) = 0, U is called a relationalsystem.

It can be seen that the concept of algebras is a generalization of the conceptsof rings, groups, and the like. Any n -ary operation is an (n + 1)-ary relation.Therefore, the concept of relational systems generalizes the idea of algebras, andthe concept of structures combines those of algebras and relational systems. Thefact that any topological space is a relational system shows that the research ofrelational systems will lead to the discovery of properties that topologies andalgebras have in common.

Example 9.1.1. We show that any topological space is a relational system, thusa general system. Let (X , T) be a topological space [for details see (Engelking,1975)]. Then for each open set U ∈ T , there exists an ordinal number n = n (U ) = 1such that U ∈ X n. Therefore, (X, T) is also a system with object set X, and relationset T, and the length of each relation in T is 1. Now, applying the Axiom of Choiceimplies that the topology T can be well-ordered as

(9.7)

where each open set is a 1-ary relation on X. So (X , Ø, T) becomes a structure,which is a relational system.

Page 204: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

198 Chapter 9

and

A systematic introduction to the study of structures can be found in (Gratzer,1978). Many great mathematicians worked in the field, including Whitehead,Birkhoff, Chang, Henkin, Jonsson, Keisler, Tarski, etc.

9.1.3. L-Fuzzy Systems

The concept of fuzzy systems (Lin, 1990a) is based on the concept of fuzzysets introduced in 1965 by Zadeh. An ordered set (L , ≤ ) is called a lattice iffor any elements a , b ∈ L, there exists exactly one greatest lower bound of a andb, denoted by a ∧ b , and there exists exactly one least upper bound of a and b,denoted by a ∨ b , such that

We call a lattice distributive if the lattice, in addition, satisfies

We call a lattice complete if for any nonempty subset A ⊆ L , there exists exactlyone least upper bound of the elements in A, denoted by ∨ A or supA , and thereexists exactly one greatest lower bound of the elements in A, denoted by ∧ A o rinfA .

We call a lattice completely distributive if for any a ∈ L and any subset {b i :i ∈ I} ⊆ L , where I is an index set, and exist and satisfy

(9.8)

(9.9)

We say that L is a lattice with order-reversing involution if there exists an operator' defined on L such that for any a, b ∈ L , if a ≤ b , then a' ≥ b'.

In the following, a completely distributive lattice L with order-reversing invo-lution is fixed; assume that 0 and 1 are the minimum and maximum elements inL.

Let X be a set. A is an L -fuzzy set on X iff there exists a mapping µ A ∈ LX

such that Without confusion, we consider that A is themapping µ A in LX . If µ A , or say A , has at most two values, 0 and 1, then theL-fuzzy set A can be seen as a subset of X.

Page 205: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 199

Suppose that A and B are two L -fuzzy sets on X . Then A = B iff µ A ( x ) =µ B (x ) for all x ∈ X . A ⊂ B iff for all x ∈ X . If Y ⊂ X , then

Let {Ai : i ∈ I} be a set of L-fuzzy sets on X. Then andare defined by

(9.10)

(9.11)

and

for all x ∈ X .S is an L -fuzzy system iff S is an ordered pair (M, R ) of sets, where R is a

set of some L-fuzzy relations defined on the set M; i.e., for any L-fuzzy relationr ∈ R , there exists an ordinal number n = n( r) such that r is an L-fuzzy set on theCartesian product Mn . The ordinal n is called the length of the L-fuzzy relation r.

Theorem 9.1.7. Suppose that an L-fuzzy system S = (M , R ) is such that, for anyr ∈ R , n(r) = 2. Then

(9.12)

Proof: S = (M, R ) = {{M}, {M, R}} ⊆ p(M ∪ R), and for any (x , y, i) ∈ r ⊆ M ² × L ,

So and Thus, the inclusion in Eq. (9.12)holds.

Suppose that S i = (Mi , R i), i = 1, 2, are L -fuzzy systems. The L-fuzzy systemS1 is a subsystem of the L-fuzzy system S 2 if M l ⊆ M 2 and for any L-fuzzy relationr l ∈ R1, there exists an L-fuzzy relation r2 ∈ R2 such that

Example 9.1.2. An example is constructed to show that the equation S 1 = S 2 willnot follow from the condition that the L-fuzzy systems S 1 and S 2 are subsystemsof each other.

Suppose that the completely distributive lattice with order-reversing involutionlattice L is the closed interval with the usual order relation. Let = {1, 2, …} be

Page 206: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

200 Chapter 9

for each

for all

the set of all natural numbers, and a sequence defined by a i = 1 – 1 / i.We now define two L-fuzzy systems, and as follows:

and where

(9.13)

(9.14)

and for any

and

(9.15)

Then it is easy to show that S1 and S 2 are subsystems of each other, but S1 ≠ S2 .

9.1.4. G-Systems

In this part any set A will be seen as a partially ordered set (A , ≤ A ), where theordering is defined by ≤A = {(x, x) : x ∈ A }.

S is a G-system (Lin and Ma, 1989) of type where I is an indexset and, for each i ∈ I , Ki is a set partially ordered by ≤ i iff S is an ordered pair ofsets such that for any The set K i is called the type ofthe relation r i , and the set K is called the type of the system S .

The concept of G-systems can be used to study more applied problems becauseit contains a more general meaning of relations. The interested reader is encouragedto consult (Lin and Ma, 1989).

9.2. Mappings from Systems into Systems

Let S i = (Mi , R i ), = 1, 2, be two systems and h : M l → M2 a mapping. Bytransfinite induction, two classes i = 1, 2, and a class mappingcan be defined with the following properties:

(9.16)

and for each x =

(9.17)

Page 207: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 201

For each relation is a relation on M with length n (r) .2Without confusion, h will also be used to indicate the class mapping and h is amapping from S1 into S2, denoted h : S1 → S 2. When h : M1 → M2 is surjective,injective, or bijective, h : S1 → S2 is also called surjective, injective, or bijective,respectively. Let X be a subsystem of S . Then h1 X indicates the restriction of themapping on X. Without confusion, we use h for h X.

The systems S are similar, if there exists a bijection h : S → S such thati 1 2

The mapping h is a similarity mapping from S1

onto S . Clearly, the inverse mapping h– 12 is a similarity mapping from S2 onto

S1 .A mapping h : S1 → S2 is a homomorphism from S1 into S2 if

The quotient system S/E is defined

where µ : M → M /E is the canonical mapping defined by µ(m) = [m]. ThenR /E = {µ (r) : r ∈ R }.

Theorem 9.2.1. Suppose that h : S1 → S 2 is a homomorphism from S1 into S2 .Then is a similarity mapping, where

and for each

Proof: It is easy to check that Eh is an equivalence relation on the object set M1 .We next show that is well defined. Let besuch that [m1 ] = [m2 ], then m 2 ∈ [m1 ], and so h(m2 ) = h (m1 ). This implies that

Finally, we show that is a similarity mapping; is abijection. In fact, let [m1 ] and be such that and

Therefore, h(m1) = h (m2 ). This implies that and so[m1 ] = [m2], contradiction.

For any relation r ∈ R1 /Eh , there exists a relation s ∈ R1 such that r = µ (s),where µ is the canonical mapping from M1 into M1 /Eh . Then

(9.19)

Thus, For any relation r ∈ h (R1 ), there exists a relation s ∈ R such that r = h (s).1

Therefore, This completes the proof that is a similaritymapping from S1 /Eh onto h (S 1 ) . �

Let S0 and A be two systems with no nonsystem kth-level objects for eachk < n, where n is a fixed natural number. A mapping hS 0 : S 0 → A is an n -levelhomomorphism from S0 into A if the following inductive conditions hold, and thesystem S0 is n -level homomorphic to A.

Let E be an equivalence relation on the object set M of a system S = (M, R).

(9.18)

Page 208: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

202 Chapter 9

(1) For each object S1 in S 0, there exists a homomorphism hS l , from the objectsystem S1 into the object system hS0 (S1 ).

(2) For each i < n and each ith-level object Si of S 0 , there exist level objectsystems Sk , k = 0,1, . . . ,i – 1, and homomorphisms hSk , k = 1,2, . . . , i,such that Sk is an object of the object system Sk –1 and hS k

is ahomomorphism from Sk into hS k –1

(Sk ) for k = 1,2, . . . , i.

When all homomorphisms in this definition are similarity mappings, the map-ping hS0

is termed as an n-level similarity, and the system S 0 is n -level similar toA.

Proposition 9.2.1. Suppose that A, B, and C are systems.

(a) If A is n-level homomorphic to B and B is m-level homomorphic to C, thenA is min{n, m}-level homomorphic to C.

(b) If A is n-level similar to B and B is m-level similar to C, then A ismin{n, m}-level similar to C.

The proof is straightforward and is omitted.A system S is centralizable if it is 1-level homomorphic to a centralized system

SC under a homomorphism h : S → SC such that for each object m in S, the objectsystem m and h(m) are similar. Each center of SC is also called a center of S.

Theorem 9.2.2. Let S = (M, R) be a system such that each object in M is a system.Then S is centralizable, iff there exists a nontrivial system C = ( MC , RC ) such thatC is embeddable in each object of S. (C embeddable in an object S1 in S meansthat C is similar to a partial system of S1 , and each similarity mapping here iscalled an embedding mapping from C into S1 .)

Proof: Necessity. If the system S = (M,R) is centralizable, there exists acentralized system S * = (M* , R* ) such that S is 1-level homomorphic to S * . LetC be a center of S *. Then C is embeddable in each object of S.

Sufficiency. Without loss of generality, we can assume that the collection of allobject sets of the objects in S consists of disjoint sets. For eachthe system C is embeddable in x, so there exists a one-to-one mapping

such that is a partial system of x. Define a newsystem as follows:

(9.20)

and let be the bijection defined by

(9.21)

Page 209: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 203

Then define

(9.22)

So C is a partial system of x* . Let h* be a mapping defined by letting h *(x) = x *

for each x ∈ M. Then the system h* (S) is centralized with the system C as acenter. Therefore, S is a centralizable system. �

Example 9.2.1. An example is constructed to show that the hypothesis in Theorem9.1.6 that there exists an object belonging to at least θ objects in S is essential forthe result to follow and that not every centralizable system is a centralized system.Consequently, the concepts of centralized systems and centralizable systems aredifferent.

Let ω1 be the first uncountable ordinal number, and M a collection of n-elementsubsets of ω1 , for some natural number n > 0, such that M = ω1 and for anyx,y ∈ M, x y = if x ≠ y.

We now consider a system S with object set M * such that for any x * ∈ M * ,x * is a system with some element in M as its object set, and for any x ∈ M thereexists exactly one x* ∈ M * such that x is the object set of the system x* . It isclear that S has no partial system which forms a centralized system and that S is acentralizable system.

Theorem 9.2.3. Let κ and θ be cardinalities satisfying the conditions in Theorem9.1.6. Assume that S is a system with an object set of cardinality ≥ θ and eachobject in S is a system with an object set of cardinality < κ . There then exists apartial system S' of S such that the object set of S' is of cardinality ≥ θ and S'forms a centralizable system.

The proof follows from Theorems 9.1.6 and 9.2.2.A mapping h from a system S1 = (M1 , R 1 ) into a system S2 = (M2 ,R2 ) is

S-continuous if for any relation r ∈ R2 ,

(9.23)

Proposition 9.2.2. Suppose that h : S1 → S 2 is a mapping. Then

(i) If the systems Si , i = 1,2, are topological spaces, h is S-continuous, iff it iscontinuous from S1 into S2 .

(ii) If the systems Si , i = 1,2, are groups, the S-continuity of h implies that h isa homomorphism from S1 into S2 .

(iii) If the systems S i , i = 1,2, are rings, the S-continuity of h implies that h is ahomomorphism from S1 into S2 .

Page 210: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

204 Chapter 9

Proof: (i) follows from the definition of S-continuity of mappings and Example9.1.1.

For (ii), let (X, +) be a group. A system (X,R) is defined as follows: R = {r+ }and The system (X,R) will be identified withthe group (X, +), and the relation r+ with +.

Let , i = 1,2, be two groups and h : S1 → S 2 an S-continuousmapping. Then Thus, for any x, y, and z ∈ M1 , if x +1 y = z, thenh(x)+2 h(y) = h (z) This implies that h is a homomorphism from S 1 into S 2 .

The proof of (iii) is a modification of that of (ii) and is omitted. �

Theorem 9.2.4. A bijection h : S 1 → S 2 is a similarity mapping iff h : S1 → S 2 andh– 1 : S 2 → S1 are S-continuous.

The proof is straightforward and is left to the reader.

Theorem 9.2.5. Suppose that ƒ : S1 → S 2 and g : S2 + S3 are S-continuous map-pings. Then the composition g °ƒ : S1 → S3 is also S-continuous.

Proof: For each relation r in the system S3 , from the hypothesis that themapping g is S-continuous we have

(9.24)

From the hypothesis that the mapping ƒ is S-continuous, it follows that

Therefore, from Eq. (9.25),

Thus, g °ƒ is S -continuous. �

9.3. Constructions of Systems

(9.25)

Let be a set of systems such that Mi Mj = for any

if I = {1,2, . . . ,n } is finite, is defined to be the system

(9.26)

distinct i and j ∈ I. The free sum of the systems Si, denoted ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I} or

Page 211: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 205

The concept of free sums of systems can be defined for any set {S i : i ∈ I}of systems such that the collection of all object sets of the systems in the setconsists of not necessarily pairwise disjoint sets. To show this, we simply take aset {* Si : i ∈ I} of systems with pairwise disjoint object sets such that * Si is similarto Si , for each i ∈ I, and define

(9.27)

Up to a similarity, the free sum of the systems Si is unique. Therefore, it canbe assumed that any set of systems has a free sum (uniquely determined up toa similarity), but in the proofs of some theorems in the future it will be tacitlyassumed that the set under consideration consists of systems with pairwise disjointobject sets.

A system S = (M,R) is an input–output system if two sets X and Y are givensuch that X Y = M and for each relation r ∈ R there are nonzero ordinals n = n (r)and m = m( r) such that r ⊆ X n × Y m . The sets X and Y are called the input spaceand the output space of the system S, respectively.

Proposition 9.3.1. Let S and S be two similar systems. If S is a free sum of1 2 1

some systems, then so is S2 .

Proof: Suppose that S1 = ⊕ {S i : i ∈ I }, where {S i : i ∈ I } is a set of systemsS i = (M i,R i), and h : S1 → S2 is a similarity mapping. Then

(9.28)

because for each i ∈ I, and for each r ∈ R2 there exists a relations ∈ R i , for some i ∈ I, such that h (s) = r. �

Theorem 9.3.1. Suppose that {Si = (Mi ,Ri ) : i ∈ I} is a set of systems, where Iis an index set. Then the free sum ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I} is an input–output system iff eachsystem Si = ( Mi ,Ri ) is an input–output system, i ∈ I.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose that ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I } is an input–output system with

there are nonzero ordinals n = n(r) and m = m (r) such that r ⊆ X n × Y m. Hence,

Si is an input–output system with input space Mi X and output space Mi Y.Sufficiency. Suppose that S i = (Mi i) is an input–output system with input

space Xi and output space Yi . Then for each relation r in ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I}, there existsan i ∈ I such that r ∈ Ri ; therefore,

(9.29)

input space X and output space Y. Then for any fixed i ∈ I and any relation r ∈ Ri ,

,R

Page 212: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

206 Chapter 9

Theorem 9.3.2. If a system S is embeddable in the free sum ⊕ {S i : i ∈ I} of somesystems Si , then S is also a free sum of some systems.

The proof is straightforward and is omitted.

Theorem 9.3.3. If the free sum ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I} of nontrivial systems Si is a central-ized system, then each Si is centralized, for i ∈ I.

Proof: The theorem follows from the fact that each center of the free sum⊕ {Si : i ∈ I } is a center of each system Si , i ∈ I. �

Theorem 9.3.4. Suppose that {Si : i ∈ I} is a set of centralizable systems suchthat each system Si has a center and thatfor all i and j ∈ I. Then the free sum ⊕ {S i : i ∈ I} is a centralizable system.

Proof: Let for some i ∈ I. Then the system (ℵ ,Ø) is embeddable ineach object in the free sum ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I}. Theorem 9.2.2 implies that the free sumis centralizable. �

It is easy to construct an example to show that the free sum of two centralizedsystems may not be a centralizable system.

Theorem 9.3.5. Let h : S → ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I} be a homomorphism. Then the systemS is also a free sum of some systems.

Proof: Suppose that S = (M,R) and Si = (Mi,Ri) for each i ∈ I. Then

(9.30)

Define

(9.3 1)

From the hypothesis that h is a homomorphism it follows that

(9.32)

Therefore, �

Hence, the free sum ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I } is an input–output system with input spaceand the output space �

Page 213: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 207

Theorem 9.3.6. Let ƒ : ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I } → S be an onto S-continuous mapping. Thenthere are partial systems {*Si : i ∈ I } of S such that

(9.33)

where *Si = (*Mi , *Ri), for each i ∈ I, and ƒ : S i → * S i is S-continuous.

Proof: For each i ∈ I we define a system *Si = (*Mi , *Ri ) as follows:

*Mi = ƒ (Mi) (9.34)

and

(9.35)

From the hypothesis that ƒ is surjective, it follows that Since ƒis S -continuous, Then Eq. (9.33) follows and the S-continuityof the mapping ƒ : Si → * Si follows from Eq. (9.35). �

Question 9.3.1. Under what conditions will the system S in Theorem 9.3.6 be afree sum of some systems?

Theorem 9.3.7. Suppose that h : S1 → S 2 is a homomorphism from a system S1

into an input–output system S2 . Then S1 is also an input–output system.

Proof: Suppose that S 2 has input space X and output space Y. Define

and (9.36)

Then S 1 is an input–output system with input space X* and output space Y*. Infact, let r be a relation in S 1 . Then h(r) ∈ R2. Hence, there are nonzero ordinalsn and m such that This implies that �

Theorem 9.3.8. Let ƒ : S1 → S 2 be an S-continuous mappingfrom an input–outputsystem S1 into a system S2 . Then S 2 is also an input–output system.

Proof: Suppose that S 1 has input space X1 and output space Y1. Define

X2 = ƒ (X1 ) and Y2 = ƒ (Y1) (9.37)

Then S 2 is an input–output system with input space X2 and output space Y2 . Infact, for each relation Hence, there are nonzero ordinals nand m such that Therefore, �

Page 214: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

208 Chapter 9

Let S 1 and S 2 be two systems. We define

Hom(S1, S 2) = {h : S1 → S 2 : h is a homomorphism} (9.38)

Suppose that {Si : i ∈ I} is a set of systems. A system S = (M , R) is a product ofthe systems S i if there exists a family of homomorphisms {Φ i ∈ Hom(S,S i ) : i ∈ I }such that for each system S' and a family {Ψ i ∈ Hom(S', S i ) : i ∈ I}, there existsa unique homomorphism λ ∈ Hom(S',S ) so that

(9.39)

for all i ∈ I.

Theorem 9.3.9. For each set {Si : i ∈ I } of systems, a product of the systemsSi always exists, which is unique up to a similarity and denoted by or

Proof: For the set of systems {Si : i ∈ I}, we define a system S = (M,R) asfollows:

(9.40)

(9.41)

(9.42)

and

(9.43)

where for any let for i ∈ I. and

(9.44)

Let be the projection for each i ∈ I. Then pi ∈ Hom(S , S i) .We now suppose that S' = (M',R') is a system and {Ψ i ∈ Hom(S',S i ) : i ∈ I}.

Define a mapping λ : S' → S as follows: For any object m' ∈ M', λ (m') = { Ψ(m') :i ∈ I} ∈ M. It then can be shown that λ ∈ Hom( S ' , S).

If λ ' is another such homomorphism, then i fThus, λ ' = λ as mappings from the object set M' into

the object set M. Therefore, they induce the same homomorphism. Therefore, Sis a product of the systems S i , i ∈ I. �

Let {S i : i ∈ I} be a set of systems. A system S = (M , R) is a Cartesianproduct of the systems Si if there exists a family of S-continuous mappings {pi :

Page 215: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 209

S → S i : i ∈ I} such that for each system S' and a family {qi : S' → S i : i ∈ I} ofS-continuous mappings, there exists a unique S-continuous mapping λ : S' → S sothat q i = p i ° λ for each i ∈ I.

Theorem 9.3.10. For each set {S i : i ∈ I} of systems, a Cartesian product ofthe systems S i always exists, which is unique up to a similarity and denoted by

Proof: Let S i = (Mi , R i ) for each i ∈ I. Define a system S = (M , R) as follows:

(9.45)

and

(9.46)

and define mappings pi : S → S i by letting for anyfor each i ∈ I. Then it can be readily checked that each mapping pi : S → S i isS-continuous.

Let S' = (M',R') be another system, and {qi : S' → S i : i ∈ I} a family ofS-continuous mappings. Define a mapping λ : S' → S by

(9.47)

for each object m' ∈ M'. Then λ is S -continuous. In fact, for an arbitrary relationr ∈ R, let r j ∈ R j be a relation such that

Then

To complete the proof, we show that all Cartesian products of the systems Si

are similar to each other.

Page 216: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

210 Chapter 9

Figure 9.1. Uniqueness of the Cartesian product.

Let S* = (M*,R*) be another Cartesian product of Si , i ∈ I. Then there are S -continuous mappings λ 1 : S → S * and λ 2 : S* → S such that the diagram (Fig. 9.1)commutes for each i ∈ I. That is, for each i ∈ I, we have

(9.48)

It suffices to show that

(9.49)

a n d

(9.50)

for each m ∈ M and m * ∈ M*. In fact, Eq. (9.49) implies that the mapping λ 1 is1–1, and Eq. (9.50) implies that λ 2 is 1–1; λ1 = λ 2

–1and λ 2 = λ 1

–1 . Therefore, λ l

and λ 2 are similarity mappings.Now, we prove Eqs. (9.49) and (9.50). For Eq. (9.49), let

then

Therefore, A similar argument showsEq. (9.50). �

The reason why the system S in Theorem 9.3.10 is called a Cartesian productof the systems S i is that when S i are topological spaces, S is the Cartesian productof the spaces S i . The system Π {S i : i ∈ I} in Theorem 9.3.9 is the box product ofthe spaces S i . When the systems S i are groups, Π{S i : i ∈ I} in Theorem 9.3.9 isthe direct sum of the groups Si . The mappings pi in the proofs of Theorems 9.3.9and 9.3.10 are called projections from the product systems into the factor systems.

Page 217: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 211

Let be a set of systems such that each object in any one system Si inthe set is a system again. The 1-level product system, denoted byis defined by where the object set M and the relation setR are defined as follows: There exists a bijection such that

(9.5 1)

and

(9.52)

The 1-level Cartesian product, denoted by is the system (M, R)defined by the following: There exists a bijection such that

(9.53)

and

(9.54)

Theorem 9.3.11. Let be a set of centralizable systems. Then the1-level product system and the 1-level Cartesian product system

are also centralizable systems.

Proof: For each i ∈ I suppose that is a center of the system Si.For the 1-level product system it suffices by Theorem 9.2.2 to showthat the product system is embeddable in each productfor all

From Theorem 9.2.2 we will not lose generality by assuming that each systemCi is embeddable in each object in M for i ∈ I. For eachi

Let and be an embedding mapping. Then the productmapping

(9.55)

defined by

(9.56)

for each object is an embedding mapping. In fact, first,the product mapping is 1–1, because if and are two distinct

Page 218: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

212 Chapter 9

objects in there exists an i ∈ I such that Therefore, since hi

is an embedding mapping it follows that Therefore,

(9.57)

Second, for each relation r in there exists a relation s insuch that

(9.58)

In fact, for each relation r in there exist relations for eachi ∈ I, such that for all i ∈ I and

(9.59)

From the hypothesis that each h i is an embedding mapping, it follows that thereexists a relation for each i ∈ I, such that

(9.60)

Equation (9.60) implies that for each i ∈ I. Define a relation s inas follows:

(9.61)

We now show that s satisfies Eq. (9.58). In fact,

(9.62)

Page 219: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 213

where for each α < n (r) and i ∈ I.We complete the proof of the theorem by observing that

(9.63)

The centralizability of the 1-level Cartesian product systemcan be proved in a similar way. �

Theorem 9.3.12. A mapping h from a system S = (M, R) into a Cartesianproductsystem is S-continuous iff the composition pi°h is S-continuousfor each i ∈ I.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose that is S -continuous. FromTheorem 9.2.5 and the proof of Theorem 9.3.10, it follows that each compositionpi °h is S -continuous, i ∈ I.

Sufficiency. Suppose that each composition pi °h is S -continuous, i ∈ I. Letfor each i ∈ I. For each relation r in there exist an

i ∈ I and a relation ri ∈ Ri satisfying that

Therefore,

(9.64)

This implies that i.e., h is S -continuous. �

Theorem 9.3.13. A mapping h from a system S = (M, R) into a product systemis a homomorphism iff the composition pi°h is a homomorphism for

every i ∈ I.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose that is a homomorphism.From the fact that each projection is a homomorphism, itfollows that pi °h is a homomorphism for every i ∈ I.

Sufficiency. Suppose that pi °h is a homomorphism for every i ∈ I. Let r ∈ R.We need to show that h(r) is a relation in For each i ∈ I we have

since pi°h is a homomorphism. Therefore,

(9.65)

Page 220: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

214 Chapter 9

and for each i ∈ I and s ∈ Ri ,

(9.66)

Equation (9.66) implies that for every si ∈ R i with n (s) = n(s i ),

(9.67)

So Eq. (9.65) implies that

(9.68)

This implies that the relation h(r) belongs to the relation set of �

9.4. Structures of Systems

Let S = (M,R) be a system and r ∈ R a relation. The support of r, denotedSupp(r), is defined by

(9.69)

1 ⊕ S 2 , whereThe system S is connected if it cannot be represented in the form SS 1 and S 2 are nontrivial subsystems of S.

Theorem 9.4.1. For every system S = (M, R) the following conditions are equiv-alent:

(i) The system S is connected.

(ii) For any two objects x and y ∈ M, there exist a natural number n > 0 and nrelations ri ∈ R such that

(9.70)

and

(9.7 1)

for each i = 1,2, . . . , n – 1.

Page 221: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 215

Proof: (i) → (ii). We prove by contradiction. Suppose that the system S isconnected and there exist two objects x and y ∈ M such that there do not existrelations r i ∈ R, i = 1,2,. . . , n, for any natural number n ≥ 1, such that

(9.72)

and

(9.73)

for each i = 1,2, . . . ,n – 1. From the hypothesis that S is connected, it followsthat there must be relations r1 ,s1 ∈ R such that x ∈ Supp( r1 ) and y ∈ Supp (s1 ).Then our hypothesis implies that

(9.74)

Let and for each natural number n ∈ let

(9.75)

and

(9.76)

Then and forall natural numbers n, m ∈

We now define two subsystems of S such that

(9.77)

(9.78)

(9.79)

(9.80)

Then and In fact, for each relation r ∈ R, if r ∉ R 1,and so thus r ∈ R 2 Therefore,

contradiction.(ii) → (i). The proof is again by contradiction. Suppose condition (ii) holds

and S is disconnected. Thus, there exist nontrivial subsystems S1 and S 2 of S suchthat S = S 1 ⊕ S 2. Suppose that Pick an object mi ∈ Mi,

Page 222: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

216

i = 1,2. Then there are no relations rj ∈ R, j = 1, 2, …,n, for any fixed n ∈such that

and

for each j = 1,2, … , n – 1, contradiction.

Chapter 9

(9.81)

(9.82)

Let M* ⊆ M , where S = (M, R) is a system. Define the star neighborhood ofthe subset M* , denoted Star (M* ), as follows:

By applying induction on n ∈ we can define

Star1 (M *) = Star(M* )

and

(9.83)

(9.84)

Starn+1 (M*) = Star(Starn( M *)) (9.85)

Corollary 9.4.1. For every system S = (M, R) the following conditions are equiv-alent:

(i) The system S is connected.

(ii) For each object x ∈ M, Star

Proof: (i) → → (ii) follows from Theorem 9.4.1 directly.(ii) → (i). For any two objects x, y ∈ M , from the hypothesis that Star∞ ( {p})=

M, for every object p ∈ M , it follows that there exist n, m ∈ and relations∈ R such that

(9.86)

(9.87)

and

Thus, it follows that Theorem 9.4.1(ii) holds and from Theorem 9.4.1 that S isconnected. �

An object m in a system is isolated if there is not relation r ∈ Rsuch that the cardinality and

Page 223: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 217

Corollary 9.4.2. There is no isolated object in a connected system.

Theorem 9.4.2. Suppose that S = (M, R ) is a connected system and D =is a disconnected system. If there exists a map-

ping f : S → D with then only one of thefollowing holds:

Proof: We prove by contradiction. Suppose there exists a mapping f : S → Dsuch that and Pick elements x ∈

From Theorem 9.4.1 it follows that there exist n ∈and n relations ri ∈ R, i = 1, 2, …, n, such that

(9.88)

and

(9.89)

for each i = 1, 2, … , n – 1. Pick an i with 1≤ i ≤ n such that

(9.90)

Sinceƒ –1 (R D ) ⊇ R , it follows that there exists a relation r ∈ RD such thatƒ(ri ) = r. Now there are two possibilities: If (1) holds, wemust have Supp contradiction. If (2) holds, we will haveSupp again a contradiction. The contradictions imply that everymapping f : S → D with must satisfy �

Corollary 9.4.3. Let h : S 1 → S 2 be a homomorphism from a connected system S1

into a system S2. Then h(S1 ) = (h(M1 ), h(R1)) must be a connected partial systemof S2.

Theorem 9.4.3. Suppose that h : S 1 → S 2 is an S-continuous mapping from asystem S1 into a system S 2 . If S is connected, the S is also.2 1

Proof: Suppose that 1, 2. Let us pick two arbitrary objectsx, y ∈ M1 . There are relations for some fixed n ∈ suchthat for each

Page 224: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

218 Chapter 9

i = 1, 2, … , n – 1. From the hypothesis that h is S -continuous, it follows thatfor i = 1, 2, … , n. Thus,

(9.91)

and

(9.92)

for i = 1, 2, … , n – 1. From Theorem 9.4.1 it follows that S1 is connected. �

Example 9.4.1. We construct an example to show that the connectedness of thesystem S1 cannot guarantee the connectedness of the system S2 in Theorem 9.4.3.

Let S2 = ( R 2) be a system where is the set of all integers andwhere for each i = ±1, ±2, ±3, … , ri = {(i , i+1)}.Then the

system is disconnected, where = {0, –1, –2, … }, = {1, 2, 3, … }, = {ri : i = –1, –2, …} and = {ri : i = 1, 2, . . .}.Define a system S1 = ( , R1) as follows: R1 = {r i : i = 0, ±1, ±2, … }, where

r i = {(i, i + 1)} for each i ∈ Then S 1 is connected. In fact, for any two objectsi,j ∈ there exist relations ri , r , … , r , where we assumed that i < j, such thati + l ji ∈ Supp( r i, i + 1}, j ∈ Supp(i) = { r ) = {j,j + 1}, and Supp(rj k ) ∩ Supp(r ) =k +1{k + 1}, for k = i, i + 1, . . . ,j – 1. Therefore, it follows from Theorem 9.4.1 thatS1 is connected.

Let h : S 1 → S 2 be the identity mapping defined by h(i) = i for each i ∈Then h is S-continuous, and S1 is connected, and S2 is disconnected.

Theorem 9.4.4. If a subsystem C of a system S is connected, and for every pairS , S of subsystems of S with disjoint object sets such that C is a subsystem of1 2S1 ⊕ S2, then C is a subsystem of S1 or S2 .

Proof: We show the result by contradiction. Suppose that C is not a subsystemof S nor of S 2. Let C = (MC , R C) and S i = (Mi ,Ri ), i = 1,2. Then1

(9.93)

Pick elements x ∈ MC ∩ M1 and y ∈ MC ∩ M2 . Since C is connected and fromTheorem 9.4.1, it follows that there exist a natural number n > 0 and n relationsr i ∈ R C , for i = 1, 2, … , n , such that

(9.94)

and

(9.95)

Page 225: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 219

Therefore, there must be an i satisfying 0 < i ≤ n such that

(9.96)

From the definition of subsystems it follows that there exists a relation r in thefree sum S1 S2 such that It follows from the definition of free sumsthat r is contained either in R1 or in R 2 , but not both. Therefore, if r ∈ R1 ,Supp( ri ) ∩ M2 = Ø; if r ∈ R2 , Supp(ri) ∩ M1 = Ø, contradiction. This implies thatC is a subsystem of S1 or S 2 . �

Theorem 9.4.5. Let { Ci = (Mi , R i) : i ∈ I } be a set of connected subsystemsof a system S = (M,R). If there exists an index i0 ∈ I such that each sys-tem is connected, for each i ∈ I, then the system

is connected.

(9.97)

(9.98)

Proof: Let us pick two arbitrary objects x and y from There are twoindices i and j such that x ∈ Mi and y ∈ Mj . Choose an object z ∈ Mi 0

. From thehypothesis that the systemsare connected, it follows that there are natural numbers n and m and relations rk

and qp ∈ R, for k = 1,2, … , n and p = 1,2, … , m, such that

and

(9.99)

(9.100)

Therefore, Theorem 9.4.1 implies that the system isconnected. �

Corollary 9.4.4. If the set {Ci = (Mi , Ri) : i ∈ I } of connected subsystems of thesystem S = (M, R) satisfies then the subsystemis connected.

Let S = (M, R) be a system and D ⊂ M a subset. The subset D is dense in theobject set M if the following conditions hold:

(i) For any relation r ∈ R with r ≠ Ø , Supp(r) ∩ D ≠ Ø .

(ii) Each isolated object in M belongs to D.

Page 226: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

220

there are natural number n and n relations r

and

A subsystem S* = ( M*,R* ) of S is a dense subsystem of S if the object set M* isdense in M.

Theorem 9.4.6. If a system S = ( M,R ) contains a connected dense subsystem,then S is connected.

Proof: Suppose that S* = (M*,R*) is a connected dense subsystem of S. Toshow that S is connected, we pick two arbitrary objects x, y ∈ M. There are threepossibilities: (1) x, y ∈ M – M* ; (2) one of x and y is contained in M* and theother is contained in M – M* ; (3) x, y are contained in M*.

If possibility (1) holds, x and y are not isolated objects in M. Therefore, thereare relations rx and ry ∈ R such that

(9.101)

It follows from the definition of dense subsets that there must be an object x* ∈Supp( rx ) ∩ M* and an object y* ∈ Supp( ry ) ∩ M*. Theorem 9.4.1 implies that

i ∈ R*, i = 1, 2, . . . , n, such that

(9.102)

(9.103)

For each i = 1, 2, . . . , n, let qi be a relation in R such that ri ⊂ qi M*. Then it hasto be that

(9.104)

(9.105)

and

(9.106)

Theorem 9.4.1 implies that S is connected.If possibility (2) holds, without confusion, let x ∈ M* and y ∈ M – M*. Then

y is not an isolated object in M. Let ry ∈ R be a relation such that

(9.107)

Pick y* ∈ Supp( ry) ∩ M*. From the hypothesis that S* is connected, it follows thatthere are a natural number n > 0 and n relations ri ∈ R*, i = 1, 2, . . . , n, such that

(9.108)

Chapter 9

Page 227: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 221

and

Supp(ri )∩Supp(ri + 1) ≠ Ø for each i = 1, 2, . . . , n –1 (9.109)

For each i = 1, 2, . . . , n, let qi be a relation in R such that ri ⊂ qi M* . Then

x ∈ Supp( q1 ) and y ∈ S u p p ( ry )Supp (qi ) ∩ Supp ( qi +l ) ≠ Ø for each i = 1,2, . . . n – 1

(9.110)

(9.111)

and

Supp(qn ) ∩ Supp (ry ) ≠ Ø (9.112)

Applying Theorem 9.4.1 we have showed that S is connected. �

A connected subsystem S* of S is maximal in S if there is not connectedsubsystem S + of S such that S * is a subsystem of S+ and S* ≠ S+ . Each maximalconnected subsystem of S is called a component. Then, for each object m ∈ M,the partial system (Star ∞ ({ m}), R Star ∞ ({ m})) of S is a component.

Theorem 9.4.7. Suppose that S = (M, R) is a system and E an equivalence re-lation on the object set M. Then the quotient system S/E = (M/E, R/E) i sconnected iff for any two components X = (MX, RX ) and Y = (MY, RY) of S, thereexist a natural number n and n components Si = (Mi ,R i ) of S, i = 1, 2, . . . , n,such that there exist x ∈ MX ,y ∈ M Y and mxi , m y i ∈ M i , i = 1, 2, . . . , n, satisfying( x,mx1 ) ∈ E, ( mxi ,m+1 y i ) ∈ E, i = 1, 2, . . . , n – 1, and ( myn ,y) ∈ E.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose that the quotient system S/E = (M/E, R/E) isconnected, and there exist two components X = (MX , RX ) and Y = (MY , RY ) of Ssuch that there do not exist components Si = (Mi , Ri ) of S, i = 1, 2, . . . , n, for eachnatural number n, such that there exist x ∈ MX and y ∈ M Y and m xi , myi ∈ Mi , foreach i, satisfying (x,m x1) ∈ E, (mx i , m+1 y i ) ∈ E, i = 1, 2, . . . , n – 1, and (my n ,y) ∈E.

Pick objects x ∈ MX and y ∈ MY . We then make a claim.

Claim. The subsystems

and

of the quotient system S/E are not identical, where µ : M → M/E is the canonicalmapping.

Page 228: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

222 Chapter 9

This claim implies that the quotient system S/E is not connected. In fact,from the hypothesis that the quotient system S/E is connected, it follows that foreach object µ(m) ∈ M /E, the connected component of S/E containing the objectµ(m) must equal the whole system S/E.

We now see the proof of Claim 1. It suffices to show that Star∞ ({ µ (x)}) ≠Star∞ ( {µ(y)}). To this end, it suffices to show that

(9.113)

which we do by contradiction. Suppose that

(9.114)

for some x ∈ MX and some y ∈ MY . Choosewhere m is an object in M. Then there exist components and (Myi , z), for i = 1, 2, . . . , n and j = 1, 2, . . . , m, for some natural numbers n andm, such that there are objects xi , mx i ∈ Mxi and y j , m y ∈ Mj yj

, for each i = 1, 2, . . . , nand j = 1, 2, . . . , m, such that (x, x1), (x i+1, m x ) ∈ E, for i = 1, 2, . . . , n – 1, andi

, for j = 1, 2, . . . , m – 1. This contradictsthe assumption in the first paragraph of the necessary part of the proof.

Sufficiency. Suppose that for any two components X = (MX ,RX ) and Y =(MY , RY ) of S, there exist a natural number n and components Si = (Mi,Ri ) of S,i = 1, 2, . . . , n, such that there exist x ∈ MX , y ∈ M Y , and mx i , m y i ∈ Mi , for eachi = 1, 2, . . . , n, satisfying , i = 1, 2, . . . , n – 1.To show that S/E is connected, it suffices to verify that, for each object x ∈ M,

Star∞ ({µ(x)}) = M / E (9.115)

by Corollary 9.4.1.It is clear that Star∞({µ (x)}) ⊂ M/E. Suppose M/E ≠ Star ∞({µ (x)}). We

can then pick an object [m ] ∈ M/E – Star∞ ({µ (x)}), where m is an object inM. This implies that there are two connected components X = (M X ,RX ) andY = (MY , R Y ), such that x ∈ M X and m ∈ M Y and for any two objects mx ∈MX and m y ∈ M Y there do not exist connected components Si = (Mi , Ri ) of S,i = 1, 2, . . . , n, for any n ∈ such that there exist mxi , myi ∈ M i , i = 1, 2, . . . , n,satisfying , i = 1, 2, . . . , n – 1, contradictionwhich implies that M/E = Star∞ ({µ( x )}) . �

Theorem 9.4.8. Let {Si : i ∈ I } be a set of systems such that there exists ani0 ∈ I such that the system Si 0

is connected. Then the Cartesian product system∏ cp {Si : i ∈ I} is connected.

Proof: Pick objects and from the Cartesian productsystem ∏cp {Si : i ∈ I}. Then and . From Theorem

Page 229: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 223

9.4.1 it follows that there are a natural number n > 0 and n relations rj ∈ R i 0 ,j = 1, 2, . . . , n, such that

and

(9.116)

(9.117)

Therefore, the relations satisfy

and

(9.119)

for each i = 1, 2, …, n–1. Applying Theorem 9.4.1 we have proved the theorem. �

Theorem 9.4.9. Let {Si : i ∈ I} be a set of systems such that the product ∏{S i :i ∈ I} is connected. Then each factor system Si is connected.

Proof: Pick two arbitrary objects xi and y i from a system Si for any fixed i ∈ I.There then are two objects x and y in the product system such that pi (x) = x i andpi (y) = y i . From the hypothesis that the product system is connected, it followsthat there are a natural number n > 0 and n relations r j from the product system,j = 1,2, . . . , n, such that

x ∈ Supp ( r1 ) and y ∈ Supp(rn )

and

for each j = 1, 2, …, n–1. Then the relations pi (rj) ∈ R i , j = 1, 2, . . . , n, satisfy

and

(9.121)

(9.122)

(9.120)

(9.123)

for each j = 1, 2, . . . , n–1. Theorem 9.4.1 implies that Si is connected. �

Page 230: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

224 Chapter 9

9.5. Hierarchies of Systems

Let (T, ≤) be a partially ordered set with order type α. An α -type hierarchyS of systems over the partially ordered set (T, ≤ ) is a function defined on T suchthat for each t ∈ T,S( t) = S t = ( Mt , Rt ) is a system, called the state of the α-typehierarchy S at the moment t. Without causing confusion, we omit the words “overthe partially ordered set (T, ≤) .”

For an α-type hierarchy S of systems, let l tr : S r → S t be a mapping from thesystem Sr into the system St, for any r, t ∈ T, with r ≥ t such that

and (9.124)

where r, s, t are arbitrary elements in T satisfying s ≥ r ≤ t, and idSt = idMt isthe identity mapping on the set Mt . The family { lt s : t, s ∈ T, s ≥ t } is a familyof linkage mappings of the α-type hierarchy S, and each mapping l ts a linkagemapping from Ss into S t .

An α-type hierarchy of systems S, denoted {S, l Tt s } or {S(t), l t s , T}, isreferred to as a linked α-type hierarchy (of systems) if a family {l t s : t, s ∈ T, s ≥ t}of linkage mappings is given.

Theorem 9.5.1 [ZFC]. Let S be a nontrivial α -type hierarchy of systems; i.e.,each state S t is a nontrivial system. Then there exists a family {l ts : t,s ≤ T, s ≥ t}of linkage mappings of S.

Proof: Suppose S ), for each t ∈ T. From the Axiom of Choiceit follows that there exists a choice function C : T →

t = (Mt , Rt

{Mt : t ∈ T} such thatC (t) ∈ M t for each t ∈ T. A family { l t s : t ,s ∈ T, s ≥ t} of linkage mappings ofS can now be defined. For any s, t ∈ T with s > t, let

l t s (X) = C(t) (9.125)

for all x ∈ Ms and l tt = idMt. �

Question 9.5.1. How many families of linkage mappings are there for a givenα -type hierarchy of systems?

Suppose {S, l t s , T} is a linked α-type hierarchy of systems, where St = ( Mt , Rt )for all t ∈ T. An element is called a thread of the linkedα -type hierarchy S if lt s (xs ) = x t for all s, t ∈ T with s ≥ t. Let be the subset of all threads, which will be called the thread set of the hierarchy{ S, l t s , T}.

Page 231: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 225

Theorem 9.5.2 [ZFC]. Let κ be a cardinal number and S an α -type hierarchy ofsystems such that Mt ≥ κ for each t ∈ T. Then for any nonzero cardinal numberκ ' ≤ κ, there exists a family { l ts : t, s ∈ T, s ≥ t} of linkage mappings of S suchthat ∑ ≥ k '.

Proof: From the hypothesis that for any t ∈ T, Mt ≥ κ ', and the Axiom ofChoice, it follows that, for any t ∈ T, there exist At ⊂ Mt satisfying At = κ ', andan equivalence relation Et on the object set Mt such that Mt /Et = { [a]Et : a ∈ A t}and that for any distinct a, b ∈ At ,

(9.126)

Again, from the Axiom of Choice it follows that there exists a set of well-orderrelations {≤ t : t ∈ T} such that, for each t ∈ T, the relation ≤ t well-orders At asfollows:

(9.127)

For any s, t ∈ T with s > t, we now define a mapping l t s : S s → St . For any x ∈ Ms ,there exists exactly one α < κ such that x ∈ [a α s ]Es

. Then define

(9.128)

Then { lt s : t, s ∈ T, s ≥ t} is a family of linkage mappings, where lt t = idS t , andfor any t ∈ T. Thus

Question 9.5.2. Suppose that S is an α -type hierarchy of systems over a partiallyordered set (T, ≤) and { l t s : s, t ∈ T* , s ≥ t} is a family of linkage mappings of thehierarchy of systems {St : t ∈ T * }, where T* is a proper subset of T. Under whatconditions does there exist a family of linkage mappings forS such that

(9.129)

for all s, t ∈ T * with s ≥ t?

Lemma 9.5.1 [ZFC]. Let D ⊂ T be a cofinal and coinitial subset in a partiallyordered set (T, ≤ ). Then there exists a subset T* = D*_ ∪ D*

+ of D such that

(a) for some ordinals η andξ such that

(9.130)

Page 232: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

226 Chapter 9

(b) Let then D +β is a maximal

antichain in D – E+β for any β < η.

(c) Let Then D –β is a maximal

antichain in D – E –β for each β < ξ.

(d) T * is cofinal and coinitial in T.

Proof: First, note the construction of D *+ . From the Axiom of Choice it

follows that there exists an order relation ≤ * on T which well-orders T as

(9.131)

where ≤ and ≤ * are generally different. Let d0 be the < * -initial element of D,and D 1

0 ⊂ D such that

and d0 and d are incomparable under ≤} (9.132)

If otherwise, let d1 be the initial element of (D 10 , < *).

Suppose that sequences {dα : α < η} and {Dα0 : 0 ≠ α < η } have been defined,

for some ordinal η > 1, such that

(i) {dα : α < η} is an antichain under the order <.

(ii) for all α, β < η with α > β.

(iii) For each α < η, d α is the initial element of the well-ordered set (D α0 , ≤ * ).

(iv) For each α < η , dα < *d, for all d ∈ D β0 , and dα is incomparable with d

under the relation <, for each d ∈ Dβ0 , for each β with α < β < η.

If η is a limit ordinal, let

(9.133)

If . Then D +0 is a maximal antichain in D under ≤.

If be the initial element of (D η0 , < *). By (iv) {dα : α < η + 1} is

an antichain under the relation ≤; and for each α < η, d α < *d for each d ∈ D η0 ,

dα and d are incomparable under ≤ for each d ∈ D η0 .

If η = ξ + 1 is isolated, let be defined by

and d are incomparable under ≤} (9.134)

If then D +0 is a maximal antichain in D under the

order ≤ . If let d η be the initial element of (D η0 , ≤ *). Then [dα : α < η + 1}

is an antichain in D under ≤ , and for all β < η. For each α < η + 1,

Page 233: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 227

d α < * d, for all d ∈ D β0

, and dα is incomparable with d ∈ Dβ0 under ≤ for any β,

with α < β < η + 1.By transfinite induction, sequences {dα : α < η } and wi th

properties (i)–(iv) can be defined, such that if a subset withproperty (iv) can be defined in the way discussed earlier, it must be that Dη = Ø0

Let Then D +0 is a maximal antichain in (D, ≤ ). Using

transfinite induction to consider sets such that x > d } andand applying the same technique we used before,

we can show that ordinals η and ξ and subsetsand 0 ≠ β < ξ, exist such that properties (a)–(d) in the lemma hold. �

Theorem 9.5.3 [ZFC]. Suppose that S is an α -type hierarchy of systems over apartially ordered set (T, ≤ ) such that there exists a cofinal and coinitial subsetD ⊂ T such that is a family of linkage mappings for thehierarchy of systems {St : t ∈ D } satisfying

(9.135)

for any s,r,t ∈ D with s ≥ r > t. Then there exists a subset T* ⊂ D such that

(i) T* is cofinal and coinitial in T.

(ii) There is a family of linkage mappings for S.

(iii) For any s, t ∈ T* with

Proof: Let T* ⊂ D be the subset defined in the proof of Lemma 9.5.1. Let usrewrite T = TL ∪ TR where,,

(9.136)

and

(9.137)

and pick one t ∈ T. There are two possibilities: (1) t ∈ TL and (2) t ∈ TR .Case 1: t ∈ TL . There then exists an ordinal α < ξ such that there exists

and assume that α is the initial one in ξ with this property.If Now we assume that eα < t.

If α = δ + 1 is isolated, there exists such that From theAxiom of Choice it follows that for any s ∈ T satisfying there existan As ⊂ M s such that an equivalence relation Es on Ms

such that and satisfies, for any distinct a, b ∈ As ,

(9.138)

Page 234: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

228 Chapter 9

and a set of well-order relations such that, for any s ∈ Tsatisfying eα < s < e δ, the relation < s well-orders Ms /Es as follows:

(9.139)

wherefollows:

for all i < As , and the relation < eα well-orders as

(9.140)

We now define mappings for all s, t ∈ T, with eα ≤ s < t < e δas follows: For any x ∈ Mt there exists exactly one at i ∈ At such thatIf s > eα , let

(9.141)

If s = eα, let

(9.142)

Define mappings for all s ∈ T with e α < s < e δ as follows:

(9.143)

If α is a limit ordinal, then by definition α > 0. Let

(9.144)

From the Axiom of Choice it follows that for any s ∈ T α , there exists an As ⊂ Ms

satisfying where q ∈ D –0 satisfies t < q. An equivalence relation

Es on Ms exists such that satisfies, for any distinctbe a set of order relations such

that, for any s ∈ Tα , the relation <s well-orders Ms /Es as follows:

(9.145)

where for all i, and the relation <eα well-orders as follows:

(9.146)

We now define mappings for all as follows: Forany x ∈ Mj there exists exactly one such that let

(9.147)

Page 235: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 229

If j = eα , let

(9.148)

Define mappings for all s ∈ T α and all δ < α by

(9.149)

Then it is easy to check that is a family of linkage mappings,where Furthermore, for any s, t ∈ T L with s > t, if t s is undefinedabove, then there exist α, β < ξ such that there exist dα ∈ D –

α and dβ ∈ D β , withdβ < t < d α < s. Let α and β be the least ordinals with this property. (1) Ifβ = δ + 1, then there exists exactly one d δ ∈ D–

δ such that dβ < t ≤ dδ. Define

(9.150)

(2) If β is a limit ordinal, define

(9.151)

Case 2: t ∈ TR . A similar method can be used to define a familyT, t ≥ s} of linkage mappings such that for any s, t ∈ D *

+ with s ≤ t.Now let s ∈ TR and TL satisfying s > t. There exists exactly one q ∈ D +

0 suchthat t ≤ q ≤ s. Define Then is a family oflinkage mappings for S such that for all s, t ∈ T * with s ≥ t. �

Let H = {S, l t s , T } and H' = {S', l t's' , T'} be two hierarchies of systems. Amapping from the hierarchy H into the hierarchy H' is a set {φ,ƒt '} of mappings,where φ is a nondecreasing mapping from T' into T with φ(T') cofinal in T, andfor each t' ∈ T' ,ƒt' is a mapping from Sφ( t ') into S't' such that

(9.152)

i.e., such that the diagram in Fig. 9.2 commutes for any s', t' ∈ T' satisfying s' ≥ t'.A mapping {φ ,ƒt '} from H into H' is a similarity mapping if φ is a similarity

mapping from T' onto T and each is a similarity mapping. It iseasy to show that is a similarity mapping from H' into H.

When the partially ordered set (T, ≤ ) is a pseudo-tree (i.e., for each t ∈ T theset {y ∈ T : y ≤ x } is a chain), each hierarchy S of systems over T is called atreelike hierarchy of systems; each linked hierarchy {S, lt s , T} of systems is calleda linked treelike hierarchy of systems. A treelike hierarchy B of systems over atree T is a partial treelike hierarchy of a treelike hierarchy A of systems over thesame tree T if for each t ∈ T, the state B t is a partial system of the state At .

Page 236: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

230 Chapter 9

Figure 9.2. A hierarchy mapping guarantees the diagram is commutative.

Theorem 9.5.4 [ZFC]. Let {S, l t s ,T } be a linked treelike hierarchy of systemssuch that the partially ordered set (T, ≤ ) satisfies

(i) T has a subset T0 consisting of all minimal elements in T such that foreach t ∈ T, there exists at0 ∈ T 0 such that t0 ≤ t.

(ii) There exists a cofinal subset D ⊂ T such that l t s is an onto mapping for alls,t ∈ D ∪ T0 with s ≥ t.

Then there exists a nontrivialpartial linked hierarchy of {S, lt s , T}such that the state S' ( t ) is embeddable in the state S'( s ) for all t,s ∈ T with s ≥ t.

Proof: From Lemma 9.5.1 it follows that there exists D* ⊂ D such that

(a) for some ordinal η > 0.

(b) D *β is a maximal antichain in D – Eβ , for each β < η , where

(c) D * is cofinal in T.

Let ≤ * indicate the order relation on T defined in the proof of Lemma 9.5.1.From the hypothesis that lt s is onto for any s,t ∈ D ∪ T0 with s ≥ t , it follows thateach linkage mapping l t0 r is onto, for all r ∈ T and t0 ∈ T0 satisfying r ≥ t0. Let d 0

be the initial element of the well-ordered set (D* , ≤ *). We define an equivalencerelation Ed0 on Md0 such that the equivalence class

(9.153)

for each m ∈ Md0. By transfinite induction, for each element d in (D *, ≤ * ) anequivalence relation Ed on the object set Md of the state Sd can be defined suchthat the equivalence class

(9.154)

Page 237: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 231

The linkage mapping lt r , for any t,r ∈ D* with r ≥ t , can induce a mappingfrom Sr / Er onto S t / E t such that

(9.155)

where [mt]Et ∈ Mt / Et satisfies l t r(mr ) = m t . In fact, for each [mr ] Er ∈ Mr / Er ,there exists exactly one [mt] Et ∈ Mt / Et such that

(9.156)

Therefore, and is well defined.For any maximal linearly ordered set B ⊂ D* T0 , called a branch, Lemma

9.5.1 implies that (B , ≤ ) is well-ordered. Let b be the initial element in B. For anyfixed element x ∈ Mb , from the fact that (B, ≤ ) is well-ordered and AC, it followsthat there exists an element such that

(9.157)

and that there exists an element such that

(9.158)

for all i,j ∈ B with i ≥ j.From AC it follows that there exists a subset

such that, for each x ∈ Mb,

(9.159)

where l t s (gs) = g t , for all s,t ∈ B with s ≥ t. Let P d : M (B) → Md , for each d ∈ B,be the projection, and define

(9.160)

Then is a hierarchy of systems and a partial linked hierarchyof

Let X be the set of all branches in the set D* T0. By transfinite induction,hierarchies of systems, for each B ∈ X , can be defined such thatfor any branches C ,B ∈ X and d ∈ C B,

(9.161)

Here we used the hypothesis that T is a pseudotree. Therefore, for each d ∈ D* T0,we can define

(9.162)

Page 238: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

232 Chapter 9

where B is a branch containing d. Then S ' d is a partial system of S d andis a nontrivial linked hierarchy of systems such that the state

S’ (t ) = S't is embeddable in the state S’(s) = S’s , for any t,s ∈ D * T0 satisfyingt ≤ s.

For any t ∈ T – ( D * T0 ), choose s ∈ D* such that s ∈ D*α , where α is the

least ordinal in η with this property, and s > t. We take a partial system S' of thetsystem St defined by

(9.163)

Then it is not hard to check that is a nontrivial partial linkedhierarchy of {S , l t s, T } such that the state S’ (t ) is embeddable in the state S’(s )for any s,t ∈ T , with s ≥ t.

When the partially ordered set (T, ≤ ) is a total ordering, each hierarchy S ofsystems over T is called a time system; each linked hierarchy {S , l t s, T} of systemsis called a linked time system. In this case, T is called the time set (or time axis)of the time system S.

An ordered triple (T, +, ≤ ) is called an ordered Abelian group if (T, +) isan Abelian group and (T, ≤ ) is a linearly ordered set such that for any elements

(9.164)

We conclude this section with a discussion of time systems over orderedAbelian groups. This kind of time system is called a system over a group. If thetime system is also a linked time system, we call the system a linked system overa group.

Suppose (T, +, ≤ ) is an ordered Abelian group. We let 0 be the identity in T,and, for any x ∈ T, x indicates the absolute value of x, defined by

x = max{ – x,x } (9.165)

where –x is the additive inverse of x. For any integer n ,

if n = 0if n > 0

if n < 0(9.166)

Page 239: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 233

The following notation will be used:

Let S be a system over a group and t0 ∈ T a fixed element. The right transfor-mation of S, denoted S –t 0, is defined by S – t0 ( t) = S ( t – t0) for each t ∈ T ; the lefttransformation of S, denoted S+t 0 , is defined by S +t0 (t ) = S( t + t0) for each t ∈ T.

Theorem 9.5.5. Suppose that S is a system over a group. Then for any a,b ∈ T,

and

A system S over a group T is periodic if there exists p ∈ T such that p ≠ 0 andS +p = S. The element p is called a period of S.

Theorem 9.5.6. Let S be a system over a group T. If S is periodic with p ∈ Tas its period, then for each integer n, S np = S, where Snp = S +np if n ≥ 0, andS np = S – [(– n) p ] if n < 0.

Proof: We show the theorem by induction on n.Case 1 : n ≥ 0. If n = 0, the result is clear. Suppose S+kp = S for each integer

k satisfying 0 ≤ k < n. Then it follows that

Thus, by induction, we have S+np = S for each n ≥ 0.Case 2: n < 0. If n = –1, in the condition that S ( t + p ) = S ( t ), for each

t ∈ T , let t = x – p. Then S (x) = S (x – p ) for each x ∈ T. This says that S– p = S .Suppose S –kp = S for each integer k satisfying 0 ≤ k < –n. Then it follows that

Page 240: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

234 Chapter 9

Hence, by induction we have showed that Snp = S for each integer n < 0.Combining cases 1 and 2 completed the proof.

Corollary 9.5.1. If a system S over a group is periodic, there then is a positiveperiod for S.

A linked system {S, lt s , T} over a group is periodic, if S is a periodic systemover a group with a period such that for any t, s ∈ T satisfyings ≥ t. This element in T is called a period of the linked system {S, l t s , T}.

Theorem 9.5.7. If is a period of a linked system {S, lt s, T } over a group, thenso is n for each integer n ≠ 0.

The proof is straightforward and is omitted.

Theorem 9.5.8. Suppose that a linked system {S, lt s, T } over a group is periodicwith > 0 as a period. Then the hierarchy is similar to thehierarchy for any integer n.

Proof: First we show that n < (n + 1) for each integer n. In fact, ifn ≥ ( n + 1) for some integer n, then

(9.167)

This contradicts the hypothesis that > 0.Second, we define a mapping by

(9.168)

Then φ is a similarity mapping from the ordered set onto the orderedset We next define mappings for each a sidentity mappings. Then {φ,ƒx } is a similarity mapping from the hierarchy H intothe hierarchy K.

Corollary 9.5.2. In Theorem 9.5.8, the ordered sets and can bereplaced by each of the following pairs:

Generally, for a periodic system {S, lt s,T } over a group, the hierarchiesand are not similar.

Page 241: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

9.6. Controllabilities

The concept of controllability of systems was originally introduced as a prop-erty of input–output systems. The main idea behind the concept says that aninput–output system S is controllable provided that, if we need to obtain someoutput of the system with certain predetermined properties, we then can find someinput such that the corresponding output satisfies the required properties. In thissection we study different concepts of controllability not only of input–outputsystems but also of general systems.

Let S = ( M,R ) be an input–output system with input space X and output spaceY. In the following, the symbols (x ,y) andwill be used congruently, where andWe now define

(9.169)

(9.170)

(9.171)

(9.172)

(9.173)

(9.174)

(9.175)

for any i ∈ o( X),

for any j ∈ o (Y ),

and

and

Suppose V is a set and G a mapping such that

G : Dom( X) × Ran( Y ) → V

For an element v ∈ V, the system S is v -controllable relative to G if and only ifthere exists a mapping cg : Dom( X ) → Dam( X ) such that, for any x ∈ Dom( X ) ,there exists a yx ∈ Ran(Y ) such that

(9.176)

The mapping cg is called a control function of S.

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 235

Page 242: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

236

G(cg(x), yz ) = v

Chapter 9

For example, suppose we are processing a chemical reaction. To reach acollection of desired results (denoted by yx ) which satisfy an assigned target(denoted by v), we could choose various methods (denoted by x) for processingthe wanted results. But, in order to control the whole reaction procedure, we mayadd relative materials [denoted by cg(x)] together with those “choices” we havehad. We would like to deem the “input” (the relative materials) as “control” forthe whole reaction procedure.

Theorem 9.6.1. For each element v ∈ V, the input–output system S is v-controllable relative to the mapping G iff v ∈ G(Dom(X) × Ran(Y )).

Proof: The necessity part of the proof follows from Eq. (9.176).Sufficiency. Let v ∈ G (Dom(X) × Ran( Y )). Then there exists (x, y) ∈

Dom(X) × Ran( Y ) such that G(x, y) = v. Define a control function of S ,cg : Dom(X) → Dom( X), as follows: cg(w) = x for all w ∈ D o m ( X). Thenfor each w ∈ Dom(X) there exists yw = y ∈ Ran(Y ) such that

G(cg(w), yw ) = G(x, y) = v�

Let V' ⊂ V be a subset. The input–output system S is controllable on V' relativeto G : Dom(X) × Ran(Y ) → V iff there exists a mapping cg : Dom(X) → Dom(X )such that, for each v ∈ V' and any x ∈ Dom( X), there exists yz = y (v, x) ∈ Ran(Y )such that

(9.177)

The mapping cg is called a control function of S.

Theorem 9.6.2. For a subset V' ⊂ V, the input–output system S is controllableon V' relative to the mapping G iff there exists an element x ∈ Dom(X) such thatG({x} × Ran(Y )) ⊃ V'.

Proof: Necessity. Let cg : Dom(X) → Dom( X) be a control function ofthe system S. Then, for each v ∈ V' and each x ∈ cg(Dom( X)), there exists ay ∈ Ran( Y ) such that G (x, y) = v. Hence, G (x, Ran(Y)) ⊃ V' .

Sufficiency. Suppose there exists an element x ∈ Dom(X) such that G ({x } ×Ran(Y )) ⊃ V'. Define a control function cg : Dom(X) → Dom( X) by lettingcg(w) = x for all w ∈ Dom( X). Clearly, each v ∈ V' and any w ∈ Dom( X), thereexists a y ∈ Ran(Y ) such that

G(cg(w), y ) = G(x, y) = v

Page 243: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 237

Therefore, S is controllable on V' relative to G. �

For V' ⊂ V, the input–output system S is collectively controllable on V'relative to the mapping G : Dom(X )× Ran(Y ) → V iff there exists a mappingcg : Dom(X) → p(Dom(X)), where p(Dom(X)) is the power set of Dom(X), suchthat for any v ∈ V' and any x ∈ Dom(X), there exists y = y(v, x) ∈ Ran(Y ) suchthat

G(z, y) = v for some z ∈ cg(x ) (9.178)

Theorem 9.6.3. For a subset V' ⊂ V, the input–output system S is collectivelycontrollable on V' relative to the mapping G : Dom(X ) × Ran(Y ) → V iff thereexists a nonempty subset A ⊆ Dom(X) such that G(A × Ran(Y )) ⊇ V'.

Proof: Necessity. Let cg : Dom(X) → p (Dom(X)) be a control function forS. Then for any v ∈ V' and each x ∈ Dom( X), there exists a y ∈ Ran(Y ) suchthat G(z, y) = v for some z ∈ cg(x). Hence, there exists an x ∈ Dom(X ) such thatG(cg(x) × Ran(Y )) ⊇ V ', where cg(x) ≠ Ø.

Sufficiency. Suppose there exists a nonempty subset A ⊆ Dom( X) such thatG(A × Ran(Y )) ⊇ V'. Let us define a control function cg : Dom(X) → p (Dom(X ))as follows: cg(x) = A for all x ∈ D o m ( X). Then for any v ∈ V' there exists(z, y) ∈ A × Ran( Y ) such that G(z, y) = v. This implies that, for any v ∈ V' andany x ∈ Dom(X), there exists y = y (v, x) ∈ Ran(Y ) such that G(z, y) = v. Thiscompletes the proof of the theorem. �

Examples can be given to show that not all systems are input–output systems.In the following, we study the concept of controllability of general systems.

Suppose S = (M, R) is a general system. For any relation r ∈ R and any ordinalnumber µ > 0, we define the µ-initial section of r, denoted by I( rµ ), as follows:For any x ∈ I(r µ ) ⊂ M µ , there exists y ∈ M v such that (x, y) ∈ r, where v is anonzero ordinal number such that µ + v = n(r) such that r ⊂ M

n (r). We define

the µ-final section of r, denoted by E(rµ ), as follows: for any x ∈ E(r µ ) ⊂ Mv,

there exists y ∈ I(r µ ) such that (y, x) ∈ r.Let

(9.179)

(9.180)

(9.181)

and

and (9.182)

Page 244: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

238 Chapter 9

If M * ⊂ M,

and (9.183)

are used to indicate all the elements in I R and all the elements in E R, respectively,in which only the elements of M* appear as coordinates.

Let V be an another set and V' ⊂ V. The general system S is generallycontrollable on V' relative to a mapping

(9.184)

if, for each v ∈ V', there exist a set Wv, an M v ⊂ M, and a mapping

(9.185)

such that for each u ∈ W v there exists a yu ∈ ER such that

for some (9.186)

The mapping C v is called a control function of S.The main idea of general controllability of systems is the following. Suppose

we are given a set of desired targets V. For each v ∈ V, there exists a set of“commands” given to a system S so that S can realize the desired target v. WhenS receives the commands, there will be some “well-organized” objects of S toaccomplish the task. Therefore, there should be some “receivers” and “accom-plishers” in S such that the whole process of executing the task is under a goodcontrol with a “fine” cooperation between the “receivers” and the “accomplishers.”

Theorem 9.6.4. Let S be a general system and V' ⊂ V a subset. Then S isgenerally controllable on V' relative to a mapping iff thereexists a nonempty subset MV ' ⊂ V such that for some nonempty

Proof: Necessity. Suppose S is generally controllable on V' relative to G.Then for each v ∈ V' there exist M v ⊂ M and a nonempty A v suchthat

(9.187)

Let and Then

(9.188)

and from Eq. (9.187) we have G( A × E R) ⊃ V'.

Page 245: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 239

Sufficiency. Suppose there exists a nonempty subset MV' ⊂ M such that forsome nonempty Thus, for each v ∈ V' thereare subsets Av ⊂ A and B v ⊂ ER such that

G(Av × Bv ) = {v} (9.189)

Define Mv ⊂ M by ON (m = x µ )}. Let Wv be anynonempty set and a mapping defined by Cv ( u) = A v foreach u ∈ Wv. Then for each u ∈ Wv there exists a yu ∈ Bv ⊂ E R such that

G(z,yu ) = v for some z ∈ Cv (u)

This proves the assertion. �

Proposition 9.6.1. Suppose that S = (M, R) is an input–output system with inputspace X and output space Y, and that S is v-controllable relative to a mappingG : Dom(X) × Ran(Y ) → V. Then S is generally controllable on {v} relative tothe mapping where G * is an extension of G.

Proof: Because Dom(X ) ⊂ I R and Ran(Y ) ⊂ ER, we can define extensionsfor the mapping G.

We now show the general controllability of S. For v ∈ {v} there exist a setWv = Dom(X) and a mapping

(9.190)

defined by Cv (u) = {cg(u)}, where cg : Dom(X) → Dom(X) is a control functionfor S. Hence, for each u ∈ Wvthere exists a yu ∈ Ran(Y ) ⊂ E R such that

(9.191)

�where cg(u) ∈ Cv (u).

Proposition 9.6.2. Let V' ⊂ V be a subset such that an input–output system S =(M, R) is controllable on V' relative to a mapping G : Dom(X) × Ran( Y ) → V,where X and Y are the input and the output spaces of S, respectively. Then S isgenerally controllable on V' relative to each extension G* of G.

Proof: For each v ∈ V' there exist sets W v = Dom(X) and M v = M and amapping

(9.192)

Page 246: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Chapter 9240

defined by Cv (u) = {cg(u)} for each u ∈ Wv . Then for each u ∈ Wu , there existsyu = y (v, u) ∈ Ran(Y ) ⊂ ER such that

(9.193)

where cg(u) ∈ C v (u). �

Proposition 9.6.3. Suppose that S = (M, R) is an input–output system with inputspace X and output space Y such that S is collectively controllable on V' relativeto a mapping G : Dom(X) × Ran(Y ) → V. Let be an extensionof G. Then S is generally controllable on V' relative to G* .

Proof: For each v ∈ V' there exist sets Wv = Dom(X) and M v = M and amapping

(9.194)

such that, for each u ∈ Wv , there exists yu = y (v, u) ∈Ran(Y ) ⊂ ER such that

G* (z, y z ) = G (z,yu ) = v (9.195)

for some z ∈ Cv (u ) = cg(u). �

Theorem 9.6.5. Suppose that h : S1 = (M1 , R1 ) → S = (M, R) is an S-continuousmapping from a system S1 into a system S such that S is generally controllable onV' relative to a mapping Then S1 is generally controllable onV' relative to a mapping

Proof: First, we construct a desired mapping Let v0 ∈ Vbe a fixed element. For any x ∈ I R 1 and y ∈ E R1 , if there exist relations rx , ry ∈ Rsuch that

and (9.196)

then define

G1 (x,y) = G (h(x),h(y)) (9.197)

If either rx or ry or both do not exist, we define

G1 (x,y) = v0 (9.198)

defined by Cv (u) = cg(u)

Page 247: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 241

It can be shown that is well defined.Second, we show that S1 is generally controllable on V' relative to

Suppose that for each v ∈ V' there exist sets W v and Mv ⊂ M and amapping Cv : Wv → p(I R(Mv )) such that, for each u ∈ Wv , there exists a yu ∈ E Rsuch that G (z,yu ) = v for some z ∈ Cv (u). We now let h– 1 (Mv ) ⊂ M 1 and definea control function as follows: For each u ∈ Wv ,

(9.199)

Now it only remains to show that ¹Cv is a control function of S1 . In fact, for eachu ∈ W there exists y ∈ E

v u R such that

G( z,y ) = v for some z ∈ C v (u) (9.200)u

so there exists such that

where Therefore, S 1 is generally controllable on V' relativeto G1 .

Theorem 9.6.6. Let {Si : i ∈ I } be a set of systems, where I is an index set, suchthat there exists an i 0 ∈ I such that the system Si 0 is generally controllable on V'relative to a mapping Then the Cartesian product systemΠcp {S i : i ∈ I } is also generally controllable on V' (relative to a different mapping

where it is assumed that(M,R).

The proof follows from Theorems 9.3.10 and 9.6.5.

Theorem 9.6.7. Suppose that h : S = (M, R) → S 1 = (M1 ,R1) is an embeddingmapping from a system S into a system S 1 such that S is generally controllable onV’ relative to a mapping G : I R × ER → V. Then, S 1 is generally controllable onV’ relative to a mapping G1 : I R1 × E R1 → V.

Proof: We first construct a desired mapping Let v 0 ∈ Vbe a fixed element. For any x ∈ IR1 and y ∈ ER1 , if there exist x* ∈ I R and y* ∈ ERsuch that h(x* ) = x and h (y* ) = y, we define

G 1 (x,y) = G (x* ,y* ) (9.201)

Page 248: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

242 Chapter 9

From the hypothesis that h is 1–1, we see that Eq. (9.201) is well-defined, for theexistence of x * and y * is unique. If one or both of the elements x* and y* do notexist, then we define

G (x,y) = v (9.202)1 0

We then have defined a mappingSecond, we show that the system S1 is generally controllable on V' relative to

the mapping G1 . Suppose that for each v ∈ V' there exist sets W v and M v ⊂ Mand a mapping such that, for each u ∈ Wv , there exists ay E

u ∈ R such that G(z,yu ) = v for some z ∈ Cv (u). We now let h(M v ) ⊂ M 1 anddefine a control function as follows: For each u ∈ Wv ,

(9.203)

It remains to show that ¹1 C v is indeed a control function for S1 . For each u ∈ W v

there exists a y Eu ∈ R such that

G(z,yu ) = v for some z ∈ C v (u) (9.204)

Therefore,

(9.205)

where and

Corollary 9.6.1. If a subsystem A = (MA , RA ) of a system S = (M, R) is generallycontrollable on V’ relative to a mapping then S is generallycontrollable on V' relative to a mapping

Theorem 9.6.8. Let {Si = (Mi , Ri ) : i ∈ I } be a set of systems and {Vi ⊂ V : i ∈ I}a set of nonempty subsets of V. If each system S i is generally controllable on the

is generally controllable on ∪subset Vi relative to a mapping then ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I } = (M , R)

{V i : i ∈ I} relative to a mappingwhere for each i ∈ I and any

Proof: From the definition of free sums of systems, it follows that

(9.206)

where for any distinct i,j ∈ I. Let G be an extension ofthe mappings {Gi : i ∈ I}; i.e., G is a mapping from I R × E R into V such that forany then G(x,y) = G i (x,y).

Page 249: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 243

To show that the free sum ⊕ {Si : i ∈ I} is generally controllable on ∪ { Vi : i ∈ I}relative to G, we pick an arbitrary v ∈ ∪ { Vi : i ∈ I}. Then there exists an i ∈ Isuch that v ∈ V i . Therefore, there exist sets Wv and Mv ⊂ Mi ⊂ ∪ {Mj : j ∈ I} anda mapping

(9.207)

such that for each u ∈ Wv , there exists a yu ∈ ERi ⊂ ER such that

G(z,yu ) = v for some z ∈ C v (u) (9.208)

This proves the theorem.

In the following, we conclude this section with a discussion of controllabilitiesof time systems.

Theorem 9.6.9. Suppose that {S , l t s, T } is a linked time system. If there exists at ∈ T such that

(a) S t is a nondiscrete input–output system,

(b) for each s < t,

(c) for each s > t,

then each state Ss of the linked time system has a nondiscrete partial system whichis an input–output system.

Proof: Let St = ( Mt , Rt ) and X t and Y t be input and output spaces of the stateSt , respectively. If s < t, let be a partial system of the system Ss

defined by Then is a nondiscrete input–output system with input space ls t (X t ) and output space ls t (Y t ). Finally, if s > t,let be a partial system of S s defined byRs : l t s(r) ∈ Rt }. Then is a nondiscrete input–output system with input spaceX s = {x ∈ Ms : l t s (x ) ∈ X t } and output space Ys = {y ∈ Ms : l t s (y) ∈ Yt }.

Theorem 9.6.10. Suppose that {S, l t s , T } is a linked time system such that

(a) T has an initial element t0 .

(b) Each lt 0 s is surjective with lt 0s (Rs ) ∩ R t 0 ≠ Ø.

(c) St 0 is a nondiscrete input–output system with input space Xt 0 and outputspace Yt .0

(d) St 0 is v-controllable relative to a mapping G : Dom(Xt 0 ) × Ran( Yt 0 ) → V.

Page 250: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

244 Chapter 9

Then there exists a linked time system such that each state i s anondiscrete input–output system and is v-controllable relative to some mappingGt .

Proof: First we see the construction of the linked time system B yAC we well-order the time set T

t0 , t1 , . . . , tα , . . . ,α < T (9.209)

where t 0 is the initial element in T. Suppose that the original order on T is ≤ , andin Eq. (9.209) T is well-ordered by a well-order relation ≤ * . Generally, ≤ and< * are different.

Define Suppose that for some α < T the systemand the mappings have been defined such that for each

k < α and any i, r, j < α such that Now define andand and as follows: Let Etα be the equivalencerelation on the object set M t a defined byand

(9.210)

where and For each β < α ,if tα > tβ, define

(9.211)

for each where If tα < tβ , we define

(9.212)

for each where It is then not hard to provethat is a family of linkage mappings.

By transfinite induction, a linked time system is defined such thatand each state is a nondiscrete input–output system with input space

and output space

Second, we show that each state is v -controllable relative to some mapping

(9.213)

Let Dom and Ran For any x t ∈ Dom(X t ) thereexists x t 0 ∈ Dom (Xt 0 ) such that

(9.214)

Page 251: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 245

where cgt 0 is a control function of St 0 . Thus, there exists a y t 0 ∈ Ran(Yt 0) such that

(9.215)

Let a n d I f w e a s s i g n

t h e n

(9.216)

and Therefore, the sys-tem is v-controllable relative to the mapping Gt .

Theorem 9.6.11. Assume hypotheses (a)–(c) of Theorem 9.6. 10 and that St 0 i scontrollable on V’ ⊂ V relative to a mapping G : Dom (X t 0 ) × Ran (Yt 0) → V. Thenthere exists a linked time system such that each state is a nondiscreteinput–output system and is controllable on V' relative to some mapping Gt .

The proof is a slight modification of that of Theorem 9.6.10 and is omitted.

Theorem 9.6.12. Assume hypotheses (a)–(c) of Theorem 9.6.10 and that St 0 is col-lectively controllable on V* ⊂ V relative to a mapping G : Dom (Xt 0 ) × Ran (Yt 0 ) →V. Then there exists a linked time system such that each state Q t is anondiscrete input—output system and is collectively controllable on V* relative tosome mapping Gt .

The proof is a slight modification of that of Theorem 9.6.10 and is left to thereader.

9.7. Limit Systems

We say that is a category if consists of a class of objects, denoted by objpairwise disjoint sets of morphisms, denoted by Hom (A, B), for every ordered pairof objects (A, B), and a composition Hom (A, B) × Hom (B, C) → Hom (A, C),denoted by (ƒ, g) → gf, satisfying the following axioms:

(i) For each object A there exists an identity morphism IA ∈ Hom (A,A) suchthat ƒ I A = ƒ, for all ƒ ∈ Hom (A, B) and IA g = g, for all g ∈ Hom (C,A).

(ii) Associativity of composition holds whenever possible; that is, ifƒ ∈ Hom (A,B), g ∈ Hom (B,C) and h ∈ Hom (C,D), then

h(gƒ) = (hg)ƒ (9.217)

Page 252: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

246 Chapter 9

Figure 9.3. Universal mapping property of limit systems.

We give some examples of categories.a . Suppose is the category consisting of all general systems and all S-

continuous mappings between systems. Thus, for any two systems S1 and S 2 theset Hom equals the set of all S-continuous mappings from S1 into S 2 .

b. Suppose is the category consisting of all general systems and allhomomorphisms between systems. Thus, for two arbitrary systems S1 and S 2 theset Hom of morphisms equals the set of all homomorphisms from S1

into S2 .Let be an α-type hierarchy of systems in (respectively, in

i.e., each linkage mapping lt s is an S -continuous mapping (respectively, a homo-morphism). The inverse limit of this hierarchy, denoted by lim orlim ←C St (respectively, lim or lim , is a system and a family ofS-continuous mappings (respectively, homomorphisms

with whenever i ≤ j satisfying the univer-sal mapping property, contained in Fig. 9.3 (respectively, the universal mappingproperty, contained in Fig. 9.4) satisfying: For every system X and S-continuousmappings (respectively, homomorphisms) making the correspondingdiagram commute whenever i ≤ j, there exists a unique S-continuous mapping

(respectively, a homomorphism making thediagram commute.

Figure 9.4. Universal mapping property of limit systems.

Page 253: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 247

From the definition of inverse limits, it can be seen that if a linked hierarchyof systems has an inverse limit, the limit is unique up to a similarity.

Theorem 9.7.1. Let be a linked α -type hierarchy of systems in thecategory Then the inverse limit lim exists.

Proof: Let for each t ∈ T. Define a desired system lim(M,R) as follows:

(9.218)

and

and define mappings α i : lim←C St → Si by letting

(9.219)

(9.220)

for every object and any i ∈ T. Then it can be checked that themappings α t are S -continuous and satisfy whenever t ≤ s.

We now let Y = (MY, RY) be a system and a family ofS-continuous mappings such that whenever t ≤ s. Define a mapping

by letting

(9.221)

for each y ∈ M Y . Then from the hypothesis that whenever t ≤ s, itfollows that is well defined.

We now show that is S -continuous. For any relation r ∈ Rthere exist j ∈ T and r j ∈ Rj such that Therefore,

From the definition of S -continuity it follows that is S -continuous. The uniqueness of β follows from the commutative diagram in thetheorem or Fig. 9.3. �

Page 254: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

248 Chapter 9

Corollary 9.7.1. Suppose that is a linked α-type hierarchy of systemssuch that each linkage mapping l t s is S-continuous. Then lim ←C St is a partialsystem of

The proof follows from the proofs of Theorems 9.7.1 and 9.3.10.

Theorem 9.7.2. Let be a linked α -type hierarchy of systems in thecategory Then the inverse limit lim exists.

Proof: We define a system lim←h St = ( M,R ) as follows:

(9.222)

and

(9.223)

and for any define n = n (rt), for t ∈ T, and

(9.224)

and

(9.225)

Let α t : M → M t, for each t ∈ T, be the projection; i.e., Then,for any relation r ∈ R, there exists such that r is defined byEq. (9.224). Thus, for each t ∈ T. That implies thateach α t is a homomorphism from (M,R) into S t .

We now show that the system (M,R) is the inverse limit of the linked hierarchyOnly two things need to be proven: (i) For any system and

any set of homomorphisms such that

(9.226)

whenever t ≤ s, there exists a homomorphism so that

(9.227)

for each t ∈ T. To prove (i), define Then β isa homomorphism from into S. Since for any relation , then

Page 255: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach

Since for all , we havefor each t ∈ T, as mappings between sets. On the other hand, for any relation

and any

so

This implies that as mappings from the relation set into the relationset Rt for each t ∈ T. Hence, for each t ∈ T, as homomorphisms from

(ii) The homomorphism β is unique. Suppose is another homo-morphism satisfying for each t ∈ T. Let Then

for all t ∈ T. Thus, for allThis implies that β ' = β on the set , so β ' and β induce the same

homomorphism. Hence, β' = β as homomorphisms. �

Theorem 9.7.3. Each mapping {g , fs '} of a linked hierarchy H = ofsystems into a linked hierarchy H' = of systems induces a mappingfrom lim ← H into lim← H', where lim← indicates either lim←C or lim ← h.

Proof: For an object x = (xt) t ∈ T in lim← H and every s' ∈ T', define

(9.228)

The element thus obtained is an object in lim← H'. Indeed, for anys', t' ∈ T' satisfying t' ≤ s', then

For the object x in lim← H define ƒ(x) = y in lim ← H'. Then ƒ is a mapping fromlim ← H into lim← H'.

The mapping ƒ : lim← H → lim← H' in the proof of Theorem 9.7.3 is calledthe limit mapping induced by {g,ƒs'} and is denoted by ƒ = lim← {g,ƒs'}.

Theorem 9.7.4. Let {g,ƒs '} be a mapping of a linked hierarchy of systems H =to a linked hierarchy of systems H' = If all mappings ƒ s '

are one-to-one, the limit mapping ƒ = lim← {g,ƒs '} is also one-to-one. If, moreover,all mappings ƒs ' are onto, ƒ is also an onto mapping.

2 4 9

systems into systems.

Page 256: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Proof: Let and be two distinct objects of the limitsystem lim← H. Take an s0 ∈ T such that and an s' ∈ T' satisfying

Clearly, so it follows from the hypothesis that ƒs' is one-to-one, that is, which shows that Therefore,the limit mapping ƒ is one-to-one.

We now suppose that ƒs' is a one-to-one mapping from Sg (s ' ) onto for everys' ∈ T'. Take an object from lim← H'. It follows thatimplies for any satisfying s' ≥ t', so that for any

the element

(9.229)

is well defined. For any s ∈ T choose an element s' ∈ T' such that s ≤ g (s') anddefine

(9.230)

It can be verified that xs does not depend on the choice of s', that isan element in lim ← H, and that ƒ(x) = y. That shows ƒ is an onto mapping. �

Theorem 9.7.5. Suppose that {g,ƒs '} is a mapping of a linked hierarchy of systemsH = into a linked hierarchy of systems where H andH' are in the category If all mappings ƒ s ' are S-continuous, the limit mapping

is also S-continuous.

Proof: Suppose lim and lim Theorem 9.7.3implies that the limit mapping is well defined. Let r be arelation in lim ←C H'. There exist j ∈ T' and such that

(9.231)

Then

Thus, from the definition of S-continuity, the limit mapping ƒ is S-continuous. �

250 Chapter 9

Page 257: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 251

Theorem 9.7.6. Suppose that H = { S, l t s , T } and H' = { S', lt's' , T'} are twolinked hierarchies of systems in the category and {g,ƒs '} is a mappingfrom H into H'. If all mappings ƒs ' are similarity mappings, the limit mappingf : lim is also a similarity mapping.

Proof: Applying Theorem 9.7.4, we know that the limit mapping f is abijection from lim←C H onto lim←C H'. Theorems 9.2.4 and 9.7.5 imply that f isalso S-continuous. Now, in order to show that f –1 is S-continuous from lim← C H 'onto lim ←C H, it suffices to show that f is a homomorphism from lim←C H intolim ← C H'.

Let r ∈ R be a relation such that there exist j ∈ T and rj ∈ Rj satisfying

Then

(9.232)

Therefore, the limit mapping f is a similarity mapping from lim←C H o n t olim← C H ' .

Theorem 9.7.7. Suppose that H = {S, l t s, T} and H' = { S', lt's' , T' } are twolinked hierarchies of systems in the category and that {g,ƒs '} is a map-ping from H into H'. If all mappings ƒs' are homomorphisms, the limit mappingf : lim ← h H → lim ← h H' is also a homomorphism.

Proof: It suffices to show that for any relation r in the system lim ←h H =(M, R ), ƒ(r ) is a relation in the system lim←h H' = ( M', R' ). To this end, let

where R* is defined by Eq. (9.223), such that

(9.233)

Then

Hence, f (r ) ∈ R'.

(9.234)

Page 258: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

252 Chapter 9

Theorem 9.7.8. Under the same hypotheses as in Theorem 9.7.7, if all mappingsƒs' , in addition, are similarity mappings, the limit mapping f :is also a similarity mapping.

Proof: By Theorems 9.7.4 and 9.7.7, it suffices to show that for any relationr' in the system lim←h H’ = (M',R' ), there exists a relation r in the systemlim ← h H = ( M,R ) such that f (r ) = r'. Pick an elementwhere R'* is defined by Eq. (9.223) with Rt , T, and l t s replaced by R't ', T', andl t's' , respectively, such that

(9.235)

From the hypothesis that each ft ' is a similarity mapping from Sg( t ' ) onto S't' , itfollows that there exists exactly one relation rg(t ') ∈ R g ( t ') such that

(9.236)

Now for any t ∈ T choose a t' ∈ T' such that g( t' ) ≥ t. Define a relation r t ∈ Rt by

(9.237)

It can be shown that the definition of rt does not depend on the choice of t'. Thenan element is well defined, where R* is defined by Eq. (9.223).The relation r ∈ R, defined by

(9.238)

satisfies f (r ) = r * .

Corollary 9.7.2. Let {S, lt s ,T } be a linked α -type hierarchy of systems in cate-gory or T' a cofinal subset of T. Then lim ← {S, l t s, T } is similar tolim← {S, lt s , T' }, where lim← indicates either lim← h or lim ← C.

The result follows from Theorems 9.7.6 and 9.7.8.

Corollary 9.7.3. Let {S, lt s, T} be a linked α-type hierarchy of systems in categoryor If the partially ordered set T has a maximum element t0 ∈ T, then

the systems lim← h {S, l t s , T}, lim←C {S, lt s, T }, and St0 are similar.

The result follows from Corollary 9.7.2.

Page 259: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

General Systems: A Multirelation Approach 253

Corollary 9.7.4. Suppose that {S, lt s, T } is a linked α -type hierarchy of systemsin the category Then the limit system lim ←h St is a partial system of ∏{ St :t ∈ T }.

The result follows from the proofs of Theorems 9.7.2 and 9.3.9.

Theorem 9.7.9. Let {S, l t s, T } be a linked α -type hierarchy of systems in thecategory such that one of the states St is connected. Then the inverse limitsystem lim ←C{S, l t s, T} is connected.

The result follows from Theorems 9.7.1 and 9.4.3.Let {S, lt s , T } be a linked α -type hierarchy of systems such that for every

element in the thread set Σ, there exists a setT, s ≥ t } of linkage mappings, where each ms is again a system. The 1-levelinverse limit, denoted by or when all relevant linkagemappings are S -continuous, or or when all relevantlinkage mappings are homomorphisms, is defined by lim←St = (M , R), wherelim← indicates or and the object set M and the relation set R aredefined as follows: There exists a bijection h :Σ → M such that

(9.239)

and

R = { h (r ) : r is a relation in lim St}←

where lim← indicates either lim←c or lim ←h .

Theorem 9.7.10. Let {S , lt s, T } be a linked α -type hierarchy of centralizablesystems in the category If the 1-level inverse limit systemexists, then the system is centralizable.

Proof: The proof follows from the fact that if Ct is a center of the system St ,for each t ∈ T, then the inverse limit lim←c Ct is a center of the 1-level inverselimit

Theorem 9.7.11. Let {S, lt s, T } be a linked α-type hierarchy of centralizablesystems in the category If the 1-level inverse limit systemexists, then the limit system is also centralizable.

Proof: This theorem follows from the fact that if Ct is a center of the systemS t, for each t ∈ T, then the inverse limit lim←h Ct is a center of the 1-level inverselimit

Page 260: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

254 Chapter 9

Theorem 9.7.12. Suppose that {S, l t s, T } is a linked α -type hierarchy of systemsin the category such that for some index t0 ∈ T, the state St = ( Mt0 ,Rt0 ) is

0

generally controllable on V' relative to a mapping Thenthe inverse limit lim ← C{S, lt s , T} is also generally controllable (but relative to adiffrent mapping G*).

Proof: From Theorem 9.6.5 it follows that we need only show that the mappingis S-continuous. Theorem 9.7.1 implies this.

9.8. References for Further Study

The search for an ideal definition of general systems has been going on fordecades: see von Bertalanffy (1972), Mesarovic and Tahakara (1975), Gratzer(1978), Klir (1985) and Lin (1987). The study of time systems can be foundin many publications. For example, Schetzen (1980) studied continuous timesystems of multilinearity; Rugh (198 1 ) gave a systematic theory on nonlinearcontinuous and discrete time systems; a more general setting of the concept oftime systems can be found in Mesarovic and Takahara (1975), and their definitionwas generalized by Ma and Lin (1987).

The constructions of new systems, such as free sum, products and limit sys-tems, were first given by Ma and Lin (1987; 1987; 1988d). Studies on variouscontrollabilities of systems can be found in almost all books on systems. Forexample, Deng (1985) studied the concept of gray control, Wonham (1979) pre-sented a concept of controllability of linear systems of differential equations, anda study of controllabilities of nonlinear systems can be found in (Casti, 1985).Not all of the concepts of controllabilities are equivalent. The concepts of con-trollabilities presented here are based on research contained in (Mesarovic andTakahara, 1975; Ma and Lin, 1987). Periodic and order structures of families ofsystems were studied intensively in (Lin, 1988b; Lin, 1989a). Connectedness andS-continuity were first studied in (Lin, 1990c; Ma and Lin, 1990e). Cornacchio(1972) showed what an important role the concept of continuity played in researchof general systems theory and its impacts on engineering, computer science, socialand behavioral sciences, and natural sciences.

Page 261: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 10

Systems of Single Relations

As studied in Chapter 9, a (general) system consists of a set of objects and aset of relations between the objects. In practice, many systems, which can bedescribed by one relation, have many complicated structures and properties thatwe still do not completely understand. In this chapter, we concentrate on systemsof one relation and related concepts. Section 10.1 is devoted to the study oftwo very new concepts: chaos and attractor. The second section contains thegeneral concept of linear systems and characterizations of feedback systems, andthe following section introduces important concepts, including MT-time systems,linear time systems, stationary systems, and time invariably realizable systems,and study some feedback-invariant properties. Section 10.4 shows how “whole”systems can be decomposed into factor systems by feedback, and an example isgiven. Section 10.5 studies the conditions under which “whole” systems can bedecomposed.

10.1. Chaos and Attractors

A system S = ( M, {r }) is called an input–output system if there are nonzeroordinal numbers n and m such that

(10.1)

Without loss of generality, we let X = M n and Y = M m ; instead of using theordered pair (M, {r }), we will think of S as the binary relation r such that

(10.2)

where the sets X and Y are called the input space and the output space of S,respectively. In the real world, most systems we see are input–output systems. Forexample, each human being and each factory are input–output systems.

If we let Z = X ∪ Y, the input–output system S in Eq. (10.2) is a binary relationon Z. Let D ⊂ Z be an arbitrary subset. If D2 ∩ S = then D is called a chaos of

255

Page 262: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

256 Chapter 10

S. Intuitively, the reason why D is known as a chaos is because S has no controlover the elements in D.

Theorem 10.1.1. The necessary and sufficient condition under which an input–output system S over a set Z has a chaotic subset D ≠ Ø, is

S is not a subset of I (10.3)

where I is the diagonal of the set Z defined by I = {(x,x) : x ∈ Z }.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose that the input–output system S over the set Z has anonempty chaos D. Then D² ∩ S = Ø. Therefore, for each d ∈ D, (d, d) ∉ S. Thisimplies that S ⊄ I.

Sufficiency. Suppose that (10.3) holds. Then there exists d ∈ Z such that(d, d) ∉ S. Let D = {d}. Then the nonempty subset D is a chaos of S. �

Let S ⊂ Z ² and define

(10.4)

where D ⊂ Z.

Theorem 10.1.2. Let D ⊂ Z. Then D is a chaos of the system S iff D ⊂ S * D.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose D is a chaos of S. Then for each object d ∈ D andany y ∈ D ,

(d,y) ∉ S (10.5)

Therefore, d ∈ S * D. That is, D ⊂ S * D.Sufficiency. Suppose D satisfies D ⊂ S * D. Then D² ∩ S = Ø. Therefore, D is

a chaos of S. �

Let COS(S) denote the set of all chaotic subsets on Z of the input–outputsystem S. If S ⊄ I, then

(10.6)

We denote the complement of SI by S –I = Z – S I . Then Theorem 10.1.1 implies

that each chaos of S is a certain subset of S–I

. Therefore,

(10.7)

The following theorem is concerned with determining how many chaotic sub-sets an input–output system has.

Page 263: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 257

Theorem 10.1.3. Suppose that an input–output system S ⊂ ⊂ Z ² satisfies the fol-lowing conditions:

(i) S is symmetric, i.e., (x, y) ∈ ∈ S implies (y,x) ∈ ∈ S,

(ii) S is not a subset of I,

(iii) and

(iv) there exists at most one such that either (x,y) ∈ ∈ S or

(y,x) ∈ S.

Let Then

(10.8)

where k = n/2.

Proof: According to the discussion prior to the theorem, it is known that everychaotic subset of Z is a subset of S –

I . The total number of all subsets of S –I is 2m .

Under the assumption of this theorem, a subset of S–I is a chaos of S if the subset

does not contain two elements of S –I which have S-relations. Among the elements

of S –I , there are n/2 pairs of elements with S-relations, and every two pairs do not

have common elements. Let {x, y} be a pair of elements in S–I with an S-relation,

then every subset of S – – {x,y} ∪ {x,y} forms a subset of S–

I I not belonging toCOS(S). There are a total of 2 m – 2 of this kind of subset. There are n/2 pairs ofelements in S–

I with S-relations, we subtract these (n/2) × 2m –2 subsets from the2m subsets of S –

I . But, some of the (n/2) × 2m – 2 subsets, them are in fact thesame ones. Naturally, every subset of S –

I, containing two pairs of elements in S

–I

with S-relations, has been subtracted twice. There are such sets. Weadd the number of subsets which have been subtracted twice, and obtain

(10.9)

However, when we add subsets, the subsets of S –I containing three pairs

of elements of S –I with S-relations, have been added once more than they should

have. Therefore, this number should be subtracted. Continuing this process, we

Page 264: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

258 Chapter 10

have

By using the same method, the constraint in Theorem 10.1.3 that the system Sis symmetric can be relaxed.

Theorem 10.1.4. Suppose that an input–output system S ⊂ Z² satisfies conditions(ii)–(iv) of Theorem 10.1.3. Let n =and k = n/2. Then

(10.10)

Let S be an input–output system on a set Z. A subset D ⊂ Z is called an attractorof S if for each where Figures10.1 and 10.2 show the geometric meaning of the concept of attractors. When S isnot a function, Fig. 10.1 shows that the graph of S outside the vertical bar D × Zoverlaps the horizontal bar Z × D. When S is a function, Figure 10.2 shows thatthe graph of S outside the vertical bar D × Z must be contained in the horizontalregion Z × D.

Theorem 10.1.5. Suppose that S ⊂ Z² is an input–output system over the set Zand D ⊂ Z. Then D is an attractor of S, iff D ⊃ S * D.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose that D is an attractor of S. Let d ∈ S * D be anarbitrary element. By Eq. (10.4), for every x ∈ D, (d,x) ∉ S. Therefore, d ∈ D.That is, S * D ⊂ D.

Page 265: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 259

Figure 10.1. D is an attractor of S, and S(x) contains at least one element for each x in Z – D.

Sufficiency. Suppose that D satisfies D ⊃ S * D. It follows from Eq. (10.4)that for each object x ∈ Z – D, x ∉ S * D, so there exists at least one object d ∈ Dsuch that (d,x) ∈ S. That is, S (d) ∩ D ≠ Ø This implies that D is an attractor ofS. �

Theorem 10.1.6. The necessary and sufficient condition under which an input–output system S ⊂ Z² has an attractor D ⊂ Z is that S is not a subset of I.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose S has an attractor D such that D ⊂ Z. By contra-≠

diction, suppose S ⊂ I. Then for each D ⊂ Z, Z – D ⊂ S * D. Therefore, whenZ – D ≠ D ⊄ S * D; i.e., S, according to Theorem 10.1.5, does not have anyattractor not equal to Z. This tells that the hypothesis that S has an attractor Dsuch that D ⊂ Z implies that S ⊄ I.

Figure 10.2. D is an attractor of S, and S is a function from Z to Z.

Ø ,

Page 266: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

260 Chapter 10

Figure 10.3. D is a strange attractor of the system S.

Sufficiency. Suppose S ⊄ I. Choose distinct objects x,y ∈ Z such that ( x,y) ∈S, and define D = Z – {x}. Then, according to Eq. (10.4), D ⊃ S * D. ApplyingTheorem 10.1.5, it follows that S has attractors. �

Theorem 10.1.7. Suppose that an input–output system S ⊂ Z² satisfies the con-dition that if (x,y) ∈ S then, for any z ∈ Z, (y,z) ∉ S. Let

(10.11)

and ATR(S) be the set of all attractors of the system S. Then

ATR (S ) = 2n (10.12)

Proof: For each subset A ⊂ SI –, let DA = Z – A. Then DA ⊃ S * DA . Infact, for each object d ∈ S * DA (d,x) ∉ S for every x ∈ D, A . Therefore, d ∉ A.Otherwise, there exists an element y ∈ Z such that y ≠ d and (d,y) ∈ S . Thehypothesis stating that if (x,y) ∈ S then for any z ∈ Z, ( y,z) ∉ S, implies that theelement y ∈ Z – A, contradiction; so d ∈ Z – A = DA . This says that DA ⊃ S * DA .Applying Theorem 10.1.5, it follows that the subset DA is an attractor of S. Nowit can be seen that there are 2n many such subsets DA in Z. This completes theproof of the theorem. �

A subset D ⊂ Z is a strange attractor of an input–output system S ⊂ Z ² if D isboth a chaos and an attractor of S. Figure 10.3 shows the case when a subset Dof Z is a strange attractor of an input–output system S, where the square D × D isthe only portion of the band Z × D over which the graph of S does not step.

Theorem 10.1.8. Let D ⊂ Z. Then D is a strange attractor of the input–outputsystem S iff D = S * D.

Page 267: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 261

The proof follows from Theorems 10.1.2 and 10.1.5.

Theorem 10.1.9. Suppose that S ⊂ Z2 is an input–output system and D ⊂ Z. Letus denote

(10.13)

Then the following statements hold:

(i) D is a chaos of S iff D ⊂ Z – S D.

(ii) D is an attractor of S iff D ⊃ Z – S D.

(iii) D is a strange attractor of S iff D = Z – S D.

Proof: It suffices to show that S * D = Z – S D. Let x ∈ S * D be anarbitrary element. Then for any element y ∈ D, (x, y ) ∉ D. Thus, x ∉ S D; i.e.,x ∈ Z – S D. If an element x ∉ S * D , there exists at least one element y ∈ Dsuch that (x ,y ) ∈ S. This implies that x ∈ S D; therefore, x ∉ Z – S D. Thiscompletes the proof that S * D = Z – S D. The rest of the proof of the theoremfollows from Theorems 10.1.2, 10.1.5, and 10.1.8.

of input–output systems.We conclude this section with a discussion of the existence of strange attractors

Theorem 10.1.10. Suppose that S ⊂ Z 2 is a symmetric input–output system. Thena necessary and sufficient condition under which there exists a strange attractorof the system S is that there exists a subset D ⊂ Z such that D 2 ∩ S = ø and foreach x ∈ SI , D ∩ S( x ) ≠ ø.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose S has a strange attractor D. From the definition,it follows that D 2 ∩ S = ø . At the same time, if there exists an element x ∈ S I

satisfying D ∩ S (x) = ø then x ∈ S * D. By Theorem 10.1.8, x ∈ D. However,x ∈ SI , we must have x ∉ S * {x}, which implies that x ∉ S * D. This leads to acontradiction.

Sufficiency. Suppose there exists D ⊂ Z such that D 2 ∩ S = ø and for eachx ∈ S I , D ∩ S(x ) ≠ ø. Let be the collection of subsets of Z defined by

and (10.14)

Since D ∈ is not empty. It is clear that for each linearly ordered subsetof , ordered by inclusion, is also contained

in . Therefore, contains all maximal elements under the order relation ofinclusion.

Page 268: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

262 Chapter 10

Let B be a maximal element in . By Theorem 10.1.2, it follows that B ⊂ S *B.If B ≠ S *B, pick an element x ∈ S *B – B and define

(10.15)

According to the definition of the element x, for each y ∈ B , (x ,y ) ∉ S. From thehypothesis that S is symmetric, it follows that (y, x) ∉ S for every y ∈ B. Besides,since for each for each A ∈ , we have ; i.e.,x ∉ S I . Therefore, . This contradicts the assumption that B is amaximal element in

We next discuss the conditions under which a composition of input–outputsystems has strange attractors.

Theorem 10.1.11. Suppose that ƒ and g are two input–output systems on a set Zsuch that . Then a necessary and sufficient condition under whichthe composition system g f has a strange attractor is that there exists a subsetD ⊂ Z such that the following conditions hold:

(i)

(ii) For every is not a subset of (Z 2 – g) (x).

Proof: Applying Theorem 10.1.10, the composition system g f has a strangeattractor if and only if there is a subset D ⊂ Z such that

(i′)

(ii′) For each

It now suffices to show that (a) conditions (i) and (i’) are equivalent and (b)conditions (ii) and (ii’) are equivalent.

Proof of (a). Condition (i’) is true iff for any x , y ∈ D , (x, y) ∉ g f , iff theredoes not exist a z ∈ Z such that (x ,z ) ∈ g and (z , y ) ∈ ƒ , iff for any x ∈ D and any

; i.e., (i) holds.Proof of (b). condition (ii’) holds iff for each x ∈ (g f )I there exists d ∈ D

such that (x , d ) ∈ g f, iff for each x ∈ (g f ) I there exist d ∈ D and z ∈ Z suchthat (x, z ) ∈ g and (z , y ) ∈ ƒ, iff for each x ∈ (g f ) I there exists z ∈ f D such that(x ,z ) ∈ g , iff for each x ∈ (g If ) there exists z ∈ f D such that ( x ,z ) ∉ Z – g;iff for each ; i.e., (ii) is true.

Page 269: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 263

10.2. Feedback Transformations

Letsuch that

be a field, X and Y linear spaces over , and S an input–output system

(i) ø ≠ S ⊂ X × Y.

(ii) s ∈ S and s' ∈ S implify s + s' ∈ S.

(iii) s ∈ S and α ∈ implify α · s ∈ S.

Here + and · are addition and scalar multiplication in X × Y , respectively, anddefined as follows: For any (x1,y 1), (x2 ,y 2 ) ∈ X × Y and any α ∈ ,

(10.16)

(10.17)

The input–output system S is then called a linear system.

Theorem 10.2.1. Suppose that X and Y are linear spaces over the same fieldThen the following statements are equivalent:

(1) S ⊂ X × Y is a linear system;

(2) There exist a linear space C over and a linear mappingρ : C × D (S ) → Y such that (x ,y ) ∈ S iff there exists a c ∈ C such thatρ(c ,x ) = y.

(3) There exist a linear space C over and linear mappings R1 : C → Y andR2 : D(S) → Y such that the mapping ρ in (2) is such thatρ (c , x) = R1 (c ) + R 2(x ) for every ( c , x ) ∈ C × D (S).

Here D (S) is the domain of the input–output system S.

Proof: First, the domain D (S) is a linear subspace of the space X. For anyx1 ,x2 ∈ D (S ) and any α ∈ , there exist y1 ,y 2 ∈ Y such that (x 1,y 1 ) , (x2 ,y 2) ∈ S.From the hypothesis that S is linear, it follows that

(10.18)

and

(10.19)

and thus x1 + x2 and α x1 ∈ D(S).

Page 270: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

264 Chapter 10

The proofs that (3) implies (1) and (2) implies (3) are clear because we candefine the desired mappings R1 and R2 by andwhere 0x and 0c are the additive identities in the linear spaces X and C, respectively.

Proof that (1) implies (2). Suppose S is a linear system and 0x and 0 y are theadditive identities in X and Y , respectively. Define

(10.20)

Then C ≠ ø; in fact, 0 y ∈ C because , and C is a linear subspaceover . Consider the quotient space with addition +*and scalar multiplication ·* defined by and

for any α ∈ and any (b1 + C ) andDefine a mapping by letting

(10.21)

if (x, y ) ∈ S for every x ∈ D (S). Then σ is well defined. In fact, for each x ∈ D(S)and any y1 , y2 ∈ Y satisfyingand thus , so . This means that

Define a linear mapping as follows:

(10.22)

We now choose an isomorphism I : Y /C ⊕ C → Y satisfying I (y , C) = y for everyy ∈ Y /C. Now the desired mapping ρ : C × D (S) → Y can be defined byThen ( x,y ) ∈ S if and only if there exists c ∈ C such that ρ (c, x) = y. In fact, if(x, y ) ∈ S , there exists c ∈ C such that , soOn the other hand, if (x ,y) ∈ X × Y is such that there exists c ∈ C with ρ ( c,x ) =y ,then , so . SupposeThen y = y1 + c1 for some c1 ∈ C; hence,

(10.23)

This completes the proof of the theorem.

Example 10.2.1. Three examples are given to show that the concept of linearsystems is an abstraction of different mathematical structures.

(a) Suppose S is a system described by the following linear equations:

Page 271: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 265

where xi , i = 1,2, . . . , n, are n variables, m is the number of equations, ai j, (i =1,2 , . . . , m;j = 1,2, . . . , n ) are the coefficients of the system, and bj ,j = 1,2,. . . , m ,are the constraints of the system. The system S can then be rewritten as a linearsystem (M, {r}), where the object set M is the set of all real numbers, and

where is fixed such that foreach i = 1, 2, … , m.

(b) Suppose a given system S is described by the differential equations

where , and f ( t ) are continuous functions defined on theinterval [a, b ]. The system S can be rewritten as a linear system (M, {r}) in thefollowing way: The object set M is the set of all continuous functions defined on[a, b], and the relation r is defined by

where y ∈ M is a fixed function such that

a system such that the object set M is a linear space oversystem if for each relation r ∈ R there exists an ordinal number n = n ( r) such

. Then S is a linear

(c) Suppose X is a linear space over a field , and Y a set of some lineartransformations on X. Then Y can be studied as a linear system (X ,R), where,for each relation r ∈ R , there exists a transformation y ∈ Y such that for any

if and only if y(x1 ) = x2 .In Example 10.2.1(b), S is not an input–output linear system. Generally, the

concept of general linear systems is the following: Let be a field and S = (M,R)

that r is a linear subspace of M n . We will study only input–output linear systemsdefined in the beginning of this section.

An input–output system S ⊂ X × Y is a functional system if S is a functionfrom the input space X into the output space Y. Let S ⊂ X × Y and S ƒ : Y → Xbe a linear system and a linear functional system, respectively. Then the feedbacksystem of S by Sƒ is defined as the input–output system S′ such that

and (10.24)

Page 272: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

266 Chapter 10

Figure 10.4. Structure of feedback systems.

The systems S and Sƒ are called an original system and a feedback componentsystem, respectively.

Let

= { S ⊂ X × Y : S is a linear system} (10.25)

ƒ = {Sƒ : Y → X : Sƒ is a linear functional system} (10.26)

and

= {S' ⊂ X × Y : S' is a subset} (10.27)

Then a feedback transformation is defined by Eq. (10.24), whichis called the feedback transformation over the linear spaces X and Y . Figure 10.4shows the geometric meaning of the concept of feedback systems.

The following theorem gives a concrete structure of each feedback system.

Theorem 10.2.2. Suppose that S ⊂ X × Y is a linear system and Sƒ : Y → X alinear functional system. Then a subset S' ⊂ X × Y is the feedback system of S bySƒ , iff

(10.28)

Proof: Necessity. Suppose S' is the feedback system of S by Sƒ . Then,by the definition of feedback systems, for each (x, y) ∈ S ', (x + Sƒ (y), y ) ∈ S .This implies that (x , y ) ∈ { (z – Sƒ (y), y) : (z , y) ∈ S}. Again, the relation inEq. (10.24) implies that for each element (x, y) ∈ S , (x – S ƒ (y), y) ∈ S '. That is,

Sufficiency. Clear because Eq. (10.28) implies the relation in Eq. (10.24). �

Page 273: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 267

Theorem 10.2.3. Suppose that S, S' ⊂ X × Y are linear systems and Sf : Y → Xis a linear functional system such that

(10.29)

Then F(S',–S f ) = S, where –Sf : Y → X is the linear functional system definedby

(10.30)

for every y ∈ Y.

The proof is straightforward and omitted.

Theorem 10.2.4. For each linear system S ⊂ X × Y, there exists a linear functionalsystem Sf : Y → X such that F(S,Sf ) = S, that is, S is a feedback system of itself.

Proof: The desired linear functional system Sf : Y → X can be defined by

(10.31)

for every y ∈ Y . Then, Eq. (10.28) says that S = F(S,Sf). �

Theorem 10.2.5 discusses the control problem: A linear structure (say, system)S ⊂ X × Y is fixed. According to some predefined targets, we need to produce anew linear structure (say, a linear subspace) S' ⊂ X × Y . Can we design a feedbackprocess Sf : Y → X such that F ( S, Sf ) = S' ?

Theorem 10.2.5. Assume the axiom of choice. For each linear system S ⊂ X × Yand arbitrary linear subspace S' ⊂ X × Y, there exists a linear functional systemS f : Y → X such that F(S,Sf) = S' iff R(S') = R(S) and N(S') = N(S), whereN(W) indicates the null space of the input–output system W ⊂ X × Y, defined by

(10.32)

Proof: Necessity. Suppose there exists a linear functional system Sƒ : Y → Xsuch that F(S,Sƒ ) = S '. Then Theorem 10.2.2 implies that R(S') = R (S) and that

Page 274: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

268 Chapter 10

Sufficiency. Suppose that S and S' have the same output space and the nullspace; i.e., R(S') = R (S) and N(S') = N (S). We define a linear functional systemSf : Y → X such that F (S,S f) = S'.

For each element y ∈ R (S'), let

(10.33)

and

(10.34)

From the Axiom of Choice, it follows that there exist mappings

(10.35)

and

(10.36)

such that [ i.e.,(C(y),y) ∈ S ].

and [i.e.,We are now ready to check that for each y ∈ R (S') = R(S),

(10.37)

Thus, the mappings C and C' are well defined.Let {yi : i ∈ I} be a basis in the linear space R(S'), where I is a finite or infinite

index set. We now define a linear functional system

(10.38)

satisfying , for each i ∈ I . Then we make the followingclaim.

Claim. The systems S, S', and Sf have the property that F(S, Sf )= S'.

In fact, for each element (x,yi ) ∈ S', for an i ∈ I , we havesince

(10.39)

Therefore, from Eq. (10.39),

(10.40)

Page 275: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 269

Now let (x,yi ) ∈ S we then have , because

(10.41)

Hence, we have from Eq. (10.41) the opposite implication of Eq. (10.40). That is,for every i ∈ I,

(10.42)

It now remains to show that for each pair (x,y) ∈ X × Y, the relation inEq. (10.24) holds. Let (x,y) be an arbitrary element in S'. Then for afinite number of yi ’s from the basis {yi : i ∈ I}, where each ci is a nonzero number.Then In fact,

(10.43)

This gives us the implication from the right to left in Eq. (10.24). The oppositeimplication can be shown as follows. For each pairIn fact, let for some finite number of nonzero coefficients ci , whereeach yi is from the basis {yi : i ∈ I}. Then

(10.44)

Page 276: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

270 Chapter 10

Figure 10.5. Structure of cascade connections of systems.

This completes the proof of Theorem 10.2.5. �

We conclude this section with a discussion of a more general definition of theconcept of feedback systems. Let * be a system connecting operator, termed thecascade (connecting) operation. The operation * is defined as follows: Let Si ,i = 1,2,3, be input–output systems such that

(10.45)

(10.46)

(10.47)

where it is assumed that no algebraic properties are given on each set involved.The three systems satisfy S 1 * S 2 = S3 if and only if

(10.48)

Figure 10.5 shows the geometric meaning of the cascade connection of systems.We now let S and Sƒ be two input–output systems such that

(10.49)

and

(10.50)

where S ƒ is called a feedback component of S. The relationship between the twosystems is displayed in Fig. 10.6.

The feedback system F(S,Sƒ) of S by S ƒ is defined by

(10.51)

Page 277: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 271

Figure 10.6. Construction of general feedback systems.

In constructing F(S, Sƒ ) step by step, we first cascade S and Sƒ (i.e., find S * Sƒ)and then input one of the two outputs of the system S * Sƒ .

Without special explanation in this book, by feedback system we always meanthe definition given by Eq. (10.24).

10.3. Feedback-Invariant Properties

Some properties of original systems may be kept by their feedback systemsand some may not. Those properties of original systems invariant under thefeedback transformation F are of special interest in research on feedback systems.Feedback invariance has played a crucial role in characterizing homeostatic orexplosive system behaviors in various areas such as biology, engineering, socialscience, and so on.

A property of a linear system S ⊂ X × Y is called feedback invariant withrespect to ƒ if the property also holds for the feedback system F(S, S ƒ ) for eachlinear functional system Sƒ ∈ ƒ.

Corollary 10.3.1. Let S ⊂ X × Y and S ƒ : Y → X be a linear system and a linearfunctional system, respectively. Then the feedback system F(S, Sƒ ) is a linearsystem over X × Y and R(F(S, Sƒ )) = R (S) and N(F(S, Sƒ )) = N (S).

Proof: The linearity of the feedback system F(S, S ƒ ) follows from Theorem10.2.2. The equations R(F(S, S ƒ )) = R (S) and N(F(S, Sƒ )) = N (S) come fromTheorem 10.2.5 here the Axiom of Choice is not used. �

Page 278: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

272 Chapter 10

Theorem 10.3.1. Let S : X → Y and Sƒ : Y → X be linear functional systems suchthat S is surjective. Then D(F(S, Sƒ )) = D(S) iff ( I – S ° Sƒ ) : Y → Y is surjective,where I : Y → Y indicates the identity mapping; i.e., I(y) = y for each y ∈ Y.

Proof: Sufficiency. It is clear that D (F(S, Sƒ )) ⊂ D (S). Let x ∈ D (S) bearbitrary. There then exists some y ∈ Y such that (x, y) ∈ S. Since (I – S °Sƒ ) :Y → Y is surjective, there exists exactly one ∈ Y such that

(10.52)

This implies that

(10.53)

That is, ∈ S. Hence, x ∈ D (F(S, Sƒ )).Necessity. Pick an arbitrary y ∈ Y. From the hypothesis that S is a surjec-

tive system, it follows that there exists some x ∈ X such that S (x) = y. SinceD(F(S, Sƒ )) = D(S), for this x there exists some ∈ Y such that (x, ) ∈ F(S, Sƒ ) ;i.e., ∈ S. Hence,

(10.54)

Thus , i.e., This proves that (I – S °Sƒ ) : Y → Yis surjective. �

Theorem 10.3.2. Let S ⊂ X × Y be a linear system and Sƒ : Y → X a linearfunctional system. Then D(F(S, Sƒ )) = X iff for each x ∈ X there exists a y ∈ R(S )such that (x + S ƒ (y), y) ∈ S.

The proof is clear from Eq. (10.24).

Theorem 10.3.3. Let S : X → Y be a linear functional system. Then for eacharbitrarily fixed Sƒ ∈ ƒ, the feedback system F(S, Sƒ ) is injective iff the originalsystem S is injective.

Proof: Sufficiency. Suppose the original system S is injective, and let Sƒ ∈ ƒ

be arbitrary. Suppose the feedback system F(S, Sƒ ) is not injective. Thus, thereexist distinct x1, x2 ∈ D(F(S, Sƒ )) such that

(10.55)

Page 279: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 273

for some y ∈ R (S). By Eq. (10.24), we have (x 1 + Sƒ (y),y), (x2 + Sƒ (y),y) ∈ S.Therefore, from the hypothesis that the system S : X → Y is injective, it followsthat x 1 + Sƒ (y) = x2 + Sƒ (y); i.e., x1 = x 2, contradiction.

Necessity. Suppose F(S, Sƒ ) is injective. From Theorem 10.2.3,

F(F(S, Sƒ ), –Sƒ ) = S

Applying the proof for sufficiency, we know that S is injective. �

Combining what have been obtained in this section, the following theorem isevident.

Theorem 10.3.4. Range space, null space, linearity, injectivity, surjectivity, andbijectivity of original systems are feedback invariant with respect to ƒ.

In the rest of this section, we study feedback-invariant properties of MT-timesystems. Let T be the time axis defined as the positive half of the real numberline; i.e., T = [0, + ∞). Let A and B be two linear spaces over the same field .We define

A T = {x : x is a mapping T → A } (10.56)

and

BT = {x : x is a mapping T → B } (10.57)

Then the sets AT and BT can be made linear spaces over as follows: For anyelements ƒ, g ∈ A T (respectively, ∈ BT ), and α ∈ ,

(ƒ + g)(t) = ƒ (t) + g (t) (10.58)

and

(αƒ)( t) = α · ƒ (t ) (10.59)

for each t ∈ T.Assume the input space X and the output space Y in the preceding discussion

are linear subspaces of AT and B T , respectively; i.e., X ⊂ AT and Y ⊂ B T .

Proposition 10.3.1. For any linear system S ⊂ X × Y and any linear functionalsystem Sƒ : Y → X, the feedback system F (S, Sƒ ) is a linear system over AT × BT.

The proof is straightforward and is omitted.Each input–output system S ⊂ A T × B T is termed an MT-time system,

(Mesarovic–Takahara time system). Therefore, Proposition 10.3.1 implies thatthe feedback transformation defined in Section 10.2 is well defined on the class ofall MT-time systems.

Page 280: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

274 Chapter 10

Figure 10.7. The graph of x in the plane T × A.

For any t, t' ∈ T with t < t', let

(10.60)

(10.61)

Then the restrictions of a time function x ∈ X with respect to these time intervalsare denoted by

(10.62)

and

(10.63)

For each y ∈ Y, or in general, for sets and vectors similar notation will be used;for example, for each etc.

A subset S ⊂ X × Y ⊂ A T × BT is called a linear time system if S is a linearsubspace of X × Y and the input space D (S) satisfies the condition:

(10.64)

where xt °x't is a time function ∈ AT , called the concatenation of xt and x't , and is

defined by the following: For any s ∈ T,

(10.65)

Without loss of generality, we will always assume that D(S) = X and R (S) = Y .Let στ be the shift operator defined as follows: For each x ∈ X,

(10.66)

for each ξ ∈ Tτ , where τ ∈ can be any value if σ τ (x) is meaningful. Figures 10.7–10.9 show the geometric meaning of the concept of shift operators. In Figs. 10.8

Page 281: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 275

Figure 10.8. The graph of στ (x) with τ > 0.

and 10.9 the dotted A × T planes indicate the locations of the A × T plane beforethe shift operation στ functions. Therefore, when τ > 0, the application of σ τ

implies that we move the graph of x τ units to the right; when τ < 0, the applicationof στ tells us to consider the portion of the graph of x on the right of the verticalline t = τ .

A linear time system S ⊂ X × Y is called strongly stationary if S satisfies thecondition

(10.67)

Theorem 10.3.5. Let S ⊂ X × Y and Sƒ : Y → X be a linear time system and astrongly stationary linear functional time system, respectively. Then the feedbacksystem F(S, Sƒ ) is strongly stationary iff the original system S is strongly stationary.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose that the feedback system F (S, Sƒ ) is stronglystationary. Then

S = {(x + Sƒ (y), y) : (x, y) ∈ F(S, Sƒ )} (10.68)

Figure 10.9. The graph of στ (x) with τ < 0.

Page 282: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

276 Chapter 10

It suffices to show that for any for every t ∈ T. wenow pick an arbitrary (x,y) ∈ S and t ∈ T. Then

(10.69)

From the hypothesis that the systems F(S , S f ) and S f are strongly stationary, itfollows that

(10.70)

and

(10.71)

Let and Then, Eq. (10.71) shows thatTherefore,

(10.72)

where so Eq. (10.72) implies thatSufficiency. This follows from Theorem 10.2.3 and the necessity part of this

proof.

A linear time system S ⊂ X × Y is called precausal if it satisfies the condition:

(10.73)

where A linear functional time system S : X → Y iscalled causal if it is precausal.

Theorem 10.3.6. Let S ⊂ X × Y be a linear time system. Then S is precausal iff

Proof: Necessity. Suppose S is precausal. Then for anyimplies that This shows that when

because is the same as Hence, andimplies that so

Sufficiency. Suppose Thisimplies that �

Page 283: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 277

Theorem 10.3.7. Let S : X → Y and Sƒ : Y → X be linear functional causal timesystems. Then the feedback system F (S,Sƒ ) is causal iff the composition timesystem is causal.

Proof: The argument of the necessity part follows from the fact that eachcomposition of causal functional time systems is causal.

Sufficiency. Suppose that the composition system is causal.

That is, for any t ∈ T and any implies that

(10.74)

Let y = F (S,Sƒ ) (x ). We need to show that By Eq. (10.24),

(10.75)

Therefore, where and

Thus,

This implies that the feedback system F (S,Sƒ ) is causal. �

A linear functional time system S : X → Y is called time invariably realizableif it satisfies the condition

(10.76)

where

Theorem 10.3.8. A linear functional time system S : X → Y is time invariablyrealizable iff for any t ∈ T and any x ∈ X

(10.77)

Proof: Necessity. Suppose S is time invariably realizable. Then S satisfies therelation in Eq. (10.76). It suffices to show that Eq. (10.77) is derivable from therelation in Eq. (10.76). For any t ∈ T and any Then

(10.78)

Page 284: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

278 Chapter 10

The last equality of Eq. (10.78) shows that

(10.79)

Sufficiency. Suppose S satisfies Eq. (10.77) for any t ∈ T and any x ∈ X. Then

(10.80)

Comparing Eq. (10.80) and the relation in Eq. (10.76), we see that S is timeinvariably realizable. �

Theorem 10.3.9. Suppose that S : X → Y and Sƒ : Y → X are two linear func-tional time systems such that S and Sƒ are time invariably realizable. Then thefeedback system F (S,Sƒ ) is time invariably realizable iff for any t ∈ T and any

i.e., the system is time invariably realizable.

(10.81)

Proof: Sufficiency. Suppose the system is time invariablyrealizable. Then for any t ∈ T and any Eq. (10.81) holds. Fromthe hypothesis that S is time invariably realizable, it follows from Theorem 10.3.8that Eq. (10.77) holds. Therefore,

This implies that

This equation is the same as

(10.82)

(10.83)

(10.84)

Therefore, applying Theorem 10.3.8, we have showed that the feedback systemF (S,Sƒ ) is time invariably realizable.

Necessity. Suppose F (S,Sƒ) is time invariably realizable. Then Theorem10.3.8 says that

(10.85)

Page 285: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 279

Let Then from Eq. (10.85) we have

(10.86)

(10.87)

From the hypothesis that S is time invariably realizable and Theorem 10.3.8, itfollows that Eq. (10.87) can be written as

(10.88)

Equation (10.88) is the same as Eq. (10.81). This ends the proof. �

We conclude this section with some discussion of chaos, attractor, and feedbacktransformation.

Theorem 10.3.10. For each linear system S ⊂ X × X there exists a feedbackcomponent system Sƒ : X → X, such that D ⊂ X is a chaos, attractor, or strangeattractor, respectively, of S, iff D is a chaos, attractor, or strange attractor ofF (S,Sƒ) , respectively.

The proof follows from Theorem 10.2.4.

Theorem 10.3.11. Suppose that S ⊂ X × X and Sƒ : X → X are a linear systemand a functional linear system, respectively. Then a subset D ⊂ X is a chaos of S[iff D is a chaos of the feedback system F(S,Sƒ )], if

(10.89)

Proof: Necessity. Suppose D ⊂ X is a chaos of S but not a chaos of F (S,Sƒ).Pick an element Then

This contradicts relation (10.89). Therefore, D must be achaos of F (S,Sƒ ).

Sufficiency. Suppose D ⊂ X is a chaos of F(S,S ƒ ) but not a chaos of S. Pickan element Then Therefore, it must bethat Now which contradicts relation (10.89).So D must be a chaos of S. �

Theorem 10.3.12. Suppose that S ⊂ X × X and Sƒ : X → X are a linear systemand a functional linear system, respectively. Then D ⊂ X is an attractor of S (iffD is an attractor of the feedback system F (S,Sƒ)), if

(10.90)

and

(10.91)

Page 286: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

280 Chapter 10

Proof: Necessity. Suppose D ⊂ X , satisfying condition (10.90), is an attractorof S but not of F (S,Sƒ ). Then there exists an element x ∈ X – D such that

(10.92)

From condition (10.90) it follows that there exists suchthat Thus, contradiction.

Sufficiency. Suppose D ⊂ X , satisfying condition (10.91), is an attractor ofF (S,Sƒ ), but not of the original system S. There then exists an element x ∈ X – Dsuch that

(10.93)

From condition (10.91) it follows that there existssuch that Therefore, contradiction.�

10.4. Decoupling of Single-Relation Systems

Let S ⊂ X × Y be an input–output system. We assume that the input space Xand the output space Y can be represented in terms of the factor sets; i.e., there aresets , where I is a fixed index set, such that

(10.94)

and

(10.95)

For each index i ∈ I, let

(10.96)

be the projection defined by letting suchthat and

We now can represent factor systems of S on the factorsets Xi and Yi; i.e., for each i ∈ I , the factor system Si of S can be defined by

(10.97)

The system S can now be viewed as decomposed into a family of factorsystems and S can be represented as a relation among its factor

Page 287: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 281

systems (i.e., by identifying withThe systems S and S i are called the overall system

and the factor (or component) system, respectively, and is calleda complex system representation over {Si : i ∈ I }.

Generally, there are many interactions among subsystems, so S is a propersubset of the product of its factor systems ∏{Si : i ∈ I }. If S = ∏{Si : i ∈ I }, S iscalled noninteracted

We now consider what properties are transferable from the overall system S toits component systems Si or from the component systems Si to an overall systemS.

Proposition 10.4.1. Let S ⊂ ∏ {Si : i ∈ I } be an input–output system which hasbeen decomposed into a family of factor systems = {Si : i ∈ I}. If S is a linearsystem over a field A, each component system Si is then also a linear system overthe field A.

Proof: From the hypothesis that S is a linear system over the field A, itfollows that, for each i ∈ I, Si is a nonempty system on Xi × Yi . We need to showtwo things: (1) For any for any(x ,y) ∈ Si and α ∈ A, α (x,y ) ∈ S i .

The argument of (1). For any (ai , ci ) and (bi , di) ∈ Si , there are (x 1, y1 ) and(x2 ,y2) ∈ S such that and Therefore,

becauseThe argument of (2). For any (ai , ci ) ∈ Si and any α ∈ A, there exists a pair

(x,y) ∈ S such that Therefore,

(10.98)

(10.99)

because α(x,y) ∈ S .

Proposition 10.4.2. Suppose that S ⊂ X × Y is a linear time system that hasbeen decomposed into a family of component systems {Si ⊂ Xi × Yi : i ∈ I }; i.e.,S ⊂ ∏ {Si : i ∈ I }. Then each component system Si is also a linear time system.

Page 288: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

282 Chapter 10

Proof: It suffices from Proposition 10.4.1 to show that for any x,y ∈ D (Si )and any t ∈ T, the concatenation of for each i ∈ I. In fact, forany x,y ∈ D(Si ) and any t ∈ T, there exist u, v ∈ D (S) such that

(10.100)

Therefore, because �

Proposition 10.4.3. Under the same assumption as Proposition 10.4.2 and if thesystem S is strongly stationary, then each component system Si is also stronglystationary.

Proof: Let be arbitrary. There then exists some elementsuch that Furthermore, there exists some (x , y) ∈ S

such that Sincewhere which implies that Hence,

Consequently,Conversely, let be arbitrary. There then exists some (xi , yi ) ∈ Si

such that Furthermore, there exists some (x,y ) ∈ S such thatwe have

That is, there exists some (x',y') ∈ S such thatHence,

That is,Combining these arguments, we obtain the following: For each index i ∈ I and

any From Eq. (10.66), we can showthat the component system S is strongly stationary. �

i

Proposition 10.4.4. Under the same assumption as in Proposition 10.4.2 andif the system S is precausal with D(S) = X, each component system S i is alsoprecausal.

Page 289: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 283

Proof: Let i ∈ I be arbitrarily fixed. It can then be seen that D (Si) = Xi . Infact, if D (Si ) ≠ Xi , we can pick an element xi ∈ Xi – D (Si). This implies thatD(S) ≠ X, because no x ∈ D (S) satisfies contradiction.

Let arbitrary, and assume Since it is assumed that S is

precausal, for any implies that from Theorem10.3.6. Therefore, when the elements x,y ∈ X satisfyand for every j ∈ I with j ≠ i, we have Thus

(10.101)

Applying Theorem 10.3.6 we have shown that each component system Si isprecausal. �

Example 10.4.1. We will construct an example to show that even though an overallsystem S is functional, none of the component systems Si is functional.

Suppose the index set I = {1,2} and the sets X1 , X 2, Y1 , and Y2 are all thesame, namely the set of all integers. Let S be a functional linear system fromX1 × X2 into Y1 × Y2 defined by

S(n,m) = (m,n) (10.102)

for any andThen it can be easily seen that neither S1 nor S 2 is functional.

Proposition 10.4.5. Suppose that S ⊂ X × Y is a functional system that has beendecomposed into a family of component systems with

Then each component system S i is also functional. If, moreover, theoverall system S is bijective, each component system Si is also bijective.

Proof: For any fixed i ∈ I, let be arbitrary. Sincedue to the assumption, there exist elements (x , y), (x , z) ∈ S such

that and Because S is functional, y = z, so,That is, the component system Si is functional.

Suppose S is a bijective function from X onto Y. For any yi ∈ Y i there existsan element y ∈ Y such that From the hypothesis that S is bijective,it follows that there exists an element x ∈ X such that S (x) = y. Therefore, for

That is, S i is surjective. Let (xi ,yi) and (wi ,yi) ∈ S i bearbitrary. Then there exist (x,y) and (w,y) ∈ S such that and

Page 290: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

284 Chapter 10

From the hypothesis that S is injective, it follows that x = w,that is, Hence, Si is bijective. �

Proposition 10.4.6. Suppose that S ⊂ X × Y is a functional linear time system thatS has been decomposed into a family of component systemssuch that S is noninteracted; i.e., If S is time invariablyrealizable, each component system Si is then also time invariably realizable.

Proof: From the hypothesis that S is a functional system from X into Y, itfollows that D(S) ⊂ X. Thus, from the proof of Proposition 10.4.4, for each fixedi ∈ I, D(Si ) = Xi .

We now let t ∈ T and xi ∈ Xi be arbitrary. There exists an element x0 ∈ X suchthat Since S is time invariably realizable, from Eq. (10.76) it followsthat for t ∈ T,

(10.103)

Let Then x0 ∈ A ≠ Ø and each x ∈ A satisfiesEq. (10.103), which implies that

(10.104)

Therefore,

(10.105)

Applying Eq. (10.76), we complete the proof that Si is time invariably realizab1e.�

The following result combines Propositions 10.4.1–10.4.6.

Page 291: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 285

Theorem 10.4.1. Let S ⊂ X × Y be an input–output system which has been decom-posed into a family of factor systems such thatThen the following statements hold:

(1) S is a linear system if and only if each Si is a linear system.

(2) S is a linear time system if and only if each Si is a linear time system.

(3) S is strongly stationary if and only if each Si is strongly stationary.

(4) S is causal if and only if each Si is causal.

(5) S is bijective if and only if each Si is bijective.

(6) The functional system S is time invariably realizable if and only if each Si

is functional and time invariably realizable.

The proof is not hard and is left to the reader.Theorem 10.4.1 shows that the theoretical properties of many important sys-

tems are either hereditary from the overall system S to each component system Si

or able to be lifted up from Si to S. In practice, we always hope to study S bystudying each component system Si .

Let S ⊂ X × Y be a linear system. We say that S can be decoupled by feedbackif there exists some functional system Sƒ ∈ ƒ such that

(10.106)

where it is assumed thatis the projection defined by relation (10.96).

The concept of decoupling by feedback shows the following actions: Theoriginal system S may not be noninteracted, so there might be some propertieswhich cannot be lifted up from component systems to the overall system S. If S isdecoupled by feedback, after applying appropriate feedback transformation, S istransformed to a system which has a noninteracted complex systems representation.We now can use that representation to analyze and control S.

Theorem 10.4.2. Suppose that S ⊂ X × Y and Sƒ : Y → X are a linear system anda functional linear system, respectively, such that S is decomposed into

and Sƒ is decomposed into Then, for each i ∈ I,

(10.107)

Page 292: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

286 Chapter 10

Proof: For each there exists (x,y) ∈ F(S,Sƒ) such thatΠ i (x ,y) = (x i , yi ). Since, it follows that

(10.108)

Equation (10.108) implies that That is,

Let be arbitrary. There then exists (x,y) ∈ S such that

(10.109)

Therefore, From this, we have

(10.110)

Equation (10.110) gives �

Theorem 10.4.3. Assume the Axiom of Choice. Suppose that S ⊂ X × Y is a linearsystem that can be decomposed into a family of component systems = {S i : i ∈ I}.Then S can be decoupled by feedback if and only if R(S) = Π {R(Si ) : i ∈ I } andN (S) = Π{N(Si ) : i ∈ I}.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose S can be decoupled by feedback. By the definitionof decoupling by feedback, there exists a functional linear system Sƒ ∈ ƒ suchthat

(10.111)

Page 293: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 287

Therefore, by Theorem 10.2.5,

(10.112)

and

(10.113)

Sufficiency. Let S' ⊂ X × Y be the system defined by

(10.114)

Since and due to our assumption,we see that R(S) = R (S') and N (S) = N (S'). By applying Theorem 10.2.5, wefind there exists a functional linear system Sƒ ∈ ƒ such that

(10.115)

�That is, S can be decoupled by feedback.

Example 10.4.2. As an example of decoupling by feedback, consider the multi-variable system S defined by

= Az + Bx

y = Cz + D x

z (0) = 0 (10.116)

where z is an m × 1 variable vector, A an m × m constant matrix, B an m × nconstant matrix, C an n × m constant matrix, D an n × n nonsingular constantmatrix, and

: x is piecewise continuous} (10.117)

Page 294: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

288

is the input space and

: y is piecewise continuous}

is the output space. For each i = 1, 2, . . . , n, define the system Si by

= Az+Bi x i

yi = C i z + D ixi

z(0) = 0

Chapter 10

(10.118)

(10.119)

where B i is an m × 1 constant matrix such that B = [B l B2 . . . Bn], C i is a 1 × mconstant matrix such that

Di is a nonzero constant, and

: xi is piecewise continuous}

is the input space and

: y i is piecewise continuous}

(10.120)

(10.121)

(10.122)

is the output space. Then the systems S and Si , i = 1, 2, . . . , n, satisfy

and (10.123)

In fact, for any x ∈ X, the solution of the differential equation (10.116) in S isgiven by

(10.124)

Thus, D(S) = X. At the same time, since the matrix D is nonsingular, the inversesystem S –1 of S is obtained as follows:

(10.125)

Page 295: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 289

Therefore, a similar argument shows that R(S ) = D (S –1 ) = Y. For the samereason, we can show that for each i = 1, 2, . . . , n, R(Si) = Yi . That is,

For the null spaces of the systems S and S i , i = 1, 2, . . . , n,

(10.128)

Therefore, N(S ) = Π {N( S i ) : i = 1, 2, . . . , n }. By Theorem 10.4.3, S can bedecoupled by feedback. In fact, define

(10.126)

(10.127)

and

Page 296: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

290 Chapter 10

Then the system Sd = S1 × S2 × . . . × Sn is represented by

= α z + βx

y = γz + δx

z ( 0 ) = 0

Since δ is nonsingular, S –1d is obtained as follows:

(10.129)

(10.130)

If we define a functional linear system Sƒ : Y → X as follows:

(10.131)

Then the original system S can be transferred into Sd by this feedback componentsystem Sƒ . In fact, for any pair (x , y) ∈ X × Y, ( x , y) ∈ Sd iff the input x and theoutput y satisfy the systems representation in Eq. (10.130) iff (x + Sƒ (y ), y ) ∈ S.We show the last “if and only if” condition as follows.

First, suppose that the input x and the output y satisfy the systems represen-tation in Eq. (10.130). Let z' be the solution of the differential equation in therepresentation in Eq. (10.130), and let z be the solution of the differential equa-tion in the systems representation in Eq. (10.125). Then [z z ' ]T is the solution ofthe differential equation in the systems representation in Eq. (10.131). From thedefinition of Sƒ , it follows that

(10.132)

Therefore,

(10.133)

where the membership relation comes from the systems representation inEq. (10.125) of the inverse system S –1 .

Page 297: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 291

Second, suppose that a pair (x, y) ∈ X × Y satisfies (x + Sƒ (y), y) ∈ S. Fromthe systems representations in Eqs. (10.125) and (10.131), we have

(10.134)

That is,

(10.135)

Combining Eq. (10.135) with the systems representation in Eq. (10.130) provesthat the pair (x, y) satisfies the systems representation in Eq. (10.130).

10.5. Decomposability Conditions

Intuitively speaking, a complex system consists of several subsystems (see,for example, Sections 9.3 and 9.6). Let us first consider the following example.Suppose that

(10.136)

for i = 1, 2, 3, are three input–output systems such that1, 2, 3 if and only if and

Suppose these three systems are connected in series; that is, x2 = y and x1 3 = y 2

hold; furthermore, suppose and are the input space and the outputspace of a new system , defined as

(10.137)

Then is the composition of S1, S , and S . However, in Eq. (10.137), the2 3

component systems S1, S2, and S3 completely disappeared.Let us now consider another construction of a new system S. We let

(10.138)

and the new system S ⊂ X × Y is defined by

(10.139)

Figures 10.10 and 10.11 show the geometric meanings of and S. The systemS is a representation of the whole system, which explicitly reflects the fact that

∈ Si , i =

Page 298: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

292 Chapter 10

Figure 10.10. Structure of the system

the whole system is composed of three component systems Si , i = 1, 2, 3. Thestructure of is called a global system representation of the whole system, whileS is a complex system representation of the whole system. In fact, S is the productsystem of Si, i = 1, 2, 3.

The complex system S is defined over X and Y, but to emphasizefact that S consists of the component systems S 1, S 2, and S 3 , we identify

withand denote the complex system S by S ⊂ S1 × S2 × S3 . For the global systemwe emphasize the structure by writing

The global system and the complex system S are intimately related to eachother. In fact, if we define two mappings

(10.140)

and

(10.141)

If we define two mappings and by andthen k1 and k2 satisfy the relations

(10.142)

and

(10.143)

Figure 10.11. Structure of the system S.

by h ,1(x1, x2andx3 ) = x1 and h2 (y1 , y2, y3) = y3, then

Page 299: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 293

Combining relations (10.140)–(10.143), we can see that for any (x, y) ∈ X × Y ,

(10.144)

and for any

(10.145)

Therefore, S and are similar.Generally, let S ⊂ X × Y and S' ⊂ X' × Y' be two input–output systems, and

hi, i = 1, 2, be mappings such that

h1: X → X' and h2 : Y → Y' (10.146)

satisfying the condition

(10.147)

Then h = (h1, h2 ) is called a modeling relation from S to S' and is denoted by

Notice that h is actually a mapping from S into S'.

Proposition 10.5.1. Suppose that h = (h1, h2 ) and k = (k1, k2 ) are modeling re-lations from system S1 to system S2 and from S2 to system S3 , respectively. Thenthe composition is a modeling relationfrom S1 to S3.

The proof is straightforward and is omitted.Yi : i ∈ I } are families of sets and that {ƒi : Xi →

Yi : i ∈ I} is a family of mappings. The product mappingis defined by

(10.148)

for any When I = {1, 2, . . . , n} is finite, we denote theproduct mapping ƒ by ƒ1 × ƒ 2 × … × ƒn . The following result shows the relation between the concept of modeling relations and that of product mappings.

and k = (k1 , 2 ) are two modeling relations from system S to system S'. Then the restriction of the product mappings

Suppose {Xi : i ∈ I} and {

Proposition 10.5.2. Suppose that h = ( h1 , h2) k

h1 × h2 and k1 × k2 on S are mappings from S to S'. Furthermore, if D (S) = X and R(S) = Y, then h1 × h 12 S = k × k2 if and only if hS i = ki , i = 1, 2.

Page 300: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

294 Chapter 10

The proof is straightforward and is omitted.Due to Proposition 10.5.2, we still use h for the mapping h 1 × h2 S and the

modeling relation (h1, h2) : S → S', whenever no confusion occurs.A modeling relation h = (h : S → S'1, h 2) is called an epimorphism from the

system S into the system S' if for any fixed system S" and modeling relations h'and h" from S' to S", h' ° h = h" ° h implies h' = h".

Theorem 10.5.1. Let h = (h 1, h2 ) be a modeling relation from a system S to asystem S' such that D(S) = X, R(S) = Y, D(S') = X', and R(S') = Y'. Then h isan epimorphism from S to S' if and only if h1 and h2 are surjective.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose h is an epimorphism from S to S' and, withoutloss of generality, the mapping h1 is not surjective. That is, h1 (X) ≠ D (S') = X'.There exist mappings h'1 and h" such that1

(10.149)

where, for each arbitrarily fixed system S'' ⊂ X" × Y", h' 1 and h" are from X' to1X". Pick mappings h' h" Y' → Y" such that 2 and 2 : h"2 = h" . Then we h' h = h" ° h,

2 °but h' ≠ h". This contradicts the fact that h is an epimorphism from S to S'.

Sufficiency. Suppose h1 and h 2 are surjective. Let S" be an arbitrary systemover X" × Y" and h' = (h'1 , h'2 ) and h" = (h"1 , h"2) modeling relations from S' toS" such that h' ° h = h" ° h. Then

(10.150)

The last implication follows because h1 : X → X' is surjective and because D (S) =X. A similar argument gives h ' = h" . Hence, applying Proposition 10.5.2, we2 2have h' = h". That is, h is an epimorphism from S to S'. �

Theorem 10.5.2. Under the same assumption as in Theorem 10.5.1, if the model-ing relation h is also surjective as a mapping (that is, h 1 × h2 S is surjective), thenh is an epimorphism. The converse is not true.

Proof: It can be clearly seen from the assumptions that the mappings h1 andh 2 are surjective. Applying Theorem 10.5.1, it follows that h is an epimorphism.

We now see an example when the converse is not true. Let X = Y, S = { (x, x):x ∈ X}, S' = X × X, and h 1 = h2 = idX . Then h = (h1, h2 ) is an epimorphism butnot surjective. �

Page 301: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 295

Theorem 10.5.3. Under the same assumption as in Theorem 10.5.1, if the mod-eling relation h is also a relation (that is, h has a right cancellation), then h issurjective as a mapping. The converse is not true.

Proof: Let k : S' → S be a right cancellation of h ; i.e., h°k = (idX, idY ). Let( x', y' ) ∈ S' be arbitrary. Then h°k (x', y') = h(k(x', y')) = (x', y'). That is, h issurjective.

We now construct an example to show the converse may not be true. Supposethat S ⊂ X × Y and S' ⊂ X' × Y' are systems defined by

(10.151)

and

(10.152)

Let h1 : D(S) → D(S') and h2 : R(S) → R(S') be two mappings defined by If h = (h1, h 2) has a right

cancellation k = (k1, k2 ), we have k1 (x1) = x1 or x2 , k2 ( y'1) = y1 , and k2 ( y'2 ) = y2.Case 1: Suppose that k1 (x'1) = x1 . It then follows that (k 1, k2 ) (x'1 ,y'2 ) = (x1 ,y2) ∉S, which contradicts the hypothesis that k is a modeling relation from S' to S.Case 2: Suppose k1 (x' (k1, k2) (x'1 ,y'1) = (x2 y1 ) ∉ S,1) = x2. We then have thatwhich contradicts the hypothesis that k is a modeling relation from S' to S. Thecontradictions imply that the modeling relation h does not have a right cancellation;i.e., h is not a retraction. �

A modeling relation h from a system S to a system S' is an isomorphism fromS onto S' if h has both right and left cancellation. In this case, S is isomorphic toS'.

Theorem 10.5.4. A modeling relation h: S → S' is an isomorphism from S ontoS' if and only if h is bijective from S onto S' as a mapping.

Proof: Necessity. Suppose h : S → S' is an isomorphism. From Theorem10.5.3 it follows that h : S → S' is surjective as a mapping. It remains for usto show that h is injective. Let p : S' → S be a left cancellation of h. That is,p° h = (id X , idY ). By contradiction, suppose h : S → S' is not injective as amapping. There then exist distinct (x , y) and (u, V ) ∈ S such that h (x, y) = h (u, v).So, p°h (x, y) = p°h (u, v), which contradicts the assumption that p° h = (id X ,

idY ) is the identity mapping on S. �

Page 302: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

296 Chapter 10

Figure 10.12. Properties of the mapping h from S to S' with D(S ) = X and R ( S) = Y.

Example 10.5.1. We show that retraction does not guarantee an isomorphism.Let S ⊂ X × Y and S' ⊂ X' × Y' be two systems defined by

(10.153)

and

(10.154)

Define a modeling relation h = (h1 , h2 ) from S to S' by letting h1 (x1 ) = h 1(x2 ) =Let k = (k ) from1 ,k2

D (S' ) × R ( S' ) → D( S ) × R (S ) be defined by

(10.155)

Then k is a modeling relation from S' to S and h k = (idX' , idY' ). But, accordingto Theorem 10.5.4, S is not isomorphic to S' because S ≠ S' .

Combining Theorems 10.5.2 and 10.5.3 we obtain Fig. 10.12.A modeling relation h = ( h1 , h2 ) from S to S' is termed as a monomorphism

from S to S' if h is injective as a mapping from S to S'. Then, similar to theprevious results, we have the following.

Theorem 10.5.5. Under the same assumption as in Theorem 10.5.1, the followinghold:

(i)

(ii)

If both mappings h1 and h2 are injective, then h is a monomorphism, butthe converse is not true.

If the modeling relation h is a section (that is, h has a left cancellation),then h1 and h2 are injective, but the converse is not true.

(iii) If h is an isomorphism, then h is a section, but the converse is not true.

Proof: (i) If h1 and h2 are injective, then the modeling relation h is injectiveas a mapping from S to S'. Therefore, h is a monomorphism. Conversely, definetwo systems S ⊂ X × Y and S' ⊂ X' × Y' such that

(10.156)

Page 303: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 297

and

(10.157)

and define by lettingand Then h : S → S' is an injective modeling

relation, but none of the mappings h1 nor h 2 is injective.(ii) Let be a left cancellation of

Then h1 and h 2 are injective. Conversely, define systemsS ⊂ X × Y and S' ⊂ X' × Y' such that

(10.158)

and

(10.159)

and define mappings h1 and h2 by andh2(y2 ) = y'2 . Then h 1 and h 2 are both injective. Now if the modeling relationh has a left cancellation k = ( k1 , k 2 ), then either If

then

(10.160)

a contradiction. If then

(10.161)

This contradicts the hypothesis that k is a modeling relation from S' to S.(iii) We need only define two systems S ⊂ X × Y and S' ⊂ X' × Y' and a section

h : S → S' such that h is not an isomorphism. Let

(10.162)

and

(10.163)

and let the modeling relation h be defined as in the proof of (ii). Define aleft cancellation k = (k1 , k2 ) of h as follows:

and But h cannot be an isomorphism from S to S' byTheorem 10.5.4 because

Theorem 10.5.6. A modeling relation h = (h1 , h 2) : S → S' is an isomorphism ifand only if h 1 : D (S) → D(S' ) and h2 : R (S ) → R (S' ) are bijective.

Page 304: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

298 Chapter 10

Proof: Necessity. Suppose h is an isomorphism. Then Theorems 10.5.3 and10.5.5 imply that the mappings h1 : D (S ) → D( S' ) and h2 : R ( S) → R (S' ) aresurjective and injective.

Sufficiency follows from Theorem 10.5.4.

Theorem 10.5.7. Let h1 : X → X' and h2 : Y → Y' be two mappings, and S ⊂ X × Yand S' ⊂ X' × Y' be two systems. Then the product mapping h1 × h 2 reduces amodeling relation from S to S'; i.e., h 1 × h 2 S is a mapping from S to S' if and onlyif for any

Proof: Necessity. Suppose h1 × h 2 S is a mapping from S to S'. Then for anyx ∈ D (S) and any y ∈ S (x ), we have Thatis, h2 (y ) ∈ S'(h 1(x )). This gives

Sufficiency. Suppose, for any Then, for eachTherefore, h = (h1 , h 2 ) is

a modeling relation from S to S'.

From Theorem 10.5.6, it can be seen that if a system S is isomorphic to a systemS', then S' is also isomorphic to S. In fact, let h = (h1 , h 2 ) be an isomorphismfrom S to S'. Then there are mappings k : Y' → Y such that1 : X' → X and k2

and (10.164)

Applying Theorem 10.5.6, it follows that k = (k1 ,k2 ) is an isomorphism from S'to S. Therefore, in the future we can speak about isomorphic systems.

Suppose S ⊂ X × Y is an input–output system such that D(S) = X and R (S ) =Y, and where I is an index set, is a covering of S;i.e., satisfies The collection is referred to as aninput–output system covering of S if satisfies the following two conditions:

(i) There are coverings of the inputspace X and the output space Y, respectively.

(ii) There is a relation Is ⊂ Ix × Iy with D (Is ) = Ix and R ( Is ) = I y such thatand are related by a one-to-one correspondenceψ : Is→ I with

(10.165)

In particular, if the collections and are partitions of the sets S, X, andY, the corresponding input–output system covering of S will be referred to as aninput–output system partition. The system covering will be denoted by

Page 305: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 299

A system covering will be used when viewing a system macroscopically by ig-noring its detailed structures. Generally, not every covering is compatible with aninput–output model structure. When it is compatible, it can generate an approxi-mation of the original input–output system. Here, the relation Is is a representationof the approximation and will be called an associated input–output system of thecovering.

Theorem 10.5.8. Each input–output system S ⊂ X × Y has an input–output systemcovering, which is also an input–output system partition.

Proof: We define the collections and as follows:

(10.166)

The rest of the proof is clear.

Example 10.5.2. An input–output system covering (respectively, partition)

is termed a trivial covering (respectively, partition) if Ix = 1 or Iy = 1. Wenow construct an input–output system S ⊂ X × Y which does not have a nontrivialpartition. Let S ⊂ X × Y be the system defined by

(10.167)

where x1 ,x2 ∈ X and y 1 ,y2 ∈ Y are distinct elements in X and Y, respectively.Then S may not have a nontrivial partition. In fact, by contradiction, suppose Shas a nontrivial input–output system partition Then the associatedinput–output system Is ⊂ Ix × Iy must satisfy Ix = 2 = Iy . In fact, if Ix > 2,there is an i ∈ I x such that Xi ∈ contains neither x 1 nor x2. That is, for each

(10.168)

Equation (10.168) contradicts the condition that and each elementin is nonempty. A similar argument shows that Iy has to be 2.

Suppose and Then for each i = 1,2,

(10.169)

To guarantee that for each i = 1,2 and j = 1,2,

(10.170)

the sets Xi and Yj must contain {x1 ,x2} and {y1 ,y2 }, respectively. This fact impliesthat if the input space X = {x1 ,x2} and the output space Y = {y1 ,y2}, then thesystem covering would be a trivial covering, contradiction.

Page 306: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

300 Chapter 10

When a system covering is a partition, the associated input–output system I s

is characterized by the following results.

Theorem 10.5.9. Let and i ∈ I } be an input–output system par-tition of a system S ⊂ X × Y. Then the following holds:

and

(10.171)

where Is is the associated input–output system of the partition, Xi∈ and Yj ∈ In particular, if the system Is exists, Is is unique for the given sets of and

Proof: The following is clear:

(10.172)

Suppose (i , j) ∈ I s . The definition of a system covering implies that (Xi ×so there is Consequently,

Conversely, suppose there exists (x,y ) ∈ S suchthat x ∈ Xi and y ∈ Yj . Since (x,y ) we have

(x,y ) ∈ Sk for some k ∈ I (10.173)

Let Since and (x,y ) ∈ S k hold, wehave x ∈ Xi ' and y ∈ Yj '. Since and are partitions, we must have Xi = Xi' andYj = Yj '. The uniqueness of existence of the associated input–output system I s

comes from the fact that

Let f: X → Y be a mapping from a set X to a set Y. An equivalence relationEf can then be defined on X as follows:

(10.174)

The quotient set X/E f will be denoted by X/f.

Theorem 10.5.10. Suppose that h = ( h1 ,h2 ) : S → is a modeling relation withD (S ) = X and R (S) = Y. There then exists an input–output system partition

of S such that and is definedby

(10.175)

A one-to-one correspondence ψ : Is → S/h1 × h 2 is given by

ψ([x],[y]) = [( x,y )] (10.176)

Page 307: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 301

Figure 10.13. Epi–mono decomposition of a modeling relation h.

Proof: We first show that the correspondence ψ is well defined. Let ([x], [y]) ∈Is and be arbitrary such that and It suffices toshow that

(10.177)

From the definition of equivalence class, it follows thatthat is, ψ is a mapping from Is into X × Y/h 1 × h2 . We

now need to show that for each i.e., thereexists such that The last equation follows from thefact that ([x] × [y]) ∩ S ≠

Second, we show that is a one-to-one correspondence. Letbe arbitrary. Since holds, ψ is surjective.

Suppose Then and i.e., the mapping ψis injective. �

Theorem 10.5.11. Suppose that S ⊂ X × Y and S' ⊂ X' × Y' are input–outputsystems such that D(S) = X, R(S) = Y, D(S') =X', and R(S') = Y', and h =(h1 , h2 ) : S → S' is a modeling relation. Let µ1 : X → X/h 1 and µ2 : Y → Y/h2be canonical mappings. Then the following statements hold:

(i) µ = (µ1 , µ 2 ) is an epimorphism from S to S/h. In particular, µ issurjective.

(ii) A modeling relation σ = (σ1, σ2 ) : S/h → S' can be defined by

σ([x ],[y ]) = (h1(x) ,h2 (y )) such that σ i , i = 1,2, are injective.

(iii) The diagram in Fig. 10.13 is commutative; that is, there is an epi–monodecomposition of h.

(iv) If h1 and h2 are injective, then the modeling relation µ is an isomorphism.

(v) If h is surjective, then σ is an isomorphism.

Page 308: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

302 Chapter 10

Proof: (i) It is clear that the canonical mappings µ1 : X → X/h 1 and µ 2 :Y → Y/h 2 are surjective when defined by µ i (m) = [m] for i = 1, 2. If (x, y) ∈ S,(x, y) ∈ ([x] × [y]) ∩ S, and thus µ(x, y) = (µ1(x), µ2 (y)) = ([x], [y]) ∈ S/h. ByTheorem 10.5.1, the modeling relation µ is an epimorphism. Since there is(x',y') ∈ S for any ([x], [y]) ∈ S/h such that [x'] = [x] and [y'] = [y], µ is surjective.

(ii) Since [x] = [x'] implies is well defined.The mapping σ2is also well defined. Suppose ([x], [y]) ∈ S/h. Then the definitionof S/h implies there exists such that Consequently,

andHence, σ is a modeling relation, and σl and σ2 are clearly injective.

(iii) The commutativity of the diagram in Fig. 10.13 is clear from the definitionsof µ and σ.

(iv) If h1 and h2 are injective, says that µ 1 is injective. Similarly,the mapping µ2 is also injective. From statement (i) and Theorem 10.5.6, we knowthat µ is an isomorphism.

(v) The desired result can be shown as in the proof of (iv).

Suppose is a system, is a collectionof systems, and S ⊂ X × Y satisfies the conditions

(10.178)

and

(10.179)

where we identify each element with

The system S is called a surjective complex system representation of withorder n if there exist mappings and such thatS is called an injective complex system representation of with order n if thereexist mappings and such that ⊂ S and k 1 and k2

are injective. S is called an isomorphic complex system representation of withorder n if there exist mappings and such thatis an isomorphism from S onto S'.

Proposition 10.5.3. For each system and each natural number n > 0,has a surjective, an injective, and an isomorphic complex system representation

with order n.

Proof: Let and be the diagonals of the product sets, respec-tively. That is,

(10.180)

Page 309: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 303

We now define S ⊂ X × Y by letting

(10.181)

and define mappings and a n dThen we have the desired results with respect to (h1 , h 2 ). �

Theorem 10.5.12. A system has an injective complex system repre-sentation S with order n over a class of systems iffthere exist n partitions of for each i = 1, 2,. . . , n, suchthat the following conditions hold:

(i)

(ii)

(iii)

Pi is an input–output system partition of , for each i = 1,2, . . . , n.

where is anassociated input–output system of Pi with σ1 i and σ2 i injective.There exists an embedding

Let and be the input and outputspaces of respectively, where and are partitions by definition and[ xj]i and [yj ] i are equivalence classes of and , respectively. Then, forarbitrary and for each i = 1,2, . . . , n,

(10.182)

and

(10.183)

Proof: Necessity. Let S ⊂ X × Y be an injective complex system representationwith order n, where X ⊂ X1 × X 2 ×. . . × X and Y ⊂ Y 1× Y × . . . × Y n . Letn 2

be the projection defined by Eq. (10.96). Then

Π i : S → S i is a modeling relation. Let be an injective modelingrelation. Since is a modeling relation, we can

define a partition Pi of by

(10.184)

We now check the conditions (i)–(iii) for these partitions Pi , i = 1, 2, . . . ,n. SinceTheorem 10.5.10 implies that Pi is an input–output system partition, condition(i) holds. Since the associated input–output system is given by

Page 310: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

304 Chapter 10

there is an embedding mapping due to Theorem 10.5.11(ii). Hence,condition (ii) also holds. We will check condition (iii). In the present case,

(10.185)

Choose an equivalence class [xi ]i from each for i = 1,2, . . . , n. The definitionof implies for some so

(10.186)

Suppose Since for each i,

(10.187)

Hence, Consequently,

(10.188)

Since, in general, implies

(10.189)

Since e1 is injective, is empty or singleton. A similar argument worksfor the collection . Hence, we have showed condition (iii).

Sufficiency. Suppose satisfies conditions (i)–(iii). Let bedefined by

(10.190)

where we identify singleton sets with the elements. Let X' = D(S') and Y' = R (S')and mappings and be defined by

(10.191)

for each and

Claim. The mapping k = (k1 , k2) is an isomorphism from to S'.

Page 311: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 305

In fact, let be arbitrary. Theorem 10.5.9 implies thatSince condition (iii) implies that

(10.192)

we have That is, k is a modeling relation from to S'. To showk is one-to-one, we let It follows from the definition of k1 that

The condition (iii) implies that

(10.193)

Hence, k1 is injective. The same argument can be used to show that k2 is alsoinjective.

To show that k is surjective from onto S', let

be arbitrary. Then the definition of S' implies that there exists such that

(10.194)

Consequently, for any and i.e., andTherefore,

(10.195)

This completes the proof that k is an isomorphism from to S'.We now let S = S1 × S 2 × . . . × S n . Since there is an embedding σi from to

Si , an injective modeling relation from to S is

(10.196)

This ends the proof of Theorem 10.5.12. �

Theorem 10.5.13. If a system has a surjective complex system rep-resentation S with order n over a class then thefollowing conditions hold:

(i) has n input–output coverings

(10.197)

Page 312: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

306 Chapter 10

(ii) There is a surjective mapping from Si to an associated input–output systemof Ci.

Proof: Let h = (h1 , h2 ) : S → be a surjective modeling relation, and the projection. For each i let

(10.198)

Then C ' is a covering of In fact, let be arbitrary. Since h is surjective,ifor some

(10.199)

That is,

(10.200)

Next let Ci be the subset of C' defined by deleting empty sets and duplicated setsi

and write

(10.201)

Then Ci is an input–output system covering. In fact, let andand

(10.202)

and

(10.203)

Then Xi and Yi are coverings of the sets and respectively. Next let the desiredrelation between I i and I i

x y b e I is , and let ψ be the identity mapping on I

is . Then (ii)

holds. �

Page 313: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

307Systems of Single Relations

Theorem 10.5.14. Suppose that is a system and {Si ⊂ Xi × Yi : i =1, 2, . . . , n} is a family of systems. If the following conditions are true, has asurjective complex system representation with order n, S ⊂ X × Y, where

and (10.204)

and

(10.205)

(i) has n input–output coverings

(10.206)

(ii) There is a surjective modeling relation from Si to anassociated input–output system of C i.

(iii) Let and be the input and

output spaces of respectively. Then for any and

and

(10.207)

(10.208)

Proof: Suppose (i)–(iii) hold and Iis is an associated input–output system of

Ci . Define a system as follows:

(10.209)

where each singleton set is identified with its element. Let X' = D ( S') andY '=R (S ') and and be the mappings defined by

(10.210)

Page 314: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

308 Chapter 10

and

Condition (iii) and the definition of S' ensure that h1 and h 2 are well defined.We now show that h = (h1 , h2 ) is a surjective modeling relation from S to S'. If(x,y) ∈ S' , then the definitions of S' and h imply that ( h1 (x ), h2 (y )) ∈ and henceh is a modeling relation. Suppose is arbitrary. For each i,

(10.211)

The definition of an input–output system covering implies that for some

(10.212)

Consequently, and that is,

(10.213)

The modeling relation h is surjective. We now define and σ : S → S' b y

and

(10.214)

Then h ° σ is a surjective modeling relation from S to �

Theorem 10.5.15. A system has an isomorphic complex system rep-resentation S of order n over a family of systemsif and only if there are partitions Pi , i = 1 ,2,. . . , n, of such that the followingconditions hold:

(i) P i is an input–output system partition.

(ii) There is an isomorphism σi from an associated input–output system ofP i to S' ×

i , where S' ⊂ Si i and S ⊂ S' × . . . S'1 n .

(iii) Condition (iii) in Theorem 10. 5.14 is true.

The proof is similar to those of Theorems 10.5.12 and 10.5.14 and is left to thereader.

Page 315: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Systems of Single Relations 309

10.6. Some References for Further Study

The concepts of chaos and attractors of single-relation systems were introducedby Zhu and Wu (1987). They named the concepts panchaos and panattractor,and systematically studied them under the name pansystems theory. The theoryappeared in the late 1970s. For more information consult Wu’s work (1981b;1982a; 1982b; 1982c; 1983a; 1983b; 1984b; 1984c; 1984d; 1985).

The concept of feedback systems has been a major research topic in systemstheory and has been studied in many different ways by, for example, Mesarovicand Takahara (1975), Bunge (1979), Rugh (1981), Deng (1985), Klir (1985), andSaito and Mesarovic (1985). The definition of feedback systems, given in thischapter was introduced by Saito and Mesarovic (1985), and some results are fromLin and Ma (1990).

General systems of a single relation originated with Mesarovic, who beganto study this concept in 1964 (Mesarovic, 1964). Its final form was containedin the book by Mesarovic and Takahara (1975), in which the concept of generallinear systems was studied in detail. Theorem 10.2.1 is a combination of a result in(Lin, 1989b) and a fundamental theorem given by Mesarovic and Takahara (1975).

Feedback transformation has been a really hot topic in recent years. Because allliving and many nonliving systems are feedback systems, the method of studyingthese systems is important. The concepts of feedback transformation and feedbackdecoupling shed some light on the matter, because the concepts tell when the systemunder consideration can be divided into smaller systems. For recent research, seeTakahara and Asahi (1985) and Saito (1986; 1987).

The study of decomposability conditions enlightens the research of relationsbetween “parts” and “whole.” Section 10.5 is mainly from Takahara’s excellentarticle (1982). The concept of decomposition of systems shows its power inSection 10.4.

Page 316: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 11

Calculus of Generalized Numbers

As before, boldface letters are used for GNS-related concepts and lightfaceletters for real-valued concepts. For example, ƒ(x ) represents a real-valued func-tion, and f(x) a function from a subset of GNS to a subset of GNS . Without loss ofgenerality, we will always assume that each real-valued function is from intoand each generalized number-valued function is from GNS into GNS, where isthe set of all real numbers and GNS stands for the set of all generalized numbers.A comprehensive understanding of mathematical analysis is needed to understandthis chapter.

As shown in Chapter 6, it is necessary to develop a more mature theory of math-ematics of levels. In this chapter the system of generalized numbers is treatedrigorously, such that the concepts of limit, continuity, differential calculus, in-tegral calculus, and their applications in the well-known Schwartz distributiontheory are introduced. Further research topics are also listed.

11.1. Introduction

Let be the set of all integers, the set of all real numbers, and the setof all natural numbers. A generalized number x is a function from into suchthat there exists a number k = k(x) ∈ called the level index of x, satisfying thecondition

(11.1)

For convenience, the zero function, denoted by 0, from into will also beconsidered a generalized number, and each such x is expressed as

(11.2)

311

Page 317: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

312 Chapter 11

where 1 (t) stands for the function from into such that

if s ≠ tif s = t

(11.3)

and x(t ) = x t . The set of all generalized numbers will be written as GNS . Theoperations of addition, subtraction, scalar multiplication, multiplication, division,and ordering relation of the generalized numbers are defined as follows:

(1) Addition and subtraction. Let x and y be arbitrary from GNS . Define

(11.4)

(2) Ordering. The ordering relation between x, y ∈ GNS is the lexicographicalordering; i.e., x < y iff there is an integer k0 such thatand

(3) Scalar multiplication. Let c ∈ and x ∈ GNS , and define

(11.5)

(4) Multiplication. Let x, y ∈ GNS. The product of x and y, denoted x × y orxy, is defined as

(11.6)

(5) Division. For x, y ∈ GNS, if there exists a z ∈ GNS such that

y × z = x (11.7)

then the generalized number z is called the quotient of x divided by y,denoted by x ÷ y or x /y. As shown in Chapter 6, if y ≠ 0 ∈ GNS , thenx ÷ y always uniquely exists.

Theorem 11.1.1. (GNS, +, × , <) forms a non-Archimedean field.

A3 There exists 0 ∈ GNS such that x + 0 = x, for any x ∈ GNS.

Proof: It suffices to show that (GNS, +, × , <) satisfies the following axioms:

A1 x + y = y + x, for any x, y ∈ GNS.

A2 x + ( y + z) = ( x + y ) + z, for any x, y, z ∈ GNS.

Page 318: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 313

A4 For any x ∈ GNS , there exists y ∈ GNS such that x + y = 0.

M1 x × y = y × x, for any x , y ∈ GNS .

M2 x × (y × z) = (x × y) × z, for any x , y, z ∈ GNS .

M3 There exists 1 ∈ GNS such that x × 1 = x , for any x ∈ GNS .

M4 For any 0 ≠ x ∈ GNS , there exists y ∈ GNS such that x × y = 1.

D1 0 ≠ l.

D2 x × (y + z) = (x + y) + (x × z), for any x , y,z ∈ GNS .

R1 x < x can never be true, for any x ∈ GNS.

R2 For any x , y , z ∈ GNS, x < y and y < z imply x < z .

R3 For any x, y ∈ GNS , one of the following must be true:

x < y, x = y, x > y

R4 For any x , y , z ∈ GNS , x < y implies x + z < y + z .

R5 For any x, y, z ∈ GNS , x < y and z > 0 imply x × z < y × z .

N1 For each natural number n ∈ there exists x ∈ GNS such that n < x.

It is straightforward to check all these axioms except, M4 and R5, if oneobserves the following facts: In GNS 0 is the zero function from to definedby 0(t ) = 0 for all t ∈ in GNS 1 is the unit element 1 ( 0 ) of the zeroth level, and foreach natural number n ∈ treat n as the generalized number n = (. . . , 0, n, 0, . . . )such that k(n) = 0.

Proof of Axiom M4: Assume that the fixed and unknown generalized numbersx and y have expressions

Then the equation x × y = 1 to be satisfied by x and y is equivalent to

(11.8)

where 1 = 1 (0) . That is, 1 (u) = 0, if u ≠ 0, and l(0) = 1. If u = 0 in Eq. (11.8),we see that k(y) can be defined as –k(x), and

Page 319: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

314 Chapter 11

If u = 1, Eq. (11.8) becomes

Hence, can be defined by By mathematical induction, thegeneralized number y is defined.

It can also be shown that y is unique. To this end, it suffices to show thatthere is no other way to define the level index k(y). By contradiction, assume thatk (y) = –k(x) –d, for some d ∈ Replacing u by – d, in Eq. (11.8), we get

This contradicts the fact that This ends the proof of Axiom M4.Proof of Axiom R5: The assumption that x < y and z > 0 implies that there

is t 0 ∈ such that x (t ) = y (t ) for all t < t0 , x( t0 ) < y ( t0) and z(k (z)) > 0. Tocompare x × z and y × z, let k 0 = t0 + k(z). It then suffices to show that for alls < k 0 , (x × z) (s) = (y × z) (s) and (x × z) (k0 ) < (y × z) (k0 ). To this end, fors < k 0, one has

since v ≥ k (z ) implies u < t 0 and x( u) = y( u). If s = k 0 = t 0 + k (z), x (t 0) < y (t 0)implies

since if v = k(z), u has to equal t0, so

while other terms in the summation are the same as the corre-sponding terms in This ends the proof of axiom R5.

Theorem 11.1.2. Let If h,k ∈ satisfy k < h,then the generalized numbers in I(k) are infinities compared with those in I(h) , andthe generalized numbers in I( h) are infinitesimals compared with those in I( k) .

Page 320: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers

The proof is straightforward and omitted.

Theorem 11.1.3. Let x, y ∈ GNS such that y ≠ 0 ≠ x. Then

(1) k (x + y ) ≥ min{ k( x), k(y)}.

(2) k(x × y) = k (x) + k (y).

(3) k(x / y) = k (x ) – k (y) .

315

Proof: The argument for (1) is straightforward and is left to the reader.The proof of (2). Assume that z = x × y and that

Hence, x × y = z is equivalent to, for any integer s,

(11.9)

where k (x) ≤ m ≤ s – k (y ) and k (y) ≤ n ≤ s – k (z ). We can now define k(z) =k(x ) + k (y ). When s = k (z ), Eq. (11.9) becomes

When s = k(z ) + 1, Eq. (11.9) becomes

By applying induction on the index k( z ) + i, the generalized number z can be welldefined.

To show the uniqueness of the index number k(z), it suffices to see thatk(z ) cannot be less than k(x) + k (y), as defined. To this end, assume k(z) =k(x ) + k( y) – n, for some nonzero whole number n. Replacing s by k(x) + k(y) – nin Eq. (11.9) gives

contradiction. That is, the definition of k (z) is unique. This ends the proof of (2).

Page 321: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

316 Chapter 11

Proof of (3). Let z = x /y. Assume that

Then these numbers satisfy

(11.10)

with k(y) ≤ u ≤ s – k(z) and k(z) ≤ v ≤ s – k (y). This second inequality impliesthat we can define k(z) = k(x) – k(y). Hence, replacing s by k(x) in Eq. (11. 10),one has

That is,

Thus, z(k(z)) = x (k(x))/y(k(y)). When s is replaced by k(x) + 1 in Eq. (11. 10),one has

Therefore,

By induction, we can continue this process and define each z(m) for m ≥ k (z) =k(x) – k (y). Thus, the relation between the generalized numbers z, x , and y canbe found.

The uniqueness of k(z) can be shown as follows: Assume that k(z) = k (x) –k(y) – n for some nonzero whole number n. Then replacing s by k(x) – n inEq. (11.10) gives

contradiction. The whole number n must therefore be zero. That is, k(z) must beunique.

Page 322: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 317

11.2. Continuity

Let E be a subset of GNS and f : E → GNS a function. For a fixed a ∈ E andfixed m , n ∈ , if for any real number ε > 0 there exists a real number δ > 0 suchthat, for any x ∈ E

imply that

then f(x) is quasi-(m, n ) continuous at point a (Wang, 1985). A special case ofquasi-(m, n ) continuity is quasi-(0, 0) continuity, which is the ordinary definitionof continuity of real-valued functions. If n < m , Theorem 11.1.2 implies thatwhen the function value is infinity, one can still study the concept of continuity.That is, the concept of continuity is expanded to include the study of continuity ofinfinities.

Theorem 11.2.1. If f(x) and g (x) are quasi-(m, n) continuous at a point a , thenso are the functions h(x) = f (x) + g (x) and k(x) = f (x) – g (x).

Proof: Since f(x) and g (x) are quasi-(m, n ) continuous at point a , by thedefinition of quasi-(m, n ) continuity, for any real number ε > 0, there exist realnumbers δf > 0 and δg > 0 such that for any x ∈ GNS ,

imply that

and that for any x ∈ GNS ,

imply that

Therefore, for any x ∈ GNS satisfying

one has

Page 323: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

318 Chapter 11

and

That is, it has been shown that h(x) and k(x) are quasi-(m, n ) continuous at thepoint a.

Theorem 11.2.2. Assume that the functions f(x) and g (x) are quasi-(m, n 1) and(m, n2 ) continuous at a point a , respectively. Then the product function h(x) =f(x)g(x) is quasi-(m, n) continuous at point a, where n = min{k(f(a)) + n 2 , n 1 +

k(g(a))}.

Proof: Since f(x) and g(x) are quasi-(m, n 1 ) and quasi-(m, n 2) continuous ata, respectively, from the definition of quasi-(m, n ) continuity, it follows that forany real number ε > 0 there exist real numbers δf > 0 and δg > 0 such that, forany x ∈ GNS ,

imply that

and

k(f(x)) = k (f(a)) ≤ n2 , and for some real number M; and thatfor any x ∈ GNS,

imply that

and

Therefore, for any x ∈ GNS satisfying

Page 324: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 319

one has

and

It has thus been shown that h(x) = f (x)g(x) is quasi-(m, n ) continuous at a.

Theorem 11.2.3. Assume that f(x) is quasi-(m, n f ) continuous at a point a andthat g(x) is quasi-(m, k (g(a))) continuous at a such that g (a) ≠ 0 . Then, thequotient function f(x)/g(x) is quasi-(m, n ) continuous at a , where n = min{nf –

k(g(a)), k (f(a)) – k (g(a))}.

Proof: From the assumption that g(x) is quasi-(m, k (g(a))) continuous at a, itfollows that for any real number ε > 0 there exists a real number δ g > 0 such that,for any x ∈ GNS ,

imply that

and k(g(x)) = k (g(a)), where for some fixed positivenumbers m, M ∈ The quasi-(m, k(g(a))) continuity of g(x) at a guarantees theexistence of m and M.

Page 325: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

320 Chapter 11

Now from the assumption that f(x) is quasi-(m, n f) continuous at a, it followsthat for any real number ε > 0, there exists a real number δf > 0 such that for anyx ∈ GNS,

imply that

and

Now let x ∈ satisfy

Then from Theorem 11.1.3 it follows that

and that

Therefore, the quotient function is quasi-(m, n ) continuous at a.

Page 326: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 321

11.3. Differential Calculus

In order to simplify the discussion, let us look at the concept of ⟨ ε– δ⟩ limitsin GNS first. Assume that f : GNS → GNS is a function and a ∈ GNS a fixedgeneralized number. For a fixed L ∈

(11.11)

stands for the fact that for fixed integers m and n , for any real number ε > 0 thereexists a real number δ > 0 such that for any x ∈ GNS ,

imply that

In this case, Eq. (11.11) is read as the quasi-(m, n) limit of f (x ) at a is L.Let S ∈ be fixed such that for fixed m, n ∈ for each real number ε > 0

there exists a real number δ > 0 such that, for any x ∈ GNS,

(11.12)

imply that

(11.13)

and

(11.14)

Then the generalized number S × 1 (n–m ) is called the (m,n )-derivative of thefunction f at a (Wang, 1985). In this case, f is (m,n)-differentiable at a, and the( m,n )-derivative will be written as

(11.15)

It is obvious that the (0, 0)-derivative of f is the ordinary derivative of real-valuedfunctions.

Page 327: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

322 Chapter 11

Example 11.3.1. Let g : be an infinitely differentiable real-valued functionsuch that is bounded and dt = 1. Define

It can be shown that the (1,–1)-derivative of g : GNS → GNS is

Theorem 11.3.1. If a function f : GNS → GNS is (m,n) -differentiable at a pointa ∈ GNS , then f is quasi-(m,n) continuous at a .

Proof: To show that f is quasi-(m,n) continuous at a, let ε be an arbitrary realnumber such that 0 < ε < 1. It suffices to show that there exists a real numberδ > 0 such that, for any x ∈ GNS ,

imply that

Since f is (m , n)-differentiable at a, there exists an S ∈ such that for the chosenε > 0, there exists a real number δ > 0 such that, for any x ∈ GNS,

imply that

and

So

Page 328: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 323

and

That is, f is quasi-( m,n ) continuous at a. �

Theorem 11.3.2.

(1) If f (x) = c ∈ GNS is a constant function, then

(2) If s is a positive integer and

then

where m = k(x ) and n = sm.

Proof:

(1) From Eq. (11.15), it follows that for any fixed a ∈ GNS,

(2) For any x, a ∈ GNS, the axioms of a non-Archimedean ordered field (seethe proof of Theorem 11.1.1) can be used to prove that

Page 329: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

324 Chapter 11

Therefore, for m = k(a) and n = sm ,

Theorem 11.3.3. Suppose that c ∈ is a constant and f'(m,n )

(x) and g'(m,n ) (x )exist. Then

The proof is straightforward and is omitted.One problem with the concept of (m,n)-derivative is that the derivative is a

generalized number in I(n – m ) . In (Wang, 1991), this problem was corrected by thefollowing methods.

Suppose y = f (x) = (. . . , y– m , . . . ,y0 , . . . ,yn , . . .) is a function from GNS intoGNS. Then, for each fixed index k ∈ yk is a function of x. That is, in general yk

depends on an infinite number of variables x0 ,x1 ,x– 1 ,x2, x – 2, . . . As in the calculusof real-valued functions, let ∆x and ∆y represent increments of x and y such that

where for each i ∈Let a ∈ GNS be fixed. Let

(11.16)

If there exists a generalized number, denoted f'(a), such that for each generalizednumber ε > 0, there exists a generalized number δ > 0 satisfying, for all ∆ x ∈ GNSwith

(11.17)

Page 330: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 325

Then f'(a ) is called the derivative of the function y = f(x) at a. Symbolically,

(11.18)

Remark. Topologically speaking, the concept of derivative of f( x ) at a ∈ GNS isintroduced so that the topological space has the box product topology.For more about this topology, see (Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976).

For x, y ∈ GNS, a different ordering relation, denoted by on GNS can bedefined as follows: x y iff for each i ∈ xi < yi . With this ordering relationon GNS, the weak derivative of y = f(x), a function from GNS into GNS, can beintroduced as follows (Wang, 1991): Suppose K ∈ GNS is fixed. If for each realnumber ε > 0, there exists with the property thatδj > 0, for each j ≥ k (δ), such that whenever one has

for each s ∈ then, K is called the weak derivative of f(x) at a, denoted f'w (a) = K.

11.4. Integral Calculus

11.4.1. Lebesgue Measures

For convenience and completeness of this chapter, we briefly look at someelementary definitions and properties of Lebesgue integration, which is the centerof the theory of real analysis.

In classical mathematical analysis, functions which are continuous everywhereare basically the center of the discussion of interest. However, as the theorygrew more mature and more applications were found, it seemed that it was nolonger sufficient to consider the everywhere continuous functions only. At first,it was found that based on the consideration of continuous functions, the theoryestablished was often incomplete and also its applications were not flexible, atthe same time, it also seriously affected the development of the theory itself. Forexample, the theory of integration of continuous functions was developed with thetheory of linear algebra as its background. This background has had great impacton the establishment and development of the theory. However, even though itwas restricted to the study of continuous functions, under certain circumstancesthe harmony between the two theories was destroyed. For example, the conceptof limits introduced in the space L 2, denoted by lim is different from

Page 331: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

326 Chapter 11

This new concept of convergence has widespread applications. There are manygood reasons for introducing new concepts. For example, if it has been shownthat the boundary problems of partial differential equations of some problems inphysics do not have differentiable solutions, can one claim, based on this fact, thatthese possess no practical meaning? Obviously not! since boundary problems areoften approximations of some realistic situations, they are idealized mathematicalmodels, and the coefficients of the differential equations in the models are notabsolutely accurate. Therefore, one should look at boundary problems from theviewpoint of approximation. It is unreasonable to restrict ourselves to the range ofcontinuous and differentiable functions. Because of this, the concept of generalized

In the theory of Riemann integrals, to integrate each term of a given series,the series must be uniformly convergent. Without uniform convergence, the limitof a sequence of integrable functions may not be integrable at all, and thereforethere is no way for one to talk about integrating each terms and summing theresults. On the other hand, in applied situations, the requirement of uniformconvergence is often not satisfied or is so complicated that it only causes moretrouble. Similar problems exist in different areas of the old theory of integration.Most arise because in the definition of definite integrals, too much emphasis is puton the requirement of continuity. The essence of Riemann integrations involves(1) cutting the interval into finitely many subintervals; (2) on each subinterval,looking at the function value ƒ(x) as a constant; (3) improving accuracy of theapproximation by increasing the number of subintervals; (4) taking the limit toachieve the desired accuracy. For this process to work, ƒ(x) cannot vary “too much”on each of these subintervals. That is, ƒ(x) must be “fundamentally” continuous.If ƒ(x) is “extremely discontinuous,” no matter how small each subinterval is, thereis no way that one can look at ƒ(x) as approximately a constant. The function is

If ƒ (x ) is discontinuous, then we should try some new methods. For instance,partition the interval into small subsets, on each of which ƒ(x) does not vary “toomuch.” This is how the theory of Lebesgue integration was born.

The open interval A in the space is assumed to be the set of points, where ai and bi are constants. If A is an interval,

it means that some of the inequalities in its definition can contain the equals sign.For any interval A, A stands for , called the volume of A. Let E bea set of points in , and A1 , A2, . . . , An , . . . a sequence of open intervals such that

. Thenis defined by

then considered to be not integrable.

the concept of lim in mathematical analysis, where L² standsfor the space of all the functions which are Lebesgue square-integrable on

solutions was introduced.

. The exterior measure of E, denoted m * E,

’s are open intervals and

Page 332: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 327

Let A be an interval such that A ⊇ E , and A 1,A2 ,... , An , . . . a sequence of openintervals such that . Hence, . Define the interiormeasure of E, denoted as m *E, by

If m * E = m *E, the set E is Lebesgue measurable or simply measurable. Therefore,the collection of all bounded subsets of is classified as measurable or notmeasurable. An unbounded set B ⊆ is measurable if B ∩ A is measurablefor each chosen interval A. One equivalent condition for a subset A ⊆ to bemeasurable is given in the next theorem.

Theorem 11.4.1. A subset A ⊆ is measurable iff, for any subset T ⊆ ,

In this case, the exterior measure of A is called the measure of A and is denotedby mA.

Theorem 11.4.2. Assume that A and B are measurable subsets in and ,respectively. Then C = A × B is a measurable subset in , andm(C) = mA × mB.

Let ƒ(x ) be a real-valued function defined on a measurable set E ⊆ . Ifthere is a partition of the subset such that on each Ei the function ƒ(x )is a constant, ƒ(x) is a simple function. It is obvious that the sum and productof simple functions are still simple functions. However, the limit of a sequenceof simple functions may not be a simple function at all, since a simple functioncan only have a finite number of different function values. A function ƒ(x ) ismeasurable on E if there is a sequence of simple functions, defined onE, such that

Let ƒ(x ) = ƒ ( x1 , x2, . . . , xn ) be a function defined on a subset E ⊆ . Define

and

The set

is called the graph of ƒ(x).

Page 333: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

328 Chapter 11

Theorem 11.4.3. A function ƒ(x) defined on a measurable subset E ⊆ ismeasurable iff the graph G( E;ƒ) of the function is measurable in the (n + 1) -dimensional space

Now it is time to look at the concept of Lebesgue integrals.Case 1: Let E ⊆ be a measurable subset with mE < + ∞, and ƒ (x) a

bounded function defined on E. Let us see how the Lebesgue integral of ƒ(x) isdefined.

Assume that and are two partitions such that eachE i

* and Ej** are measurable. It is obvious that

is also a partition, which is a finer partition than either of the previous two. For, let bi and Bi be the greatest lower bound and the least upper bound

of ƒ(x ) on Ei ; i.e., bi ≤ ƒ(x) ≤ B i for each x ∈ Ei . Define

which are called the small sum and the big sum of the function with respect to thepartition . Obviously, one has

bmE ≤ s ≤ S ≤ BmE

where b and B are the greatest lower and the least upper bounds of ƒ( x) on E ,respectively. It can be shown that if D* is a finer partition than D and if s* and S*

are the small sum and the big sum of ƒ(x) with respect to D* , then

s ≤ s* ≤ S * ≤ S

No matter what kind of partition D is, the small sum and the big sum are alwaysbetween bmE and BmE one can thus define

Then

where and called the lower integral and the upper integral

of ƒ(x) on E. If , then ƒ(x) is integrable and written as

Page 334: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 329

Case 2: Let E ⊆ be a measurable subset with mE < + ∞ , and ƒ( x) ≥ 0 anonnegative function defined on E. To define the integral of ƒ(x) on E , let

for any fixed n ∈ . Then {ƒ(x )}n, is a bounded function on E and satisfies. If for each n ∈ , {f (x)} n is integrable on E, then ƒ(x) is

integrable on E, and we write

For a general function ƒ(x) defined on E, define

when ƒ(x ) ≥ 0when ƒ(x ) < 0

and

when ƒ(x) ≤ 0when ƒ(x ) > 0

If f +(x) and f –(x) have integral values on E which are not both infinities, thenƒ(x) has integral value on E, which is denoted by

If the integral values of f+(x) and f– (x) are finite, ƒ (x) is integrable on E.Case 3: Let E be a measurable subset of and ƒ ( x) a function defined on E.

Define

if x ∈ Eotherwise

Then F (x ) is a function defined on the entire space . Without loss of generality,let ƒ(x) be a function defined on . First, assume ƒ( x) ≥ 0 for all x ∈ . Foreach k ∈ , define

Then

If ƒ(x) is integrable on each , define

Page 335: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

330 Chapter 11

as the integral value of ƒ(x) on . When this is value is finite, ƒ(x ) is integrableon

Second, let ƒ (x ) be a general function defined on . Define

when ƒ(x ) ≥ 0when ƒ(x ) < 0

and

when ƒ(x ) ≤ 0when ƒ(x) > 0

If and are meaningful, define the integral value of ƒ(x )as

If these two integrals are finite, ƒ(x) is integrable on .

11.4.2. Integrals on GNS

Let us now turn our attention to the concept of integrals of functions definedon GNS. Let f : E → F be a function from a subset E of GNS into a subset F ofGNS. Define a new function f* : GNS → GNS as follows:

if x ∈ Eotherwise

Without loss of generality, it can be assumed that each function f from a subset ofGNS into a subset of GNS is a function from GNS into GNS .

To make this chapter self-contained, the definition of integrals of functionsdefined on GNS, studied in Chapter 6 will be reintroduced. After that, newconcepts of definite integrals and indefinite integrals will be studied. We definethe integral, called a GNL-integral, with GNL standing for generalized numberand Lebesgue, of functions defined on GNS inductively as follows. For a givenfunction f : GNS → GNS , let E = {x ∈ GNS : f (x) ≠ 0 }.

Case 1: Suppose that for each x ∈ E , x – m = 0, for all m ∈ and that y =f(x) = (. . . , y –m , . . . , y 0 . . . , yn , . . .), where, in general, yk = y k (x ) is a function ofall

Step 1: Define a subset H (0) ⊆ as follows: a0 ∈ H (0) iff

y– m = 0 if m > 0 and y0 = y 0 (a0) a function of a 0 (11.19)

where

Page 336: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 331

whenever x = (. . . , 0, a0 , x1 , x2 , . . .), with x(k(x)) = a0 ; let

(11.20)

If the real-valued function ƒ(0) is Lebesgue integrable on then – H ( 0 ) hasLebesgue measure zero, and set

Step n: Assume the real numbers a (0) , a (1) , . . . ,a( n– 1) have all been defined.For any fixed x0 , . . . xn –1, define a subset H (n ) ⊆ as follows: an ∈ H (n ) iff

and a function of an

where

whenever let

(11.21)

(11.22)

If the real-valued function is Lebesgue integrable on , denote the

integral on by a (n ) (x0 , . . . , xn – 1). If is meaningful,that is — if there are only countably many nonzero summands and the summationis absolutely convergent, then the sum is denoted by a( n ) .

Definition 11.4.1 [Wang (1985)]. If is convergent and equals a, thenthe function f(x) is GNL-integrable, written

Case 2: Partition the set E = {x ∈ GNS : f (x) ≠ 0 } as follows:where Ek = {x ∈ E : k (x) = –k}. For each fixed k ∈ , consider

the right-shifting of and the left-shifting of

f(x):

First, define a new function f (0) : GNS → GNS by

Page 337: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

332 Chapter 11

If f ( 0 ) is GNL-integrable, write (GNS) Second, define

That is, for any x ∈ , k(x) = 0. Define a new function f ( 1 ) : GNS → GNS by

If f (1) is GNL-integrable, write (GNL) In general, writeif f ( k ) is GNL-integrable.

Definition 11.4.2 [Wang (1985)]. If is convergent, then the function f(x) isGNL-integrable and written

A concept called (G) integrals was introduced by Wang (1985). Let f : GNS →GNS be a function and E = {x ∈ GNS : f (x) ≠ 0}. Let

As before, the concept of (G) integrals will be introduced in two parts. The firstpart is a special case, while the second part generalizes the first.

Case 1: Suppose that for any x ∈ E the generalized number x takes the formx = (… , 0, x 0 , x1 , . . . , xn , . . . ). That is, x– m = 0, for each m ∈

Step 0: Define a subset H( 0 ) ⊆ such that a0 ∈ H ( 0 ) iff y– m = y– m (a0 ) is afunction of a0 only for all m ≥ 0. Let f (0) : be a function defined by

If each y– (s ) (a0 ) is Lebesgue integrable, s = 0, 1, 2, . . . , write

Step n: Let x0 , x 1 , . . . , xn – 1 be fixed. Define a subset H (n ) ⊆ suchthat an ∈ H ( n ), iff y – m = y – m (a0 ) is a function of a 0 only for all m ≥ n .Let be a function defined as follows: i f

Page 338: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 333

If each y– (n + s ) (an) is Lebesgue integrable, s = 0, 1, 2, . . . , write

and if exists, denote it by

for s = 0, 1, 2, . . . .

Definition 11.4.3 [Wang (1985)]. For each s ≥ 0, if the sequence exists

and is convergent, define

If there are only a finite number of natural numbers s such that a– s ≠ 0, then thefunction ƒ(x) is (G)-integrable, denoted

Case 2: Suppose that for some x ∈ E there exists m ∈ such that x– m ≠ 0.Partition the set E = {x ∈ GNS : f (x) ≠ 0} as

where for each First, define

If f ( 0 ) is (G)-integrable, let (G) Second, define the right-shifting of E1 and a function f ( 1 ) : GNS → GNS by

and

If f ( 1 ) is (G)-integrable, set (G)

Page 339: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

334 Chapter 11

and

Inductively, assume that for n ∈ the generalized numbers a0 , a1 , a2 , . . . , an

have been defined. Now a generalized number an + 1 can be defined as follows:First, define the right-shifting of En and a function f( n ) : GNS → GNS by

If f ( n ) is (G)-integrable, let (G)By mathematical induction it follows that if all the generalized numbers

a 0, a1 , a2 , . . . , an , . . . have been defined as before, then we can make the followingdefinition.

Definition 11.4.4 [Wang (1985)]. If is convergent to a generalized num-ber a, then the function f is (G)-integrable,

The following result is clear.

Theorem 11.4.4. If f : GNS → GNS is (GNL)- integrable, it is then (G)-integrableand

(11.23)

Now let F be a family of (GNL)-integrable (resp., (G)-integrable) functions.Suppose that a convergence relation among functions defined on GNS has beenchosen such that there exist a sequence and a function f : GNS → GNSsuch that

(11.24)

The (GNS)F-integral (resp., (G)F -integral) of f is defined as follows:

(11.25)

(11.26)

(11.27)

Page 340: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 335

and

(11.28)

where it is assumed that the limits exist.The concept of indefinite integral of a function f : GNS → GNS was studied

by Wang (1985) as follows. Assume that (GNL) exists and that thefunction value of f(x) depends only on the real variable xk (x ). Then the indefiniteintegral of y = f(x) is defined as

where a = (… , a – m , … , a , … , a0 n , …) is fixed, and : GNS → GNS is defined

by

11.5. Schwartz Distribution and GNS

11.5.1. A Nontechnical Introduction to Schwartz Distribution

The theory of distributions was developed to correspond to situations presentedto the world of learning by physical experiences which are not adequately coveredby the classical y = ƒ(x) notion of a function in mathematical analysis. Here,the word “physical” really means “phenomenological” — i.e., pertaining to thephenomena of nature. The concept of distributions, as introduced and codified byLaurent Schwartz (1950; 1951), has been widely used to tie many important anddifferent instances, occurring in different parts of the world of learning, together.

A “distribution” is a kind of “generalized function.” The class of all distribu-tions or generalized functions includes many objects which are not functions atall in the sense of classical mathematical analysis. The reason why it is necessaryto study the theory of distributions is not mere generality; rather, the theory has acoherence and a power that the theory of mathematical analysis lacks. There aremany aspects of this conceptual power. For example, the operation of taking aderivative applies without restriction to distributions. That is, the derivative of a

Page 341: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

336 Chapter 11

Figure 11.1. A pulse function supported on [0,1].

distribution always exists and is another distribution. Since continuous functionsare distributions, the operation of taking a derivative in the theory of distributionseliminates the defect of mathematical analysis, where many continuous functionshave no derivatives.

A function is a test function if

(a) φ is infinitely differentiable.

(b) φ has compact support; i.e., φ(x) vanishes outside of some interval [a,b] .

The motivations underlying the term “test function” are that test functions serve astools in studying other functions, and that curves with certain crude geometricalshapes, like pulses or mesas (Figs. 11.1 and 11.2), can be constructed in an infinitelydifferentiable manner.

Let us now see how the idea of test functions can be used to evaluate anunknown function of interest. Assume that a chemist needs to test the propertiesof a certain substance at a fixed temperature t0. So, he gathers a batch of the stuffwith temperatures distributed in a pulse φ(T ) near T = t0. His objective is tofind some law. Mathematically speaking, the law will normally be written as afunction, say f (T). Let us see how the test function φ is used to determine theunknown function f.

There is no doubt that in reality some temperatures appear more often thanothers. Hence, the temperatures have a density φ (T) supported on [a,b], and a

Figure 11.2. A mesa function supported on [a,b] .

Page 342: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 337

“weighted average” is natural to consider:

Now φ is used to measure f. If φ is chosen differently with different temperatureranges, eventually the structure of f will be known. In the language of the chemist,he might say that by enough experiments φ we learn the “law” described by f.

Let ƒ : be such that dx exists and is finite for any finite interval[a,b ]. Then the action of a test function φ on f is defined to beThe following result supports this example.

Theorem 11.5.1 [Richards and Youn (1990)]. Let f : and g: becontinuous and satisfy that every test function φ has the same action on f and g.Then f = g.

A sequence of test functions converges to zero, written if

(a) For each k ∈ the sequence of the k th derivatives convergesuniformly to zero.

(b) The φ n have uniformly bounded supports; i.e., there is an interval [a,b],independent of n, such that every φn (x ) vanishes outside of [a,b] .Similarly, φn → φ means ( φ – φn ) → 0. The set D of all test functionstogether with the convergence relation, defined earlier, is called theelementary space.

Definition 11.5.1 [Richards and Youn (1990)]. A distribution T is a mappingfrom the set D of all test functions into the real or complex numbers, such that thefollowing conditions hold, where T ( φ) is written as

(a) (Linearity) for allD and constants a and b.

(b) (Continuity) If then

Example 11.5.1. Let f: be piecewise continuous. For any φ ∈ D define

It can be shown readily that T is a distribution.

Page 343: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

338 Chapter 11

Example 11.5.2. Dirac’s δ function δ is a symbol which satisfies the followingconditions:

(11.29)

where φ ∈ D is any test function. For a different discussion on the δ function, seeChapter 6.

In terms of distributions, the δ function is defined by the equation

Now shift the δ function through a distance +a. This should give the functionδ ( x – a ), and

That is, the shifting δ(x – a ) evaluates the test function φ at x = a. The followingmay be a little surprising:

and in general,Let be a sequence of distributions and T a distribution. is

convergent to T, written as Tn → T if

Based on this concept, the following theorem is interesting.

Theorem 11.5.2 [Richards and Youn (1990)]. Let f(x ) be a piecewise continu-ous function such that

Denote fa (x ) = af ( ax ). Then

where the convergence is in the sense of distribution.

Page 344: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 339

For a more comprehensive nontechnical introduction to the theory of Schwartzdistributions, refer to the splendid work by Richards and Youn (1990).

11.5.2. GNS Representation of Schwartz Distributions

Let be functions from into These functions arelinearly independent if for any constants the equation

implies that Otherwise, the functions are linearly depen-dent. For a set F of functions from into F is linearly independent if eachfinite subset of F contains linearly independent functions.

Lemma 11.5.1. For linearly independent continuous functions

1,2,..., there are sequences of real numbers, k = 1,2,3,..., such thatfor each k ∈

det (11.30)

and, if then

Proof: Since the set F = is assumed to be linearlyindependent for any constants the equation

implies that Therefore, none of the functions

in F is the zero function. Thus, there exists a real number such that

Assume that for a natural number n, the real numbers

have been defined such that Eq. (11.30) holds and that implies

Now we define the real numbers such thatthe desired conditions are satisfied.

Since fn+1 is not the zero function, pick a real number such that

is different from all previously chosen and that

Page 345: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

340 Chapter 11

The existence of comes from the fact that fn +1 is continuous and that all

previously chosen are a finite number. Now pick a real number suchthat

The existence of such a number comes from the fact that fn and fn + 1 arelinearly independent, which implies that

The continuity of fn and f n +1 guarantees that the can be different from all

previousBy mathematical induction it can be shown that the real numbers

can be chosen one after another so that each one

is different from all previous and that for each i satisfying

Therefore, induction guarantees that there are sequences of real numbers,k = 1,2,..., such that for each Eq. (11.30) holds true and if

then

Lemma 11.5.2. The elementary space D of all test functions is separable; i.e.,there exists a countable subset F ⊆ D such that for any φ ∈ D, there exists asequence F such that φn → φ.

Proof: Let h : be defined by

(11.31)

Then is a test function with support [0,1]. For any a, b ∈define

Page 346: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 341

Then φa,b is a test function with support [a, b].

Then pn (x) φ (x ) is a test function. Let F = {pn (x) φa,b (x) : pn (x) is a polynomialof degree n with all rational number coefficients, n ∈ , and a and b are rational}.Then F ⊆ is countable. It is left to the reader to show that for any φ ∈ thereexists a sequence ⊆ F such that φn → φ.

For each infinitely differentiable function ƒ : → , define a function f :GNS → GNS as follows:

(11.32)

Here f is called the GNS function induced by ƒ.

Theorem 11.5.3 [Wang (1985)]. Let T be a distribution and F as in Lemma11.5.2. Then there exists K : GNS → GNS such that, for each ƒ ∈ F,

(11.33)

Proof: Let

For any rational numbers a and b, define

Let G = {pn (x) Φa,b (x) : pn (x) is a polynomial of degree n with all rational coeffi-cients, for n ∈ , and a and b are rational numbers}. Then the families F and G canbe put into 1–1 correspondence by matching up pn (x) φa,b (x) p (x) Φa,b (x).

Let pn (x) be a polynomial of degree n with all rational number coefficients.

a,b

where f : GNS → GNS is induced by ƒ.

n

Page 347: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

342 Chapter 11

Now we show that the family G is linearly independent. Pick an arbitrary finitesubset H ⊆ G, say

Let d 1 ,d2 , … , dk be constants satisfying

(11.34)

It suffices to show that d1 = d2 = . . . = dk = 0.Case 1: For each i with 1 ≤ i ≤ k, assume

and that (ai , bi ) ≠ (a j , bj ), whenever i ≠ j. Thus, Eq. (11.34) becomes

(11.35)

Now choose k different values of x for which it is easy to evaluate the e-functions.We obtain S, k linear equations in k variables d1, d2 , … , dk , from which it can beshown that the system has zero solution only. That is, d1 = d2 = . . . = dk = 0.

where Φ ai ,bi (x) is defined by Eq. (11.35) satisfying (ai , b i ) ≠ (a j , bj ), wheneveri ≠ j, and the polynomial

(11.36)

where the coefficients c ij’s are rational. Equation (11.34) then becomes

(11.37)

Now group the terms of Eq. (11.37) according to the powers of x appearing in the

That completes the proof that ƒ1,ƒ 2 , . . . ,ƒk are linearly independent.Case 2: For each i with 1 ≤ i ≤ k, assume

polynomials Pni (x), i = 1,2 , . . . , k, so that each power of x appears at most once.

Page 348: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 343

Equation (11.37) is true iff the coefficient of each power of x equals zero. Hence,Eq. (11.37) is equivalent to n = max{n1 , n 2 , . . . , n k} + 1 many equations, each ofwhich looks similar to Eq. (11.35). The only difference which might occur isthat some constant coefficients may show up in front of some di’s in Eq. (11.35).Therefore, the argument in Case 1 implies that d1 = d 2 = . . . = d k = 0. That is,ƒ1,ƒ2 , . . . ,ƒk are linearly independent. This completes the proof that the family Gis linearly independent.

Since G is countable, enumerate the elements in G as

From Lemma 11.5.1 it follows that there are sequences of real numbers,for k = 1,2,3, . . . , satisfying Eq. (11.30).

(11.38)

(1) Since there must be a real number c1(0)

such that

(11.39)

(2) When n = 2, Eq. (11.30) is true. Hence the system

(11.40)

has a unique solution which is denoted c1(1)

and c 2(1)

.

(3) In general, assume that for a fixed have been defined fork ≤ m + 1 ≤ m0 + 1. Since Eq. (11.30) holds for n = m0 + 1, the following

, k = 1,2 , . . . , m0 + 1 has A unique solution:

(11.41)

where

Choose a real-valued infinitely differentiable function g(x ) satisfying {x ∈ :g(x) ≠ 0} is bounded and g(x)dx = 1. Define a function K : GNS → GNSas follows: for m ≥ 0,

system with unknowns

Page 349: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

344 Chapter 11

It then follows from the definition of (GNL)-integrals and Eq. (11.41) that K :GNS → GNS satisfies Eq. (11.33). This completes the proof of the theorem.

For the countable subset F ⊆ given in Lemma 11.5.2 and for the functionK : GNS → GNS introduced in Theorem 11.5.3, let K · F = {K · f :ƒ ∈ F }, wherefor each ƒ ∈ F, f : GNS → GNS is the GNS function induced by ƒ; see Eq. (11.32).Then the following result is not difficult to see.

Theorem 11.5.4 [Wang (1985)]. For each arbitrary test function ƒ ∈ of ele-mentary space,

where T is the distribution used to determine K.

11.6. A Bit of History

Research in non-Archimedean fields has been closely related to those ofnon-Archimedean topology and non-Archimedean analysis. The study of non-Archimedean topological structures has been valuable in the study of dimensiontheory and in research in algebra and algebraic geometry. To see this, one needonly to consult the p-adic topology and Stone duality theorem in Boolean alge-bra (Nyikos and Reichel, 1975). The concept of linear uniformity, introducedby Frechet (1945), and the theory of ωµ -additive topological spaces, studied bymany, including Hausdorff, Sikorski (1950), Shu-Tang Wang (1964), Stevensonand Thron (1971), Hodel (1975), Juhasz (1965), Husek and Reichel (1983), Ya-sui (1975), and Nyikos and Reichel (1976), are related to the general study ofnon-Archimedean topology. Also, non-Archimedean topology has been appliedin research of abstract distances, introduced and studied by Frechet (1946), Kurepa(1934; 1936a; 1936b; 1956), Doss (1947), Colmez (1947), etc.

As for the study of non-Archimedean analysis, Italian differential geome-ter Levi-Civita (1892) introduced and studied the concept of formal powerseries. In particular, he discussed some algebraic problems of his non-Archimedean field and applications in Voronese’s non-Archimedean geometry(Voronese, 1896; Voronese, 1891), at the time criticized and not trusted by many.The purpose of Levi-Civita’s work was to establish an extremely rigorous “arith-metic” foundation for Voronese’s geometry. Later, Hilbert employed Levi-Civita’swork on formal power series in his work on foundations of geometry. Hans Hahnhas been commonly recognized as the first person to study ordered algebraicstructures. In fact, his work on ordered algebraic structures is a continuation ofLevi-Civita’s formal power series. The generalized number system, introduced by

Page 350: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Calculus of Generalized Numbers 345

Wang (1985), and studied in some detail in this chapter, was first studied with thedefinition of multiplication operation (by Wang) in 1963. His goal was to studystrange functions, which appear in modern physics. Unfortunately, the paper wasnot published and got lost. Until 1977, Wang did not have a chance to reorganizehis work, due to the Cultural Revolution in China. In 1978, Wang learned ofLaugwitz’s work (1968), through whom Levi-Civita’s formal power series was in-troduced to Wang. In Laugwitz’s research, he discussed formal power series fromthe angle of classical mathematical analysis. The major difference between thestudy of formal power series and that of generalized number system is that eventhough algebraically the generalized number system is a subfield of the formalpower series, Wang, on GNS, introduced the concepts of various integrals andapplied the theory of GNS to the study of various problems in modern physics.Particularly, Dirac’s δ function in quantum mechanics and the Heaviside functionin quantum field theory have been given concrete representations in GNS . Also,the concept of Taylor expansion, and all elementary functions were extended tothe GNS field.

As shown in Chapter 6, one can be sure that the theory of generalized numberswill be developed a great deal, along with the successes which have been or willbe accomplished in the realm of systems science and its applications.

11.7. Some Leads for Further Research

Comparing the study of the generalized number system with those containedin mathematical analysis, real analysis, and complex analysis, it can be seen thatunderstanding the GNS is still at the germinating stage. More work needs to becarried out in order for us to gain a deeper understanding of nature and the worldin which we live.

For instance, it is necessary to

(1)

(2)

(3)

(4)

(5)

Study the ordering relation, defined in Section 11.1. It is obvious that theGNS field is not complete in the sense of Dedekind cuts.

Find the relation between the ordering relations defined in Sections 11.1and 11.3.

Develop workable and concrete formulas for the operations ofmultiplication, division, and taking roots.

Introduce the concept of continuity based on the ordering relation definedin Section 11.3.

Establish a law, similar to the transfer principle in nonstandard analysis(Davis, 1977), governing the relation between a set of properties of realnumbers and a set of properties of generalized numbers.

Page 351: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

346 Chapter 11

(6) Develop the results of generalized numbers corresponding to theorems inmathematical analysis, such as intermediate value theorem, maximum andminimum theorem, etc.

(7) Find detailed formulas to compute various derivatives, definite andindefinite integrals of given functions from GNS into GNS .

(8) Generalize the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus to the case of GNS,linking GNS differential calculus to GNS integral calculus.

(9) Develop an integral calculus of GNS based on Lebesgue integrals.

(10) Use GNS representations of Schwartz’s distributions to explore newexplanations of equations, appearing in the theory of distributions, whichdo not make sense in classical mathematical analysis.

(11) Employ GNS representations of Schwartz’s distributions to solve openproblems in the theory of distributions, such as the problem of definingproducts of distributions. Can the theory of GNS be used to explain why,in general, the products of distributions might not exist?

(12) Redevelop quantum mechanics based on GNS so that, hopefully, morepuzzles in current quantum mechanics can be explained more rationally.

(13) Explore applications of the theory of GNS in other branches of humanknowledge. The future success of the theory of GNS may well depend onvarious successful applications.

Page 352: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

CHAPTER 12

Some Unsolved Problems in GeneralSystems Theory

In this chapter some open problems in set-theoretic general systems theory arelisted. A common feature of these problems is that their studies will lead to somenew understanding in several research areas and the introduction of new concepts.The main part of this chapter is also contained in (Lin et al., 1997).

12.1. Introduction

Von Bertalanffy introduced the concept of systems in biology in the late 1920s(von Bertalanffy, 1934), and it has been developed a great deal in the last 70 yearsor so. Starting in the early 1960s, scholars began to establish a theory of generalsystems in order to lay down a theoretical foundation for all approaches of systemsanalysis developed in different disciplines. Led by von Bertalanffy and supportedby several of the most powerful minds of our time, a global systems movementhas been going on for several decades.

Along the development path of the systems movement, many scholars fromdifferent disciplines have tried to first define the concept of general systems andthen apply the concept and the theory, developed on the concept of general systems,to solving problems in various research areas. Technical difficulties of introducingan ideal definition for general systems, and notably unsuccessful applications ofgeneral systems theory [for details see (Berlinski, 1976; Lilienfeld, 1978)], havetaught many painful lessons. Among them are: (1) There might not exist anideal definition for general systems, upon which a general systems theory couldbe developed so that this theory would serve as the theoretical foundation for allapproaches of systems analysis, developed in various disciplines. (2) Without anideal definition of general systems in place, “general systems theory” would bemeaningless. In this circumstance, under the name of systems analysis, senselesstransfer of results from one discipline to another have really made many scholarsdoubt the value of “general systems theory.” (3) Based on historical experience and

347

Page 353: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

348 Chapter 12

the “unreasonable effectiveness” of mathematics (Wigner, 1960), several fruitfuldefinitions of general systems have been introduced since the early 1960s. Eventhough abstract general systems theory has been established through the effortsof many scholars, including Mesarovic and Takahara, the real challenge fromscholars — namely to show the need and power of the concept of general systemsand its theory it is necessary to obtain results which have not been nor could be,achieved without using the concept and its theory — has not been very well met.

To meet the challenge of showing the need and power of the concept andtheory of general systems, we list some the following problems: infinite or finitedivisibility of the material world; why the concept of systems was not studiedmore intensively until now; meaning of a system with contradictory relations;existence of absolute truths unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics; philosophyof mathematical modeling; the need to study an applied set theory; multilevelstructure of the world; the Law of Conservation of Matter–Energy; the materialfoundation of human thought; the origin of the universe; the need to develop amathematics of multilevels and its application in Einstein’s relativity theory.

From this brief list, one can see that the study of general systems theorywill surely impact the entire spectrum of human knowledge. How the systemsmovement is regarded is each scholar’s opinion and position. No matter howsuspicious some scholars are, history will still proceed at its own pace. To this end,the development histories of Cantor’s set theory, Einstein’s relativity theory, etc.,have taught us that no new theory would be born without suffering from suspicions,prejudices, and calumnies. In fact, meeting challenges and self-renewing areamong the most important motivations for a newborn theory to grow, to mature,and to gain a visible position in scientific history.

12.2. The Concept of Systems

The fundamental characteristics of a system are the unification of “isolated”objects, relations between the objects, and the structure of layers.

The idea of systems appeared at least as early as the one-element Ionians(624–500 B.C.). For example, in the search for order, Ionians had a naturalisticand materialistic bent. They sought causes and explanations in terms of theeternal working of things themselves rather than in any divine, mythological, orsupernatural intervention. Looking for a single basic reality, each Ionian believedthat all things have their origin in a single knowable element: water, air, fire, orsome indeterminate, nebulous substance (Perlman, 1970).

In history the idea of systems has been used by many great thinkers to studydifferent problems. For example, Aristotle’s statement “the whole is greater thanthe sum of its parts” could be an early definition of a basic systems problem.Nicholas of Cusa, a profound thinker of the fifteenth century, linking medieval

Page 354: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 349

mysticism with the first beginnings of modern science, introduced the notion ofthe coincidentia oppositorum. Leibniz’s hierarchy of monads looks quite like thatof modern systems. Gustav Fechev, known as the author of the psychophysicallaw, elaborated, in the way of the naive philosophers of the nineteenth century,supraindividual organizations of higher order than the usual objects of observation,thus romantically anticipating the ecosystems of modern parlance (von Bertalanffy,1972). We list only a few of the great thinkers.

In the second decade of this century, von Bertalanffy (1934) wrote

Since the fundamental character of the living thing is its organization, the customaryinvestigation of the single parts and processes cannot provide a complete expla-nation of the vital phenomena. This investigation gives us no information aboutthe coordination of parts and processes. Thus the chief task of biology must be todiscover the laws of biological systems (at all levels of organization). We believethat the attempts to find a foundation for theoretical biology point at a fundamentalchange in the world picture. This view, considered as a method of investigation, weshall call “organismic biology” and, as an attempt at an explanation, “the systemtheory of the organism.”

Here, a new concept, “system” was introduced. After 70 years of testing, thisconcept has been widely accepted by scientists in all disciplines (Blauberg et al.,1977). To establish a theoretical foundation for all approaches of systems analysis,developed in different disciplines, Mesarovic, in the early 1960s introduced themathematical definition of (general) systems, based on Cantor’s set theory, asfollows (Mesarovic and Takahara, 1975): A (general) system S is a relation onnonempty sets Vi :

where I is an index set. This structure of general systems reflects the unification of“isolated” objects, relations between the objects, and the structure of layers. Here,elements in the nonempty sets Vi , i ∈ I , are the objects of the system, S representsa relation between objects, and elements of the sets Vi , i ∈ I , could be systems too.Using this idea of layers inductively, we can see that an element S1 of S could be asystem, an element S2 of the system S1 could be a system, … Can this process goon forever? If the answer is “yes,” then “the world would be infinitely divisible”!If the answer to the question is “No,” does that mean the world is made up offundamental elements?

The idea that the world is infinitely divisible can be found in Anaxagoras’“seeds” philosophy (510–428 B.C.). He was unwilling to submerge the tremen-dous varieties of things into any common denominator, and preferred to accept theimmediate diversity of things as is. With his philosophy, every object is infinitelydivisible. No matter how far an object is divided, what is left would have charac-teristics of the original substance. The opposite idea that the world is made up offundamental particles appeared during 500–55 B.C. The Leucippus–Democritus

Page 355: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

350 Chapter 12

atom combined features of the Ionians’ single element, Anaxagoras’ seeds, andsome thoughts of other schools, and yet was an improvement over all of them.“Atom” means “not divisible” in Greek. This term was intentionally chosen byDemocritus to emphasize a particle so small that it could no longer be divided. ToLeucippus and Democritus, the universe originally and basically consisted entirelyof atoms and a “void” in which atoms move.

Upon consideration of the interrelationship between the systems under concernand some environments of the systems, Bunge (1979) gave a model of systems asfollows: For nonempty set T, the ordered triple W = ( C ,E, S ) is a system overT if and only if C and E are mutually disjoint subsets of T and S is a nonemptyset of relations on C∪ E; C and E are called the composition and an environmentof the system W , respectively. Klir (1985) introduced a philosophical conceptof general systems, which reads “a system is what is distinguished as a system.”Theoretically, Klir’s definition contains the most general meaning of the conceptof systems originally posed by von Bertalanffy. Starting in 1976, Xuemou Wu andhis followers have studied many different theories, under the name “pansystems.”Pansystems analysis is a new research of multilevels across all disciplines. Thetheory deals with general systems, relations, symmetry, transformation, general-ized calculus, and shengke (means survival and vanquishing), called the emphasesof pansystems. Based on research of these emphases, the theory blends philosoph-ical reasoning, mathematical logic, and mechanical structures into one solid bodyof knowledge.

The discussion here gives rise naturally to the following question: Why wasthe concept of systems not studied more before now? One answer is that the de-velopment of modern technology, e.g., computer technology, designs of satellites,climate control of giant buildings, etc., reveals one fact: History is in a specialmoment, where the accumulation of knowledge has reached such a level thateach discovery of a relation between different areas of knowledge will materiallyproduce a useful or consumable product.

Closely related to the concept of systems are the following questions: (1) Whatis the meaning of a system with two contradictory relations, e.g., { x > y, x ≤ y } asthe relation set? (2) How can we know whether there exist contradictory relationsin a given realistic system? From Klir’s definition of systems, which is one of thedefinitions with the widest meaning among all definitions of systems, it followsthat generally these two questions cannot be answered. Concerning this, a theoremof Gödel shows that it is impossible to show whether the systems representation ofmathematics, developed on the ZFC axioms is consistent. For a detailed discussionof the systems representation of mathematics, see (Lin, 1989c). This fact impliesthat there are systems, for example, the system of set theory on ZFC, so that we donot know if propositions with contradictory meanings exist or not. This means thatmaybe not every system is consistent or that not every system has no contradictoryrelations.

Page 356: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 351

By rewriting Russell’s famous paradox in the language of systems theory, thefollowing is true: There does not exist a system whose object set consists of allsystems, where S is a system, if and only if S is an ordered pair (M,R ) of sets suchthat R is a set of some relations defined on the set M (Lin, 1987). The elementsin M are called the objects of S. The sets M and R are called the object set andthe relation set of S, respectively. Now, for any given system S = (M,R ), eachrelation r ∈ R can be understood as an S -truth. That is, r is true among the objectsin S. Hence, Russell’s paradox implies that there does not exist any statement (orrelation) which describes a fact among all systems. If any structure in the worldcan be studied as a system, as Klir’s definition of systems says, does Russell’sparadox say that there is no universal truth or absolute truth? It is well known inthe mathematics community that no theorem is true in all axiom systems.

Descartes and Galileo developed individually the following methods aboutscientific research and administration: Divide the problem under considerationinto as many small parts as possible, study each isolated part (Kline, 1972), andsimplify the complicated phenomenon into basic parts and processes (Kuhn, 1962).In the history of science and technology, Descartes’ and Galileo’s methods havebeen very successfully applied. They guaranteed that physics would win greatvictories one by one (von Bertalanffy, 1972), and not only those, because theirmethods are still widely used for research of fundamental theories and in modernlaboratories. At the same time, due to the tendency of modern science towardsynthesis and the transverse development of modem technology, more and morescientists and administrators are forced to study problems with many cause–effectchains (i.e., systems). Some examples are the many-body problem in mechanics,the body structure of living things (but not the particles constituting the livingthings), etc. In the study of such problems, Descartes’ and Galileo’s methodsneed to be modified somehow, because their methods emphasize separating theproblem and phenomenon under consideration into isolated parts and processes.But according to von Bertalanffy, it should be recognized that the world we livein is not a pile of innumerable isolated “parts”; and any practical problem andphenomenon cannot be described perfectly by only one cause–effect chain. Thebasic character of the world is its organization, and the connection between theinterior and the exterior of different things. Thus, the chief task of modem scienceshould be a systematic study of the world.

12.3. Mathematical Modeling and the Origin of theUniverse

It is well known that almost all laws of nature can be studied in the languageof mathematics. Countless examples have shown that mathematics is extremelyeffective when applied to the analysis of natural systems. However, mathematics

Page 357: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

352 Chapter 12

seems to be an intellectual activity separate from the development of science andtechnology. Its postulates come from pure thought or experience. In either case,once formulated, they form a basis for which the structure of a mathematical theorycan be developed independently of their genesis.

Wigner (1960) asserted that “the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics”is a mystery whose understanding and solution have yet to come: The miracleof the appropriateness of the language of mathematics for the formulation of thelaws of physics is a wonderful gift which we neither understand nor deserve. Weshould be grateful for it and hope that it will remain valid in future research andthat it will extend, for better or for worse, for our pleasure, though perhaps also toour bafflement, to wide branches of learning.

In this section, we discuss some problems related to the structure of mathe-matics, applications of mathematics, and the origin of the universe.

By a (general) system, we mean an ordered pair S = (M,R) of sets, where R isa set of some relations defined on M. The elements in M are called objects of S andM and R are called the object set and the relation set of S, respectively. It has beenshown that each formal language can be described as a system (M,K), where M isa set containing all words in the language and K is the collection of all grammaticalrules in a fixed grammar book (Lin, 1989c); and each theory can be described asa system (M,T ∪ K ), where M and K are defined as before and T is a set ofbasic principles upon which the theory is developed (Lin, 1989c). As an example,mathematics can be described as a system (M, T ∪ K ) with T the collection of allaxioms in the ZFC axiom system (Kuratowski and Mostowski, 1976).

Now the application of mathematics is an activity of matching a subsystemof the systems representation (M , T ∪ K ) of mathematics to the situation underconsideration. For example, a hibiscus flower has five petals. The mathematicalword “five” provides a certain description of the flower. This description serves todistinguish it from flowers with three, four, six, . . ., petals.

The whole structure of mathematics might be said to be true by virtue of meredefinitions (namely, of the nonprimitive mathematical terms) if the ZFC axiomsare true. However, at this juncture, we cannot refer to ZFC axioms as propositionswhich are either true or false, for they contain free primitive terms, “set” and therelation “∈ ” of membership, which have not been assigned any specific meanings.All we can assert so far is that any specific interpretation of the primitives whichsatisfies the axioms — i.e., turns them into true statements — will also satisfy allthe theorems deduced from them. Examples can be given to show that the freeprimitive terms “set” and ∈ permit many different interpretations in everyday lifeas well as in the investigation of laws of nature and from each interpretation we un-derstand something more about nature, even though these new understandings maynot necessarily be correct. At the same time, we feel that mathematics is unreason-ably effective as applied to the study of natural problems. The following example,called the vase puzzle, will show that different mathematical understandings couldbe contradictory.

Page 358: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 353

12.3.1. Vase Puzzle

Suppose a vase and an infinite number of pieces of paper are available. Thepieces of paper are labeled with natural numbers 1,2,3, . . ., such that each piecehas exactly one label. The following recursive procedure is performed: Step 1:Put the pieces of paper, labeled from 1 through 10, into the vase, then remove thepiece labeled 1. Step n: Put the pieces of paper, labeled from 10n – 9 through 10 n,into the vase, then remove the piece labeled n. After the procedure is completed,how many pieces of paper are left in the vase?

First, define a function ƒ(n) = 9n, which tells how many pieces of paper areleft in the vase after step n, for n = 1,2,3, . . . Therefore, if the recursive procedurecan be finished, the number of pieces of paper left in the vase should be equal tothe limit of the function ƒ(n) as n → ∞. Hence, the answer is that infinitely manypieces of paper are left in the vase. Second, for each natural number n, we definethe set Mn of pieces of paper left in the vase after the n th step is finished. Afterthe recursive procedure is finished, the set of pieces of paper left in the vase equalsthe intersection That is, no piece of paper is left in the vase.

Lin, Ma, and Port (1990) pointed out theoretically that there must be animpassable chasm between pure and applied mathematics. The reason is that puremathematics is established upon a set of axioms, say ZFC. The theory possesses abeauty analogous to painting, music, and poetry, and a harmony between numbersand figures, whereas in applied mathematics each object of interest is always firstgiven some “mathematical meaning,” and then conclusions are drawn based onthe relations of these meanings to the objects involved. It is the assignment ofa mathematical meaning to each object that causes problems, because differentinterpretations can be given to the same object. As described in (Lin et al., 1990),some interpretations can result in contradictory mathematical models.

If we go back to the vase puzzle, it can be seen that the contradiction has veryfruitful implications. First, one could argue that since there is no way to finish therecursive procedure in the puzzle, the contradiction does not exist. However, if thisargument is correct, a large portion of mathematics would be incorrect, includingthe concept of limits, existence of subsequences, and Cantor’s diagonal methodin set theory, since they all require completion of a similar recursive procedure.Second, if information about a phenomenon has not all been used, the phenomenoncan either not be understand because of the lack of knowledge or be understood at amore global level and more information is needed to be more specific. However, thevase puzzle does not satisfy this general methodology of recognition. Informationabout the ordering really made understanding more controversial rather than morespecific. Third, among the most common practices of modern scientific activitiesis the science and technology of data analysis. It is known in analysis that the moredata that are collected, the more misleading conclusion could be. This is due tothe accumulation of errors. An extraordinary amount of errors can easily concealthe actual state of a phenomenon. The vase puzzle is another example showing

Page 359: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

354 Chapter 12

that the more facts we know, the more confused we become. At the same time,the vase puzzle also questions the accuracy of scientific predictions, because theignorance of a fact will lead to a completely different prediction.

Now instead of looking at the concept of mathematical modeling exclusively,let us take a more general stand. General systems theory, derived from the work ofvon Bertalanffy (1968), has greatly influenced all current approaches of systemsanalysis. Because of its promise, many people have tried to apply general systemstheory to solving practical problems (Klir, 1970). This attempt has been notablyunsuccessful; for detailed discussion on this, see (Berlinski, 1976; Lilienfeld,1978). Wood-Harper and Fitzgerald (1982) thought that the reason for this lackof success was that the very generality of the theory made it difficult to use andto develop a methodological solution. Lin (1988c) analyzed the points on whicheach application of general systems theory is based and pointed out that these arethe most probable places from which unexpected troubles arise.

A well-known fact is that the basic concepts of general systems theory wereintroduced in the language of set theory. Therefore, in applications, an elementaryquestion is, What is a set? For example, is the collection of all living organisms ina certain experimental “container” a set? This problem seems to be simple, sincein applications no one ever doubts the reasonableness of the statement that thecollection of living organisms is a set. It is also a fundamental problem, becausein each application of general systems theory, determining if a collection of someobjects is a set is always the first problem we encounter before we can draw anyuseful conclusions based on theoretical results. The second question is, What doesthe formula x ∈ y mean? Here ∈ is a primitive notation, so in applications ofgeneral systems theory ∈ can be defined in different ways. This is apparently asource of confusion in applications of the theory. The third question is, what doesthe statement “x is a set” mean? It is well known that some collections of objectsare not sets. This is another source of confusion in applications of general systemstheory.

By using axioms in the ZFC system, we can see that if A is a collection ofobjects and there exists a one-to-one correspondence h : A → X for some set X,then A is a set. It is natural to consider the following: How can we establish aone-to-one correspondence between a set and a collection of objects that we arestudying? For example, we are studying the collection of all products of a certainkind, which are continuously coming out of several assembly lines. The difficultyis that the collection of interest is not fixed and is dependent on time. Surely, thecollection cannot be assumed to be finite; however, it cannot be assumed to beinfinite either. Otherwise, we would run into the same situation as described in thevase puzzle.

It is a known fact that human eyes can offer the brain wrong information.Another problem we have to face before any mathematical modeling is establishedis, How do we know anything? Descartes had pondered this question for a longtime; for details see (Kline, 1972, p. 305). After comparing several definitions of

Page 360: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 355

systems, Lin (1989d) proposed the following axiom: The existence of any realmatter is known by the existence of all particles in some level of the matter andby some relations between the particles in the matter and some particles in anenvironment of the matter.

As mentioned by Kunen (1980), a collection of cows cannot be considered aset. When can a collection of objects in an application be studied as a set so that theresults in set theory and general systems theory can be used to make inferences?Can we introduce a procedure to check when a given collection of real matter is a“set”? Studying this question will lead to the creation of “applied set theory.”

Since a system is what is distinguished as a system, according to Klir (1985),another difficulty we have to face to apply general systems theory is how to writea realistic relation, such as a human relation, as one or several relations in settheory, based upon the language of formal logic. After several systems modelshave been established, do we have a procedure to select additional models so thatthey produce the most desirable and most reasonable conclusions on the materialsystem of interest?

When faced with practical problems, new abstract mathematical theories aredeveloped to investigate them. At the same time, predictions based on the newlydeveloped theories are so “accurate” that the following question appears naturally:Does the human way of thinking have the same structure as that of the materialworld?

As shown in (Lin, 1990d), mathematics can be built upon the “empty set, Ø.”History gradually shows that almost all natural phenomena can be described andstudied with mathematics. We thus ask: If all laws of nature could be written inthe language of mathematics, could we conclude that the universe we live in restson the empty set Ø, even as Genesis states that “in the beginning, God created theheaven and the earth. And the earth was without form, and void?”

In applications of general systems theory and mathematics, it has never beenchecked whether the collection of objects and the membership relation betweenthe objects satisfy all the ZFC axioms. Only when ∈ makes all ZFC axioms truepropositions can general systems theory and mathematics be applied to a situation.Therefore, it is necessary to develop a method to check whether a collection ofobjects and a membership relation defined on the collection satisfy the ZFC axiomsystem.

Another interesting and important question, related to the concept of systemsmodeling and systems identification, is: How can we bring in the idea of “noise”?For instance, current achievements in modern quantum mechanics strongly supportthe fact that the laws of nature, if any, are written in terms of probability. Also,as pointed out by Masani (1994), each study of human relations is subject to thecorrection of the human noise. In some sense, human noises are different fromthose observed in any other systems containing no human beings.

Page 361: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

356 Chapter 12

12.4. Laws of Conservation and the Multilevel Structureof Nature

As shown in Section 12.1, the concept of systems characterizes the organi-zational structure of the world, including the structure of layers. One inference,based on the structure of layers, that can be made from the concept of systems isthat the world is finitely divisible. Hence, a system S n = (Mn , R n ) is an n th-levelobject system of a system S 0 = (M0 , R 0 ) if there exist systems S i = (Mi, Ri), fori = 1, 2, … , n – 1, such that S i ∈ Mi –1, for i = 1, 2, … , n, where n is a naturalnumber (Lin and Ma, 1987). Under the assumption that the ZFC axiom system isconsistent, the following has been shown: For any system S each chain of objectsystems of S must be finite, where a sequence of systems, with n an ordinalnumber, is a chain of object systems of S if S 0 is an i 0 th-level object system ofS, and for any i,j ∈ n, if i < j , there then is a natural number n(i,j) such that thesystem S j is an n (i,j)th-level object system of Si . An object x is an n th-level ob-ject of a system S 0 = (M0 , R 0 ), where n is a positive integer, if there exist systemsS i = (Mi,Ri ), i = 1,2,… , n , such that S i ∈ M i –1 , for i = 1, 2, … , n , and x ∈ M n .If the object x is no longer a system, then it is called a fundamental object of S0 .The previous result then says that each system must be finitely divisible.

Based on this discussion, it can be shown that for any system S = (M, R )there exists a unique set M(S ) consisting of all fundamental objects in S. The setM(S) is constructed as follows: For each object x ∈ M (S), there exists a chainof object systems for some natural number n = n(x), such that S 0 ∈ M ,Si ∈ M i–1, i ∈ n , and x ∈ M n . Intuitively speaking, this result says that each systemis built on fundamental objects. Does this result imply that the world is made upof fundamental particles, where a fundamental particle is a particle which cannotbe divided into smaller particles? We know that the world consists of atoms. Afixed atom A can be thought of as a system S consisting of the set of all electronsand the nucleus in A and a set of some relations between the electrons and thenucleus. The collection of all electrons and the nucleus in A is a set because of thefiniteness of the collection. Generally, if a particle X can be divided into smallerparticles, it can be considered as an ordered pair (M, R), where M is the totality ofthe smaller particles in X, and R is a set of some relations between the particles inM. Therefore, if M is a set, X can be described as a system. Hence, the previousresult implies that if M is a set, then X consists of fundamental particles. The lastconclusion is subject to three possibilities:

(i) The world is made up of fundamental particles.

(ii) There exists a particle X such that X can be divided into smaller particlesand the collection of all smaller particles in X is not a set.

(iii) The ZFC axiom system is not consistent.

Page 362: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 357

Man has spent hundreds of years on the first possibility. When molecules werefirst found, they were thought to be the fundamental bricks of the natural world.Before long, smaller structures were found (i.e., atoms). At this time, peoplereally believed that the smallest bricks of the world were found. But, once again,scientific achievement disproved that. Hence, people gradually began to believethat there did not exist any fundamental particles in the world at all. Here it isshown that each system is made up of fundamental objects. Can we concludethat the world is made up of fundamental particles? This depends on whether thesecond or third possibilities and the following reason are true:

There are some covert mistakes in the application of the result of systemstheory.

Because all classical mathematics, which has been the “unreasonably” effectivepart of mathematics when applied to analyze practical problems, and consequently,all modern science and technology can be developed on ZFC (Kunen, 1980), wecan be convinced that the ZFC axiom system is consistent. (Notice that there is noway to prove this yet!): Now the reasons are: (1) There are some mistakes in theapplication of systems theory. (2) There is a particle X such that X can be dividedinto smaller particles and the collection of all smaller particles in X is not a set.

On the other hand, if the foregoing discussion is correct and if the world ismade up of fundamental particles, then each fundamental particle must be so smallthat it has no size. Otherwise, it can still be cut into smaller pieces. Thus, underthe assumption that the world consists of fundamental particles, what the meaningof particles is becomes an important problem, because each fundamental particlecannot have a size.

As introduced by Klir (1985), a system is what is distinguished as a system.We can do the following systems modeling: For each chosen matter, real situationproblem, or environment, such as a chemical reaction process, a system describingthe matter of interest can always be defined. For example, let S = (M, R ) be asystems representation of a chemical reaction process, such that M stands for theset of all substances used in the reaction and R is the set of all relations betweensubstances in M. It can be seen that S represents the chemical reaction of interest.Changes of the system represents changes of the objects in M and changes ofrelations in R. Based on this understanding and the result of systems theory thateach chain of object systems of a given system must be finite, the following axiom,due to Lavoisier given in 1789, has been proven theoretically: In all the operationsof art and nature, nothing is created! An equal quantity of matter exists bothbefore and after the experiment … and nothing takes place beyond changes andmodifications in the combination of the elements. Upon this principle, the wholeart of performing chemical experiments depends.

Based on this understanding, the conservation principle of ancient atomists,(Perlman, 1970, p. 414), which states that the total count of atoms in the universeis constant, so the total amount of matter remains the same regardless of changes,can be recast as follows:

Page 363: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

358 Chapter 12

12.4.1. Law of Conservation of Fundamental Particles(Lin, submitted)

The total count of fundamental particles in the universe is constant; therefore,the total amount of matter remains the same regardless of changes and modifica-tions.

Let us discuss some impacts of what has been done on the Law of Conservationof Matter–Energy. The law states that the total amount of matter and energy isalways the same. Historically, this law was developed based on the new devel-opment of science and technology: energy and matter are two different forms ofthe same thing. That is, matter can be transferred into energy, and energy intomatter. All matter consists of fundamental particles, as already discussed and sodoes energy. Since energy can be in different forms, such as light, it confirmsthat each fundamental particle has no volume or size. Now, as a consequence ofthe Law of Conservation of Fundamental Particles, the Law of Conservation ofMatter–Energy becomes clear and obvious.

One of the many important open problems is to develop conservation equationsin terms of fundamental particles and to write them in modern symbolic form. Onlywith the indispensable “=” in the equations can the theory, developed on the Lawof Conservation of Fundamental Particles, become an “exact science” with thecapacity of prediction.

12.5. Set-Theoretic General Systems Theory

This section focuses on general systems theory developed on ZFC set theory.As mentioned in Section 12.2, this general theory will establish a theoreticalfoundation for all approaches of systems analysis developed in various disciplines.

Let S be a (general) system if S equals an ordered pair (M , R ) of sets such thatR is a set of some relations defined on the set M (Lin, 1987). The elements inM are called the objects of S and M and R are the object set and the relation setof S , respectively. As pointed out by Mesarovic and Takahara (1989), an objectin M is recognized as a building block, a component of the system; it can bereal matter or a conceptual entity. Since the existence of an object is recognizedthrough its attributes or characteristics, a more appropriate definition for generalsystems should be an ordered pair of a set of attributes of some objects and a setof relations among the attributes of the objects. However, if one just simply usesthe attributes here as the objects, then the definition of general systems would bereasonable.

For a relation r ∈ R, where S = (M, R ) is a system, there exists an ordinalnumber n = n(r) such that r ⊆ M n . The number n is called the length of r . It isassumed that the length of the empty relation is zero; that is, n = 0.

Page 364: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 359

One goal of systems theory, based on this definition, is to possess the samebeauty as mathematics possesses. Beauty ensures that the theory will be handeddown from generation to generation, since only beauty can make the theory as-similated into our daily thoughts process and brought again and again before themind with ever-renewed encouragement. To achieve this goal, the general struc-ture of a system, mappings from systems into systems, constructions of systems,hierarchies of systems, etc., need to be studied systematically. Along this line areseveral open problems.

It can be shown that for any system S = (M ,R ), where for any r ∈ R , n(r) = 2,S is a subset of the set p ²(M)∪ p(p(M ) ∪ p4(M)), where p ¹(X) = p (X) is thepower set of X and pi +1(X ) = p(pi (X)) for each i = 1,2,3,…. Is it possible that astructural representation for general systems can be given similar to the one givenearlier? The characteristic of this representation is that only ordinal numbers andpower set operations are involved.

A system S = (M ,R) is called centralized system if each object in S is asystem and there exists a system C = (M C , R C ) satisfying M C ≠ such that forany distinct elements x,y ∈ M , say x = (Mx ,R x) and y = (My ,Ry ), MC = M x ∩ My

and where and

The system C is called a center of S . If in, in addition,S is called strongly centralized. For centralized systems, it

has been shown that under the assumption that ZFC axiom system is consistent, forκ an infinite cardinality and θ > κ a regular cardinality such that, for any α < θ,

then for each system S = (M ,R) where |M| ≥ θ and |Mm | < κ , for each objectm ∈ M a system with m = (Mm , R m ), and where there exists an object containedin at least θ objects in M , there exists a partial system S' = (M',R') of S s u c hthat S' forms a centralized system and |M' | ≥ θ. This result is a restatement ofthe general ∆ -lemma in set theory (Kunen, 1980). Since this result has foundseveral interesting applications in sociology and epidemiology (Lin, 1988a; Linand Vierthaler, 1998; Lin and Forrest, 1995), it is worth asking: the question below:Under what conditions is the partial system S' a strongly centralized system?

It can be seen that the concept of systems is a higher-level abstraction of math-ematical structures. For example, n-tuple relations, networks, abstract automaticmachines, algebraic systems, topological spaces, vector spaces, algebras, fuzzysets and fuzzy relations, manifolds, metric spaces, normed spaces, Frechet spaces,Banach spaces, Banach algebras, normed rings, Hilbert spaces, semigroups, Rieszspaces, semiordered spaces, and systems of axioms and formal languages are allsystems. From these examples it is natural to consider the problem: Find proper-ties of networks, automatic machines, topological spaces, vector spaces, algebras,fuzzy structures, systems of axioms, etc., such that in general systems theory theyhave the same appearance.

Page 365: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

360 Chapter 12

Let S i = (Mi,Ri ), i = 1,2, be two systems and h : M 1 → M 2 a mapping. Bytransfinite induction, two classes i = 1,2, and a class mappingcan be defined with the following properties:

and for each x = (x0 ,x1 , … ,xα ,…)

where ON stands for the class of all ordinal numbers. For each relation r ∈ R ,is a relation on the set M 2 with length n(r). Without causing

confusion, h will also be used to indicate the class mapping and h is a mappingfrom S 1 into S 2 , denoted by h : S 1→ S 2 .

A mapping h : S 1 = (M1 , R1) → S 2 = (M2, R2) is S-continuous (Ma and Lin,1990e) if for any relation r ∈ R2 ,

It then can be shown that if the systems Si , i = 1,2, are topological spaces, h isS-continuous iff h is a continuous mapping from the topological space S 1 into thetopological space S2 , and that if the systems S i , i = 1,2, are rings in algebra, theS-continuity of h implies that h is a homomorphism from the ring S1 into the ringS2. This example shows the need to find the topological properties of topologicalspaces and algebraic properties of algebras, such as groups, rings, etc., such thatin systems analysis they have the same appearance.

A mapping ƒ : S 1 → S 2 is a morphism from a system S 1 into a system S2

if ƒ (R1 ) ⊆ R . Let Hom(S 1, S 2 ) = {ƒ : S 1 → S 2 : ƒ is a morphism}. Suppose{S i : i ∈ I} is a set of systems. A system S = (M ,R ) is a product (resp., Cartesianproduct) of S i , if there is a family of morphisms (resp., S-continuous mappings){Φ i ∈ Hom(S ,S i) : i ∈ I} (resp., {p i : S → S i : i ∈ I }) such that for each systemS' and a family {Ψ i ∈ Hom(S',S i ) : i ∈ I ) (resp., {qi : S' → S i : i ∈ I} of S -continuous mappings) there is a unique morphism (resp., S-continuous mapping)λ ∈ Hom(S',S) (resp., λ : S' → S ) so that

for each i ∈ I

It can be shown that for each set {S i : i ∈ I} of systems, a product and a Cartesianproduct of Si always exist, which are unique up to a similarity and denoted by

and respectively. The reason why the systemis called the Cartesian product of S i is that when S i are topological spaces, thissystem is the Cartesian product of the spaces S i . In this case, the system isthe box product of the spaces S i . When the systems S i are algebras, such as groups,

Page 366: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 361

rings, etc., the system ∏ i ∈ I Si is the direct sum of the algebras Si . That is, the boxproduct in topology and the direct sum in algebra have the same structure. Thisfact gives rise to the following problem: Find topological structures and algebraicstructures such that in systems analysis they appear to be the same. Conversely, itis natural to ask: When can a system be studied as a topological space or a specificalgebra?

Let (T,≤ ) be a partially ordered set with order type α. An α -type hierarchy Sof systems [over the partially ordered set (T, ≤ )] is a function defined on T suchthat for each t ∈ T, S(t) = St = ( Mt , Rt ) is a system (Lin, 1989a). For an α- t y p ehierarchy S of systems, let l : St r r → St be a mapping from the system Sr into thesystem St , for any r, t ∈ T with r ≥ t, such that

and

where r, s, t are arbitrary elements in T satisfying s ≥ r ≥ t and idSt = idMt is theidentity mapping on the set Mt . The family { l ts : t, s ∈ T,s ≥ t } is termed a familyof linkage mappings of the α-type hierarchy S, and each lt s is termed a linkagemapping from the system Ss into the system St .

It has been shown (Lin, 1989a) that for each α -type hierarchy S of systemssatisfying that for each t ∈ T, Mt ≠ Ø where S t = (Mt ,Rt ), there exists a family{lt s : t,s ∈ T,s ≥ t} of linkage mappings of S. An interesting question is, howmany families of linkage mappings are there for a given α -type hierarchy ofsystems? Or, how many families of linkage mappings with certain properties,such as S-continuous, are there for a given α -type hierarchy of systems? Anotherquestion, which is similar to the question of expanding a given function, is thefollowing: Suppose S is an α-type hierarchy of systems over a partially ordered set(T, ≤) and { lt s : t,s ∈ T * , s ≥ t} is a family of linkage mappings of the hierarchyof systems {St : t ∈ T * }, where T * ⊂ T. Under what conditions does there exist afamily { ts : t,s ∈ T, s ≥ t} of linkage mappings for S such that ts = lt s for all s,t ∈ T * with s ≥ t?

As shown by Omran (197l), there is strong evidence for the existence of theepidemiological transition, which describes the transition of health and diseasepatterns, namely that infectious diseases are gradually replaced by noncommu-nicable diseases as the economic and industrial development of a region takesplace. Its main characteristic is that the transition history of the health and diseasepatterns of industrialized nations have been repeated, or are yet to be repeated,in developing regions or nations. To model this important concept, Lin and Lin(1995) employed the concepts of systems over groups and of periodic systemsover groups. To be specific, suppose (T, +, ≤ ) is an ordered Abelian group. Ahierarchy S of systems over (T, +, ≤ ) is called a system over a group. If, in ad-dition, the hierarchy is linked, the system is termed a linked system over a group.For a fixed t0 ∈ T, the right transformation of S, denoted S – t0, is defined to beS – t0(t ) = S (t – t 0 ) for each t ∈ T; and the left transformation of S, denoted S + t0,

Page 367: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

362 Chapter 12

and

is defined by S +t 0 (t ) = S (t + t0) for each t ∈ T. A system S over a group T isperiodic if there exists p ∈ T such that p ≠ 0 and S + p = S. The element p is calleda period of S. As pointed out in (Lin and Forrest, 1995), there is a need to studymultiperiodic systems where a system S over a group T is multiperiodic if thereexists a subset D ⊆ T such that S+P = S for each p ∈ D.

Feedback has been a hot topic in recent years since all living, and many non-living systems are feedback systems. How to study these systems is an importantquestion. The concepts of feedback transformation and feedback decoupling havebrought some light because they tell when the system under consideration canbe divided into smaller systems. For recent research, consult Takahara and Asahi(1985), and Saito (1986; 1987). Let us take a brief look at the concepts of feedbacktransformation and feedback decoupling and several related open questions.

Let be a field, X and Y linear spaces over the field , and S an (input–output) system satisfying the following conditions: (i) Ø ≠ S ⊆ X × Y ; (ii) s ∈ Sand s' ∈ S imply that s + s' ∈ S ; (iii) s ∈ S and α ∈ imply α · s ∈ S, where +and · are addition and scalar multiplication in X × Y, respectively, defined by: forany (x1 ,y 1), (x2 ,y2 ) ∈ X × Y and any α ∈ (x1 ,y1) + (x , y2 2 ) = (x 1 + x2, y1 + y2)and α · ( x1 ,y 1 ) = (αx1 , αy 1 ). Then S is called an (input–output) linear system(Mesarovic and Takahara, 1975). An input–output system S ⊂ X × Y is a functionalsystem if S is a function from the input set X into the output set Y. Let S ⊂ X × Yand S ƒ : Y → X be a linear system and a linear functional system, respectively.Then the feedback system of S by Sƒ is defined as the input–output system S' suchthat

The systems S and Sƒ are called an original system and a feedback componentsystem, respectively. For details, see (Saito and Mesarovic, 1985).

Let = {S ⊂ X × Y : S is a linear system}, ƒ = {Sƒ : Y → X : S ƒ is a linearfunctional system}; and = { S' ⊂ X × Y : S' is a subset}. Then a feedbacktransformation is defined by the last equivalence relation for each

The transformation F is called the feedback transformation overthe linear spaces X and Y.

Assume that the input space X and the output space Y can be writtenand For each i ∈ I, the projection pi = (pix ,piy ) : X × Y →

Xi × Yi is defined by pix : X → X i and piy : Y → Y i satisfying pix (x ) = x i andp iy (y ) = yi , for any x ∈ X and y ∈ Y. Let Si = p i ( S ) for i ∈ I. Then the system S isdecomposed into a family of factor systems Ifis identified with then A linearsystem S ∈ is decoupled by feedback (Saito and Mesarovic, 1985) if there isSƒ ∈ ƒ such that

Page 368: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 363

Under the assumption that ZFC is consistent, it has been shown (Lin, 1994)that if S ∈ is decomposed into a family of factor systems then S isdecoupled by feedback iff andwhere andBased on this result, (Lin, 1994) gives a concrete procedure to decouple the linearsystem

= Az + Bx

y = Cz + Dx

z(0) = 0

where z is an m × 1 variable vector, called the state of the system, A, B, C, and Dare constant matrices of size m × m, m × n, n × m, and n × n, respectively, suchthat D is nonsingular, and the input space X and the output space Y are

X = Y = { r : [0, ∞ ) → : r is piecewise continuous}

where is the set of all real numbers. The family of factor systems consists of none-dimensional linear systems of the following form:

= Az + B xi i

yi = Ciz + Di xi

z (0) = 0

for i = 1,2, … , n, where B = [B1 B2 … Bn], C = [C1 C2 … Cn ]T, D i is a nonzeroconstant, and the input space Xi and the output space Yi are given by Xi = Yi ={r : [0, ∞ ) → : r is piecewise continuous}.

Many questions are left open. For example, do the input space X and the outputspace Y have to be the same dimension in order to apply the theory? Find examplesof systems such that some of their important properties are not kept by feedbacksystems. If some properties of the original system are not kept by feedbacksystems, can the properties be studied by using the concept of pullback? For theconcept of pullback, see (Negoita, 1992). Is it possible to construct the solutionof the n-dimensional linear system described earlier, based on the solutions of theone-dimensional factor systems?

12.6. Analytic Foundation for an Applicable GeneralSystems Theory

During a recent and fruitful conversation with Professor Pesi Masani, hepointed out a fact, which could also be considered a challenge to systems sci-ence, that to show the need for the concept of (general) systems it is absolutely

Page 369: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

364 Chapter 12

necessary to obtain some results which have not or could not be achieved withoutusing the concept of systems. To meet this challenge and to make up a deficiencyof the current theory of general systems analysis, where no quantitative studybased on general systems analysis can be carried out, it will be shown that the non-Archimedean number field, first introduced by Shu-tang Wang in the late 1970sand early 1980s, is an excellent starting point.

Historically speaking, nonstandard analysis, established in the early 1960s byRobinson (1977), introduced the concepts of infinitesimals and infinities formallyand legally, based on mathematical logic. This theory broke through the limitationof classical concept of real numbers, where infinities are considered ideal objects.With nonstandard analysis, many classical theories, such as mathematical analysis,algebra, normed spaces, some classical mechanics problems, etc., can be greatlysimplified and become more intuitive. However, the shortfall of Robinson’s non-standard analysis is that infinitesimals and infinities can only be shown to existand have no concrete expressions of any tangible form. Based on the argumentof the existence of infinitesimals and infinities given in Robinson’s theory, thenon-Archimedean number field, called the generalized number system (GNS) byWang (1985), has a computational advantage, since each number, whether ordi-nary real number, infinitesimal, or infinity, has an exact expression in terms of thereal numbers in the classical sense.

A generalized number x is a function from into where is the set ofall integers and the set of all real numbers, such that there exists a numberk = k (x) ∈ called the level index of x, satisfying x (t) = 0, for t < k, a n dx ( k (x)) ≠ 0. Let GNS stand for the field consisting of all generalized numbersand the zero function 0 : with the following operations: (1) Addition andsubtraction: for any x, y ∈ GNS, (x ± y )( t) = x( t ) ± y ( t ), for t ∈ (2) Ordering:for any x, y ∈ GNS, x < y iff there is a k0 ∈ I such that x ( t ) = y (t ), if t < k 0 ,and x(k0 ) < y (k0 ); (3) Scalar multiplication: let c ∈ and x ∈ GNS, and define( c x)(t ) = c x(t ) for t ∈ (4) Multiplication: for x ∈ GNS, write x as a generalizedpower series

where 1(t) ∈ GNS is defined by 1(t ) (s ) = 0, if s ≠ t, and 1 (t) ( t ) = 1. Let x, y ∈ GNS.The product x × y or xy is defined by

(5) Division: For x, y ∈ GNS, if there exists a z ∈ GNS such that y × z = x, thenthe generalized number z is called the quotient of x divided by y, denoted by x ÷ yor x /y.

Throughout history, “laws” of nature have been frequently expressed andtreated with the rigor and beauty of mathematical symbols. For the most part,

Page 370: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 365

this kind of application of mathematics has been very successful. However, inthe past 40 years, theoretical physicists have often been faced with difficultiesin mathematical calculation. According to Wang (1991), such difficulties arisemainly because the modern world of physics is multilevel in its character, whileapplicable mathematics still remains single level where the only infinities aredenoted by – ∞ or +∞, and are considered in our macroscopic world as idealobjects and are treated with a different set of rules, compared with those of ordinaryreal numbers. Now, in GNS the field of all real numbers is isomorphic to (0) ={x ∈ GNS : x (t) = 0 if t ≠ 0}, which represents the quantities measurable withinthe macroscopic world. Furthermore, all numbers in GNS, whether infinities orinfinitesimals, are treated with the same set of rules.

To give the reader a taste of how GNS can be applied to the study of physics,we look at the calculation of the rest mass of a photon. According to Einstein, theinertial mass m of a moving particle relates to its rest mass m0 as follows:

(12.1)

where c stands for the speed of light and v is the particle speed. Since thephoton’s speed is v = c, the rest mass m0 should be m 0 = 0. Otherwise, onewould obtain from Eq. (12.1) that m = ∞ , contradicting observations. However,even it is assumed that m0 = 0, injustice involved in the calculation still remains.This is because in classical mathematics on the real number line, m = 0 ÷ 0 isundetermined.

This difficulty can be overcome by using generalized numbers. Suppose therest mass m0 of a photon is

and that the inertial mass m in Eq. (12.1) is a finite real number; that is, m ∈ (0)

has a representation

Now the velocity of a photon is

where v2 < 0, since c is assumed by Einstein to be the maximum speed in theuniverse. So Eq. (12.1) can be written

Page 371: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

366 Chapter 12

where c is understood in the same way as we did with m ∈ (0). By substituting theGNS values of m , m0 , 1 (0) , v , and c into this equation and comparing the leadingnonzero terms, one obtains (–2c)m2 v2 = m 2

1 . That gives the relation between v2

and m1 . For technical details, see (Lin and Wang, 1998).Comparing the generalized number system with those contained in mathemati-

cal analysis, real, and complex analysis, we see that our understanding of the GNSis still superficial. More work needs to be carried out to gain deeper understandingabout nature and the world in which we live.

For instance, it is necessary to

(1)

(2)

(3)

(4)

(5)

(6)

(7)

(8)

(9)

(10)

(11)

Study the ordering relation. It is obvious that the GNS field is not completein the sense of Dedekind cuts.

Explore applications of the theory of GNS in other branches of humanknowledge. The future success of the theory of GNS may well depend onvarious successful applications.

Develop workable and concrete formulas for the operations ofmultiplication, division, and taking roots.

Redevelop quantum mechanics based on GNS so that, hopefully, morepuzzles in the current quantum mechanics can be explained more rationally.

Establish a law, similar to the transfer law in nonstandard analysis(Davis, 1977), governing the relation between a set of properties of realnumbers and a set of properties of generalized numbers.

Develop the results of generalized numbers, corresponding to theorems inmathematical analysis, such as the intermediate value theorem, maximumand minimum theorem, etc.

Find detailed formulas to compute various derivatives, definite andindefinite integrals of given functions from GNS into GNS.

Generalize the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus to the case of GNS,linking GNS differential calculus to GNS integral calculus.

Develop an integral calculus of GNS based on the same mechanism ofLebesgue integrals.

Use GNS representations of Schwartz’s distributions to explore newexplanations of equations, appearing in the theory of distributions, whichdo not make sense in classical mathematical analysis.

Employ GNS representations of Schwartz’s distributions to solve openproblems in the theory of distributions, such as defining products ofdistributions. Can the theory of GNS be used to explain why in general theproducts of distributions might not exist?

Page 372: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 367

12.7. A Few Final Words

To face challenges, the study of general systems theory must further the re-search of the concept of (general) systems and related topics so that the theorypossesses more systems, more large-scale combination, more pragmatism, moreaccuracy, and more unification (blending philosophy, mathematics, physical sci-ence, technology, etc., into one body of knowledge).

Based on the history of general systems theory and its current development,among the keys for its future success are publicity and practicalities. Only withthese two tasks being accomplished, will the scientific community be truly movedso that research of general systems theory and applications moves to a higher level.

Man is both a reflection reduced with the size of history and an enlarged imageof history. He is the creature of interactions between himself and the physicalworld. Research and application of general systems theory are a natural extensionof his intelligent and comprehensive pursuits for the past several thousand years.They are also creatures of interactions between them and the physical world andreduced reflections and enlarged images of the history of the world of learning.Any one with a prepared mind can achieve a great deal in the development andapplication of such a theory.

The general systems enterprise has been, and will continue to be, developingand self-completing. In the scientific garden with various theories which willstand the test of time and history, general systems theory has been set off from thegrayer background, self-realizing, self-coquetting, self-dedicating, self-rebelingand self-surpassing. Even though the general systems enterprise has not been, andwill not be, pursuing eternity, it will definitely become a powerful force sweepingthrough the world of learning.

Page 373: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

References

Ackoff, R. L. (1959). Games, decisions and organizations. General Systems, 4 , 145–150.

Baldwin, J., and B. Pilsworth (1982). Dynamic programming for fuzzy systems with fuzzy environment.J. Math. Anal. Appl., 85, 1–23.

Bayliss, L. E. (1966). Living Control Systems. San Francisco.

Bellman, R. (1957). Dynamic Programming. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

Bellman, R., and L. A. Zadeh (1970). Decision making in fuzzy environment. Management Sci., 17, B141–B 164.

Berlinski, D. (1976). On Systems Analysis. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

von Bertalanffy, L. (1924). Einführung in Spengler’s Werk. Literaturblatt Kolnische Zeitung, May.

— (1934). Modern Theories of Development (Transl. J. H. Woodge) Oxford University Press, Oxford;Harper Torch Books, New York (1962); German Original: Kritische Theories der Formbildung,Borntäger, Berlin (1928).

— (1967). General systems theory: Application to psychology, social science. Inform. Sci. Soc., 6 ,125–136.

— (1968). General Systems Theory. George Braziller, New York.

— (1972). The history and status of general systems theory. In: G. Klir (ed.), Trends in GeneralSystems Theory. New York, pp. 21–41.

Billstein, R., S. Libeskind, and J. W. Lott (1990). A Problem Solving Approach to Mathematics forElementary School Teachers. 4th ed., Benjamin/Cummings, Redwood City, CA.

Blauberg, I. V., V. N. Sadovsky, and E. G. Yudin (1977). Systems Theory, Philosophical and Method-ological Problems. Progress Publishers, Moscow.

Box, G., W. Hunter, and J. S. Hunter (1978). Statistics for Experimenters: An Introduction to Design,Data Analysis, and Model Building. Wiley, New York.

Brown, T. A., and R. E. Strauch (1965). Dynamic programming in multiplicative lattices. J. Math.

Holland.

Anal. Appl., 12, 624–637.

Bunge, B. (1979). Treatise on Basic Philosophy. Vol. 4 : A World of Systems. Reidel, Dordrecht,

369

Page 374: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

References370

Cartan, H. (1980). Nicolas Bourbaki and contemporary mathematics. Math. Intell., 2 , 175–180.

Casti, J. (1985). Non-Linear Systems Theory. Academic Press, Orlando.

Checkland, P. B. (1975). The development of systems thinking by systems practice—A methodologyfrom action research programme. In: R. Trappl and F. de P. Hawika (eds.), Progress inCybernetics and System Research, Vol. II. Hemisphere, Washington, DC, pp. 278–283.

Cohen, J., and I. Stewart (1994). The Collapse of Chaos. Viking Press, New York.

Colmez, J. (1947). Espaces a escart generalise regulier. C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris, 244, 372–373.

Comacchio, J. V. (1972). Topological concepts in the mathematical theory of general systems. In: G.Klir (ed.), Trends in General Systems Theory. Wiley-Interscience, New York.

Davis, M. (1977). Applied Non-Standard Analysis. Wiley, New York.

Denardo, E. V. ( 1967). Contraction Mappings in the Theory Underlying Dynamic Programming. SIAMRev., No. 9, 1121–1129.

Deng, J.-L. (1985). Grey Control Systems. Hua-zhong Institute of Technology Press, Wuhan.

Department of Business Administration of Wuhan University (1983). Fundamentals of Modern Ad-ministration. Knowledge Press, Wuhan.

Department of Mathematics, Ji-Lin University (1978). Mathematical Analysis (in Chinese). People’sEducation Press.

Dieudonne, J. (1982). A Panorama of Pure Mathematics: As Seen by N. Bourbaki. Academic Press,New York.

Dirac, P. A. (1958). The Principles of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford University Press, London.

Doss, R. (1947). Sur les espaces ou la topologie peut etre definis a l’ aid d’unecart abstrait symmetriqueet regulier. C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris, 223 , 1087–1088.

Drake, F. R. (1974). Set Theory: An Introduction to Cardinals. North-Holland, Amsterdam.

Dreyfus, S., and A. Law (1977). The Art and Theory of Dynamic Programming. Academic Press, NewYork.

Einstein, A. (1922). The World as I See It. Covici, Friede, New York.

Ellis, H. C. (1978). Analyzing business information needs. In: R. N. Maddison (ed.), Data Analysisfor Information Systems Design. BCS Conference Papers, British Computer Society, London.

Engelking, R. (1975). General Topology. Polish Scientific Publishers, Warszawa.

Fraenkel,, A. A., Y. Bar-Hillel, and A. Levy (1973). Foundations of Set Theory. North-Holland,Amsterdam.

Frechet, M. (1945). La notion d’uniformite et les ecart abstrait. C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris, 221 , 337–339.

— (1946). De l’ecart numerique alecart abstrait. Portugese Math., 5 , 121–131.

N. Furukawa ( 1980). Characterization of optimal policies in vector-valued Markovian decision process.Math. Oper. Res., 5 , 271–279.

Page 375: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

References 371

Gane, C., and T. Sarsons (1979). Structured Analysis: Tools and Techniques. Prentice-Hall, EnglewoodCliffs, NJ.

Gleick, J. (1987). Chaos: Making a New Science. Viking Press, New York.

Goldberg, D. (1989). Genetic Algorithms in Search, Optimization and Machine Learning. Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA.

Graniner, J. V. (1988). Math. Mag., 61, 220–230.

Gratzer, G. (1978). Universal Algebra. Springer-Verlag, New York.

Hahn, E. (1967). Aktuelle entwicklungstendenzen der soziologischen theorie. Deutsche Z. Phil., 15,178–191.

Hall, A. D., and R. E. Fagen (1956). Definitions of systems. General Systems, 1, 18–28.

Halmos, P. R. (1957). Nicolas Bourbaki. Scientific American, May, 88–99.

— (1960). Naive Set Theory. Van Nostrand, Princeton, NJ

M. I. Henig (1983). Vector-Valued Dynamic Programming. SIAM J. Control Optim., No. 3, 237–245.

Hess, B. (1969). Modelle Enzymatischer Prozesse. Nova Acta Leopoldina (Halle, Germany).

Hodel, R. E. (1975). Extensions of metrization theorems to higher cardinality. Fund. Math., 87, 219–229.

Holland, J. (1975). Adaptation in Natural and Artificial Systems. University of Michigan Press.

Hu, T. C. (1982). Combinatorial Algorithms. Addison-Wesley, New York.

Husek, M., and H. C. Reichel (1983). Topological characterizations of linearly uniformizable spaces.Topology Appl., 15, 173–188.

Jech, T. J. (1973). The Axiom of choice. American Elsevier, New York; North-Holland, Amsterdam.

— (1978). Set Theory. Academic Press, New York.

I. Juhasz (1965). Untersuchungen über ωµ -metrisierbare raume. Ann. Univ. Sci. Sec. Mat., Budapest,8, 129–145.

Kleene, S. C. (1952). Introduction to Meta-Mathematics. North-Holland, Amsterdam.

Kline, M. (1972). Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times. Oxford University Press,Oxford.

Klir, G. (1970). An Approach to General Systems Theory. Van Nostrand, Princeton, NJ.

— (1985). Architecture of Systems Problem Solving. Plenum Press, New York.

J. Kreisel and J. L. Krivine (1967). Elements of Mathematical Logic. North-Holland, Amsterdam.

Krippendorff, K. (1980). Content Analysis: An Introduction to Its Methodology. Sage Publications,Beverly Hills, CA.

Kuhn, T. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

Page 376: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

372 References

Kunen, K. (1980). Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs. North-Holland, Amsterdam.

Kuratowski, K. (1980). A Half Century of Polish Mathematics: Remembrances and Reflections.Pergamon, Oxford.

Kuratowski, K., and A. Mostowski (1976). Set Theory: With an Introduction to Descriptive Set Theory.North-Holland, Amsterdam.

Kurepa, D. (1934). Tableu ramifies densembles: Espaces pseudo-distancies. C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris,198, 1563–1565.

— (1936). Le probleme de Souslin et les espaces abstraits. C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris, 203, 1049—1052.

— (1936). Sur les classes (E) et (D). Publ. Math. Univ. Beograd., 5, 124–132.

— (1936). L’Hypothese de Ramification. C. R. Acad. Sci., Ser. 202, 185–187.

— (1956). Sur lecart abstrait. Glasnik Mat. Fiz. Astr:, 11, 105–134.

R. Lauer (1976). Defining social problems: Public and professional perspectives. Social Problems, 24,122–30.

Laugwitz, D. (1961). Anwendungen unendlichkleiner zahlen I. J. Reine Angew. Math., 207, 53–60.

— (1962). Anwendungen unendlichkleiner zahlen II. J. Reine Angew. Math., 208, 22–34.

— (1968). Eine nichtarchimidische erweiterung anordeneter korper. Math. Nachr., 37, 225–236.

Barry Lee (1978, 1979). Introducing Systems Analysis and Design, Vols. I, II. National ComputerCenter, Manchester.

Levi-Civita, T. (1892). Sugli infinitied infinitesimi attuali quali elementianalitici. Atti. 1st Veneto Sc.,Letted Art., Ser. 7 a , 4, 1765–1815.

Lilienfeld, D. (1978). The Rise of Systems Theory. Wiley, New York.

Lin, Y. (submitted). Centralized Systems and Their Existence.

— (1987). A model of general systems. Math. Modelling, 9, 95–104.

— (1988). An application of systems analysis in sociology. Cybernetics and Systems, 19, 267–278.

— (1988). On periodic linked time systems. Int. J. Systems Sci., 19, 1299–1310.

— (1988). Can the world be studied in the viewpoint of systems? Math. Computer Model., 11, 738–742.

— (1989). Order structures of families of general systems. Cybernetics and Systems, 20, 51–66.

— (1989). Some properties of linear systems. Int. J. Systems Sci., 20, No. 6, 927–937.

— (1989). A multi-relation approach of general systems and tests of applications. Synthese: Int. J.Epistem. Methodol. Phil. Sci., 79, 473–488.

— (1989). Multi-level systems. Int. J. Sys. Sci., 20, 1875–1889.

— (1990). The concept of fuzzy systems. Kybernetes: Int. J. Systems. Cybernet., textbf19, 45–51.

Page 377: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

References 373

— (1990). A few philosophical remarks on general systems theory. Abstracts of 8th International

— (1990). Connectedness of general systems. Systems Sci., 16, 5–17.

— (1990). A few systems-colored views of the world. In: R. E. Mickens (ed.), Mathematics and

— (1994). Feedback transformation and its applications. J. Systems Eng., 3, 32–38.

Lin, Y., and K. Z Forrest (1995). Existence of major diseases and modeling of epidemiological

Lin, Y. (1996). Developing a theoretical foundation for the laws of conservation. Kybernetes: Int. J.

Lin,, Y., Q. P. Hu, and D. Li (1997). Some unsolved problems in general systems theory I and II.

Lin, Y., and Y.-H. Ma (1987). Remarks on analogy between systems. Int. J. General Systems, 13,

— (1989). Remarks on the definition of systems. Systems Anal. Model., Simu., 6, 923–931.

— (1990). General feedback systems. Int. J General Systems, 18, No. 2, 143–154.

— (1993). System — a unified concept. Cybernet. Systems, 24, 375–406.

Y. Lin, Y.-H. Ma, and R. Port (1998). Centralizability and its existence. Math. Model. Sci. Comput.

— (1990). Several epistemological problems related to the concept of systems. Math. Comput. Model.,14, 52–57.

Congress of Cybernetics and Systems, June 11–15, New York.

Science. World Scientific Press, Singapore.

.transition: A general systems theoretic approach. Cybernetics and Systems, 26, 647–664.

Systems Cybernet., 24, No. 5, 52–60.

Cybernet. Systems, 28, 287–303, and 591–605.

135–141.

Y. Lin and Y.-P. Qiu (1987). Systems analysis of the morphology of polymers. Math. Model., 9, 493–498.

Lin, Y., and E. A. Vierthaler (1998). A systems identification of social problems and its application topublic issues of contention during the twentieth century. Math. Model. Sci. Comput.

Lin, Y., and S.-T. Wang (1998). Developing a mathematical theory of computability which speaks thelanguage of levels. Math. Comput. Model.

Ma, Y.-H., and Y. Lin (1987). Some properties of linked time systems. Int. J. General Systems, 13,125–134.

— (1988). Limit properties of hierarchies of general systems. Appl. Math. Lett., 1, 157–160.

— (1990). Continuous mappings between general systems. Math. Comput. Model., 14, 58–63.

T. de Marco (1980). Structured Analysis: Systems Specifications. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.

Masani, P. R. (1994). The scientific methodology in the light of cybernetics. Kybernetes: Int. J. Systems.Cybernet., 23, No. 4, 5–132.

Mathematical sciences: a unifying and dynamical resource. (1985). Notices of the American Mathe-matical Society, 33, 463–479.

Martin, D. A., and R. M. Solovay (1970). Internal Cohen extensions. Ann. Math. Logic, 2, 143–178.

Page 378: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

374 References

Mesarovic, M.,D; (1964). Views on general systems theory. In: M. D. Mesarovic (ed.), Proceedings ofthe 2nd Systems Symposium at Case Institute of Technology Wiley, New York.

Mesarovic, M. D., and Y. Takahara (1975). General Systems Theory: Mathematical Foundations.Academic Press, New York.

— (1989). Abstract Systems Theory. Springer-Verlag, Berlin.

R. E. Mickens (1990). Mathematics and Science. World Scientific, Singapore.

Milsum, J. H. (1966). Biological Control Systems Analysis. New York, McGraw-Hill.

Minsky, M. L. (1967). Computation, Finite and Infinite Machines. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs,NJ.

Mitten, L. G. (1974). Preference order dynamic programming. Management Sci., 21, 43–46.

Moore, A. W. (1991). In: T. Honderich (ed), The Infinite: The Problems of Philosophy — Their Pastand Present. Routledge, London and New York.

Moritz, R. E. (1942). On Mathematics and Mathematicians. Dover, New York.

Mumford,, G., A. Land, and W. Hawgood (1978). A participative approach to computer systems.Impact Sci. Soc., 28, 235–253.

Negoita, C. V. (1992). Pullback versus feedback. In: C. V. Negoita (ed.), Cybernetics and AppliedSystems. Marcel Dekker, New York, 239-247.

Nyikos, P., and H. C. Reichel (1975). On the structure of zero dimensional spaces. Indag. Math., 37,120–136.

— (1976). On uniform spaces with linearly ordered bases II. Fund. Math., 93, 1–10.

Omran, A. (1971). The epidemiologic transition: A theory of the epidemiology of population change.Milband Memorial Fund Q., 49, 509–538.

Perlman, J. S. (1970). The Atom and the Universe. Wadsworth, Belmont, CA.

Polya, G. (1973). How to Solve It: A New Aspect of Mathematical Method. 2nd ed. Princeton UniversityPress, Princeton, NJ.

Popper, K. (1945). The Open Society and Its Enemies. Routledge, London.

Poston, T., and I. Stewart (1978). Catastrophe Theory and Its Applications. Pitman, London.

Qin, G.-G. (1988). Pansystems Research about Dynamic Programming. Guizhou Sci., No. 2, 73–79.

— (1991). Dynamic programming and pansystems operation epitome principle. J. Jiangsu Inst.Technol., 4, No. 2, 62–68.

Quastler, H. (1955). Information Theory in Biology. The University of Illinois Press, Urbana, IL.

— (1965). General principles of systems analysis. In: T. H. Waterman and H. J. Morowitz (eds.),Theoretical and Mathematical Biology. New York.

Quigley, F. D. (1970). Manual of Axiomatic Set Theory. Appleton-Century Crofts, New York.

Page 379: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

References 375

Rapoport, A. (1949). Outline of a probabilistic approach to animal sociology, I–III. Bull. Math. Biophys.,11, 183–196, 273–281; 12 (1950), 7–17.

Rashevsky, N. (1956). Topology and life: In: search of general mathematical principles in biology andsociology. General Systems, I, 123–138.

Rescigno, A., and G. Segre (1966). Drug and Tracer Kinetics. Blaisdell, Waltham, MA.

Richards, I., and H. Youn (1990). Theory of Distributions: A Non- Technical Introduction. CambridgeUniversity Press, Cambridge.

Rudin, M. E. (1977). Martin’s axiom. In: J. Barwise (ed.), Handbook of Mathematical Logic. North-Holland, Amsterdam.

Rugh, W. J. (1981). Nonlinear Systems Theory: The Volterra/Wiener Approach. Johns Hopkins Uni-versity Press, Baltimore.

Saito, T. (1986). Feedback transformation of linear systems. Int. J. Systems Sci., 17, No. 9, 1305–1315.

— (1987). Structure of the class of linear functional time systems under output feedback transforma-tion. Int. J. Systems Sci., 18, No. 3, 1017–1027.

Saito, T., and M. D. Mesarovic (1985). A meaning of the decoupling by feedback of linear functionaltime systems. Int. J. General Systems, 11, no. 1, 47–61.

Schetzen, M. (1980). The Volterra and Wiener Theories of Non-Linear Systems. Wiley, New York.

Schwartz, L. (1950). Theorie des Distributions, Vol. I. Hermann, Paris.

— (1951). Theorie des Distributions, Vol. II. Hermann, Paris.

Shannon, C., and W. Weaver (1949). The Mathematical Theory of Communication. University ofIllinois Press, Urbana, IL.

Shoenfield, J. R. (1975). Martin’s axiom. Am. Math. Monthly, 82, 610–617.

Shubik, M. (1983). Game Theory in the Social Science: Concepts and Solutions. MIT Press, Cambridge,MA.

Sikorski, R. (1950). Remarks on some topological spaces of higher power. Fund. Math., 37, 125–136.

Smith,, D., M. Eggen, and R. St. Andre (1990). A Transition to Advanced Mathematics. 3rd ed.,Brooks/Cole, Pacific Grove, CA.

Spector, M., and J. I. Kitsuse (1977). Constructing Social Problems. Cummings, Menlo Park, CA.

Stevenson, F. W., and W. J. Thron (1971). Results on ωµ -metric spaces and ωµ - proximities. Fund.Math., 73, 171–178.

Stewart, J. (1987). Calculus. Brooks/Cole, Pacific Grove, CA.

Suslin, M. (1920). Problems 3. Fund. Math., 1, 223.

Systems Research, Yearbook (1969–1976). Vols. I–VIII, Blauberg, I. V., et al., (eds.), Moscow.

Takahara, Y. (1982). Decomposability conditions for general systems. Large Scale Systems, 3, No. 1,57-65.

Page 380: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

376 References

Takahara, Y., and T. Asahi (1985). Causality invariance of general systems under output feedbacktransformations. Int. J. Systems Sci., 16, No. 10, 1185–1206.

Tamarkin, J. D. (1936). Twenty-five volumes of Fundamenta Mathematica. Bull. Am. Math. Soc., 42,300.

Tarski, A. (1954, 1955). Contributions to the theory of models I, II, III. Nederl. Akad. Wetensch. Proc.Ser. A., 57, 572–581, 582–588; 58, 56–64.

Tian, F., and X. C. Wang (1980). The Course of Science of Sciences. Scientific Press, Beijing.

Turing, A. M. (1936). On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungs problem.Proc. London Math. Soc., Ser. 2, 42.

Vierthaler, E. A. (1993). Wholesale content analysis: Collecting long-term data to study large-scalesocietal changes of historic importance. Math. Model. Sci, Comput., 2, 310–19.

Voronese, G. (1891). Fondamenti di Geometria a Piu Dimensioni. Padova.

— (1896). Intor noad alcune osservazioni sui segmeni infiniti e infinitesimi attuali. Math. Ann., 47,423–432.

S.-T. Wang (1964). Remarks on ωµ- additive spaces. Fund. Math., 55, 101–112.

— (1985). Generalized number system and its applications I. Tsukuba J. Math., 9, No. 2, 203–15.

— (1991). A non-Archimedean number field and its applications in modem physics. In: G. M. Rassias(ed.), The Mathematical Heritage of C. F. Gauss. World Scientific, Singapor, pp. 810–826.

Wigner, E. P. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Comm.Pure Appl. Math., 13, 1–14.

Wonham, W. M. (1979). Linear Multi- Variable Control: A Geometric Approach. Springer-Verlag,New York.

Wood-Harper, A. T., and G. Fitzgerald (1982). A taxonomy of current approaches to systems analysis.Comput. J., 25, 12–16.

Wu, C. P. (1980). Multicriteria dynamic programming. Sci. Sinica, 23, 814–822.

— (1981). Optimal control problems with nonscalar valued performance criteria and dynamic pro-gramming. Proceedings of the 8th Triennial World Congress of the IFAC, pp. X72–X76.

S.-Z. Wu and X.-M. Wu (1986). Generalized fundamental equations in pansystems network analysis.Kybernetes, 15, 181–184.

Wu, X.-M. (1981). Pansystems analysis — a new exploration of interdisciplinary investigation (withappendices on discussions on medicine, chemistry, logic and economics). Sci. Exploration, 1,No. 1. 125–164.

— (1982). Pansystems methodology: Concepts, theorems and applications I. Sci. Exploration, 2, No.1, 33–56.

— (1982). Pansystems methodology: Concepts, theorems and applications II. Sci. Exploration, 2,No. 2, 93–106.

— (1982). Pansystems methodology: Concepts, theorems and applications III. Sci. Exploration, 2,No. 4, 123–132.

Page 381: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Some Unsolved Problems in General Systems Theory 377

— (1983). Pansystems methodology: Concepts, theorems and applications IV. Sci. Exploration, 3,No. 1, 125–137.

— (1983). Pansystems methodology: Concepts, theorems and applications V. Sci. Exploration, 3,No. 4 97–104.

— (1984). Pansystems methodology: Concepts, theorems and applications VI. Sci. Exploration, 4,No. 1, 107–116.

— (1984). Pansystems methodology: Concepts, theorems and applications VII. Sci. Exploration, 4,No. 4, 1–14.

— (1984). Investigation and applications of pansystems recognition theory and pansystems-operations research of large-scale systems. Appl. Math. Mech., 5, No. 1, 995–1010.

— (1984). Approximation Transformation Theory and the Pansystems Concepts in Mathematics.Hunan Science and Technology Press.

— (1985). Pansystems methodology: Concepts, theorems and applications VIII. Sci. Exploration, 5,No. 1, 9–23.

— (1994). From pansystems philosophy to pansystems poetry. Tianshui Shichuan Xue Bao, 30, Nos.3–4, 91- - 150.

S.-Z. Wu and X.-M. Wu (1984). Generalized principle of optimality in pansystems network analysis.Kybernetes, 13, 231–235.

Yablonsky, A. I. (1984). The development of science as an open system. In: J. M. Gvishiani (ed.),Systems Research: Methodological Problems. Oxford University Press, New York, pp. 211–228.

Yasui, Y. (1975). On ωµ - metrizable spaces. Math. Japon., 20, 159–180.

Zadeh, L. (1962). From circuit theory to systems theory. Proc. IRE, 50, 856–865.

Zhu, X.-D., and X.-M. Wu (1987). An approach on fixed pansystems theorems: Panchaos and strangepanattractor. Appl. Math. Mech., 8, No. 4, 339–344.

Page 382: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Index

(G) integrals, 332(m, n) -derivative, 3211–1 mapping, 16

Abstract distances, 344AC, 62Addition, 27Addition of order types, 35Algebraic geometry, 344Almost disjoint family, 78Ancient atomists, 114Antichain, 33Apollo project, 5Arithmetic of natural numbers, 168Associated input–output system, 299Atom, 113Atomic theory, 114Attractor, 258Attributes, 9Axiom of choice, 62Axiomatic set theory, 59

Beauty of mathematics, 164Bellman’s Principle of Optimality, 137, 148Bellman’s principle of optimality, 135Bernstein’s Equipollence Theorem, 25Big sum, 328Bijective mapping, 16Black box, 2Boolean algebra, 344Box product topology, 325Burali-Forti paradox, 57

Calorists, 114Cartesian product of two sets, 22Catastrophe theory, 10Causal relation, 5

Causal system, 276Chain, 33Chain of object systems, 116, 123Chaos, 12, 256Class of all sets, 95Classical systems theory, 10Cofinal, 34Cofinality, 75Coinitial, 34Color, 164Compartment theory, 11Complement, 19Complex system representation, 292Complexity, 6Component system, 281Concatenation, 274Conservation of matter, 113Conservation of mechanical energy, 115Consistent set, 61Continuous everywhere, 325Continuously ordered set, 41Continuum hypothesis, 75Crystalline material, 174Crystallization process, 175Cut, 41Cybernetics, 2

Data analysis approach, 8De Morgan’s Laws, 20Decision theory, 2Decomposability, 309Decoupled by feedback, 285Dedekind cut, 345Densely ordered set, 40Density, 336Denumerable set, 16Derivative, 325

379

Page 383: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

380 Index

Descartes’ second principle, 3Dimension theory, 344Dirac’s δ function, 124Dirac’s quantum mechanics, 124Distribution, 125Divisibility, 111Dynamic programming, 135

Einstein’s relativity, 124Elementary functions, 345Elementary space, 337Empty set, 19Energies, 5Epimorphism, 294Epistemology, 174Equipment-replacement models, 135Equipollence, 16Exponentiation, 27Extensionality, 62Exterior measure, 326

Factor system, 281Feedback component, 266Feedback decoupling, 309Feedback invariant property, 271Feedback system, 265, 309Feedback transformation, 266Filter, 80Finite set, 73Finitist, 64First-order predicate calculus, 59Formal language, 171Formal power series, 344Formalist, 64Formula, 60Foundations of geometry, 344Four-element philosopher, 113Function, 16, 67Functional system, 265Fundamental equation, 136, 143Fundamental particle, 111Fundamental Theorem of Calculus, 346Fuzzy mathematics, 11

Galileo’s method, 4Game Theory, 12Game theory, 2General linear system, 309General system, 123General systems methodology, 6Generalized continuum hypothesis, 75Generalized number, 126, 311Generalized number system, 125

Generalized power series, 125

Generalized Principle of Optimality, 139

Generalized solution, 326

Genetic algorithm, 12

Global system representation, 292GNL-integrable function, 133

GNL-integral, 330

GNS function induced by f, 341

Gödel completeness theorem, 64

Gödel’s theorem, 172

Graph of a function, 327

Graph theory, 12

Heat of friction, 114

Heaviside function, 345

Height, 84

Hierarchy of monads, 3

Hu’s counterexample, 136

Human activity systems approach, 7

Hyperreal number, 188

Identical systems, 123

Impassable chasm, 180

Increasing function, 43

Indefinite integral, 335

Infinite set, 73Infinitesimal, 125, 314

Infinities, 125

Infinity, 314

Information highway, 5

Injective complex system representation, 302

Injective mapping, 16

Input space, 255

Input–output system, 255

Input–output system covering, 298

Input–output system partition, 298

Interior measure, 327

Inventory problem, 135

Isolated ordinal, 70

Isomorphism, 67, 295

ith-order generalized extreme value, 157

κ-disjoint sets, 77

Page 384: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

Index 381

Lavoisier’s Axiom, 117Law of Conservation of Fundamental Particles,

117Lebesgue integral, 328Lebesgue integration, 325Lebesgue measurable set, 327Length of a relation, 123Level index, 126, 311Limit of the λ -sequence, 48Limit ordinal, 47Linear order relation, 33Linear ordering, 67Linear system, 263Linear time system, 274Linear uniformity, 344Linearly independent functions, 339

Mapping, 16, 67Martin’s Axiom, 80Materials science, 174Mathematical induction, 179Mathematical proofs, 181Maximal, 33Maximum, 33Medieval mysticism, 3Minimal, 33Minimum, 33Modeling relation, 293Molecular spatial structure, 174Monad, 188Monomorphism, 296MT-time system, 273Multilevel structure, 122Multiplication, 27Music, 166

Naive set theory, 15Navier–Stokes equation, 12Network, 13Newton’s law of action and reaction, 115Non-Archimedean analysis, 344Non-Archimedean number field, 125Non-Archimedean topology, 344Noninteracted system, 281Nonstandard analysis, 125nth-level object system, 116, 123nth-order optimization solution, 157

Objects, 9ωµ -additive topological spaces, 344One-element Ionians, 112One-to-one mapping, 16Open interval, 326

Operation Epitome Principle, 149Optimization model, 150Optimization model, 148Optimum-preserving law, 138Order topology, 87Order type, 35Ordered algebraic structures, 344Ordered pair, 10, 22Ordered set, 32Ordered sum, 35Ordinal exponentiation, 72Ordinal number, 45Ordinalities, 45Ordinals, 45Original system, 266Output space, 255Overall system, 281

p-adic topology, 344p-resolving mapping, 155Painting, 166Pansystems theory, 309Paradox of a moving particle, 180Paradox of the hotel, 180Partial function, 23Partial order, 80Participant approach, 7Peano’s axioms, 168Platonists, 64Poetry, 166Power set, 26, 62Precausal system, 276Problem-oriented systems approaches, 6Product mapping, 293Product of order types, 36Products of distributions, 346Proper subset, 19

Quantifier, 60Quantum field theory, 345Quantum mechanics, 346Quasi-(m , n) continuity, 317Quasi-(m , n) limit, 321

Regular ordinal, 75Regularity, 62Relation, 10, 67Resource allocation problems, 135Rest mass, 124Riemann integral, 326Russell’s paradox, 57, 123

Page 385: General Systems Theory a Mathematical Approach

382 Index

Schwartz’s distributions, 346Science of science, 1Scientific revolution, 4Seeds, 113Self-controlled equipment, 5Sentence, 61Set, 15Set existence, 62Set theory, 10Shift operator, 274Shortest-path problem, 135Similarity mapping, 34Simple function, 327Simulation, 13Small sum, 328Stationary set, 148Statistics, 13Stone duality theorem, 344Strange attractor, 260Strict total ordering, 67Strictly order-preserving function, 149Strictly strongly antisymmetric relation, 150Strongly antisymmetric relation, 150Strongly stationary system, 275Structured systems analysis approach, 8Subformula, 60Subsystem, 123Successor, 70Successor ordinal, 70Surjective complex system representation, 302Surjective mapping, 16Suslin line, 88Suslin tree, 85Suslin’s hypothesis, 88System with relations, 9Systemality, 6Systems connected in series, 291Systems description of mathematics, 172Systems movement, 347Systems research, 4Systems theory, 2

Taylor expansion, 345Test function, 336Theory of automata, 14Theory of distributions, 335Theory of science of science, 176Three-body problem, 5Time invariably realizable system, 277Topological space, 87Total ordering, 67Totality, 6Traditional approach, 7Transfer principle, 345Transfinite Induction, 72Transfinite Recursion, 72Traveling-salesman problem, 135Tree, 84∆-system, 78∆ -System Lemma, 79Type class, 38

Unbordered set, 40Uncountable set, 16Uniform convergency, 326Unit cell, 174Universal closure, 61Utopian project, 4

Vase puzzle, 178Volume of a interval, 326Voronese’s non-Archimedean geometry, 344

Weak derivative, 325Well-founded set, 91Well-ordered set, 42Well-Ordering Theorem, 52White box, 2Wholeness, 1

Zermelo–Russell paradox, 57Zero, 138Zeroth-order optimization solution, 156ZFC axiom system, 59