Frankel -- GeneralTheoretical Anthropology- Rationality and Relativism

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/17/2019 Frankel -- GeneralTheoretical Anthropology- Rationality and Relativism

    1/2

    GENERAL/

    HEORETIC L

    NTHROPOLOGY 769

    more influenced by

    G.

    H. Mead perhaps

    or

    C.

    H. Cooley

    or K

    Burke, have also put forth the

    drama of the pronouns as central to the hu-

    man situation. But Singer adds new under-

    standing to that emphasis both as to the rela-

    tion of the pronouns, which are indexicals, to

    iconic and symbolic signs

    as

    well as to

    our

    un-

    derstanding of the evolutionary dynamic, the

    culture change, in pronoun use. This indexical

    theory centers anthropology where it should

    be centered-in the colloquy that the self car-

    ries on inwardly with itself and outwardly

    with the other persons singular and plural.

    Perhaps the emblem that serves us best is not

    semiotic,

    or

    semiologic,

    or

    semantic anthro-

    pology but jus t plain colloquial anthropology.

    Measuring Culture: aradigm for

    th

    Analysis

    of

    Social

    Organization

    onathan L.

    ross

    and

    Steve

    Raper

    New York: Columbia

    University Press, 1985.

    176

    pp.

    32.50

    (cloth).

    BRIAN .FOSTER

    rizona tate

    niversity

    This

    book

    can be divided into three concep-

    tual parts: discussion of Mary Douglas’s no-

    tion of gridfgroup analysis; an attempt to for-

    malize its basic concepts and propositions; an

    analysis of a fictitious community conflict.

    What is good about the book is the authors’

    belief that sociocultural investigation can and

    must be precise, and that a deep and compre-

    hensive cultural understanding of the case un-

    der study is a prerequisite for precision. Less

    good is that the link between the book’s theo-

    retical ideas and formal model is tenuous, and

    that the data demands of the model range

    from very difficult to unreasonable.

    In the authors’ words, the purpose of grid/

    group analysis is to “provide a framework

    within which a cultural analyst may consis-

    tently relate differences in organizational

    structures to the strength

    of

    values that sus-

    tain them” (p. 14). The authors argue that so-

    cial units can usefully be placed in a two-di-

    mensional space, one dimension being

    strength of “groupness,” and the other being

    strength of hierarchy/role differentiation. Th e

    location of a unit in this space is held to cor-

    respond with the unit’s important cultural

    properties

    p.

    15).

    The proposed method has little to do with

    the more interesting cultural part

    of

    grid/

    group analysis. The authors themselves say

    that “it is not yet clear how actual patterns of

    belief and behavior superimpose on the four-

    quadrant grid/group diagram” (p. 114). The

    book, then, turns out to be about a method for

    describing social structure.

    Gross

    and Rayner

    say that the “principal novelty”

    of

    their ap-

    proach v i s -h i s network analysis is that they

    “use the justification of polythetic classifica-

    tion” (p. 67). I would question this claim to

    novelty. Novel

    or

    not, the authors take little

    advantage of recent conceptual advances in

    network analysis.

    For

    instance, their notion of

    “group boundary” is conceptually a clique-

    like idea (p. 65), but the clique literature is not

    discussed, and conceptual and computational

    difficulties are simply glossed over. The same

    might be said of network contributions to role

    theory.

    The authors’ measures ofgrid and group re-

    semble early anthropological network analy-

    sis-for example, Kapferer’s much riche r

    analysis of conflict in a Zambian factory. The

    strength ofthese measures is that they are sim-

    ple mathematically and directly interpretable

    sociologically (though, as already mentioned,

    the links between the measures and the theory

    in the

    Gross

    and Rayner book are tenuous).

    Th e major weaknesses are that in the process

    of aggregating the data a great deal of the

    structure is lost, since there are many radically

    different structures that would produce the

    same scores. The problem is reduced by the

    multiplicity of indices, but it is unexamined.

    Chapter 4 is where the connection between

    the method and the underlying theoretical

    ideas becomes tenuous. Five “predicates” of

    “group” (proximity, transitivity, frequency,

    scope, and impermeability) and four of “grid”

    (specialization, asymmetry, entitlement, and

    accountability) are enumerated. The connec-

    tion of these measures with the underlying

    grid/group theory is not worked out in detail.

    Chapter 5 gives a straightforward statement

    on computing the various indices. Chapter 6

    is an operational guide; the content is very di-

    verse and contains few surprises. Much of the

    discussion takes the form of a some times

    rather cute description of how fieldwork was

    done in the study of the fictitious conflict.

    On the whole, I found the book disappoint-

    ing. It will be of relatively little interest to

    mathematically oriented anthropologists. 1do

    not think the method is a fair or particularly

    useful formalization of grid/group analysis.

    And I doubt that the book will convince any

    nonbelievers of the utility of mathematical

    modeling.

    Rationality

    and

    Relativism:InSearchof a

    Philosophy

    and

    History of Anthropology

    I C Jarvie. International Library of Sociology.

    Boston: Routledge Kegan Paul, 1984. 171

    pp.

    30.00

    (cloth).

    BARBARARANKEL

    high niversity

  • 8/17/2019 Frankel -- GeneralTheoretical Anthropology- Rationality and Relativism

    2/2

    770

    A M E R I C A N ANTHROPOLOGIST

    [88 986

    In so brief a review, one cannot criticize this

    book

    with the seriousness it deserves or that

    Jarvie’s Popperian faith would prescribe.

    I

    therefore recommend that those seriously in-

    terested either in philosophical anthropology

    (which asks “what is the human species?”)

    or

    the philosophy of anthropology (which asks “how

    should we study the human species?”) will

    want this book on their shelves, ifonly to quar-

    rel with the author-who abandoned anthro-

    pology for philosophy

    25

    years ago, and has

    since made a useful career as anthropological

    gadfly.

    In this book the core argument opposes the

    terms “rationality” and “relativism.” Profes-

    sor Jarvie believes it is contradictory for an-

    thropology to assert both the rational unity of

    humankind and relativism as fundamental

    principles. The rest is elaboration-much of it

    highly rhetorical

    or

    thinly argued, but all of it

    interesting, pungently written, and provoca-

    tive.

    The book begins with a prologue on “Meta-

    physical Anthropology” which asserts that if

    we assume the rational unity of the human

    species, the notion o cultural relativism fails,

    and vice versa; thus, in upholding both, an-

    thropology becomes incoherent as a disci-

    pline. This judgment seems based on Jarvie’s

    confusing unity with uniformity-a category

    mistake undermining his main argument,

    since it does not follow from the doctrine of

    species unity regarding rational capacity that

    we should expect unifomi9 in i ts expression.

    Part 1, “Rationality,” defines that term as

    “the application of reason to tasks.” Ration-

    ality comes in several strengths, depending on

    whether actors employ sound standards in

    evaluating information and ideas used for goal

    attainment. The strongest form of rationality

    is to learn via the “best” standard (i.e., the sci-

    entific one Popper calls “conjectures and re-

    futations”) and

    is

    thus purely instrumental.

    Here the argument is difficult to summarize

    fairly, being marred by inconsistencies and

    peremptoriness. Jarvie’s view is ontologically

    realist (there is an independent world that al-

    lows

    us

    to learn by trial and error), culturally

    intellectualist (ideas determine social behav-

    ior, not the reverse), and markedly ethnocen-

    tric (all cultures are less rational than

    ours,

    since it produced Modern Science).

    Part 2, “Relativism,” is centered around an

    odd conception of that term. Though ac-

    knowledging relativism’s cognitive aspects,

    here Jarvie weighs only anthropology’s ap-

    proach to moral systems, and finds it wanting.

    His premise that even well-meaning relativ-

    ism entails accepting all moral systems as hav-

    ing equal value, no matter how depraved (or

    itself intolerant) a given system may be-leads

    to his conclusion that “it is immoral and irre-

    sponsible to preach

    (or) .

    practice relativ-

    ism” (p. 91).

    Clearly, Jarvie tilts at windmills. As he re-

    alizes (p. 79), in practice anthropologists nei-

    ther can nor do give automatic toleration and

    approval to all moral systems. But it is part of

    the work of anthropology to describe such sys-

    tems and to learn how they articulate with

    other aspects of the societies to which they be-

    long. T o the extent that this end is served by

    near-term reservation ofjudgment, we doSD

    but this becoming modesty is hardly endorse-

    ment of evil. Indeed, Jarvie’s bizarre defini-

    tion of relativism leads not only to moral but

    methodological absurdity, for it would require

    that we deculturate ourselves (becoming amo-

    ral in the process) in order to study the cul-

    tures of others. Indeed, Jarvie indicates a t one

    point that he sees this (p. 79), which makes his

    view still more peculiar.

    “Weak absolutism,” Jarvie’s alternative to

    moral relativism, is explicated in “Rationality

    and Relativism,” part 3. It is designed not

    only to save

    us

    from permitting all things, but

    to resolve the contradictions between Jarvie’s

    two key terms. I cannot summarize the argu-

    ment here, but suggest that use of the more ac-

    curate term “relativity” rather than “relativ-

    ism” to describe the anthropological attitude

    might calm Jarvie’s fear that anthropology

    will engender the international moral chaos he

    so righteously fulminates against in this out-

    rageously flawed but oddly engaging essay.