Experimental Tests of Rationality

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    1/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    ..............................................................................................................

    EXPERIMENTALT E S T S O F

    RATIONALITY..............................................................................................................

    . I..........................................................................................................................................

    R choice theory is an instrumental theory. It assumes that agents have a

    set of basic preferences and values which they undertake to satisfy, and it then

    specifies the optimal way to achieve those values. Rational choice theory is some-

    times proposed as a purely normative theory, with no bearing on the descriptive

    question of what people actually do. It is also widely used as a working hypoth-

    esis about real human behavior, with many taking the view that behavior, when

    properly understood, follows the tenets of the theory, and an equally large number

    taking the opposite view. The majority of experimental studies in the fields of

    behavioral economics and judgment and decision-making are either explicit tests

    of rational choice theory or developments of theories that started out that way.The focus of this chapter is on the success of rational choice theory as a behavioral

    hypothesis.

    The chapter is organized as follows. Section . is an informal account of the

    conditions which preferences must meet if they are to be judged rational. This

    I am grateful to Paul Anand, Ken Binmore, and Jon Leland for useful discussion and comments, and

    especially to Stephen Humphrey for a very useful review. Special gratitude is also due to John Conliskfor providing me with his unpublished data.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    2/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    Table 8.1.Decision table showing states, options, and consequences

    Option State of the world

    S1 S2 . . . Sm

    O1 C11 C21 . . . Cm1O2 C12 C22 . . . Cm2. . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

    On C1n C2n . . . Cmn

    section draws primarily on the influential work of Savage (), who will through-

    out act as our guide to what is rational. Sections .. consider some empiri-cal challenges to the view that behavior conforms to these rationality conditions.

    The challenges involve showing that the preference ordering over options depends

    significantly on differences between choice circumstances that, according to the

    rationality conditions, are normatively irrelevant. In Section . I will return to

    Savages own discussion of the descriptive applicability of his conditions.

    . I C

    RC ..........................................................................................................................................

    In this section I provide a sketch of rational choice theory that will form the

    backdrop to the subsequent discussion. I adopt a highly simplified version of the

    framework used by Savage () in his Foundations of Statistics. Savages views

    are of particular interest to empirical researchers because he was concerned both

    with providing a normative system, and with the problem of whether this system

    was descriptively accurate. On the latter point he was more optimistic than many

    subsequent researchers.

    In Savages framework the decision-maker is seen as choosing between a range

    of options, which have consequences that are uncertain because they depend onunknown states of the world. The general situation can be described with the aid

    of Table.. We can illustrate this with the decision of whether to take an umbrella

    to the office on a day that threatens rain (Table .). Stated this way the options

    are {Take umbrella; Dont take umbrella}, the states are {Rain; No rain}, and the

    consequences are the anticipated outcome from choosing each option, conditional

    1 Anormative theory concerns what a rational agent shoulddo, and a descriptive theory what heactuallydoes.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    3/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    Table 8.2.Decision of whether to take an umbrella

    Option State of the world

    Rain No rain

    Take umbrella Dry DryDont take umbrella Wet Dry

    on whether or not it rains. In the table the consequences are simply Dry or Wet.

    Both options and states are mutually exclusive and exhaustive, meaning that no

    other options and states are possible, although it is always possible to describe them

    at different levels of detail. The option Dont take umbrella, for example, can bebroken down into Take a raincoat but no umbrella, and Take neither a raincoat

    nor an umbrella.

    Rational choice theory specifies certain minimal conditions whichshouldbe met

    for the choosing agent to be rational. There are two kinds of justification for main-

    taining that these are conditions of rationality. First, the rationality conditions are

    such that people will, on reflection,wantto conform to them. Although someone

    might occasionally express preferences contrary to the conditions, when the contra-

    diction is pointed out to her, she will want to change the expressed preferences and

    bring them in line. Or, as Robert Strotz put it, it would be a strange man indeed

    who would persist in violating these precepts once he understood clearly in what

    way he was violating them (, p.).Second, they are necessary for preferences to be consistent. Someone who does

    not comply with the conditions, it is argued, runs the risk of having a Dutch

    Book taken against them, or being turned into a money pump. To illustrate a

    money pump, imagine someone who prefers an orange to a lemon, a lemon to

    an apple, and an apple to an orange. This is, as will be indicated in the next

    paragraph, an intransitive preference. Someone with this preference (and, it must

    be acknowledged, no memory or common sense) might be induced to give a lemon

    plus a small amount of money for an orange, to give an orange plus a small

    amount for an apple, to give an apple plus a small amount for a lemon, and so on,

    forever.

    The rationality conditions are often presented as axioms or postulates. In thischapter they are presented informally, with many technical details being dropped.

    Hence I use the term condition. The first two conditions are:

    2 It should be emphasized that Savages view (and the closely related one of von Neumann andMorgenstern ) are mainstream accounts of rational choice, and alternatives are available which

    drop or replace the rationality conditions described here. Whether these alternatives are indeed theo-ries of rational choice is a matter for debate (see Sugden).

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    4/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    Completeness: For any pair of options O1and O2, either O1is preferred to O2, O2is preferred to O1, or the decision-maker is indifferent between them.

    Transitivity: For any triple of options, O1, O2, and O3, if O1is preferred to O2and

    O2is preferred to O3, then O1is preferred to O3.

    Combined, these produce apreference orderingover options, so that all options

    can be rank-ordered and equivalence classes can be formed, which are sets of options

    between which the decision-maker is indifferent. Consequently, these condi-

    tions are all that is necessary for what are called riskless choices, meaning choices

    between options when only one state can actually occur (Marschak). Such a

    riskless choice is made when you must decide whether to take an umbrella given

    that it is already raining.

    When risk and uncertainty enter the picturemeaning that the decision prob-lem requires at least two states to be fully specifiedfurther rationality conditions

    are required. I will describe two, which are enough to get our discussion started.

    The first is:

    Independence: Given a pair of options O1and O2that have the same consequences

    under some states of the world, then these common consequences will not influence

    preference between the options. (This is also called the sure-thing principle.)

    This principle appears innocuous. To illustrate with the umbrella example above,

    it merely says that because the consequences for you are the same regardless of what

    you choose if it doesnt rain tomorrow, these consequences should not influence

    your ultimate decision. Some readers may be tempted to object that the conse-quences described in the umbrella example are incompleteit is annoying to carry

    an umbrella, so we should fill in the cells with consequences like Dry, but carrying

    umbrellabut for the moment we will assume that the consequences given are

    correct. The readers hypothetical objection will soon be given its voice.

    Closely related to the independence condition is dominance:

    Dominance: If under at least one state of the world the consequence of O1 is

    preferred to that of O2, and if under no state of the world is the consequence of

    O2preferred to that of O1, then O1is preferred to O2.

    One option dominates the other if, no matter what occurs, it leads to a better

    outcome. In the umbrella example, taking an umbrella dominates not taking one,

    3 Bothconditions have been challenged as necessary foundations for rationality. Briefly, why should

    an agent have a preference between all options, even those they have never encountered before orwill never have to choose between? (e.g. Sugden; Binmore). Likewise, cannot an agent havechoice-set-dependent values that make the consequences of (say) getting a lemon from the set {lemon,orange} be different from those of getting a lemon from {lemon, apple}? (e.g. Anand, Ch. above;

    Sugden). The discussion of regret theory below hints at this issue, which goes well beyond thescope of this chapter.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    5/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    because if it rains you stay dry if you take an umbrella, but if it doesnt rain it makes

    no difference.

    This dominance condition is sometimes called state dominance, which can be

    distinguished from stochastic dominance. We can illustrate the difference with a

    simple gamble based on the toss of a coin. Imagine I toss a singlefair coin and give

    you a prize based on the outcome. You have two options, which pay offas follows:

    Heads Tails

    O1 $ 0

    O2 $ 0

    If you choose O1 I will pay $if heads comes up and nothing if tails comes up,

    while if you choose O2I will pay $if heads comes up and nothing if tails comes

    up.Statedominance dictates that you should choose O1because it might make youbetter offthan O2 and will certainly not make you worse off. Now imagine that I

    offer you a similar gamble, but this time I toss two fair coins (A and B), and O1and

    O2represent the choice of coin. Now the decision table is as follows:

    A: Heads A: Heads A: Tails A: Tails

    B: Heads B: Tails B: Heads B: Tails

    O1(Coin A) 0 0

    O2(Coin B) 0 0

    In probability terms, O1 dominates O2 (a percent chance of $, versus a

    percent chance of $), but it is nonetheless possible for the O2coin to come up

    heads while the O1coin comes up tails.Stochasticdominance refers to dominancein these probability terms. More formally, if O1 can be transformed from O2 by

    iteratively increasing the probability of a preferred consequence over a less preferred

    one, or by improving a consequence while holding its probability constant, then O1stochastically dominates O2.

    In the next four sections I describe experimental findings that appear to demon-

    strate how changing the circumstances of choice can make preferences vary in ways

    that systematically depart from the rationality conditions. The effect of changing

    circumstances can be considered a kind of spotlight effect, analogous to the con-

    cept of attentional spotlight from cognitive psychology (e.g. Cave and Bichot ).

    The fundamental idea is one that is more or less the default among psychologists

    who study choice behavior. It starts with the notion that people, and indeed allorganisms, have a severe limitation in their capacity to process information. More-

    over, and indeed as a consequence of this limitation, they do not have well-defined

    preferences over all options. Rather, when making a choice, the valuation is done at

    the moment, based on information recruited by the specific choice circumstances.

    These circumstances direct attention to certain problem featuresfeatures that

    can be described using the terminology of states, options, and consequences

    and deflect attention from others. The circumstances also act as memory cues and

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    6/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    triggers for the construction of scenarios. Our preferences are a function, always

    partly and sometimes decisively, of what the spotlight reveals.

    This spotlight effect, under a variety of names and descriptions, is the central

    principle underlying the experimental investigation of preference. We can even

    summarize the core research strategy of behavioral economics and behavioral

    decision-making as having three steps. The researcher

    . Infers, based on introspection or other evidence, that certain option charac-

    teristics will influence preference in a specific way.

    . Demonstrates logically how the influence from () can appear contrary to one

    or more of the rationality conditions.

    . Develops a method for shining a spotlight on those characteristics from () by

    varying some element of the decision context.To give an example that will reappear below, a researcher might notice that

    he is willing to pay $ for a high-priced car stereo when it is an option on a

    new car but not when it is an after-market purchase. From this he hypothesizes a

    general tendency to evaluate the magnitude of costs relative to irrelevant back-

    ground costs (step ); he then shows that this tendency can lead to preferences

    inconsistent with the incompleteness axiom (step ), and then develops a method

    for showing this in the laboratory by asking people to decide how much e ffort

    they would exert to save $X when their attention is drawn to a large or small

    background cost (step ). The next sections discuss many results from applying

    this research strategy, with each sections having a heading indicating how step is

    accomplished.

    . C C , W I

    RC ..........................................................................................................................................

    In many demonstrations of apparently irrational preference reversals, agents areplaced in two situations in which options appear to differ objectively, but the

    rationality conditions do not admit the relevance of these differences. Among

    these are two of the most famous, and historically the earliest, examples of

    4 Variations of this view are found in, among many other places, Payne, Bettman, and Johnson

    (); Read, Loewenstein, and Rabin (); Simon (); Trope and Liberman (); and Tverskyand Kahneman ().

    5 The reason for using the term appear becomes evident in Sect. ..

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    7/26

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    8/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    Table 8.4.Allais questions reformulated as a lotteryover lotteries

    Option State of the world

    1% 10% 89%

    O1 Lottery I Lottery I 1 millionO2 Lottery II Lottery II 1 million

    O1 Lottery I Lottery I 0O2 Lottery II Lottery II 0

    This effect of problem description on the Allais task is profound. Conlisk ()showed that the paradox practically goes away if the problem is described as a

    lottery over lotteries. He first informed respondents of two available lotteries:

    Lottery I: Certainty ofmillion

    Lottery II: /chance of nothing;/chance ofmillion

    He then asked them to make the standard Allais choices, now described as a lottery

    over these lotteries. These choices are depicted, in state form, in Table .. There

    were no longer any systematicpreference reversals, and the same proportion of

    people chose O1over O2as O

    1over O

    2 .

    If the Allais paradox can be eliminated this way, it might seem that the prob-

    lem has disappeared. Perhaps it arises only when we choose the wrong way toformulate the problem, and when we find the right wayone that does not bam-

    boozle the respondent with irrelevant detail, or induce them to misrepresent the

    problem in their mindtheir true preferences are revealed. Some variant on this

    viewpoint has been proposed by many researchers, and the debate continues (e.g.

    Binmore ). I will point out two objections to this defense of the rationality

    conditions.

    First, merely because preferences can change, and even become consistent

    through choice redescription, does not mean that these now consistent preferences

    are the agents true preferences, and that the inconsistent preferences were counter-

    feit. Using the spotlight metaphor helps. Each form of the Allais question is a spot-

    light that highlights some aspects of the question and produces corresponding pref-erences. Two spotlights can produce the same preferences because they highlight the

    same aspects of the question, or because, while they highlight different aspects, they

    both produce the same preference ordering. From a theoretical perspective, there

    7 A third issue, deliberately avoided in this chapter, is that merely because choices are consistentdoes not mean that they are optimal from an instrumental point of view. An agent can consistently

    choose options that are worse for him over those that are better (some discussion: Sugden ; Read).

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    9/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    is an inferential asymmetrywhile inconsistency in one context demonstrates the

    operation of the spotlight, consistency in another context does not demonstrate

    that it is not operating.

    The second objection to the defense invokes a theme that will be present through-

    out the remainder of this chapter. The fact that preferences vary as a function of

    choice description might be a greater challenge to the rationality conditions than

    any local violation of those conditions. If I simultaneously prefer O 1to O2, and O

    2

    to O1 it is bad enough, but if I also sometimes prefer O

    1 to O

    2 and/or O2 to O1I am doing more than just violating the independence condition, and I am prime

    material for money pumps and Dutch Books. This point has led many researchers

    to propose a further rationality condition that is perhaps more fundamental than

    the original conditions themselves:

    Invariance: Preferences do not depend upon irrelevantaspects of the context, of

    the option descriptions, or of the procedures used to elicit those preferences.

    An alternative way of putting this is that the rationality conditions are defined

    over the consequences of options and the states under which they occur, and not

    over how those options are described or how preferences are obtained. The key

    word in the definition is irrelevant, and this word could bring an uncomfortably

    subjective element to the rationality conditions. Since every preference reversal is

    a consequence ofsome variation in the options, we must then decide whether a

    difference is relevant or not.

    To illustrate the problem, while most might agree that Conlisks two versions of

    the Allais paradox should not have yielded different preferences, it is not obviousthat the differences between the two original choice pairs are irrelevant in this way.

    Loomes and Sugden (; see also Bell) proposed that one way the two pairs

    might differ is in the degree of regret the respondent anticipates if he does badly. In

    the first pair, choosing O2 and ending up with nothing could produce great regret

    because the agent will know with certainty that she would have had $ million if

    she had chosen differently. To avoid this regret, she might choose O1. In the second

    pair, however, choosing O2 and ending up with nothing does not lead to much

    regret because you doubt that you would have got anything anyway. Perhaps this

    is a good explanation of the Allais paradox, and it does rescue the rationality

    conditions. But similar justifications may not be available in every case. It is a

    major challenge to determine whether a given difference between options does ordoes not justify the resultant variation in preference. If invariance is not obviously

    followed, and if we permit some at-first-glance irrelevant variations in the task to

    be rationalized using a method like the one just described, then deciding whether

    the rationality conditions are being met becomes a matter for judgement. We will

    8 Anands discussion of intransitivity in Ch. above and elsewhere (Anand ) involves a closeexamination of what differences are relevant in the context of intransitive choice.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    10/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    return, inevitably, to this question once we have seen more apparent violations of

    the principle of invariance.

    The Allais paradox is noteworthy because, for many people at least, the rational-

    ity of their paradoxical choices is compelling even after reflection. It is difficult

    to persuade people that the differences between the two choice tasks are in fact

    irrelevant (Slovic and Tversky), a fact that will be well known to anyone who

    uses them in teaching. The preference reversals discussed next are more like those

    observed in comparisons between Conlisks different ways of describing the same

    problem. The fact that there is a problem is obvious, and most people will feel that

    something about the preference pattern needs to be explained.

    . C M O E

    ..........................................................................................................................................

    If preferences for options that we agree are exactly the samechange systematically in

    response to apparently irrelevant changes in circumstances, then we have a prima

    facie case for violations of invariance and decidability. Of the many ways to elicit

    such preference changes, perhaps the most venerable and reliable is through chang-

    ing the valuation procedure. For instance, we can ask people to choose between

    pairs of options, to reject one option from a pair, to rank several options, to assign avalue to them, or to otherwise specify an option that is equivalent to another option.

    It turns out that preferences are systematically influenced by all these procedures,

    and others as well. Simply stating your preferences in one way versus another seems

    to direct the spotlight on different reasons for having those preferences, and thus

    change the preferences altogether.

    The term preference reversal was coined by Lichtenstein and Slovic ()

    to describe a systematic discrepancy between choice and pricing. They offered

    respondents a choice between gambles, and later asked them to price each gamble

    separately. One gamble in each pair offered a high probability of winning a small

    prize (the so-called P-bet, e.g. apercent chance of winning $.and apercent

    chance of losing $.), the other offered a moderate probability of winning a largerprize (the$-bet, e.g. a percent chance of winning $., a percent chance of

    losing $.). There were many preference reversals, with the P-bet being chosen

    more often than the$-bet, but the$-bet being priced higher. This was a very strong

    effect: in their first experiment, percent of respondents always put a lower price

    on a P-bet they had chosen than on a $-bet they had not chosen. Lichtenstein

    and Slovic () replicated this with gamblers in Las Vegas, and, in a later pa-

    per, Grether and Plott () imposed all the controls available to experimental

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    11/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    economics (such as greater task transparency and the use of real monetary incen-

    tives) and replicated Lichtenstein and Slovics results almost exactly.

    An appealing explanation for preference reversals is that they arise from what

    Tversky, Sattath, and Slovic () called compatibility effects. When values are

    expressed on a quantitative dimension (such as price), they are disproportionately

    influenced by information in the same or similar currency to that dimension.

    When pricing a gamble, for instance, the price put on it will be highly influenced

    by the potential payoffs. Hence, the $-bet gets a higher price than the P-bet.

    Compatibility effects can be viewed as one instantiation of the anchoring-and-

    adjustment heuristic, by which quantities are estimated by starting with an available

    estimate (even an arbitrary one), and then incompletely adjusting that estimate in

    the appropriate direction based on other information. When pricing a gamble, the

    logical starting point is the prize to be won, which is then adjusted downward basedon the probability of that prize. The insufficient adjustment leads the$-gamble to

    be overpriced.

    These classic preference reversals are a special case of a systematic difference

    in preferences elicited under choiceand matching. Matching is the procedure, like

    pricing, in which one option is given (e.g. a gamble) and the respondent specifies

    another option equivalent in value to the first (e.g. a price). Tversky, Sattath,

    and Slovic () showed this using a series of questions such as the following

    (p.):

    About people are killed each year in Israel in traffic accidents. The ministry of trans-

    portation investigates various programs to reduce the number of casualties. Consider thefollowing two programs, described in terms of yearly costs (in millions of dollars) and

    the number of casualties per year that is expected following the implementation of each

    program:

    Expected casualties Cost

    Program X $million

    Program Y $million

    (Notice that in this problem the future states are not given explicitly, as in the

    Savage table, but rather given as a summary of consequences multiplied by their

    probability and summed over all possible states.) One group chose between the

    two programs, while another group (theImplicit choicegroup) saw the matrix with

    one value missing, which they then completed to make the two programs equal in

    9 Grether and Plott () also provided evidence about whether people will spontaneously recog-nize inconsistencies. Their respondents first priced several items, then immediately made a set of

    choices, and then priced the remaining items. The likelihood of a preference reversal was not in-fluenced by whether choice preceded pricing or pricing preceded choice, suggesting that the choiceinconsistency was not noticed. Lichtenstein and Slovic had deliberately separated their two tasks bysome time and with a lot of filler tasks,presumably because they were concerned that their respondents

    would strive to be consistent. Grether and Plotts research suggests that inconsistencies must be veryobvious for them to be noticed.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    12/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    value. To see how the responses were compared, imagine someone who has chosen

    Program X, implying they would be willing to pay $million to save seventy lives.

    Now, suppose she is asked to complete the matrix below:

    Option Expected casualties Cost

    Program X ??

    Program Y $million

    For choice and implicit choice to be consistent, the value specified should be no

    less than $million, otherwise she would prefer Program Y. For each blank, there

    is a similar range of values consistent with a choice of X over Y (e.g. casualties in

    Program X can be no more than , and so on), and values outside of this range

    indicate an inconsistency. In fact, for this particular question Tverskyet al. ()

    found that percent of the direct choices were for Program X, as compared withonlypercent of the implicit choices.

    In general, Tverskyet al. () observed many more direct choices of the option

    superior on the primary dimension, meaning the dimension that people view as

    most important. In the Israeli traffic example, the primary dimension is the number

    of lives that can be saved. Although choice can be made using lexicographic proce-

    dures, such as choosing the option superior on the most important dimension,

    matching cannot. Matching demands an explicit tradeoffbetween option features.

    For instance, in the above example it is possible to choose Program X using the

    lexicographic rule that life has no value. But in matching, this rule would imply

    an infinite cost for Program X.

    A further example of preference reversals resulting from differing valuation pro-cedures is the comparison between choice and ranking, reported by Bateman, Day,

    Loomes, and Sugden (). They conducted a study testing Allais-type prefer-

    ences, like those above but with some modifications. Respondents either chose

    between several pairs of gambles, or else rank-ordered all the gambles contained in

    the pairs. They found that Allais-type preferences were common in choice (repli-

    cating earlier studies), but not in ranking. Ranking did not eliminate all apparent

    irrationalities, however, and actually increased the rate at which another rationality

    condition, betweenness (a derivation of those already given), was violated. Bateman

    et al. give a theoretical explanation for their finding, but for our purposes the most

    important result is that two theoretically interchangeable measurement procedures

    yield strikingly different results.One important difference between binary choice and ranking is in the number

    of options on the table. In binary choice there are two, while in ranking there are

    three or more, so that even if the agent focuses exclusively on the preference order

    10 They tested thecommon ratio effect, an extension of the original Allais task. The finding is thatif a person is indifferent between two lotteries, one riskier than the other, then they will prefer the

    riskier of the two if all the probabilities in the two lotteries are scaled down through multiplication bya common positive constant< 1.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    13/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    between O1 and O2, there is at least an O3 to which both options can be com-

    pared. It turns out that another source of violations of the rationality conditions is

    that preference order depends even on options that are never chosen.

    . IM O CS

    ..........................................................................................................................................

    A seemingly trivial implication of the rationality conditions is that if an additional

    option is taken into consideration, it will not influence the relative value of those

    already there. That is, if O1 is preferred to O2, and O3 is then made available,

    the only permissible rankings of the three options are those that maintain the

    preference of O2over O3. For example, to take the example from Table., suppose

    you are planning not to take your umbrella today, but then somebody reminds you

    that you could take a raincoat instead; this should not make you decide to take your

    umbrella. This follows both from the Decidability and Transitivity conditions, and

    is sometimes called theindependence of irrelevant alternatives.

    Batemanet al.s () comparison between ranking and choice, however, sug-

    gests that this might not always be true. For ranking and choice to di ffer, it must be

    that sometimes O1 is preferred to O2in binary choice, while O2is preferred to O1when additional options are on the table. It will not surprise the reader, therefore,

    to learn that it is easy to construct scenarios in which many people choose O1from

    the set {O1, O2} and then switch to O2when given the set {O1, O2, O3}.

    One robust set of such context effects will be explained with the aid of Figure..

    It depicts factors that might influence the choice between O1and O2, two options

    that vary on two dimensions, with higher values on the dimensions corresponding

    to improvement. The dimensions could be payoffand probability, price and quality,

    or anything. In addition to O1 and O2, two further options are depicted, labeled

    D and E for dominatedand extreme. D is dominated by O1 but not by O2; E is

    an extreme item that is better than B on one dimension, and worse than B on

    the other. Examples of such items are gambles like the following (e.g. Wedell ;

    Herne):

    O1: percent chance of $

    O2: percent chance of $

    D(O3): percent chance of $

    E(O4): percent chance of $

    There are two effects of adding the third item, either D or E. The first is the usual

    substitution effect, in which some people choose the added option rather than

    one of the original pair. Of course, this does not often happen with D, since it is

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    14/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    E: O4

    D: O3

    O1

    O2

    Dimension 1

    Dimension2

    Fig. 8.1. Adding additional items to a choice set.

    dominated by O2. The second effect is that peoples preferences among the original

    choice pair changes, with choices of O1 switching to choices of O2. The effect of

    adding D is called theasymmetric dominance effect (and sometimes the attraction

    effect), and the effect of adding E is called the compromise effect (sometimes ex-

    tremeness aversion).The labels D and E come from the proposed locus of the spotlight effect. The

    idea is that one way people determine what they prefer is by thinking of reasons

    for having the preference. The reasons are justifications elicited by the context,

    and different contexts elicit different justifications (e.g. Simonson ; Shafir,

    Simonson, and Tversky). For these options, adding a new item gives an addi-

    tional reason for choosing O2over O1which can overturn the preference expressed

    without the new item. The new reason is that O2is clearly better than D, or that it

    is a compromise between the two extremes O1 and E. The role of reasons can be

    imagined by thinking of what someone would have to do to justify their choice to

    someonethey could say, for instance, that Gamble O2is a compromise between

    the boring O1 and the too-risky E. This, however, is a contingent argument. Ifthe added option had been different, one that instead made O1 the compromise

    candidate, matters would be quite different.

    The number of options has also been shown to matter in investigations ofjoint

    versusseparate evaluation (Hsee ). In joint evaluation, the menu consists of

    11 The original reports of these effects were in studies of consumer behavior. Huber, Payne, and

    Puto () first described the asymmetric dominance effect, and Simonson () the compromiseeffect.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    15/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    several items, so that people are able to make direct comparisons during evaluation.

    In separate evaluation, however, they are evaluated one at a time. The original

    preference reversal studies of Lichtenstein and Slovic are one example of such a

    situation, but in those studies the evaluation procedure (choice versus pricing)

    was confounded with whether there were one or two gambles (corresponding to

    separate and joint evaluation) being evaluated. It turns out, however, that even

    when the valuation procedure is held constant, joint and separate evaluation can

    produce different preferences. A compelling example, because it involved real-

    world transactions and real money, was described by List (), who replicated

    the method and manipulations of Hsee () with dealers and collectors at a sports

    card show. Lists participants were invited to bid on one or both of two sets of

    sports cards. The inferiorset contained ten high-quality (near-mint) cards, while

    thesuperiorset contained thirteen cards, including the ten high-quality cards plusthree low-quality cards. The estimated true market price of the superior set was

    about $ higher than that of the inferior set. There were three groups: one group

    bid separately on the inferior set, another bid on the superior set, and a third bid

    on both. The result was that during separate evaluation, both dealers and collectors

    (but especially collectors) bid more for the inferior set of cards, but during joint

    evaluation they both bid more for the superior set.

    Hsees () argument, reflecting a recurring theme, is that option features vary

    in the degree to which they can be easily evaluated in isolation, and those features

    that are difficult to evaluate will show a disproportionate increase in importance

    during joint evaluation. The traders put too little weight on the numberof cards

    when looking at only one set, while the poor quality of some of those cards is verysalient when looking at the superior set. Lists study shows just how easy it is to find

    features that are difficult to evaluate in isolation.

    . D O D W

    ..........................................................................................................................................

    In the previous sections, there were some differences between situations that pro-

    duced preference reversals. Either the evaluation method or the context was altered.

    12 The fact the asymmetry was smaller among dealers points to the importance of learning andexperience in the application of rational choice theory. Binmore (e.g. , pp. ) argues thatrational choice theory is applicable only to situations in which the conditions are favorable, and

    specifically that there is a good deal of evidence that adequately motivated people sometimes canand do learn to choose rationally if they are put in similar situations repeatedly and provided withmeaningful feedback on the outcome of their previous decisions.

    13 A robust finding is that people are quite insensitive to scopeof a good when placing a value on it(Frederick and Fischhoff ).

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    16/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    No such differences are actually required to produce preference reversals. Even

    seemingly modest redescriptions of options can accomplish the task, as demon-

    strated by the widely cited Asian disease problem of Tversky and Kahneman

    (). Their respondents chose between two medical responses to an epidemic that,

    in the absence of some response, would certainly kill people. In one version

    (they called this the loss frame) respondents chose between deaths for sure

    and a one third chance ofdeaths, and a two thirds chance of no deaths. In

    the second version (the gain frame) they chose between saving lives for sure

    and a one third chance of saving everybody, and a two thirds chance of saving

    nobody. A majority prefer to save lives for sure in the gain frame, but to take

    a chance of saving no one in the hope of saving all in the loss frame. Although

    when presented together, the two choices are transparently the same, the different

    descriptions highlight different features of the options.Kahneman and Tversky attributed this result to a general pattern of risk seeking

    for losses and risk avoidance for gains. A further demonstration of this produced

    one of the most striking examples of how relatively modest variations in problem

    description can lead to changes in preference. Kahneman and Tversky () asked

    separate groups to make the following choices:

    Group The following two gambles will be enacted simultaneously. Choose one

    from (a), and one from (b)

    (a) Choose between:

    A) Win $

    B) % chance to win $;% chance to win nothing

    (b) Choose between:

    C) Lose $

    D) % chance to lose $;

    % chance to lose nothing

    Group Choose between:

    A) % chance to win $;

    % chance to lose $

    B) % chance to win $

    % chance to lose $.The pair most frequently chosen by Group was {A, D}about percent of

    people chose this combinationwhile for Group everyone chose B. The latter

    is not surprising, sinceA stochastically dominates B. However, ifA andD are

    combined, it can be seen that theyareoptionA, while combiningB andC is the

    14 It doesnt matter whether the same group or different groups do the taskthe results are

    identical. I have used this problem in classes for many years, and these within-respondent results areinvariably indistinguishable from those reported by Kahneman and Tversky ().

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    17/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    dominantB. Kahneman and Tversky explain this using the same analysis as used

    for the Asian disease problem. The Group(a) question is in the domain of gains

    and leads to risk avoidance, while the Group (b) question is in the domain of losses

    and leads to risk seeking.

    There are three important features of responses to these questions. First, they

    demonstrate how we evaluate outcomes from the perspective of a reference point

    (i.e. as losses or gains) and that the reference point is highly malleable. Second, we

    see a violation of (stochastic) dominance, so that unlike most systematic variations

    in preference, including those described earlier, not only do people have different

    preferences under different circumstances, but it is obvious when they are making

    a mistake.

    But the most important lesson from these questions is that it demonstrates

    the central feature of the attentional spotlight. The choice of { A, D} shows thatrespondents failed to integrate their chosen options into a portfolio, but rather

    treated them as separate options, as if each choice they were making was the only

    one they would ever have to make. And they did this despite the fact that the

    two gambles were explicitly described as being enacted simultaneously and were

    given one after the other. Very similar results, often involving quite astonishing

    degrees of isolation, have been described by Redelmeier and Tversky ( ) and

    others (e.g. McCafferey and Baron; for a review and more examples see Read,

    Loewenstein, and Rabin).

    Although I earlier described the Allais paradox as a case in which the conse-

    quences were changed, but in a way that is irrelevant to the rationality conditions,

    the above result might lead us to reconsider this conclusion. Perhaps the differencein consequences between the two Allais questions is itself an illusion due to the

    operation of the spotlight. Consider the following variant of the Allais problem,

    itself adapted from one of Conlisks () variations. This shows the second pair of

    Allais options (O1and O

    2) transformed into a two-stage game.

    The decision-maker has a ticket numbered between 1 andbut does not know

    which. If the number is between and he gets nothing, but if it is between

    and he has a chance of a prize, with the chance depending on whether he chooses

    O1or O

    2. Consider two occasions on which he can make this choice, either at CN1(choice node ) or at CN2. If he chooses at CN1 he will probably choose O

    1 , as

    /people did in Conlisks study. On the other hand, if he chooses at CN 2, he

    is now much more likely to choose O2, as/did in Conlisks study. The rateof systematic preference change will be very high.

    It is difficult to rationalize this. Anyone faced with a decision like that at CN2will have come to that point by way of a series of choices and accidents, like those

    at CN1, that were not guaranteed to achieve that choice point. This uncertainty

    is represented by a single chance node in Figure ., but in reality it would be a

    15 John Conlisk kindly provided these data which were not included in hispaper.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    18/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    CN 1

    CN

    11--100

    1--10

    1--10

    1--9

    10 0

    0

    1 million

    5 million

    A2

    A1

    CN1

    CN2

    Fig. 8.2. Sequential Allais decisions.

    multiplicity of chance occurrencesfor instance, after years of struggle an entre-

    preneur has the opportunity to sell out for a big killing, or to take a chance by

    continuing with the chance of an even bigger killing or failing altogether. If the

    entrepreneur was required to decide before he knew he would get to that stage (at

    the equivalent of CN1) he would very likely make different and more risk-seeking

    decisions than if he decided afterwards (CN2).

    This is a very general pattern. Whenever we are faced with a choice, the fact that

    we have that choice at all is contingent on events that might not have occurred.

    Consequently, if we had decided in advance, based on the compounded expecta-tions in which many consequences along with their probabilities or uncertainties

    were combined, we would have made different decisions than if we decide based on

    the local returns.

    The framing effects just described work because people do not consider infor-

    mation or consequences that are not explicitly included in the frame they have

    been given. They either put too little weight on unspoken consequences (as in the

    lives saved or lost in the Asian disease problem), or do not combine sequences of

    outcomes and uncertainties into composite or portfolio prospects. The effects of

    framing can result from even more subtle manipulations. One such manipulation is

    simply to divide states into increasing numbers of categories (e.g. Fischhoff, Slovic,

    and Lichtenstein ; Fox and Clemen ). I will describe one example of this,which Starmer and Sugden () call event-splitting.

    Starmer and Sugden offered people a choice between lotteries. The respondent

    could draw a lottery ticket from a pool, and would win a prize contingent on the

    number that came up (the state of the world) and the option they had chosen.

    The choices were described using a strip display, a way of indicating separately,

    for each ticket number, what the outcomes will be for each option. This allowed

    the researchers either to combine or to divide ranges of states that yielded the

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    19/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    1--15 16--30 31--100

    1--30 31--100

    State (Ticket)

    State (Ticket)

    O1

    O1 $100

    $100$100 0

    0

    Fig. 8.3. Two strip displays like those used in the event-splitting study of Starmerand Sugden (1993).

    same outcome. An example of two strip displays for the same option is given in

    Figure .. Observe that O1and O2are identical, except that in O1the numbers

    are divided into two states.

    Starmer and Sugden obtained choices between lotteries like O1 and a standard

    lottery, and lotteries like O1 and the same standard lottery. The standard lotteries

    were always described in the same way. Since O1and O

    1are formally identical, the

    same proportion of people should have preferred them to the standard, otherwise

    this would imply that one of two identical options is preferred to the other. Infact, the option, like O1, for which the state space for the most attractive out-

    come was subdivided, was typically preferred to the one in which that space was

    undivided.

    Starmer and Sugdens result, along with an abundance of related findings, show

    that the weight we put on information is highly dependent on how closely we

    scrutinize it. We can return to our example of the decision about whether to

    take an umbrella when it rains. What this result suggests is that if we divided

    the state Rain into the two states Some rain but no more than centime-

    ters, and More than centimeters we would then be more likely to take that

    umbrella.

    16 This point is made briefly, but the central problem is related to one raised by Luce and Raiffa

    (). Suppose we have complete ignorance about which state of the world obtains. The principleof insufficient reason then dictates that we should treat each state as equally likely. But given that thestates about which we areignorant can be divided and combined in variousways, each equally sensible,it follows that the principle of insufficient reason will dictate different probability distributions over

    the same states. It turns out that people are prone to the bias that might be expected from such a naveapplication of this principle (Fox and Clemen ).

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    20/26

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    21/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    The collapsing of grand worlds into small worlds has obvious parallels with the

    process of shining a spotlight on certain aspects of the world and ignoring others.

    When deciding whether to take an umbrella to work, for instance, it is natural

    to focus on states relevant to the decision (e.g. Rain versus No rain), and on

    consequences relevant to the use of umbrellas (Will I get wet or not?), but to

    ignore everything else. This can be described as the formulation of a small world,

    or as the deployment of the attentional spotlight.

    But if the grand world can be collapsed into different (and not necessarily even

    nested) small worlds, this raises the question ofwhichsmall worlds the rationality

    conditions should apply to. One possible view is that as long as the conditions hold

    over any small world, they are satisfied. For instance, if the small world of Table .

    accurately describes how a decision-maker thinks of the problem at the moment of

    choice, then so long as he takes his umbrella, the conditions are satisfied. If changesin the evaluation circumstances change the small world inanyway, the rationality

    conditions should then be reapplied to this new situation. From this perspective,

    the rationality conditions are not definitely violated by any of the studies described

    above, and perhaps they never can be. It is unlikely that many knowingly and delib-

    erately choose to violate these conditions when their applicability is obvious, and

    if their applicability is not obvious, then no violation is possible. We can illustrate

    this point by referring back to Kahneman and Tverskys two-stage question from

    Section .. If the small world to which the rationality conditions are intended to

    apply is at the level of the question (i.e. the Group (a) and Group questions

    taken separately), then no individual choice can violate those conditions, and no

    choicepatternis even relevant, since it is a pattern formed by combining separateand independent small worlds. Likewise, the apparent inconsistency between the

    choices by Groups and is not relevant to the rationality conditions because it also

    involves comparisons between different small worlds. Finally, when, as in Group ,

    the small world involves a clear opportunity to violate a rationality condition (in

    this case stochastic dominance), nobody does so.

    Many will feel that so stripping the rationality conditions of their content is

    an unsatisfactory way to shield them from refutation. Savage did not propose

    this, and in fact provided a more restricted description of the small worlds to

    which the rationality conditions should apply. He focused on what he called real

    microcosms, which are small worlds that locally satisfy the rationality conditions (as

    in, the decision-maker takes the umbrella given Table.) but, in addition: (a) theprobabilities of states are the same in the small world as in the grand world, and (b)

    the utility of options is the same in the small world and the grand world (see Savage

    , p.). A small world that meets the rationality conditions internally but does

    not satisfy these additional requirements is, in Savages own words, a pseudo-

    microcosm that is not a real microcosm. He was, as the following passage shows,

    optimistic that the rationality conditions were applicable to circumstances beyond

    that of the small world: I feel, if I may be allowed to say so, that the possibility of

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    22/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    being taken in by a pseudo-microcosm that is not a real microcosm is remote, but

    the difficulty I find in defining an operationally applicable criterion is, to say the

    least, ground for caution (Savage, p.).

    The reason for Savages optimism is the psychologicalpremise, which he shares

    with many researchers who come to behavioral studies from the discipline of

    economics, that while someone might initially be misled by a small world, they

    will eventually settle on a real microcosm when they have time to reflect on their

    preferences. Savage illustrates this with the following example: A man buying a car

    for $.is tempted to order it with a radio installed, which will bring the total

    price to $., feeling that the difference is trifling. But when he reflects that, if

    he already had the car, he certainly would not spend $. for a radio for it, he

    realizes that he has made an error (p. ).

    Savages intuition that an expensive radio might be chosen when its price is addedto the sticker price of a car, but not when it is seen in isolation, is undoubtedly

    correct. But Savage presumes that the man changes his mind because he has

    made an error which is now corrected. But there is nothing in the rationality

    conditions themselves that shows that either option is the correct one (cf. Shafer

    , for a related discussion of the same passage from Savage).

    The difference between the small world and the spotlight viewpoints revolves

    around the question of whether or not reframing a decision moves the decision-

    maker towards a real microcosm. According to the small-world view, this is what

    happens. We can see this reflected not only in the above passage, but more forcefully

    yet in Savages reevaluation of his own preferences following his mistake when

    answering Allaiss question (see n. ). According to the spotlight view, however,while rethinking highlights different aspects of choice, the changed preferences

    are not necessarily correct or even better than those they have replaced. Rather,

    they are determined by the path taken by the process of thinking and rethinking.

    Moreover, since most people are like Savage, in that they do wish to maintain

    consistency in their preferences, even local conformity to the rationality conditions

    does not indicate that we have located a real microcosm, since a di fferent path of

    thinking could have led to different preferences that conformed equally well to those

    conditions.

    To illustrate this, consider a case of intransitive preference. It is rare to find

    situations in which people openly state that they simultaneously prefer A to B, B to

    C, and C to A. Indeed, experimentalists traditionally separate questions with filleritems so that respondents will not realize they are making a mistake. According

    to the small-world view, if we give an agent the three pairwise choices, he or

    she will eventually work out the correctpreference ordering for the three options.

    According to the spotlight view, on the other hand, the final preferences of this

    18 This passage, like many of Savages examples, inspired an extensive and ongoing research pro-gram, starting with Tversky and Kahneman ().

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    23/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    agent will depend on the order in which the choices are presented. If we start with

    the choice between C and A, then we will end up with the preference order CAB,

    while if we start with the choice between A and B, we will end up with the order

    ABC.

    This phenomenon was characterized ascoherent arbitrarinessby Ariely, Loewen-

    stein, and Prelec (, ), who investigated it with a series of clever exper-

    iments. In one study, people first stated how much they were willing to pay for

    an item, such as an average bottle of wine. The situation was engineered so that

    some would give higher prices than others, by first asking respondents whether

    they would pay a dollar amount equal to the last two digits of their social security

    number, and then to state their maximum willingness to pay. This naturally resulted

    in a strong anchoring effect, with people willing to paymuch more when their social

    security number ended with a high number than a low one. The prices they gaveto other goods were also consistent with these initial prices. Everyone, for example,

    was willing to pay more for a fancy bottle of wine than for an average one. But

    because the average bottle was so overpriced in the high number condition, the

    expensive bottle was correspondingly overpriced. The preferences were consistent,

    but based on an arbitrary starting point.

    The same authors, indeed, later showed that even whether an activity was posi-

    tive, so that one should pay to do it, or negative, so that one should pay not to do it,

    depends on apparently trivial features of the decision context, and that once this is

    decided, people will be consistent with that judgment. In their study, people asked

    how much they would pay to hear Ariely read from Walt WhitmansLeaves of Grass

    would pay more to enjoy a longer reading, while a matched group asked how muchthey would have to be paid to hear him required more if they had toendurea longer

    reading (Ariely, Loewenstein, and Prelec ).

    Research like Arielyet al.s provides a good place to conclude this survey, because

    it both demonstrates the ultimate implications of the spotlight view and raises

    other issues about rationality to which I will only allude. In this chapter I have

    deliberately restricted my focus to the question of whether preferences do, in any

    meaningful way, conform to rationality conditions like Savages. The experimental

    evidence reviewed gave scant support to the view that the rationality conditions are

    adhered to. Instead, preferences shift dramatically as we change the circumstances

    in which they are to be expressed. I likened this to the operation of a spotlight,

    where each new circumstance highlights a restricted subset of task features andleads to the creation of a correspondingly restricted (and distorted) representation

    19 This is the primary reason why we do not expect individuals to be transformed into moneypumps by repeating the same choices. Even if a person can be found to have a cycle of preferences,they will refuse to engage in a transparent cycle of transactions. But as Rabin and Thaler () haveobserved, this does not mean that we cannot create money pumps across people. If we can identify

    situations in which the majority of people have a cyclical preference and different endowments, we canbe sure to earn money by offering a single trade to each person.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    24/26

    -Anand-c OUP-Anand (Typeset by SPi, Delhi) of December, :

    of the world. This representation is not, except accidentally, coordinated with other

    representations that we would have adopted if the spotlight had been di fferent.

    In Savages words, the spotlight directs us to a pseudo-microcosm that is not a

    real microcosm. I have not unconsidered the problem of whether rationality can

    and should be identified with some degree oflocalconformity to the rationality

    conditions. That is, given that in the broad sense we are inevitably inconsistent, is

    it nonetheless better to be consistent as far as we can be? No evidence is available to

    answer this question. Arielyet al. show some ways in which local consistency can

    lead to error, but they have not shown (or tried to show) that inconsistency would

    lead tolesserror. To answer this question, we need different criteria for rationality

    than the conditions of Savage or von Neumann and Morgenstern, criteria which

    can rank choices as good or bad, so that we can know whether we are more or

    less likely to choose the good options when we are consistent or when we areinconsistent.

    R

    A, M. (). Le comportement de lhomme rationnel devant le risque: critique des

    postulats et axioms de lcole Amricaine. Econometrica,,.

    AP. (). The Philosophy of Intransitive Preference. Economic Journal,,.

    A, D., L, G., and P, D. (). Coherent Arbitrariness: Stable De-

    mand Curves without Stable Preferences. Quarterly Journal of Economics,,.

    (). Tom Sawyer and the Construction of Value. Journal of Economic

    Behavior and Organization,,.

    B, A., D, B., L, G., and S, R. (). Ranking versus Choice in the

    Elicitation of Preferences. Working Paper, University of East Anglia.

    B, D. (). Regret in Decision Making under Uncertainty.Operations Research, ,

    .

    B, K. ().Rational Decisions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    C, K R., and B, N P. (). Visuo-spatial Attention: Beyond a Spotlight

    Model.Psychonomic Bulletin and Review,/,.

    C, J. (). Three Variants on the Allais Example.American Economic Review, ,

    .

    E, D. (). Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms. Quarterly Journal of

    Economics,,.F, B., S, P., and L, S. (). Fault Trees: Sensitivity of Estimated

    Failure Probabilities to Problem Representation.Journal of Experimental Psychology: Hu-

    man Perception and Performance,,.

    F, C., and C, R. T. (). Subjective Probability Assessment in Decision Analysis:

    Partition Dependence and Bias Toward the Ignorance Prior. Management Science, ,

    .

    F, S., and F, B. (). Scope (In)Sensitivity in Elicited Valuations. Risk,

    Decision, and Policy,,.

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    25/26

  • 8/12/2019 Experimental Tests of Rationality

    26/26