30
Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1: Law must be for the common good Chapter 2: Authority and common good create fundamental legal roles Chapter 3: The Aims of Law Chapter 4: The Aims and Criminal Law Chapter 5: The Aims and Tort Law Chapter 6: Challenges to the 3 Commonplaces

Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Challenging the Law In order to be non-defective, law must be: [1] genuinely authoritative [2] genuinely for the common good If these commonplaces are false or misleading, it puts in question the roles of subject, legislator, and judge in paradigmatic [ model ] legal systems. Is law genuinely authoritative? Is it for the common good? Some say NO.

Citation preview

Page 1: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Focus in Our Reading• Remember the 3 commonplaces?

[1] Law is a matter of social fact[2] Law is authoritative[3] Law is for the common goodChapter 1: Law must be for the common goodChapter 2: Authority and common good create fundamental legal rolesChapter 3: The Aims of LawChapter 4: The Aims and Criminal LawChapter 5: The Aims and Tort LawChapter 6: Challenges to the 3 Commonplaces

Page 2: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Unit 9 and Chapter 6• This Chapter discusses legal philosophies that challenge the

fundamental roles we have studied about our Legal System.[1] Against the Role of Subject: Philosophical Anarchism[2] Against the Role of Legislator:

Marxism / Feminist Legal Theory / Critical Race Theory[3] Against the Role of Judge:

American Legal RealismCritical Legal Studies

Page 3: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Challenging the Law

• In order to be non-defective, law must be: [1] genuinely authoritative [2] genuinely for the common good • If these commonplaces are false or misleading, it

puts in question the roles of subject, legislator, and judge in paradigmatic [model] legal systems.

• Is law genuinely authoritative? • Is it for the common good? Some say NO.

Page 4: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Against the Role of Subject

• Philosophical anarchism [rebellion] challenges the duty of subjects to obey law. – How can they do that? – Isn’t it self-evident we should obey the law?

Maybe not?• There are two ways anarchists challenge the

role of subject.[1] Moral duty to be autonomous[2] Moral duty to obey is irrelevant

Page 5: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

[1] Moral Duty to be Autonomous• Robert Paul Wolff argues:[1] There is a fundamental

incompatibility between authority and autonomy,

[2] We have a moral duty to be and remain autonomous.

• Hence, to be a faithful subject asks too much in terms of sacrifice of one’s autonomy to be a role worth fulfilling.

• A response to this argument: [1] Unless the laws are grossly

unjust, one should obey because there needs to be a common standard to divide up responsibilities to promote the common good, and

[2 ] The law is a good candidate for that standard. The loss of autonomy is justifiedby the gain for the commongood.

Page 6: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Loss of AutonomyIs the loss of autonomy justified by the gain for the common good?

1. Do we have a moral duty to be autonomous rather thansomeone’s slave?

2. Does obedience to law make us a slave, impair our freedom?

3. Does the argument that it benefits the common good really address the question?

4. If we are being compelled to act on behalf of others – what do we gain individually?

Page 7: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

(2) Is Moral Duty to Obey Irrelevant?

• M.B.E. Smith, A. John Simmons, Joseph Raz, and others argue that no theory of moral requirement to obey the law is successful.

• Many acts that the law forbids, people would avoid anyway, even if the law were silent, because they are mala in se or wrong in themselves.

• Do you agree?

• Other acts, which are not mala in se, such as driving on the

right side of the road, people would obey because such customs or patterns of coordination exist and it endangers self and others to violate them.

• Even if there were no duty to obey law and honor the demands of being a subject, there are other moral requirements that would obtain

the same result.

Page 8: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Response• There are a number of situations that do not fit into the

mala in se patterns.• An important role that law has is regulating the demands we

can make on each other, e.g., not to endanger others by driving drunk.

• However, your definition of drunk might not be the same as mine. Much of the law is concerned with making more precise these standards of justice.

• Can you think of another response? • Do you agree that people would do the right thing anyway

even if there were no duty to obey law?

Page 9: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Philosophical vs Political Anarchism

• Remember that Philosophical Anarchism challenges the duty of subjects to obey law.

• Political anarchism is a claim about the undesirability of the state, rather than if one should obey the law.

Page 10: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Why is “the State” Undesirable?• Political anarchists’ viewpoints [1] Point out dangers posed by states due to hierarchical

structures ruling through coercion, with authority wielded by powerful elites.

[2] Argue that the state causes many of the harms it is supposed to remedy. - Example: states divide subjects from each other, oppressing some classes for the benefit of others.

[3] This oppression causes crime. However, this anti-state position of political anarchists does not necessarily require an anti-law position. (Distinguish between anti-hierarchy and anti-law)

Page 11: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Against the Role of Legislator

• Marx claimed that economic features of society generate constraints on noneconomic possibilities within that society. (First we look at economics, then tie that in with law)

• Is this true? Do you agree? • Do economics affect values? • Does it determine what is moral and immoral?• Is law designed to keep the rich rich and the

poor poor?

Page 12: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Other Examples Against the Role of Legislator

• Marxists are skeptical about the “science” of economics. They find two notions particularly absurd:

[1] The so-called “free market” (it’s not “free”) [2] The so-called “law” of supply and demand (it’s not a law)• Marxists say these notions, masquerading as “science,” are

simply myths that serve the interests of capitalism. • To Marxists, the capitalists control both the market (i.e. no

way is it free), and also both supply and demand (i.e., there is no neutral “law” of supply and demand).

Page 13: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

More Examples Against the Role of Legislator

• Capitalists clearly control supply, but they also control demand by their control of media, which they use to manipulate people’s perceptions of their “needs.”

• Capitalists make people think they need things that they really don’t need.

• Having created “demand,” capitalists can raise prices (leaving workers’ wages the same), and make more and more profits.

• The condition of the worker inevitably gets worse The more he produces, the less he can buy.

Page 14: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Legislation is corrupt

• Marx says the economic class to which one belongs determines the concept of morality and value that one adopts.

• It is inevitable over the long haul that the results of one class dominating another will be reflected in law itself.

• Principles that appear to be neutral on their face will turn out to be favorable to those in power.

Page 15: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Why?

• This bias could be due to:[a] Those with economic power often have control over making and applying law [b] Lawmakers and judges are drawn from the elite class[c] The legal order is unable to sustain norms too contrary to the prevailing economic relationships. • What do you think?

Page 16: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Historical “evidence”• Evidence of this phenomenon is shown as law’s initial

response to lawsuits by factory workers against their employers for injuries received on the job.

• The defenses of [1] assumption of risk [2] contributory negligence [3] the fellow servant rule

were all used by judges to deny recovery. • Even the advent of Worker’s Compensation, which provided

an alternative method of recovery, was just a concession that blocked fuller reform as it [1] does not compensate pain and suffering [2] caps damages, allowing employers to pay far less than full compensation for on the job injuries.

Why does Worker’s Comp limit damages payable to workers?

Page 17: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Remember What Marx and His Followers Say

• Rules of property are not neutral but tools by which the wealthy [1]accumulate wealth [2]accumulate power to the disadvantage of those who are poor.

• Free speech is not neutral but enables the wealthy to have a louder voice and more influence.

• The test of neutrality is not appearance but the real effects.

Page 18: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Law Can’t Be for Common Good Because of Class Conflict

• Marx’s points:– There is no neutral concept of justice and good– Class status shapes members’ concepts of justice and the common good– There is no genuine long-term prospect that law

can be for the common good. – There can be no hope for law that is for the

common good until society no longer consists of classes in conflict.

• What do you think?

Page 19: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Those Who Think Marx Was Only Partly Right

• Pluralists accept Marx’s views about power and how that precludes neutrality in law, but reject his view that economics is the ultimate determining ground.

• If not economics, then what else could determine allocation of power by law?

Page 20: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Feminist Legal Theory

• Men hold a dominant position socially and economically

• That causes law to be biased in favor of men even when it appears to be neutral on its face

• For example, Catherine MacKinnon claims that interpreting freedom of speech to protect pornography undervalues the harm pornography causes to women

Page 21: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Critical Race Theory

• A similar argument is made by Critical Race Theory regarding hate speech

• Both views say that until power relationships based upon gender or race are eliminated, the law will favor the dominant group

• Legislators will not be able to genuinely deliberate about the common good.

• What do you think?

Page 22: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Author’s response

• The point about one’s views being determined by class, gender, or race is made too strongly

• Legislators are capable of being objectively benevolent.

• In other words, they’re exaggerating

Page 23: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Against the Role of Judge

• Judges take legal rules as a guide in making decisions.

• Sometimes the law “runs out” and, it is argued, sometimes judges have to make decisions that go beyond the rules.

• This raises two questions:– (1) How pervasive is this phenomenon? – (2) To what extent does this call into question the

role of judge?

Page 24: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

American Legal Realism [Against the Role of Judge]

• American Legal Realism says law is massively indeterminate, at least for those cases that are appealed (as contrasted with mundane cases).

• This skepticism is founded on the idea that interpretive standards are not sufficient to account for what will be relevant in determining what precedent is or what statutes and other law mean in a particular case.

Page 25: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Critical Legal Studies [Against the Role of Judge]

The philosophy of Critical legal studies says:• Unlike standard Marxism, it does not hold that

the dominant group need be characterized in economic terms.

• Offshoots of this approach include: – Feminist legal theory – Critical race studies

Page 26: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

But aren’t outcomes predictable?

• The fact that judges’ decisions are largely predictable cannot be explained by the law’s determinacy but from other facts: – political beliefs– moral beliefs– social factors, such as class

• Do you agree?

Page 27: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Consequences

If realists are right, appellate judges are not making decisions in accordance with their role as judge because they are not applying law.

Do you see how this challenges the integrity ofthe legal system?

Page 28: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Critical Legal Studies Go Further

• Even in the everyday workings of the lower court the law is filled with indeterminacy

• Judges have shared substantive extralegal understandings – moral views

– political views – ideas that property understandings can’t be violated• Concluding that “law is politics.” • The critics say judges are lawmakers rather than appliers of law.

Page 29: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

If They’re Right, Do We Really Need Judges?

• If legal indeterminacy is so great, why should subjects accept judicial decisions as authoritative if those decisions are not fixed by law but are the result of judicial discretion?

• If cases are not decided based upon technical legal reasoning, but are the result of broader moral and political thinking…

• Judges as a class have no more expertise in these areas than other persons. (Should judges should be elected like legislators?)

• Response 1: An argument for having judges do this work is:– the practical need for binding decisions resolving disputes – but this raises the question of whether alternative sources of

resolution might be better

Is judging just politics?

Page 30: Focus in Our Reading Remember the 3 commonplaces? [1] Law is a matter of social fact [2] Law is authoritative [3] Law is for the common good Chapter 1:

Response 2

Response 2:– if cases are decided based upon shared moral and

political understandings, perhaps these understandings are genuine truths about human good and are generally shared and easily known.

• Do judges reflect our shared moral and political understandings?