12
This article was downloaded by: [University of Toronto Libraries] On: 14 April 2014, At: 07:30 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Word & Image: A Journal of Verbal/Visual Enquiry Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/twim20 Drawing out a new image of thought: Anne Carson's radical ekphrasis Monique Tschofen Published online: 11 Jul 2013. To cite this article: Monique Tschofen (2013) Drawing out a new image of thought: Anne Carson's radical ekphrasis, Word & Image: A Journal of Verbal/Visual Enquiry, 29:2, 233-243, DOI: 10.1080/02666286.2013.794916 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02666286.2013.794916 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http:// www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

Drawing Out a New Image of Thought: Anne Carson's Radical Ekphrasis

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • This article was downloaded by: [University of Toronto Libraries]On: 14 April 2014, At: 07:30Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Word & Image: A Journal of Verbal/Visual EnquiryPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/twim20

    Drawing out a new image of thought: Anne Carson'sradical ekphrasisMonique TschofenPublished online: 11 Jul 2013.

    To cite this article: Monique Tschofen (2013) Drawing out a new image of thought: Anne Carson's radical ekphrasis, Word &Image: A Journal of Verbal/Visual Enquiry, 29:2, 233-243, DOI: 10.1080/02666286.2013.794916

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02666286.2013.794916

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the Content) containedin the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make norepresentations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of theContent. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, andare not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon andshould be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable forany losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoeveror howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use ofthe Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematicreproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in anyform to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

  • Drawing out a new image of thought: Anne Carsonsradical ekphrasisMONIQUE TSCHOFEN

    To think is to create there is no other creation but to

    create is first of all to engender thinking in thought.1

    [A] poem, when it works, is an action of themind captured on a

    page, and a reader, when he engages it repeats that action but it is a movement through a thought, through anactivity of thinking, so by the time you get to the end youre

    different than you were at the beginning and you feel that

    difference.2

    In 1988, the artist Betty Goodwin was reading books about the

    Stalinist purges alongside the poems of Carolyn Forch aboutLatin American dictatorships when she began a series of

    drawings she titled the Seated Figures that addressed the

    history of forced disappearances, torture, and other state-

    perpetuated atrocities.3 Her images of interrogation hauntingly

    conjure human degradation and suffering. What makes her

    work important is that her treatment of interrogation is not

    merely thematic. She develops a language of formal elements

    such as lines, folds, and angles that, together, draw attention to a

    visual technique perspective that pictures the world as an

    objective structure to be represented with certainty through

    rational methods. Perspective, it has been argued, creates

    distance between the viewing subject and the object. In its

    static frame, it crystallizes fluid processes. Goodwin thus links

    her works thematic depiction of the dehumanizing practice of

    political interrogation to the larger epistemology it relies upon

    by drawing attention to a style of arts mediating role in the

    subjectobject split, and then subverting its aesthetic regime.

    In a poem titled Seated Figure with Red Angle (1988) by Betty

    Goodwin, Anne Carson responds to one of the drawings from

    Goodwins Seated Figure series.4 Torture is not an overt theme in

    Carsons poem but it remains central to the poems broader

    exploration of interrogation as a mode by which Western cul-

    ture has sought information through epistemological para-

    digms founded on conceptions of knowledge, truth, and

    certainty and expressed through representation based on resem-

    blance.5 Like Goodwin, Carson evokes and then refuses the

    grid-like structures of containment of syntax and sense. She

    also refuses to subject her words visual other to an interrogation

    by refusing to picture the picture; she will not frame, name, or

    make the image speak by representing it. Referring to the writ-

    ings of Antonin Artaud, Gilles Deleuze praises the capacity of art

    to offer a new image of thought.6 This article shows how, in

    refusing representation as its central operational mode, the

    poem reaches to the edge of the thinkable to demonstrate

    arts capacity to offer its own uncertain form of thinking that, in

    its dynamism, provisionality, and conditionality, brings into

    being that which does not yet exist.7 In so doing, her poem

    draws on and draws out interrelationships that heal the subject

    object split which Goodwins art evokes.

    It is important first to consider Goodwins image separately

    from Carsons thoughts about it. Produced after her well-known

    Carbon and Swimmer series, the drawing Seated Figure with

    Red Angle (1988) comes from a series of haunting seated figures

    such as Figure with Chair, No. 1 (1988), Hooded Figure with Chair

    (19881989), and Seated Figure with Chair and Pipe (1988). Together

    with works such as How Long Does it Take for One Voice to Reach

    Another (1988) and Bent Figure With Megaphone (1988), these draw-

    ings reduce the scene of torture to basic elements: a darkened

    figure, a chair, a light, and a room.8 If, as Elaine Scarry notes, a

    room typically represents the most benign potential of human

    life a miniaturization of civilization and its comforts the

    interrogation rooms in this series represent its annihilation in the

    form of a smudged white space emptied of the anchoring coor-

    dinates of dimension and depth.9 Rather than being represented

    in relation to their torturer, the figures are solitary and isolated.

    Goodwins figures faces are either covered with hoods or are

    smudged beyond recognition to reflect the extent of their degra-

    dation and dehumanization. Many of the figures bodies are

    hunched or bent over on themselves, and their limbs appear to

    be twisted or disconnected from the bodies. The seated figures

    are haunting images, pregnant with silence.

    The particular image from the Seated Figure series Carson takes

    up, Seated Figure with Red Angle (1988), is a drawing. Its medium is

    important because unlike painting, which in its dominant tradi-

    tion in the West from the Renaissance through to the modernist

    era has tended to appear bounded and finished, drawing is, to

    put it in the vernacular, sketchy. The kinds of surfaces one draws

    on are much less forgiving than canvas and retain traces of every

    gesture. On canvas, the brush traces obliteratively, while on

    paper, everything that is marked on the surface remains visi-

    ble.10 A drawing is often also a study and offers a means of entry

    into a problem. The knowledge that drawing seeks is thus

    exploratory rather than final; as Susan Stoops writes, by its

    own intrinsic nature, the process of drawing is one that acknowl-

    edges the conditional.11

    WORD & IMAGE, VOL. 29, NO. 2, APRILJUNE 2013 233http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02666286.2013.794916

    # 2013 Taylor & Francis

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • Goodwins drawing is a study of the abject. It is also a study of

    the connections between certain conventions of picturing the

    world and certain types of relationships fostered between subject

    and other. The figure is crowded in the middle of the page,

    surrounded by an overwhelming sea of white contaminated by

    traces, lines, gashes, erasures, and folds. A long straight black

    vertical line on the right side of the figure, extending from the

    shoulders to below the feet, anchors the grid of the drawing and

    gives the impression of a wall that presses in on the subject.

    Another group of lighter horizontal lines, or perhaps folds,

    intersect at roughly ninety degrees with the vertical and are

    disturbingly inscribed right through the figures head at the

    level where the eyes should be, obliterating the figures ability

    to see and to be seen as a person. These rectilinear lines a

    motif Goodwin uses throughout her work evoke the frame of

    a perspectival grid that artists sketch out to orient the space their

    image will inhabit.

    Perspective is a device through which the world is projected

    outward from the position of a spectator who is removed from

    the action. Often associated with Decartess rationalism and his

    search for ontological and epistemological certainty,12 the per-

    spectival grid has been argued by writers like Martin Jay to

    represent a technology of control, or, as Hubert Damisch puts

    it, a regulatory structure.13 The perspectival grid offers a way of

    mathematizing space so as to render objects realistically.

    While the grid functions as an invisible mechanism to represent

    the world objectively, it also objectifies that world. As Erwin

    Panofsky puts it, perspective creates distance between human

    beings and things.14 In the drawing, the presence of the grid

    connects perspectives mathematizing modes of abstraction,

    rationalist epistemologys purportedly objective knowledge,

    and the subjectobject ontology we have inherited from

    Descartes. The abstract grid thus links directly to the drawings

    stated theme, since interrogation (as torture) is a practice that

    materializes this epistemology.15

    However, the strength of this image has to do with the ways in

    which the grid is undermined and rendered impotent through a

    more complex and fluid spatial operation. The figure appears to

    occupy two separate planes at once, torqued around an invisible

    central turning point in a way that produces a disconnect

    between the upper and lower body. The figures legs do not

    belong to the same geometric plane as the torso and seem to be

    made of different matter; lighter and more translucent than the

    upper body, the legs give the impression that they are floating

    away. Via a delicate rupture of the fields of containment begot-

    ten by the principles of perspectivalism, Goodwins drawing

    transforms an abstracted static field into a dynamic unfolding.

    The logic of this alternate way of depicting spatial relationships

    is neither objective nor does it objectify.

    The red angle of the title of Betty Goodwins drawing hangs as

    an enigma. It is drawn forcefully and left unsmudged on the left

    side of the drawing, hovering away from the figure. Its angles

    teeter off the right angles of the grid, echoing instead the more

    organic angles of the shoulder, arm, and legs of the figures bent

    form. And yet, unlike the blood-like splotches of red on the hip

    and between the legs of the figure, the red angle firmly belongs

    to a different order than the human figure. It evokes, but is not, a

    gash in the skin of the paper. Resembling the other distresses on

    the surface of the work, the red angle transforms the flat and

    static fields of drawing into something that inscribes the work of

    arts dimensionality and unfolding in time. An abstract inscrip-

    tion of the materiality of drawing, of the trace of the hand, of the

    hidden depths art can make visible, the red angle is at once the

    lure of the image, and the detail which, as Barthes puts it in

    Camera Lucida, wounds and pierces.16

    Anne Carsons Seated Figure with Red Angle (1988) by Betty

    Goodwin was written in 1999, when she was invited by Art

    Forum to respond to a work that had special significance to her.

    Carson, whose work has frequently addressed the relationships

    between verbal and visual arts,17 described the way she chose to

    represent her encounter [b]y using the most hesitant of

    Figure 1. Betty Goodwin, Seated Figure with Red Angle (1988). Oil pastel, oil and

    graphite. 37 23 cm. Photo credit: Louis Lussier. Reproduced withpermission from Gatan Charbonneau.

    234 MONIQUE TSCHOFEN

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • syntaxes.18 Like Goodwins dynamic distortions of rectilinear

    visual geometry, Carsons disturbances of the syntax of the

    phrase, of genre, of person, of order, and of representation itself

    are designed to expose techniques of control and to subvert

    them by offering models of how new dynamic interrelationships

    might be configured.

    Towards the beginning of the poem, Carson notes that the

    seated figure started out with an idea of interrogation and later

    continues if you had the idea of interrogation.19 This careful

    slippage, from an idea of interrogation to the idea of interrogation

    delineates the way the poem moves from a consideration of

    Goodwins art and her depiction of torture to an exploration

    of a broad set of abstracted philosophical concerns, for at the

    heart of Carsons response to Goodwins art rests the double

    meaning of interrogation. The term refers to a technique

    torture and, seemingly more benignly, to a method or a mode

    of inquiry that forms an essential part of rationalist epistemol-

    ogys quest for certainty and structure behind the flux of experi-

    ence. The connection between these two meanings of the word

    interrogation seems to hang on the fact that both involve pro-

    cesses of questioning, but their imbrication runs deeper. As

    Idelber Avelar writes, torture is a key chapter in the history of

    truth.20 Anne Carsons scholarly and creative writing has sys-

    tematically worked to retrieve concepts from classical antiquity

    to show their strangeness and aliveness. There is little question

    that her translation (L. translatus, to carry across) of Goodwins

    treatment of torture, moving from an idea of interrogation to the

    idea of interrogation itself, aims to draw out a history of its

    meanings.21

    In Athenian culture, the term basanos (o) referred to atouchstone used by bankers to distinguish gold from alloys. Over

    time, the term came to be associated with judicial technique

    whereby a slave or servant, as a proxy for an accused free

    man, was physically tested by torture in order to extract the

    truth. What is significant for this analysis of Carsons poem

    based on Goodwins image is that, because of this association,

    the term came to signify processes by which we come to test the

    truth of a matter. Edward Peters notes how, in the work of

    Thucydides, the term basanos evidently connoted a kind of

    critical inquiry22 interrogation as critical method and

    later, basanos comes to signify not just the process of distilling

    truth from falsehood, but truth itself. 23 It is this last connection

    that Page duBois considers in her work Torture and Truth. She

    looks at the works of writers ranging from Theognis to Pindar to

    Plato to show how the Athenian practice of basanos is what has

    endowed philosophy with the core metaphor that organizes its

    central concept of truth as alethia (). DuBois argues thatthis concept has been conceived of as a kind of aggressive

    dragging, and bringing into light something hidden24 in a

    way that leads almost inevitably to conceiving of the body of

    the other as the site from which truth can be produced, and to

    using violence if necessary to extract that truth.25

    In the poem, Carsons retrieval of classical ideas about truth

    (aleth ia) and interrogation (basanos) materializes when Carson

    slyly raises the question of servant (or slave) and master. Art is

    the servant of allure, she writes, but importantly in this poem,

    there is no master of allure; no authenticating power submits

    arts truths to its authority.26 With these words, she suggests that

    the purpose of the art talk throughout the poem, with its refer-

    ences to colors (red), printing methods (wiping in), writing and

    videotaping, and the poems references to artists like Pascal,

    Artaud, and Nabokov, is to show how art can intervene in the

    legacy of this darker aspect of our epistemology, either in service

    of it as the technique of perspective can be seen to be doing, or

    independent from it.27

    With this context, it is possible to examine how Carson uses

    verbal form to engage the history of interrogation and truth.

    Carsons Seated Figure is difficult to categorize as essay or poem,

    as it resembles both and neither. It evokes the syllogism and

    propositional logic, and then wounds and pierces the argumen-

    tative with conditionality and non-sense. In broken lines where

    the sequence doesnt matter and where nothing sticks, its

    study of truth begins as a trickle, this thin slow falling of the

    mind, and from there, leaks.28 And yet, very little here feels

    poetic. There is no meter, no rhyme, no beautiful language. In

    order to appreciate its radical work, what I am calling Carsons

    poem needs to be understood as an ekphrasis, that is, as the

    verbal representation of a graphic representation.29

    Ekphrasis, from the Greek words ek (out) and phrasein (to

    speak forth or tell) is a genre of poetry and, more broadly, a

    mode of vivid writing that has been understood in relational

    terms as it involves a meeting between two modes of representa-

    tion one speaking and one silent; one temporal and one

    spatial; one cognitive and one possessing embodiment.30

    This act of meeting has traditionally been conceived of either

    in confrontational terms as in DaVincis notion of the paragone,

    or in sisterly or empathetic terms.31 Either way, as W. J. T.

    Mitchell has argued, in the tradition of ekphrasis the textual

    self projected as active, speaking, seeing speaks not

    only about the visual other but also presumes to speak for it

    insofar as the visual is projected as being passive, seen, and

    (usually) silent.32 Precisely because ekphrasis enacts a relational

    encounter, and precisely because this relational encounter has

    been informed by a social structure that mimics the set of power

    relationships enacted in the scene of interrogation, it is able to

    offer Carson an appropriate platform from which to launch her

    short-circuiting of the rational modes of thinking that can turn a

    method of questioning back into a practice of interrogation.33

    In her poem, the interrelations between the self of the written

    word and the other of the art image are hard to discern. The

    poems language offers no clear way of picturing the picture in

    question.34 It does not apostrophize or engage in dialogue with

    the picture. And it does not seek to put into words the pictures

    virtual discourses.35 Moreover, the speaker does not seem to

    be seeing (in the strict sense, with her eyes) or scanning for some

    clear vision of an epiphany. The poems subject matter is scat-

    tered, covering topics as diverse as aging, house pets, colors, the

    weather, art, literature, objects, propositions, and thoughts

    235

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • themselves in no easily discernible logical sequence. The poem

    thus mimics the movements of thinking as it paces rather than

    journeys, moving tangentially rather than linearly. Achieving

    the very opposite of what Krieger calls the still moment of

    ekphrasis, that is stasis, shape, closure, and silent presence, the

    poem is too unpatterned to be still or stilled.36 But for the title,

    one would have great difficulty recognizing the connections to

    Goodwins work or her theme. Yet Carsons refusal to picture

    the picture represents a refusal to render the silent image know-

    able and so extract its meanings literally to make it talk. If

    one of the questions of the poem is how to put thoughts about a

    complex work of visual art such as Betty Goodwins into words,

    Carson wants to ensure that her aesthetic response to the image

    of a human subject made into an object through the infliction of

    torture does not subordinate or contain this visual image. Just as

    Goodwin finds a way to have her work evoke the fields of

    containment of the perspectival grid and the epistemology that

    is associated with it, and yet transcend these through a fluid

    spatial operation, so too does Carson find a way to evoke the

    grid-like apparatus of genre and then, through the introduction

    of dynamism, proliferate alternative ways of figuring interrela-

    tionships between words and images and subjects and objects

    more broadly.37

    As Carsons ekphrasis about the picture hesitates to picture the

    picture, it faces another challenge, because the ekphrasis still is

    obliged to phrase that which is mute and apparently beyond

    language.38 Through a series of challenges to phrasing, the

    poem implies that structures of grammar and syntax are grid-

    like mechanisms of containment akin to the perspective para-

    digm in the visual arts.39 A sentence is a logical unit that works

    towards resolution and closure. In Carsons poem, each line has

    the outward appearance of a sentence because it is punctuated

    with a period, but, because each consists only of a conditional

    clause without the main clause or consequent, these incomplete

    sentences make visible the frame of the very structure they

    violate.40 The broken sentences in Seated Figure create a

    space for thought that cannot be fixed or pinned down. But

    they do so in a way that is specifically relevant to the fact that this

    is a poem that relates to a picture. As the unfinished preludes to

    an idea that cannot be uttered, the sentence fragments show a

    way for language to point to or reach towards rather than

    objectively represent. The poem seeks to verbalize something

    about the visual arts ineffability, and so its approach is to remain

    silent in matters that reside in the realm of the inarticulable.

    Conditionals are of great interest to philosophers because,

    J. L. Mackie explains, we do not know precisely how to con-

    strue them or precisely what their truth conditions are.41

    Carson declares in the second line of the poem that there are

    two kinds of conditionals, factual and contrafactual, and it is

    the contrafactual conditionals that have aroused the most

    anxiety and dispute.42 Rather than offer a statement of what

    is true if the antecedent is true as does the indicative conditional,

    the counterfactual statement offers what would be the case if the

    antecedent were true. Counterfactual reasoning is thus the

    process of evaluating conditional claims about possibilities

    rather than consequences, and so when Carson alludes to the

    form she raises the prospect that language can work to evade the

    burdensome literalness of facts. In the poem, however, the bulk

    of the protases are in the present indicative tense and so likely

    represent factual conditionals. With this sleight of hand, the

    poem draws attention to a delimitation between two gramma-

    tical and logical categories and thus to a way of using language to

    generate statements of possibility, and then hides this boundary

    from view so that we are left thinking about the poems own state

    of possibility, that is, about what the poem might have been if it

    had actually completed its thoughts. Her phrasing thus creates

    the structural conditions under which it is impossible for our

    thoughts to reach their consequences and there achieve a full

    stop. By excising consequence, its fragmented sentences offer a

    way to articulate potentiality.

    Carson uses the poems incomplete conditionals to comment

    self-reflexively on the conditional modes function as a connec-

    tor of two parts. Scattered through the poem is a kind of

    catalogue through a series of lines all beginning with the phrase

    If conditionals are of two kinds, which seek to parse the notion

    of the conditional, starting with the statement If conditionals

    are of two kinds factual and contrafactual.43 This statement is

    grounded in a recognizable process of logical reasoning that

    seeks to categorize and establish the boundary edge between

    different things. But the binary oppositions used to qualify the

    noun conditional that follow keep shifting the terrains within

    which their meaning resides. If the first statement is launched

    from the idea of a binary related to fact and its opposite, the next

    two iterations in the series move into dimensions that are prob-

    abilistic (possible and impossible) and then ontological (real

    and unreal).44 Then, the categories of conditionals the poem

    names begin to break down. In the line If conditionals are of

    two kinds now it is night and all cats are black, the binary terms

    no longer relate to the mode of the conditional proper.45

    Instead, they relate to each other impressionistically, dark

    thing opposed to other dark thing. The next two iterations in

    the series, If conditionals are of two kinds allure and awake,

    and (with a variation in the syntax) If conditional comes

    between condiment and condolence, offer up even more

    abstract interrelations between the terms of the binary by

    using assonance and the alphabetic order of the dictionary as

    the point of connection.46 The final lines of the poem, If

    conditionals are of two kinds graven and where is a place I can

    write this conclude the poem metatextually, setting into a faulty

    parallel syntax two notions about writing. One is passive,

    abstract and depersonalized ([conditionals are] graven). The

    other is localized (where is a place), and embodied and active

    (I can write this).47 Staged through this series of protases is

    thus an array of ways to configure interrelationships ranging

    from binary oppositional to proximal, and its overall movement

    in the poem from relationships of distance to relationships of

    closeness is one way the poem tries to think through the problem

    of interrogation as a relationship founded on a distancing of

    236 MONIQUE TSCHOFEN

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • subject and object. In its place it offers a relationship based on

    contiguity and sharing.48

    If the idea of connectors is introduced with the poems con-

    ditional syntax, it is developed in the poems core imagery

    around the idea of the edge. The central lines of the poem

    warrant repeating here because they demonstrate the complex

    work of the poems staging of thoughts and thinking within the

    encounter of visual and verbal arts:

    If you want to know why you cannot reach your own beautiful

    ideas.

    If you reach instead to the edge of the thinkable, which leaks.

    If you stop the leaks with conditionals.49

    Here are three linked protases within which the categories keep

    shifting so that, together, their instabilities work to create a

    succinct verbal picture of different conceptions of thought.

    Lying palimpsestically beneath these lines and the poem as a

    whole is Aristotle, who pictured knowing as a form of reaching

    in Metaphysics A: All men by their very nature reach out to

    know.50 In the first line cited above, desire wanting to

    know is separated from attainment reaching ones own

    beautiful ideas, and while wanting is posited as possible, attain-

    ing is not. So why could one not reach the end of ones beautiful

    ideas? To answer this, it is first necessary to look at the circum-

    stances under which one could reach the end of ones ideas. What

    is being conjured here is an epistemological framework in which

    ideas are conceived as objective entities that reside beyond some

    kind of finish line, but which can be reached through a rational line

    of questioning the interrogatory method at the heart of a

    notion of aleth ia we can trace back to the practice of basanos.Now importantly, one small preposition offers the key to under-

    standing the difference between the epistemological paradigm

    alluded to in the first cited line, and the picture of thinking

    offered in the second cited line, where knowing is understood

    more in keeping with Aristotle as a reaching to rather than as

    attaining. Reaching to can be infinite; as a model of knowledge,

    it engages a dynamic movement that cannot be stilled or

    contained.51

    There are two hinges or turning points in the second quoted

    line that relate to the edge of the thinkable that you are

    reaching to. One concerns the figure of the edge, and the second

    concerns the category of the thinkable. To begin with the figure

    of the edge, it must be noted that edges are a recurring motif in

    Carsons work.52 They are interesting because they are intrinsi-

    cally paradoxical. Edges are figures of distance. They divide and

    separate. They delineate boundaries between such categories as

    self and other or subject and object which, once conceptualized,

    create rigidities that affect all aspects of being. But at the same

    time edges are figures of contiguity and contact. The categories

    of self and other for example must touch at the place where they

    each find their identity through difference. Edges mark the place

    beyond which resides that which is not yet contained in the

    categories of the known. Ontologically, edges also delimit

    between what is and what is not but perhaps could be. And at

    this edge is the thinkable, which itself is a categorical distinc-

    tion that is unique in philosophy because one can only have

    knowledge of what is thinkable. The line separating it from the

    unthinkable is a line one can reach to, but never actually reach.

    The edges of the thinkable here are edges that leak; the poem

    thus uses a metaphor to make a picture of the limits of catego-

    rical thinking as well as thinking about categories. In the next

    line, you stop the leaks with conditionals. The humor in this

    line relates to the radical paradox of the image of conditionals as

    stopgaps because the poems experimentational form clearly

    uses the conditional to set thought in motion rather than contain

    it. If anything, it might be said that the poem stops the condi-

    tionals with leaks.

    Framed within hesitations around the constraints of ekphras-

    tic form, and conveyed through hesitations in sentence form

    and logic, the poem about Goodwins Seated Figure with Red Angle

    offers hesitations around grammatical person. It is impossible

    to reconstruct from the poem a unitary speaker because the

    speakers voice in the poem constantly shifts identity

    and address. For much of the poem the voice speaks in the

    third-person impersonal in the voice of the scholar who stands

    back from or above the text and names. Parsing the conditional

    form, philosophizing about color, art, and experience, the scho-

    lars voice moves towards precision. However, the speaker in

    the poem also uses a second-person form of address to counter

    this impersonal authoritative voice. The second person creates

    an intricate dialogic structure that breaks open the fourth wall

    of the poem and allows subjectivity to enter into the discourse.53

    The epistemological implications are great; one cannot calcu-

    late or be certain about another when one is engaged in

    a dialogue with them. Dialogue is a dynamic process that

    depends on a degree of intimate engagement between the speak-

    ers. It requires curiosity, and often accommodation and com-

    promise. Dialogue bridges distances and offers new points

    of view.

    Carson uses the second person to draw attention to the com-

    plex work of pronouns in articulating relationships. From the

    outset of the poem, the second person you becomes a moving

    field rather than a stable ground. In other words, the pronoun

    you delineates the edges of a category that leaks. At the

    beginning of the poem, the second- person addressee appears

    to be Goodwin herself and the poem an intimate letter to the one

    who inspired it. However, on closer inspection, many of the lines

    in which Carsons speaker seems to be addressing Betty

    Goodwin as you are citations of Betty Goodwin herself speak-

    ing in interviews where she frequently used the second-person

    pronoun as a synonym for the third or first person subject one

    or I. For example, in an interview with Robert Enright,

    Goodwin said that her work is based in something you dont

    even realize yourself until it gives you back information. Its like

    youre pulling and pulling and trying to get something. And then

    theres that magic time when it begins to pull you. If that doesnt

    happen, you cant push it any more and it dies.54 In the poem,

    Carson retains Goodwins idiosyncratic use of the second person

    237

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • in the phrase If youre pushing, pushing and then it begins to

    pull you.55 This habit of speech is fascinating because it results

    from a schism in self-identity, that is, from a projection of the

    mental contents of a speaking I onto the pronoun you. This

    schism paradoxically makes possible a unique kind of intimacy

    between speaker and interlocutor. The speaking I who is

    speaking as a you is in fact addressing an interlocutor,

    you, who by virtue of being addressed in the second person

    feels interpellated by and drawn into the world of the speaker.56

    Two figures inhabit the same pronominal unit. What takes the

    appearance of a dialogue (Carson the poet addressing Goodwin

    the artist) turns out to be a kind of intertextual sampling (Carson

    quoting Goodwin) within which what is presented as a dialogue

    (Goodwin addressing her interviewer) is in part actually a mono-

    logue (Goodwin is talking about herself). Even the metaphor of

    Chinese boxes cannot capture the complexity of the multiple

    frames in operation here.

    Formuchof the poem, you cogitate. You have ideas, want

    to know, remember, cannot remember, do not want to

    remember, and are bewildered.57 Whether this you refers

    to the reader of the poem, another viewer of Goodwins drawing,

    Goodwin herself, or the seated figure in the picture is not at all

    clear. What is clear is that when understood strictly in relation to

    the seated figure, these activities of thinking serve to engage

    cleverly with the thematic premise of interrogation in Goodwins

    Seated Figure with Red Angle. Carson constructs a thought-full you

    in order to juxtapose her to Goodwins image of a tortured you

    being interrogated for what she knows. Carsons thinking you is

    granted subjecthood and interiority. Goodwins interrogated

    you would seem to be merely othered.

    However, in an important twist, the poems catalogue of

    thinking acts associated with the thought-full you avoids

    merely reproducing rationalist epistemologys tendency to

    objectify. Rather, it presents a sliding between two modes of

    knowing from one that conceives of truth as certitude, correct-

    ness, or correspondence, to one that conceives of truth as what is

    unexperienced or unthought.58 Early in the poem, the thinking

    you is involved in activities grounded in the quest for cer-

    tainty. Later, the thinking you fore goes the prospect of a

    knowledge with certainty and enters into a realm in which

    nothing sticks.59 Taking up the poems central metaphor of

    leaking through the image of rain, the final lines of the poem

    place I, you, and we in a contradictory series of state-

    ments about the weather:

    If (for example) had you not destroyed the barometer it would

    have forewarned us implies that we are now standing in a

    storm of rain.

    If as a matter of fact it is a clear night I would say almost

    relentlessly clear.If the rain lashes your face like the manes of all the horses of this

    century.60

    The transformation of the you who thinks into the you who

    experiences rain leads away from thought towards perceptual

    and affective experience. And so, in the final line of the poem,

    where is a place I can write this, the speaker I has learned to

    anchor language, specifically written language, in the phenom-

    enal world, in the here and now of experience, correcting

    perhaps the mind/body split proposed by the cogito.

    The subject/object you in the poem is related closely to the

    third-person pronoun she. She appears to be the seated

    figure (who in Goodwins drawing is not gendered). She is

    represented in the poem as vulnerable, just as Goodwins seated

    figure is in the picture. In the poem, however, her abjectness

    appears to be related to senility, a process by which information

    slips away. While the result of the annihilation of thought is the

    same, Carson proposes senilitys emptying of the mind as the

    antithesis of interrogations extraction of information.61 In the

    poem, she sits the way a very old person sits, with no pants

    on, confused.62 What is important about Carsons treatment of

    she in the poem is that, unlike the seated figure in Goodwins

    image, she is cared for by you: you lead her to water

    and bring her a gift such as a thought from Pascal,

    Nabokov, or Artaud.63 In other words, in lieu of picturing a

    relationship that objectifies the other, Carson posits a relation-

    ship between first and third person that is nourishing. These

    pronominal games are highly significant for Carsons project of

    reconfiguring Western epistemologys faulty logic of instrumen-

    talizing ways of picturing and hence being in the world. The

    poem thus traces what Martin Buber describes in Ich and Du as

    the transformation from a relationship of IIt which reduces

    the other to an object and subjects it to the blind will of the I,

    towards mutual, reciprocal relationships Buber terms IYou

    (IchDu) that are grounded in dialogue and based on the recog-

    nition of the other. As Buber posits: I require a You to become;

    becoming I, I say You.64

    The poems hesitations around pronominal structures estab-

    lish a space of interpersonal exchange. This space of exchange

    extends to the text as a whole, since the poem does not delineate

    sharp edges between itself and other texts.

    Roland Barthes argues that intertextual dialogism brings a

    text into a kind of social utopia, that is, a space where no one

    language holds sway over any other, in which all languages

    circulate freely.65 Yet Carsons poem might better be described

    as what Michel Foucault calls a heterotopia. In the preface to The

    Order of Things, Foucault uses the term to describe the marvel of a

    passage from one of Borgess fictions in which the categories

    listed in a certain Chinese encyclopedia entry reveal the stark

    impossibility of a system of thought.66 Foucault wishes to under-

    stand how a system, an order of things, which must by definition

    have a grid or hidden network that determines how its elements

    relate to one another, might at the same time offer no common

    ground upon which its elements meeting is possible.

    Heterotopias, he explains, like Carsons poem, secretly under-

    mine language because they destroy syntax in advance, andnot only the syntax with which we construct sentences but also

    that less apparent syntax which causes words and things (next to

    and also opposite one another) to hold together.67 Utopias

    238 MONIQUE TSCHOFEN

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • (from ou-topos, meaning no-place or nowhere) project an

    image of idealized places that do not and cannot exist.

    Heterotopias in contrast violate all grids of coherence.68

    Carsons disorderly poem can be understood as a heterotopia

    because, like Goodwins drawing, it offers up the skeleton of

    order a logical grid or system that appears to function serially

    and then brings that order to the edge past which it becomes

    unthinkable.

    The problem that was raised at the beginning of this

    article about the way Carson refuses to picture the picture,

    refuses to make it speak, must be addressed now, because

    amidst the many destabilizing registers of the poems lan-

    guage, the poem seems blind to the drawing. How is this

    elision not ultimately to be understood as an exercise of the

    words power to silence or dominate? I argue here that it

    should not. In refusing to re-present something about

    Goodwins drawing, Carson is offering a critique of repre-

    sentation itself and its relationship to both literary language

    and visual arts. Many philosophers have argued that repre-

    sentation has for long been the fundamental category of

    knowledge both the form and the content of what we

    know.69 An order of things and a way of seeing, represen-

    tation posits relationships between thoughts and things

    based on resemblance or similitude. Its logic is that of the

    copy, and its mode of engagement is recognition.

    Recent philosophy has identified the problems inherent in

    this conception of representation. In a consideration of the work

    of Gilles Deleuze, Amy Hertzog argues that representation

    contains and constrains the object it represents: representation

    operates through immobilization, spatialization. It assertscorrespondences, analogies, and associations between elements

    at the expense of their differences, their dynamisms, their move-

    ments and changes.70 To put this in the poems words, repre-

    sentation is a tactic that seeks to stop the leaks in an otherwise

    dynamic and shifting field of knowledge.71 Ils Huygens elabo-

    rates on what the implications of representations immobiliza-

    tion and containments are for knowledge itself. The model of

    representational thinking is deficient, Huygens writes,

    because it can only re-present us what we already know. Itdoes not allow us to think the unthinkable, what has not been

    thought, what falls outside what we already know. Simply put,

    the representational image of thought cannot think qualitative

    change or real difference.72

    This is a serious deficiency, because it means that under a model

    of representation it is not possible fully to pursue and realize

    change, even when a disciplinary power is brought into view.

    And it has implications for art and philosophy both, since under

    a model of representation they are robbed of their powers to

    break with doxa and create the new.

    In order to describe the fundamental category of knowl-

    edge that underlies any epistemology, Gilles Deleuze coins

    the phrase image of thought. For Deleuze, an image of

    thought does not refer to an actual image that could be seen

    with our eyes or imagined as though seen with our eyes. Neither

    does it to refer to the notion that we perceive our thoughts as

    images. Nor does it refer to what the surrealists produced as they

    strove for material images of our unconscious thoughts. Rather,

    the phrase refers to the implicit invisible presuppositions about

    thinking that make thought possible: It is in terms of this image,

    he writes, that everybody knows and is presumed to know what

    it means to think.73

    The dominant or dogmatic image of thought that charac-

    terizes our philosophical tradition is representational. It is based

    on certitude: here, thought has an affinity with the true; it

    formally possesses the true and materially wants the true.74

    Certitude has limitations. By feigning objectivity, the represen-

    tational image of thought objectifies. It also censors the impro-

    visory and exploratory, and it ultimately limits what is knowable.

    According to Deleuze, creative arts such as philosophy, litera-

    ture, cinema, and even painting and drawing can liberate us

    from the Image and its postulates by offering a new space of

    possibility, movement, and becoming.75 Deleuze proclaims that

    the new image of thought works by writers such as Nietzsche and

    Proust make possible calls forth forces in thought which are not

    the forces of recognition but the powers of a completely othermodel, from an unrecognised and unrecognizable terra

    incognita.76

    What makes any new image of thought so powerful is that,

    much like Foucaults idea of the heterotopia, it exists in a state of

    pure potentiality, for once it has coalesced into an order, once it

    ceases to be a disorder, it produces a new homogeneity. The

    perspectival grid in Goodwins drawing, and genre, syntax, and

    grammar in Carsons poem represent orders. To set up a new

    image of thought, Deleuze offers, one seeks:

    a thinking that no longer opposes itself as from the outsideto the unthinkable or the unthought, but which would lodge

    the unthinkable, the unthought within itself as thought, and

    which would be in an essential relationship to it (desire is what

    remains always unthought at the heart of thought); a thinking

    that would of itself be in relation to the obscure, and which by

    rights would be traversed by a sort of fissure, without which

    thought could no longer operate. The fissure cannot be filled

    in, because it is the highest object of thought.77

    As an image of torture, Betty Goodwins drawing lodges unthink-

    able human violence. But rather than merely oppose the atrocity

    of a human subject made into an object, Goodwin draws these

    issues in through the motif of the grid that surrounds and pene-

    trates the seated figure, and then disrupts them through the

    delicate torsion that disrupts the coordinates of the picture

    space and the restrictions of representations certitude. This, I

    argue, powerfully exposes and erodes both the foundations of an

    entrenched system of thinking and the representational practices

    that accompany this epistemology. Even more powerfully, on the

    surface of Goodwins drawing erupts a fissure the enigmatic

    red angle in which lodges the unthinkable, and this is the very

    element that, because of its obscurity, permits a new mode of

    239

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • thought that reaches to but does not ever attain and contain, that

    draws out, but does not ever fill in. The instability of the order of

    image thus offers an opening into the central problems of philo-

    sophy and their relationship to human subjects.

    If Carsons ekphrasis were to undertake as its task the

    re-presentation of some aspects of the visual image that is its

    subject matter, and strive to make these aspects recognizable

    in some way, it would objectify the image, assert its distance

    from it, and make it speak. It would treat the image as

    though it were something that could be reached, and

    known rather than reached to and drawn out. Instead, Carson

    responded to Goodwins drawing by refusing to treat it as a

    representational image, and by refusing actually to represent

    or contain it. Her poetic approach to the drawing is in the

    spirit of drawing: exploratory, experimental, and, like her

    grammatical form, conditional. Yet her poetic approach to

    the drawing provides an image that is not an image as one

    would see with ones eyes or even imagine. Through its

    many formal strategies of hesitation, the poem protects the

    drawing from merely replicating the dominant epistemology,

    and from Carsons own practices of interrogation. Instead, it

    enters into a relationship of reciprocity with the drawing to

    offer a new image of thought, an image of that which cannot

    be pictured, which it presents as gifts. In so doing, Carsons

    poem generates a state of disorder that is vital, offers infinite

    possibilities for the generation of nourishing relationships

    based on reciprocity rather than domination. Deleuze

    writes: We live with a particular image of thought, that is

    to say, before we begin to think, we have a vague idea of

    what it means to think, its means and ends. And then

    someone comes along and proposes another idea, a whole

    other image.78 And we feel, as Foucault did upon reading

    Borgess encyclopedia, the marvel of the stark impossibility

    of thinking that and the restoration of a sense of what the

    powers of the arts can be.79

    ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

    I would like to thank Jonathan Rollins, Sarah Henstra, and

    Victor Cirone for their engagement with the project along its

    way.

    NOTES

    1 Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition (New York: Columbia University

    Press, 1995), 147.

    2 Will Aitken, The Art of Poetry No. 88: Anne Carson, The Paris Review

    46 (Fall 2004): 190226, here p. 203.

    3 Carolyn Forch, The Country Between Us (New York: Harper and Row,1981); Betty Goodwin, Betty Goodwin in Conversation with France

    Morin, in Betty Goodwin: Steel Notes, ed. France Morin (Ottawa: National

    Gallery of Canada, 1989), 108116, here 115.

    4 Anne Carson, Seated Figure with Red Angle (1988) by Betty Goodwin, in

    Decreation: Poetry, Essays, Opera (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2005), 96101.

    This work was published in an earlier version under the title Betty Goodwin

    Seated Figure with Red Angle (1988), Art Forum 38, no.1 (September 1999):

    15657.

    5 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 97. For a discussion of the notions of

    representation as likeness or resemblance, see Michel Foucault, The Order of

    Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences (New York: Vintage Books, 1970);

    Gilles Deleuze,Difference and Repetition; Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror

    of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979).

    6 See Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition; Essays in Critical and Clinical

    (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997); and Desert Islands and

    Other Texts, 19531974 (Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2004).

    7 Gilles Deleuze, Difference, 147.

    8 These images are all reproduced in Betty Goodwin, Steel Notes, Betty

    Goodwin, ed. France Morin.

    9 Elaine Scarry, The Body in Pain: The Making and Unmaking of the World (New

    York: Oxford University Press, 1985), 38.

    10 Norman Bryson, Vision and Painting: The Logic of the Gaze (New Haven:

    Yale University Press, 1983), 92.

    11 Susan L. Stoops, The Contemporary Drawing: Existence, Passage and the Dream,

    exhibition catalog (Waltham,MA, Rose Art Gallery, Brandeis University, 17

    March28 April 1991), 4.

    12 Lyle Massey, Anamorphosis through Descartes or Perspective Gone

    Awry, Renaissance Quarterly 50, no. 4 (1997): 114889, here p. 1148. See also

    Hubert Damisch, who suggests that the use of fixed perspective in lgeclassique could be taken as an indicator of certain scientific and philosophical

    positions: In this sense (and in this sense only), the cogito can be regarded as

    the translation, itself in accordance with the Cartesian ideal of world mas-

    tery, of a theme or methodical structure that recurs in all realms of knowl-

    edge and that lends itself to all manner of translations (Hubert Damisch,The Origin of Perspective (Cambridge,MA:MIT Press, 2000), 48). In this article,

    I am guilty of a gesture, echoed in the works of Heidegger and Deleuze,

    Martin Jay, and Erwin Panofsky, among many other writers, of drawing a

    relatively uncomplicated line between Greek thought, Cartesianism, and

    modern scientific rationality. I believe this thread is drawn in Goodwins

    work and Carsons as well, so to complicate the history of Western philoso-

    phy would not advance an understanding of the poem or drawing I am

    treating here.

    13 SeeMartin Jay, Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twentieth-Century

    French Thought (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994), 323, and

    Scopic Regimes of Modernity, in Vision and Visuality, ed. Hal Foster (San

    Francisco: Bay Press, 1988), 323. Hubert Damisch refers here to Erwin

    Panofskys and Ernst Cassirers work when he describes perspective as a

    regulating structure. He then in fact proceeds to debunk this conception. See

    Hubert Damisch, The Origin of Perspective (Cambridge,MA:MIT Press, 2000),

    25. Also see my previous note.

    14 Erwin Panofsky, Perspective as Symbolic Form (New York: Zone Books,

    1997), 67. Panofsky writes, thus the history of perspective may be under-

    stood with equal justice as a triumph of the distancing and objectifying sense

    of the real and as a triumph of the distance-denying human struggle for

    control. Perspective is as much a consolidation and systematization of theexternal world, as an extension of the domain of the self. [T]he claim ofthe object (to use a modern term) confronts the ambition of the subject. The

    object intends to remain distanced from the spectator (precisely as something

    objective). Ibid., 6768.15 I do not have the space to elaborate on the connections between

    Cartesianism and the animalhuman split used to justify another sort of

    violence but this is another topic woven through the poem. In 19841985,

    Betty Goodwin developed a series of images titled So Certain I Was, I Was

    a Horse which feature a bent over figure including one with a leash-like

    cord around his neck. The title of the series is an allusion to epistemologies

    based on certainty and links these with degradation. In Betty Goodwin,

    Carson refers to Goodwins series tangentially when she substitutes the

    poems her for horse: If you lead her to water. Continuing the

    reference to the construction of animality as an extension of the subject

    object split, the poem refers to the scientist Miroslav (Holub)s position that

    experimental animals should not be too smart, and then offers other

    rationalizations: If the horses were exhausted / If they dont feel pain the

    240 MONIQUE TSCHOFEN

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • way we do; Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 99100. For a very concise

    discussion of the relationship between vivisection and Cartesian thought, see

    John Rodman, The Dolphin Papers, North American Review 259, no. 1

    (Spring, 1974): 1226.

    16 Roland Barthes, Camera Lucida: Reflections on Photography, trans. Richard

    Howard (New York: Hill and Wang, 1981), 17.

    17 Carson has persistently used her creative and scholarly works to

    investigate the relation between verbal and visual media. In Autobiography of

    Red (New York: Vintage Books, 1998), for example, she constructs verbal

    photographs that attempt to distill into words photographys ability to play

    with perceptual relationships (65) in order to find a way of telling about

    photographys ways of seeing. See E. L.McCallum, Toward a Photography

    of Love: The Tain of the Photograph in Anne Carsons Autobiography of

    Red, Postmodern Culture (PMC) 17, no. 3 (2007): 8, available online at http://

    pmc.iath.virginia.edu/text-only/issue.507/17.3mccallum.txt. In Men in the

    Off Hours (New York: Vintage, 2001), Carson offers ekphrases of both real

    and imagined paintings, operas, and films. Jeff Hamilton argues that in

    poems such as Life of Towns in Plainwater: Essays and Poetry (Toronto:

    Vintage Canada, 1995), Carson constructs a verse equivalent to the vanish-

    ing point in painting as she probes the relationships between three inter-

    related conceptions of the line: the verse line, the painterly or writerly trace,

    and the perspectival grid. Jeff Hamilton, This Cold Hectic Dawn and I,

    Denver Quarterly 32, no. 12 (SummerFall 1997): 116.

    18 Phoebe Pettingell, Shards of Meaning, review of Decreation: Poetry,

    Essays, Opera by Anne Carson, The New Leader 88, no. 5 (SeptemberOctober

    2005): 3638, here p. 37, emphasis added

    19 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 97 (emphasis added).

    20 Idelber Avelar, The Letter of Violence: Essays on Narrative, Ethics and Politics

    (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004), 29.

    21 For example, in Eros the Bittersweet, Carson retrieves the ancient notion of

    eros (). Anne Carson, Eros the Bittersweet (Normal, IL: Dalkey ArchivePress, 1998). In Economy of the Unlost (Princeton: Princeton University Press,

    1999) she draws from xenia (), logos (), and eikon ().22 Edward Peters, Torture: Expanded Edition (Philadelphia: University of

    Pennsylvania Press, 1996).

    23 It is possible to trace the effects of the practice and metaphor of basanos

    across time. In ancient Greece, writers ranging from Pindar (Pythian) to

    Aristotle (Rhetoric) to Plato (Laches) refer to basanos bymeans such as whipping,

    the rack, being buried under rocks, and even, in Aristophaness The Frogs,

    putting vinegar under the nose. For connections between torture and truth

    more broadly see Edward Peters, Torture, which examines tortures emer-

    gence in Roman law through to today. Stephen Eisenman also gives a

    thorough summary of the early articulations of basanos in Greek and Roman

    culture in The Abu Ghraib Effect (London: Reaktion Books, 2007). The

    endurance of the connection between torture, truth, and interrogation can

    be traced forward from the Greeks to the Romans to early modern Europe.

    See Jennifer A. Glancy, who offers an analysis of Pilates scourge of Jesus in

    the Fourth Gospel in relation to Roman judicial interrogation (Torture:

    Flesh, Truth, and the Fourth Gospel, Biblical Interpretation 13, no. 2 (2005):

    10736). Lucy Grieg examines torture in hagiographic texts in relation to the

    Roman quaestio per tormenta (interrogation by torture). Lucy Grieg, Torture

    and Truth in Late Antique Martyrology, Early Medieval Europe 11, no. 4

    (2002): 32136. For a discussion of early modern French concepts of truth as

    being lodged in the body, requiring extraction just as tears and teeth are

    drawn out, see also Lisa Silverman, Tortured Subjects: Pain, Truth, and the Body

    in Early Modern France (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001), 118. Jody

    Enders brilliantly analyzes the relationship between torture, rhetoric, and

    spectacle. Jody Enders, The Medieval Theater of Cruelty: Rhetoric, Memory and

    Violence (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1999). Elizabeth Hanson

    argues that in the English discursive economy about torture the body gave

    truth a basis in material reality susceptible to discovery, while through pain

    made it inaccessible to all but the sufferer. Elizabeth Hanson, Torture and

    Truth in Renaissance England, Representations 34 (1991): 5384, here, p. 56.

    24 Page duBois, Torture and Truth: The New Ancient World (New York:

    Routledge, 1991), 29. DuBois discusses Martin Heidegger, whose formula-

    tion of aletheia has to a large extent defined current usage of the term. While

    she searches for rhetorical traces of basanos in his language, noting for

    example his description of truth as the constant wresting extortion of the

    unhidden, it is more effective to note that there are two competing notions

    of aleth ia in Greek thought (duBois, Torture, 132). Marcel Detienne describesthe earlier notion of aleth ia as mythical while the later conception of truthis positivist and abstract. The Masters of Truth in Archaic Greece (New York:

    Zone Books, 1999). Heidegger observes this evolution within which an ear-

    lier notion of aleth ia as an opening, or unconcealedness, becomes supplantedby a notion of correctness and certainty that hails from Plato and runs

    through Descartes and dominates our epistemology today. Linking this to

    both the subjectobject split and to representation, Heidegger writes:

    Homoisis [likeness] has since become adaequatio [correctness] and thenagreement, and since Descartes, the relation between soul and beings has

    become the subjectobject relation, mediated by a representation, the

    degenerate descendant of Platos idea. Truth becomes correctness, and its

    elbow-room [Spielraum], the open, is neglected. See Michael Inwood, A

    Heidegger Dictionary (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 14.

    25 Page duBois, Torture, 6.

    26 Anne Carson Seated Figure, 101 (emphases added). The reference to

    allure is to Husserl, who in the Analyses defines affection as the allure given

    to consciousness, the particular pull that an object given to consciousness

    exercises on the ego; it is a pull that is relaxed when the ego turns toward it

    attentively, and progresses from here, striving toward self-giving intuition.

    Allure is thus that which draws the subject to the object, holding sway until

    the ego is attentive. See Edmund Husserl, Analyses concerning Passive and Active

    Synthesis: Lectures on Transcendental Logic, trans. Anthony J. Steinbock

    (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001), 196.

    27 These three writers are known not only for the thoughts expressed in

    their writings but also for their drawings. Antonin Artaud filled notebooks with

    disturbing distorted figures surrounded and traversed by poems, rants, and

    treatises. Nabokov illustrated books for his family with intricate drawings of

    butterflies. Finally, one of the apocryphal stories about Blaise Pascal pictures

    him as a child, drawing geometric figures on the floor of his home with

    charcoal. These writers thus provide a model of a writing space that is open to

    the traces of drawing, and of a drawing space open to the traces of writing.

    28 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 99 101.

    29 Ruth Webb offers a penetrating history of the changes in the use of the

    term from ancient to contemporary times. One important contribution of

    this article is that Webb reminds us that earlier understandings of ekphrasis

    had little to do with the definition of ekphrasis that has the most currency

    today, namely as the poetic description of a pictorial or sculptural work of art

    or as a verbal representation of a visual representation. See Ruth Webb,

    Ekphrasis Ancient and Modern: The Invention of a Genre,Word & Image

    15, no. 1 (JanuaryMarch 1999): 718. For works that consolidated this

    current meaning of ekphrasis see also Leo Spitzer, The Ode on a Grecian

    Urn, or content vs. metagrammar, in Essays on English and American Literature

    (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1962), 6797; and James A.

    Heffernan, Museum of Words: The Poetics of Ekphrasis from Homer to Ashbery

    (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993.)

    30 John Hollander, The Gazers Spirit: Poems Speaking to Silent Works of Art

    (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995); Gottfried Ephraim Lessing,

    Laocoon: An Essay Upon The Limits of Painting and Poetry (Mineola, NY: Dover

    Publications, 2005); Joseph Frank, The Idea of Spatial Form (New Brunswick,

    NJ: Rutgers University Press 1991); Norman Bryson, Intertextuality and

    Visual Poetics, Style 22, no. 2 (June 1988): 18393. It is pertinent to the

    poems thematic treatment of torture via a reworking of the terms of

    wordimage relationships that Lessings Laocoon possibly the most

    important articulation of the differences between the verbal and visual arts

    refers to a sculpture that represents a scene of excruciating torment and

    agony. Lessing asks why the sculptor did not depict his figure screaming, and

    241

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • responds that transitory actions have no place in static and permanent

    modes of representation.

    31 For a summary of paragonal models, see Mitchell, Picture Theory: Essays

    on Verbal and Visual Representation (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994);

    and James A. W. Heffernan, Museum of Words. For a summary of the tradition of

    sister-arts see Jean H. Hagstrum, The Sister Arts: The Tradition of Literary Pictorialism

    and English Poetry from Dryden to Gray (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,

    1958); and Richard Wendorf, Articulate Images: The Sister Arts from Hogarth to

    Tennyson (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983). For works that

    extend beyond the sister-arts see Anne Keefe, The Ecstatic Embrace of

    Verbal and Visual: Twenty-first Century Lyric Beyond the Ekphrastic

    Paragone, Word & Image 27, no. 2 (June 2011): 13547; and Ayala Amir,

    Sunt Lacrimae Rerum: Ekphrasis and Empathy in Three Encounters

    between a Text and a Picture, Word & Image 25, no. 3 (JulySeptember

    2009): 23242.

    32 W. J. T.Mitchell, Picture Theory, 157. Mitchell draws attention to how the

    social structure of ekphrasis is grounded in our ambivalence about other

    people, regarded as subjects and objects in a field of verbal and visual

    representation (Mitchell, Picture Theory, 163). Page duBois echoes this view:

    If ekphrastic texts are about learning to see, to read visual texts, they also

    concern domination and power, the privileging of some readers over others,

    and our own tendencies to identify with elite and privileged readers in the

    past, those educated and cultured few whom we see as like ourselves (Page

    duBois, Reading the Writing on the Wall, Classical Philology 102, no. 1,

    Special Issue on Ekphrasis (January 2007): 4556, here p. 46).

    33 Nicolas Bourriaud, Relational Aesthetics (Dijon: Les Presses du rel, 2002), 18.34 Not only does the poem not resemble ekphrasis defined in terms of its

    subject matter the representation of an art object it does not resemble

    ekphrasis in its early use of the term, as what RuthWebb describes as a form

    of vivid evocation that may have as its subject-matter anything. Whatdistinguishes ekphrasis is its quality of vividness, enargeia, its impact on the

    minds eye of the listener whomust, in Theons words, be almost made to see

    the subject (Ruth Webb, Ekphrasis, 13).

    35 Jacques Derrida, The Spatial Arts: An Interview with Jacques

    Derrida by Peter Brunette and David Wills, in Deconstruction and the Visual

    Arts: Art, Media, Architecture, ed. Peter Brunette and David Wills (Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press, 1993): 1232, here p. 13.

    36 SeeMurrayKrieger, The Ekphrastic Principle and the StillMoment of

    Poetry, or Laokoon Revisited, in The Play and Place of Criticism (Baltimore:

    Johns Hopkins University Press, 1967) and Ekphrasis: The Illusion of the Natural

    Sign (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992).

    37 In Seated Figure, Carson is working in the spirit of philosophers such as

    Maurice Merleau-Ponty or Hubert Damisch, who challenge the connection

    philosophy has made between the perspectival apparatus and perception.

    Damisch writes that the problem with these ideas is how to distinguish that

    which is perceived from that which is represented. Must descriptionnecessarily resort to mean that are those of representation, borrowing its

    forms, its metaphors? (Hubert Damisch, The Origin of Perspective, 34).

    38 Gary Shapiro, The Absent Image: Ekphrasis and the Infinite Relation

    of Translation, Journal of Visual Culture 6, n. 1 (2007): 1324, here p. 21.

    39 A connection can be made between Goodwins interest in perspective

    and Carsons interest in the sentence: The formal apparatus put in place by

    the perspective paradigm is equivalent to that of a sentence, in that it assigns

    the subject a place within a previously established network that gives it

    meaning, while at the same time opening up the possibility of something like

    a statement in painting (Hubert Damisch, The Origin of Perspective 446).

    40 In interview, Carson speaks about the way a poem break leads into a

    thought that cant ever be apprehended, leaving the space where a

    thought would be, but which you cant get hold of (Will Aitken, The Art of

    Poetry No. 88: Anne Carson p. 214).

    41 J. L. Mackie, Truth, Probability and Paradox: Studies in Philosophical Logic

    (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973), 64.

    42 Ibid., 64.

    43 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 7.

    44 Ibid., 98, 99.

    45 Ibid., 100.

    46 Ibid., 101.

    47 Ibid., 101.

    48 It is possible that Carson is also thinking about Aristotles view about

    knowledge in which the mind (nous) becomes one with the object of thought

    rather than depicting it. See Charles Taylor, Overcoming Epistemology,

    in Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995).

    49 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 96101, here 99.

    50 Cited in Anne Carson, Eros the Bittersweet (Normal, IL: Dalkey Archive

    Press, 1998), 70. Betty Goodwin also uses the metaphor of reaching when she

    speaks about subsequent works in her series reaching more into the essence

    of her earlier drawings. See Betty Goodwin, Betty Goodwin: Steel Notes, 113.

    51 See Dennis Schmidt, Between Word and Image: Heidegger, Klee, and Gadamer

    on Gesture and Genesis (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2012), chapter

    3, for a discussion of Gadamers contribution to an understanding of art as a

    continuation of movement and play as opposed to as an object of cognition.

    52 See Anne Carson, Eros the Bittersweet. Here, Carson links the edge to

    desire (3031), figures of speech like puns and paradox (35), the self (35), and

    most importantly language itself. She argues that edges are what distinguish

    oral from written words, as writing gives each word its own visible boundary

    while heard words have varying edges. See also Anne Carson, Chez

    LOxymoron,Grand Street 7, no. 4 Summer 1988): 6874. Here Carson writes:

    Once I went to South America to look at the edges of shadows. It becamemy endeavour to stand on the very edge of shadow. I failed. There isshadow and there is no shadow and you can see the difference between them

    you can stare at it, measure it, describe it, you can show it in a mirror, but

    to stand on that edge no you cant do it. The edge where shadow andno shadow come together and lie side by side is a point without space. A

    contradiction without terms. Anne Carson, Chez lOxymoron, 168. Another

    place where the idea of an edge occurs is in pre-Socratic thinking. Detienne

    juxtaposes the rationalist instrumentalizing notion of al theia that duBoisdescribes with an earlier conception of truth in which al theia borders on l the(oblivion or forgetting): Thus, Aletheia (+) does not stand on one side and

    Lethe () on the other. Rather, an intermediate zone develops between the

    poles, in which Aletheia approaches Lethe and vice versa. Negativity is not

    isolated from Being. It borders the truth and forms its inseparable shadow.

    The two antithetical powers are thus not contradictory but tend toward each

    other. The positive tends toward the negative, which, in a way, denies it but

    cannot maintain itself in its absence (Detienne, Masters, 82).

    53 Hubert Damisch suggests that perspective involves a passing from the

    point of view of the subject to that of the eye via the technique of the vanishing

    point, and states that this passing is analogous to linguistic usages that allow us

    to change person in a sentence, permitting us to pass from I to you or he,

    and from the subject of a statement to that of the speaker (Hubert Damisch,

    The Origin of Perspective, 51).

    54 Betty Goodwin, A Bloodstream of Images: An Interview with Betty

    Goodwin, interview by Robert Enright, Border Crossings 14, no. 4 (Fall 1995):

    4253, here p. 48.

    55 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 97. The term pull also likely connects to

    the notion of allure she presents later in the poem via Husserl. See my note

    27 above.

    56 In an essay on Aristotles Poetics, Anne Carson refers to the use of the

    second person in Sappho: we are her. The second person singular verbs of

    the poem locate us within some woman by calling her you Anne Carson,

    Just for the Thrill: Sycophantizing Aristotles Poetics, Arion: A Journal of

    Humanities and the Classics 1, no. 1 (Dec 2001): 14254, here 147.

    57 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 97101.

    58 Martin Heidegger, The Origin, 52.

    59 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 99.

    60 Ibid., 101.

    61 Carson seems to bemaking the connection between the abjectness of the

    tortured and the senile via Elaine Scarry, inThe Body in Pain, after comparing

    torture to pain inflicted in religious contexts, who explicitly distinguishes

    242 MONIQUE TSCHOFEN

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4

  • torture from the pain of aging, where the absence of the world from oneself

    can be understood as an inversion of the eventual but unexperiencable

    absence of oneself from the world, 34.

    62 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 97.

    63 Ibid., 98, 99. Elsewhere, Carson offers an extensive theorization of the

    gift. In Economy of the Unlost, Carson compares two modes of exchange:

    commodification and gift-giving. Commodity form, she says, fragments

    and dehumanizes human being, 19. A gift, in contrast, is an act of com-

    munication that offers an extension of the interior of the giver, both in space

    and in time, into the interior of the receiver, 18. A gift has both economic

    and spiritual content, is personal and reciprocal, and depends on a rela-

    tionship that endures over time, 12. To give thoughts, and specifically to

    give thoughts as they are articulated in the works of writers, is to activate an

    understanding of language as an intimate force.

    64 Martin Buber, I and Thou, trans. Ronald Gregor Smith (New York:

    Charles Scribners Sons, 1958), 43.

    65 Roland Barthes, FromWork to Text, in Image Music Text, trans.

    Stephen Heath (New York: Hill and Wang, 1977), 15564, here p. 164.

    Jacqueline Plante has written an essay linking the idea of Utopia to Gilles

    Deleuzes notion of becoming, arguing that Carsons Autobiography of Red is

    utopian in order to extend the subversive activity of literature. See

    Jacqueline Plante, In the Spirit of Process: A Braiding Together of New

    Utopianism, Gilles Deleuze, and AnneCarson, inThe Influence of Imagination:

    Essays on Science Fiction and Fantasy as Agents of Social Change, ed. Lee Easton and

    Randy Schroeder ( Jefferson, NC: McFarland & Co, 2008), 17482. Below, I

    too connect Carson to Deleuzes thought in relation to arts subversive

    activity, but focus on what Deleuze says about the image as he describes how

    literature can move us away from representationalism and correspondence

    models of truth.

    66 Michel Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences

    (New York: Vintage Books, 1970), xv. The Borges passage with which

    Foucault opens his book is well known, but worth citing again: This passage

    quotes a certain Chinese encyclopedia in which it is written that animals

    are divided into: (a) belonging to the Emperor, (b) embalmed, (c) tame, (d)

    sucking pigs, (e) sirens, (f) fabulous, (g) stray dogs, (h) included in the present

    classification, (i) frenzied, (j) innumerable, (k) drawn with a very fine camel-

    hair brush, (l) et cetera, (m) having just broken the water pitcher, (n) that from a

    long way off look like flies.

    67 Ibid., xviii.

    68 Ibid., xvii.

    69 Ibid., 54.

    70 Amy Hertzog, Images of Thought and Acts of Creation: Deleuze,

    Bergson, and the Question of Cinema, In[ ] Visible Culture: An Electronic

    Journal of Visual Studies 3 (2000), http://www.rochester.edu/

    in_visible_culture/issue3/herzog.htm (accessed July 25, 2011).

    71 Anne Carson, Seated Figure, 99.

    72 Ils Hugens, Deleuze and Cinema: Moving Images and Movements

    of Thought, Image and Narrative 18 (2007), http://www.

    imageandnarrative.be/thinking_pictures/huygens.htm (accessed

    December 15, 2012). Hugens is echoing Michel Foucault, who in the The

    Order of Things writes, by positing resemblance as the link between signs

    and what they indicate sixteenth-century knowledge condemneditself to never knowing anything but the same thing. Michel Foucault,

    The Order of Things, 30.

    73 Gilles Deleuze, Difference, 131.

    74 Ibid., 131.

    75 Ibid., 132.

    76 Ibid., 136.

    77 Gilles Deleuze, Desert Islands and Other Texts, 19531974 (Los Angeles:

    Semiotext(e): 2004), 92.

    78 Ibid., 139.

    79 Michel Foucault, Order, xv.

    243

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    ity of

    Tor

    onto

    Libr

    aries

    ] at 0

    7:30 1

    4 Apr

    il 201

    4