Dogmatic List

  • Upload
    fjh234

  • View
    218

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    1/15

    Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism

    Edouard Machery*University of Pittsburgh

    Abstract

    This article critically examines the contemporary resurgence of empiricism (orneo-empiricism) in philosophy, psychology, neuropsychology, and artificialintelligence.This resurgence is an important and positive development. It isthe first time that this centuries-old empiricist approach to cognition is preciselyformulated in the context of cognitive science and neuroscience. Moreover,neo-empiricists have made several findings that challenge amodal theories of conceptsand higher cognition. It is argued, however, that the theoretical foundations of andthe empirical evidence for neo-empiricism are not as strong as is usually claimedby its proponents.The empirical evidence for and against neo-empiricism is discussedin detail.

    In this article, I critically examine the contemporary resurgence of empiricism(or neo-empiricism) in philosophy, psychology, neuropsychology, andartificial intelligence.1 This resurgence is an important and positivedevelopment. It is the first time that this centuries-old empiricist approachto cognition is precisely formulated in the context of cognitive science andneuroscience. Moreover, neo-empiricists have made several findings thatchallenge amodal theories of concepts and higher cognition.

    I argue however that the theoretical foundations of and the empiricalevidence for neo-empiricism are not as strong as is usually claimed by its

    proponents (see also Machery,Concept Empiricism). In the first section,I describe the two central dogmas of neo-empiricism. In the second section,I discuss two theoretical issues. In the last section, I consider some empiricalevidence for and against neo-empiricism.

    1. Neo-Empiricism

    1.1.TWO DOGMAS

    Despite some disagreements between neo-empiricists, they all endorse thefollowing two theses the dogmas of neo-empiricism:

    (1) The knowledge that is stored in a concept is encoded in severalperceptual representational systems.

    Blackwell Publishing 2006

    Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    2/15

    (2) Conceptual processing involves reenacting some perceptual states andmanipulating these perceptual states.

    Thesis 1 is about the vehicleorform of our conceptual knowledge, that is,

    roughly, about how we encode our conceptual knowledge (Prinz 109). Inagreement with most psychologists and neuropsychologists of perception,neo-empiricists assume that each perceptual system, as well as our motorsystem and our emotional system, relies on a distinct specific representationalsystem.2 Neo-empiricists seem to think that besides being distinct, theserepresentational systems are also rather different from each other.Thesis 1claims that our conceptual knowledge is encoded in these perceptual, motor,and emotional representational systems.Thus, like Hume (Enquiries 19),neo-empiricists such as Prinz (1202) and Barsalou (Perceptual Symbol

    Systems) characterize the senses broadly: Senses include proprioception,our emotions, as well as our motor systems. Prinz goes even further:Wordsin inner speech are thought of as perceptual representations (150).

    By contrast, amodal theorists argue that our conceptual knowledge isencoded in a representational system that is distinct from our perceptualrepresentational systems: Besides our perceptual representational systems,we possess a distinct, sui generis representational system, which is used toencode our conceptual knowledge (Barsalou et al.,Grounding ConceptualKnowledge 85).This distinct representational system is usually thought

    ofas being language-like and as being rather different from the modalrepresentational systems.

    To take a simple example, according to neo-empiricists, Maries conceptualknowledge about apples consists of the visual, olfactive, tactile, somato-sensory, and gustative representations of apples that are stored in herlong-term memory.These representations are a subset of the perceptualrepresentations of apples Marie has had in her life (Barsalou, PerceptualSymbol Systems 5778; Barsalou et al.,Grounding Conceptual Knowledge856).3 They are encoded in several representational systems:Visual repre-

    sentations are encoded in a visual representational system, auditory repre-sentations in an auditory representational system, and so forth.Accordingto amodal theorists, Maries conceptual knowledge about apples consists ofrepresentations that belong to a distinct representational system.Her conceptof apple contains some perceptual (visual, tactile, gustatory...) as well assome non-perceptual information about apples in a single, distinct repre-sentational system.

    Thesis 1 is inspired by a central tenet of classical empiricism. Hume arguedthat all our ideas are qualitatively similar to our percepts, although theytypically differ from percepts by their intensity (Enquiries section 2; see alsoBerkeley Introduction). Despite this convergence of views with the Britishempiricists, neo-empiricists do not necessarily endorse the pictorialism oftraditional empiricists. Berkeley and Hume thought about perceptualrepresentations, particularly about visual representations, by analogy with

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

    Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism . 399

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    3/15

    pictures (e.g., Hume, Enquiries). On the contrary, for most empiricists,pictures are an inappropriate model for thinking about perceptual states(Barsalou, Perceptual Symbol Systems 582; Prinz ch. 6). Nonetheless, inspite of this official credo, it is noteworthy that neo-empiricists often illustrate

    the mental representations they postulate by means of pictures (e.g., Barsalou,Perceptual Symbol Systems 578; Damasio,Descartes Error104; Prinz 146).Thesis 2 concerns the nature of our cognitive processes categorization,

    induction, deduction, analogy-making, planning, linguistic comprehension,and so forth:The cognitive processes that underlie our higher cognitioninvolve our senses at least, some of the processes involved in perceptualinformation processing.The central insight is the following (Barsalou,Perceptual Symbol Systems 586; Prinz 148; Stein). Retrieving a conceptfrom long-term memory during reasoning, categorization (etc.) consists in

    creating some perceptual representations. For instance, retrieving the conceptof dog consists in creating some visual, auditory (etc.) representations ofdogs.This process is called simulation or reenactment. Simulation involvessome perceptual brain systems. Reenacted percepts and the products ofperceptual imagery, for instance visual images, are assumed to be the samekind of representation (Barsalou et al.,Grounding Conceptual Knowledge85). Neo-empiricists propose also that reenacted percepts are not necessarilyidentical to past actual percepts (e.g., Barsalou,Perceptual Symbol Systems584). For instance, following Hume (Enquiries section 2, p.19), they suggest

    that we combine reenacted percepts to create new representations (Barsalou,Abstraction).

    Our cognitive processes consist in manipulating these reenacted percepts(e.g., Barsalou, Perceptual Symbol Systems 578).This idea is wellillustrated by how the psychologist Lawrence Barsalou, one of the leadingneo-empiricists, describes the process of verifying whether some object hasa given part, for example whether lions have a mane.We produce a visualrepresentation of a lion and another of a mane and we match these tworepresentations. If both representations match, we decide that lions have a

    mane (Solomon and Barsalou, Representing Properties Locally 1356).Thesis 2 can be seen as a modern development of Berkeleys insight thatreasoning consists in manipulating mental states that are similar to percepts(Berkeley Introduction, paras 1213, pp. 1314).

    Noticeably, most neo-empiricists do not endorse Humes associationism.Hume proposed that processing relies on three laws: resemblance, contiguity,and causation (Hume, Enquiries, section 3). By contrast, neo-empiricists areusually committed to computational theories of our cognitive processes.Nonetheless, association by contiguity plays a significant role in someneo-empiricist accounts. For instance, Barsalou argues that we store togetherand we retrieve simultaneously percepts that are experienced simultaneouslyor successively (e.g., Barsalou et al., Grounding Conceptual Knowledge85; Barsalou, Continuity). I retrieve simultaneously the auditory perceptof Fidos barking and the visual percept of Fidos running because I have

    400 . Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    4/15

    often experienced together these two percepts, which have been, as a result,associated in memory.

    Finally, besides rejecting pictorialism and associationism, neo-empiricistsdiffer from traditional empiricists on two counts.Traditionally, empiricists

    have assumed that mental representations, which they thought of as mentalimages, refer by means ofsimilarity (e.g., Russell). Roughly, a mental imagerefers to the set of objects that are similar to it.There are many well-knownproblems with this view (e.g., Prinz ch. 2). Similarity is an unconstrainednotion:Any two things are similar in some respect (Goodman). Similarity,but not reference, is symmetric.And, prima facie, conscious mental imagesdo not refer by means of similarity:While wolves are similar to my mentalimage of dogs, my mental image of dogs is not about wolves.Asimilarity-based theory of reference is a burden for empiricist theories of

    mental states. However, Prinz has cogently argued that empiricist theoriesare not necessarily committed to a similarity-based theory of reference (ch.9). On the contrary, they can be combined with most contemporary theoriesof reference, including Fodors covariance theory (see Theory of Content)and Millikans teleological theory (see Language). Perceptual simulations ofapples may refer to apples, not because they are similar to apples, but becausethey covary with apples.

    Furthermore, neo-empiricists are not necessarily committed to animportant tenet of traditional empiricism, namely, anti-nativism (Barsalou,

    Perpectual Symbol Systems; Prinz, ch. 8). Perceptual representations canbe innate.4 For instance, evidence suggests that some perceptual repre-sentations of snake-like stimuli are innate (Mineka et al.).Thus, neo-empiricists could endorse some degree of representational nativism, roughly,the idea that some representations are innate.

    1.2. DISCUSSION

    Neo-empiricists claim that our conceptual knowledge is encoded in

    perceptual representations. Despite its apparent clarity, the notion ofperceptualrepresentation needs further explanation. Contrary to traditional empiricists,neo-empiricists cannot rely on introspection to illustrate this notion. Forthey propose that we should not think of perceptual representations on themodel of our conscious perceptual experiences (Barsalou,Perceptual SymbolSystems 582).

    There are two possible strategies to spell out the notion of perceptualrepresentation.The first strategy has been endorsed by Barsalou. He proposesthat amodal representations form linguisticsystems, while modal representationsare analogic (578).This strategy is not without problems.Analogicrepresentations are usually thought to be such that some properties of theirvehicles covary with what is represented. Maps and mercury thermometersare good examples. Evidence shows that there are some analogicrepresentations in the brain retinocentric maps, for instance. However,

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

    Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism . 401

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    5/15

    there is no evidence that analogic representations, so understood, arepervasive in the brain. Moreover, there are additional reasons to resistBarsalous proposal. Many perceptual representations could in fact belinguistic (Pylyshyn, Seeing and Visualizing).And, as we shall see in Section

    3, there is evidence that some representations are analogic andamodal inthe sense that they do not belong to any perceptual system. It is thusinadequate to contrast amodal and perceptual representations by means ofthe notion of analogic representations.

    As an alternative strategy, neo-empiricists could propose that perceptualrepresentations are whatever psychologists of perception say perceptioninvolves (Prinz 113). If psychologists of perception propose that perceptualrepresentations are similar to traditional amodal symbols, for instance ifperceptual representations form linguistic representational systems (Pylyshyn,

    Seeing and Visualizing), neo-empiricism would propose that our conceptualknowledge is stored in several linguistic systems. In this case, the distinctionbetween neo-empiricism and the amodal approach would be rather thin.

    Finally, it is useful to distinguish between wide-scope and narrow-scopeneo-empiricism.Wide-scope neo-empiricism claims that the two dogmasof neo-empiricism characterize all our conceptual knowledge and ourconceptual processes (Barsalou,Perceptual Symbol Systems). Narrow-scopeneo-empiricism claims instead that these two dogmas characterize merelya subset of our conceptual knowledge and of our conceptual processes

    (Goldstone and Barsalou).A similar distinction applies to amodaltheories.While some amodal theorists may claim that our higher cognitiveprocesses involve exclusively some knowledge stored in a distinct, amodalrepresentational system (exclusive amodal theories), most amodal theoristsassume in fact that besides our amodal representations, we also store inlong-term memory some perceptual states and that we use these perceptualstates in our higher cognition (e.g., Fodor, Language ofThought; Simon; fordiscussion, see Machery, Concept Empiricism). Interestingly, this secondkind of amodal theory may be compatible with narrow-scope neo-

    empiricism.This suggests that instead of a strict distinction, there is in facta continuum of positions between wide-scope neo-empiricism and anexclusive amodal theory.

    1.3. MAJOR STRENGTHS

    Like traditional empiricism, neo-empiricism provides a seductive (thoughinsufficiently detailed) account ofconcept acquisition. In brief, amodal theoriesof concepts typically assume that learning a concept consists in forminga complex concept out of primitive concepts. For instance, learning theconcept BACHELOR consists in forming the complex conceptUNMARRIED ADULT MALE.The concept MALE may itself becompounded out of other concepts. Primitive concepts are not learned(Fodor,Present Status). Since it is unlikely that all our concepts can be

    402 . Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    6/15

    produced out of a few primitive concepts, amodal theories of concepts seemat least committed to many non-learned primitive concepts.5 Neo-empiricisttheories of concepts seem to circumvent this problem. For these theories,acquiring a concept consists in selecting a subset of our percepts of the

    referent of this concept, maybe on the basis of the recurrence of thesepercepts, and in being able to reenact these percepts.There is thus no needof postulating a large class of primitive concepts, out of which other conceptscould be compounded. Instead, concepts are made out of perceptualrepresentations.

    Neo-empiricism is alsoparsimonious. Few deny that we store perceptualstates in long-term memory and that mental imagery is a real phenomenon.Wide-scope neo-empiricism proposes that our perceptual representationstogether with the mechanisms involved in imagery are sufficient to account

    for our higher cognition.Finally, Barsalou has recently proposed that the two dogmas ofneo-empiricism highlight the continuity between human cognition and otheranimal species cognition (Barsalou, Continuity). By contrast, he claimsthat amodal accounts of our conceptual knowledge typically assume adiscontinuity between humans and other animal species cognition.

    2.Theoretical IssuesBarsalou and Prinz recognize that traditional empiricism faced serioustheoretical challenges. But they claim that neo-empiricism meets thesechallenges (e.g., Barsalou,Perceptual Symbol Systems 581; Prinz 16988).In this section, I consider this claim.

    2.1.ABSTRACT CONCEPTS

    A common objection against empiricism is that it cannot account for abstractconcepts. In his sixth Meditation (1642), Descartes argued that some

    mathematical ideas cannot be images, because we know introspectively thatwe cannot entertain a visual image of complex mathematical entities suchas a chiliogon. Since neo-empiricists do not assume that reenacted perceptualrepresentations are conscious, they could reply that introspection may misleadus in this and similar cases.The gist of Descartess objection remains,however. For we have many concepts of entities for which there is, primafacie, no perceptual representation.What are indeed the perceptualrepresentations of democracy, freedom, spin, square roots, and primenumbers?

    Neo-empiricists have taken up the challenge (e.g., Barsalou,PerceptualSymbol Systems; Barsalou and Wiemer-Hastings; Prinz ch. 7). Focusingon specific abstract concepts, they have argued that entertaining theseconcepts could consist in reenacting a specific kind of perceptualrepresentation.Their strategy consists in specifying a typical situation where

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

    Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism . 403

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    7/15

    we would apply the abstract concept at hand and to propose that entertainingthis concept consists in simulating this situation. For instance, we typicallyapply the concept TRUE to an utterance, say the sky is blue, when wesuccessfully match the utterance to the world.Thus, neo-empiricists propose

    that to entertain the concept of truth could consist in simulating a situationwhere a speaker utters a sentence and a hearer verifies that this sentencematches the situation (Barsalou, Perceptual Symbol Systems 601; Prinz1778). Simulations corresponding to abstract concepts are assumed tobe dynamic, that is, to involve some changes in what is simulated.Thesimulation corresponding to the concept of truth involves successively aspeech act and the verification of its correspondence to a situation by ahearer. Simulations corresponding to abstract concepts are also assumed torecruit introspective states. Prinz argues that such simulations enable us to

    track and thus to refer to the referents of these abstract concepts.It is unclear whether this strategy can be applied to all abstract concepts,for instance, to the mathematical concept of a limit.6 The main problem,however, is that perceptual simulations, including dynamic and introspection-based simulations, are not sufficiently thin-grained to individuate abstractconcepts.As a result, such simulations are ill-suited to track the referent ofthese abstract concepts. For example, the simulation assumed to correspondto the concept of truth could also correspond to the concepts of accuracy,appropriateness, truthfulness, and reliability. Similarly, in most neo-empiricist

    experiments on abstract concepts, the motor and spatial simulations associatedwith entertaining abstract concepts (e.g., imagining something vertical orsomething horizontal) are too thick-grained to individuate the concepts athand.

    2.2. PROPOSITIONS

    The capacity of empiricist theories to account for propositional thoughtshas often been called into question (e.g., Fodor,Language ofThought17984).Barsalou and Prinz have taken up this challenge, since they assume thatconcepts compose to form propositional thoughts (Barsalou, PerceptualSymbol Systems 5957; Abstraction 1178; Prinz). Roughly, the idea isthe following.When we represent a simple proposition, such as theproposition that planes have wings, we reenact a perceptual representationof a plane and we bind this reenacted percept to the simulator of wings (seenote 2 on Barsalous notion of simulator). For instance, Barsalou writes(Abstraction 1182): [the proposition has(AEROPLANE, wings)] wouldonly exist after deliberately binding the wings simulator to the holistic

    AEROPLANEsimulation.There are two main issues. First, Barsalou says very little about the notion

    of binding. Despite intense work in cognitive and neural modeling, it remainsunclear how a non-linguistic system could allow for binding between

    404 . Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    8/15

    concepts.This is prima facie inconsistent with Barsalous rejection of alinguistic representational system for our conceptual knowledge.

    Second, concepts can be combined, or bound, in many ways. I couldcorrectly think that planes havewings, but I could also incorrectly think that

    planes are wings.

    To account for these different types of combination,Barsalou would have to introduce specific representations, IS or HAVE.When I think that planes are wings, the reenacted representation of planescould be bound to the representation of being and to the simulator forwings.When I think that planes have wings, the reenacted representationof planes could be bound to the representation of having and to the simulatorfor wings. Now, either these additional representations are amodal or theyare themselves perceptual representations.Although Barsalou may be readyto endorse the second alternative, it is unclear to me what perceptual

    representation could correspond to being.The problem does not stop here, however.The proposition that planeshave wings is different from the proposition that wings have planes. Hence,to express the proposition that planes have wings, it is insufficient to merelybind the perceptual simulation of planes to the simulators of having and ofwings.To distinguish between the two ways of binding the representationsof planes, wings and having, Barsalou would have to introducerepresentations of subject and object.Again, it is unclear what perceptualrepresentations correspond to subject and object.This argument suggests

    that entertaining a proposition might require amodal symbols.

    3. Empirical Evidence for Neo-Empiricism

    Contrary to its philosophical antecedents, neo-empiricism is not a meretheory of concepts and higher cognition. It also inspires a thriving experimentalresearch program.7 Barsalou has even argued that while (1) there is very littleempirical evidence for amodal theories of concepts, (2) there is a growingbody of evidence for neo-empiricism. Hence, if theoretical arguments do not

    weigh disproportionately in favor of amodal theories of concepts andBarsalou believes they dont we should prefer empiricist theories ofconcepts to their competitors.Thus, Barsalou et al. write:

    Amodal theories have been attractive theoretically because they implementimportant conceptual functions, such as the type-token distinction, categoricalinference, productivity and propositions....Conversely, indirect empiricalevidence has accumulated for modality-specific representations in workingmemory, long-term memory, language and thought. (Grounding ConceptualKnowledge 856)

    In this section, I succinctly question this argument. I argue that there is asubstantial body of evidence for the existence of amodal symbols. Moreover,the evidence for neo-empiricism is not fully convincing (for more details,see Machery,Concept Empiricism).

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

    Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism . 405

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    9/15

    3.1. EVIDENCE FOR AMODAL REPRESENTATIONS

    As noted above, amodal representations can take two forms linguistic oranalogic. Evidence for any of these two types of amodal representationwould be inconsistent with wide-scope neo-empiricism. I describe briefly

    a large body of behavioral and neuropsychological evidence that humanshave in fact amodal, analogic representations of the approximate cardinality of classesof entities (objects, sounds, events).

    Adults as well as, to some extent, babies are able to estimate theapproximate cardinality of classes of objects and to compare classes accordingto their cardinality, suggesting that they represent the approximate cardinalityof classes (for recent reviews, see Hauser and Spelke; Piazza andDehaene).Although there are several models of these representations, thesemodels concur in regarding the representations of cardinality as amodaland

    analogic(Piazza and Dehaene).This claim is supported by the following evidence.Adults can estimate

    the cardinality of classes, compare classes according to their cardinality, andadd cardinalities in several modalities, including vision and audition.Theirperformances have similar properties in both modalities.The developmentof these competences is also similar in both modalities: Children show thesame pattern of failures and successes in both modalities. Finally, adults cancompare the approximate cardinality of classes across, at least, vision andaudition (Barth, Kanwisher, and Spelke). Crucially, performance across

    modalities is as accurate as within a single modality.The same is true ofadults capacity to add cardinalities.

    Neo-empiricists seem committed to the claim that subjects rely only onperceptual, that is, visual, auditory, tactile (etc.) representations of cardinality.If this were the case, we would not expect similar performances in differentmodalities, similar developmental patterns, and, most important, equalaccuracy of subjects performances within modality and across modalities.Instead, these phenomena are strong evidence that subjects abstract amodalrepresentations of the cardinality of perceived classes from the auditory andvisual representations of theses classes.

    Other vertebrates, including pigeons, rats, new-world monkeys (tamarins)and old-world monkeys (macaques), are able to estimate and comparecardinality. Behavioral evidence suggests that cardinality estimation andcomparison display the same signature properties across species includingthe absence of modality effects (Meck and Church). Neurological evidencesuggests tentatively that cardinality representations involve the same neuralsubstrate in humans and macaques the intraparietal sulcus (Piazza and

    Dehaene).This provides evidence that cardinality estimation and comparison,together with the representations of the cardinality of classes, might be

    homologies phenotypic traits shared in virtue of common descent. If thisisthe case, amodal representations are phylogenetically ancient and independentof language.PaceBarsalou (Section 1), continuity between human cognition

    406 . Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    10/15

    and other species cognition does not require human cognition to beperceptual.

    This is evidence for amodal representations in only one domain number.However, this body of evidence is inconsistent with neo-empiricists claim

    that there is little evidence for amodal representations.

    3.2. PROBLEMS WITH THE EVIDENCE FOR NEO-EMPIRICISM

    There is, prima facie, a large body of evidence for neo-empiricism (for arecent review, see Barsalou et al., Multi-modal Simulation). For the sakeof space, I focus on the most striking empirical findings, which come fromBarsalous lab (Barsalou, Perceptual Symbol Systems; Barsalou et al.,Grounding Conceptual Knowledge; Barsalou et al., Multi-modal

    Simulation).Barsalou and colleagues results are derived from two experimental

    designs.The first design is called the feature listing task. Subjects are askedto list the properties of some type of objects, for example the properties oftables.This task has been commonly used in the psychology of concepts,because it is often thought that people access the information stored inconcepts to solve this task. Barsalou and the psychologist Ling-Ling Wustwo main findings can be put succinctly (Wu; Barsalou, Solomon, and Wu,Perceptual Simulation). First, the performance of subjects who have been

    told to visualize the target objects, for instance tables, while listing theproperties of these objects is similar to the performance of subjects that havenot received any explicit instruction. Barsalou and colleagues call thisphenomenon instructional equivalence. Second, subjects list significantlymore internal properties, for example, red, for the instances of adjective-nouncompounds, such as half watermelon, than for the instances of thecorresponding nouns, such as watermelon. Barsalou and colleagues callthis phenomenon perceptual work. Consistent with Thesis 2 (Section 1),these two phenomena suggest that subjects are spontaneously visualizing,

    while accessing concepts.We should however resist this conclusion. For, pace Barsalou and

    colleagues, these two findings are accommodated by some standardamodaltheories of concepts and higher cognition. Instructional equivalence isaccommodated by any theory of mental imagery that assumes that weentertain visual images under a description that is, a theory according towhich when we visualize a table, we entertain a visual representation togetherwith our concept of table (Fodor, Language ofThought). Perceptual work isaccommodated by amodal theories of concept combination inspired by thepragmatic requirements of communication (e.g., Costello and Keane; fordiscussion, see Machery, Concept Empiricism). In brief, these theoriespropose that when we interpret a noun phrase, such as half watermelon,we assume that the speaker intends to communicate as much specificinformation about the extension of the noun phrase as possible. If the

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

    Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism . 407

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    11/15

    outward aspect of the instances of the noun phrase (half watermelon)differs from the outward aspect of the instances of the noun (watermelon),outward aspect is a good candidate for such specific information.As a result,subjects are expected to list more internal properties for a noun phrase such

    as half watermelon than for a noun such as watermelon.The second design, which is also commonly used in the psychology ofconcepts, is called feature verification. Subjects see on a computer screenthe name of a class of objects, such as blouse, followed by the name of apart, such as sleeve. They have to decide whether the latter is usually apart of the former. Barsalou and the psychologist Karen Solomons mainfindings are the following (Solomon and Barsalou,Representing PropertiesLocally; Perceptual Simulation).When subjects decide successivelywhether a given part belongs to two types of objects, the second decision

    is primed only if the part has a similar shape in these two types of objects.Toillustrate, after having decided that horses have a mane, subjects are quickerto decide that ponies have a mane than to decide that lions have a mane.Second, the ratio of the volume of the part to the volume of the wholeobject, for instance, the ratio of the volume of a mane to the volume of alion, is a predictor of how fast subjects are to decide whether the part belongsto the object. Barsalou and colleagues argue that these findings are evidencefor Thesis 2.

    We should resist this conclusion. For, as noted in Section 1, many

    proponents of amodal theories recognize that in some tasks, we do visualizeobjects and manipulate visual representations.What they insist on is thatnot all tasks are solved this way. Now, verifying that an object has a givenpart is precisely the kind of task where amodal theorists expect people torely on visual imagery. For relying on imagery seems to be a fast and efficientway to solve this task.As a result, Barsalou and colleagues findings are notideally suited to distinguish between neo-empiricism and amodal theoriesof concepts and higher cognition.

    Barsalou and the psychologist Diane Pecher have developed a clever

    variant of the feature verification task (Pecher, Zeelenberg, and Barsalou,Verifying Different-Modality Properties; Sensorimotor Simulations).Subjects are presented with names of objects, such as leaves, and withnames of sounds, colors, and other perceptual properties, for instance,rustle.The main finding is that subjects are quicker to decide that leavesrustle, if this decision follows a previous decision involving the samemodality, for instance if subjects had to decide whether lions roar, thananother modality, for instance if subjects had to decide whether leaves aregreen.This is a very interesting finding. It may, however, be accommodatedby amodal theories of concepts, if concepts of perceptual properties (e.g.,GREEN) are located in the brain near the relevant perceptual modality:Thatis, if concepts of colors are located near the visual system, concepts of soundsare located near the auditory system, and so on. If this is the case, the braininstantiations of visual concepts are likely to overlap with each other, but

    408 . Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    12/15

    not with the brain instantiations of auditory concepts, and so on. Hence,the activation of a visual concept is likely to be primed by the activation ofanother visual concept, but not by the activation of an auditory concept.Neuropsychological evidence suggests that perceptual concepts are located

    in precisely this way (e.g., Martin and Chao).Finally, even if Barsalous findings were decisive, we should be cautiousin generalizing any conclusion to our whole conceptual system: For manyhigher cognitive functions, such as reasoning under uncertainty or induction,there is no evidence for or against neo-empiricism.

    4. Conclusion

    In spite of the criticisms developed in this article, there is little doubt that

    the recent revival of empiricism in philosophy, psychology, neuropsychology,and artificial intelligence is a positive development. Neo-empiricistsempirical findings constrain any present and future theory of representation

    be it amodal or empiricist. Moreover, proponents of amodal theoriescannot take anymore for granted that higher cognition involves themanipulation of amodal representations.They are compelled to specify theirviews in more details and to gather empirical evidence for them.

    It remains that neither the theory nor the evidence pulls decisively infavor of neo-empiricism. Despite laudable theoretical proposals, neo-empiricism

    seems ill-equipped to deal with abstract concepts and propositions. Moreover,despite its interest, the evidence for perceptual representations in highercognition falls short of being inconsistent with all standard amodal theoriesof concepts and higher cognition.

    I would like to conclude on a speculative note. Elsewhere (Machery,Concepts;Doing without Concepts), I have argued that the class of conceptsdivides into several heterogeneous subclasses, which have little in common. AsI put it, concepts are not a natural kind.Thus, it could be that one of thesesubclasses consists of perceptual representations.8

    Notes

    * Correspondence address: Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University ofPittsburgh, 1017 CL Pittsburgh 15260 USA.1 L.W. Barsalou et al.,Grounding Conceptual Knowledge in Modality-Specific Systems, Trendsin Cognitive Sciences 7 (2003): 8491; A. R. Damasio, Time-Locked Multiregional Retroactiva-tion: A Systems-Level Proposal for the Neural Substrates of Recall and Recognition, Cognition33 (1989): 2562; Damasio, Descartes Error: Emotions, Reason, and the Human Brain (NewYork:Avon Books, 1994); A. M. Glenberg, What Memory is for? Behavioral and Brain Sciences

    20 (1997): 155; G. Lakoff and M. Johnson, Philosophy in the Flesh:The Embodied Mind and itsChallenge to Western Thought (New York: Basic Books, 1999); J. M. Mandler, How to Build aBaby II: Conceptual Primitives, Psychological Review99 (1992): 587604; A. Martin and L. L.Chao.Semantic Memory and the Brain: Structure and Processes, Current Opinion in Neurobiology11 (2001): 194201; P. Poirier and B. Hardy-Valle, The Spatial-Motor View, TheCompositionality of Meaning and Content:Applications to Linguistics, Psychology and Neuroscience, eds.E. Machery, M.Werning, and G. Schurz (Heusenstamm: Ontos, 2005), 22950; J. J. Prinz,

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

    Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism . 409

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    13/15

    Furnishing the Mind. Concepts and their Perceptual Basis (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002); L.A.Stein,Imagination and Situated Cognition,Android Epistemology, eds. K. M. Ford, C. Glymour,and P. Hayes (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), 16782; S. L.Thompson-Schill,NeuroimagingStudies of Semantic Memory: Inferring How from Where, Neuropsychologia 41 (2003): 28092; R.A. Zwaan, R.A. Stanfield, and R. H.Yaxley, Language Comprehenders MentallyRepresent the Shapes of Objects, Psychological Science13.2 (2002): 16871.2 See Section 1.2 on how to characterize these perceptual representational systems.3 Barsalou calls simulator our knowledge in long-term memory.At times, he seems to argue thatsimulators are not representations, but merely mechanisms that underlie the reenactment ofperceptual representations when we grasp a concept (Abstraction 1180). He speaks howeverabout the content of these simulators; moreover, these simulators can be bound with occurrentperceptual representations into propositions (1182).As such, they are similar to what psychologistscall concepts.4 For the sake of the discussion, I assume that the notion of innateness is not bankrupt. See P.Griffiths,What is Innateness?The Monist85.1 (2002): 7085.5 Fodor argues that all lexical concepts are primitive, thus innate.6 Prinz could reply that for such concepts, grasping a concept is to know how to use the corres-

    ponding words.This reply would open Pandoras box, however. Since this strategy could beapplied to all lexical concepts, there would be little need forperceptualrepresentations proper.7 Introspective psychologists at the beginning of the twentieth century tried also to gather evidencefor empiricism. For example, S. C. Fisher, The Process of Generalizing Abstraction; and itsProduct, the General Concept, Psychological Monographs XXI, 2.90 (1916): 1209; E. Machery,100 Years of Psychology of Concepts:The Theoretical Notion of Concept and itsOperationalization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, forthcoming.8 I would like to thank Peter Machamer and Shaun Nichols for their comments on a previousversion of this article.

    Works Cited

    Barsalou, L.W. Abstraction in perceptual symbol systems. Philosophical Transactions of the RoyalSociety of London: Biological Sciences 358 (2003): 117787.

    .Continuity of the Conceptual System across Species. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (2005):309311.

    . Perceptual Symbol Systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (1999): 577609., K. O. Solomon, and L. L. Wu. Perceptual Simulation in Conceptual Tasks. Cultural,

    Typological, and Psychological Perspectives in Cognitive Linguistics:The Proceedings of the 4th Conferenceof the International Cognitive Linguistics Association.Vol. 3. Eds. M. K. Hiraga, C. Sinha, and S.Wilcox.Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 1999. 20928.

    and K.Wiemer-Hastings. Situating Abstract Concepts. Grounding Cognition:The Role ofPerception and Action in Memory, Language, and Thought. Eds. D. Pecher and R. Zwaan. NewYork: Cambridge UP, 2005. 129163.

    , et al.Grounding Conceptual Knowledge in Modality-Specific Systems. Trends in CognitiveSciences 7 (2003): 8491.

    , et al. Multi-Modal Simulation in Conceptual Processing. Categorization Inside and Outsidethe Lab: Essays in Honor of Douglas L. Medin. Eds. W. Ahn et al.Washington, DC: AmericanPsychological Association, 2005. 24970.

    Barth, H., N. Kanwisher, and E. Spelke. The Construction of Large Number Representationsin Adults. Cognition 86 (2003): 20121.

    Berkeley, G.A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. Ed. K.Winkler. Indianapolis:

    Hackett Publishing Company, 1734.Costello, F. J. and M. T. Keane. Efficient Creativity: Constraint Guided ConceptualCombination. Cognitive Science24.2 (2000): 299349.

    Damasio, A. R. Descartes Error: Emotions, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Avon Books,1994.

    . Time-Locked Multiregional Retroactivation:A Systems-Level Proposal for the NeuralSubstrates of Recall and Recognition. Cognition 33 (1989): 2562.

    410 . Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    14/15

    Descartes, R. Meditations on First Philosophy, with Selections from the Objections and Replies .Trans. J.Cottingham. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1637.

    Fisher, S. C. The Process of Generalizing Abstraction; and its Product, the General Concept.Psychological Monographs XXI, 2.90 (1916): 1209.

    Fodor, J.A. The Language ofThought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1975.. The Present Status of the Innateness Controversy. Representations: Philosophical Essays on

    the Foundations of Cognitive Science. Ed. J.A. Fodor, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981. 257316..A Theory of Content and Other Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990.Glenberg,A. M. What Memory is for? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1997): 155.Goldstone, R. L. and L. W. Barsalou. Reuniting Perception and Conception. Cognition 65

    (1998): 23162.Goodman, N. Languages of Art:An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett,

    1976.Griffiths, P. What is Innateness? The Monist85.1 (2002): 7085.Hauser, M. D. and E. S. Spelke. Evolutionary and Developmental Foundations of Human

    Knowledge:A Case Study of Mathematics. The Cognitive Neurosciences. 3rd ed. Ed. M.Gazzaniga. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004. 85364.

    Hume, D. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals (1748).Ed. P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1975.

    .A Treatise of Human Nature(1739). Ed. P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1975.Kan, I. P., et al. Role of Mental Imagery in a Property Verification Task: FMRI Evidence for

    Perceptual Representations of Conceptual Knowledge. Cognitive Neuropsychology 20 (2003):52540.

    Lakoff, G. and M. Johnson. Philosophy in the Flesh:The Embodied Mind and its Challenge to WesternThought. New York: Basic Books, 1999.

    Machery, E. Concept Empiricism:A Methodological Critique. Cognition. Forthcoming.. Concepts are not a Natural Kind. Philosophy of Science72.3 (2005): 44467.. Doing without Concepts. New York: Oxford UP. Forthcoming.

    . 100 Years of Psychology of Concepts:The Theoretical Notion of Concept and itsOperationalization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. Forthcoming.

    , M.Werning, and G. Schurz, eds. The Compositionality of Meaning and Content:Applicationsto Linguistics, Psychology and Neuroscience. Heusenstamm: Ontos, 2005.

    Mandler, J. M. How to Build a Baby II: Conceptual Primitives. Psychological Review99 (1992):587604.

    Martin, A. and L. L. Chao. Semantic Memory and the Brain: Structure and Processes. CurrentOpinion in Neurobiology 11 (2001): 194201.

    Meck,W. H. and R. M. Church. A Mode-Control Model of Counting and Timing Processes.Journal of Experimental Psychology:Animal Behavior Processes 9 (1983): 32034.

    Millikan, R. G. Language,Thought and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,

    1984.Mineka, S., et al. Observational Conditioning of Snake Fear in Rhesus Monkeys. Journal of

    Abnormal Psychology 93 (1984): 35572.Pecher, D., R. Zeelenberg, and L. W. Barsalou. Sensorimotor Simulations underlie Conceptual

    Representations: Modality-Specific Effects of Prior Activation. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review11 (2004): 1647.

    . Verifying Different-Modality Properties for Concepts Produces Switching Costs.Psychological Science14.2 (2003): 11924.

    Piazza, M. and S. Dehaene. From Number Neurons to Mental Arithmetic:The CognitiveNeuroscience of Number Sense. The Cognitive Neurosciences. 3rd ed. Ed. M. Gazzaniga.Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004. 86576.

    Poirier, P. and B. Hardy-Valle. The Spatial-Motor View. The Compositionality of Meaning andContent:Applications to Linguistics, Psychology and Neuroscience. Eds. E. Machery, M. Werning,and G. Schurz. Heusenstamm: Ontos, 2005. 22950.

    Prinz, J. J. Furnishing the Mind. Concepts and their Perceptual Basis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,2002.

    Pylyshyn, Z.W. Computation and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984.. Seeing and Visualizing: Its not What You Think. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2003.

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x

    Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism . 411

  • 7/29/2019 Dogmatic List

    15/15

    Russell, B. The Analysis of Mind. New York: Macmillan, 1921.Simon, H. A. Machine as Mind.Android Epistemology. Eds. K. M. Ford, C. Glymour, and P. J.

    Hayes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995. 2340.Smith, E. E., et al. Combining Concepts:A Selective Modification Model. Cognitive Science12

    (1988): 485527.Solomon, K. O., and L. W. Barsalou. Perceptual Simulation in Property Verification. Memory

    & Cognition 32.2 (2004): 24459.. Representing Properties Locally. Cognitive Psychology 43 (2001): 12969.Stein, L. A. Imagination and Situated Cognition. Android Epistemology. Eds. K. M. Ford, C.

    Glymour, and P. Hayes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995. 16782.Thompson-Schill, S. L. Neuroimaging Studies of Semantic Memory: Inferring How from

    Where. Neuropsychologia 41 (2003): 28092.Wu, L. L.Perceptual Representation in Conceptual Combination. Diss. U of Chicago, 1995.Zwaan, R.A., R.A. Stanfield, and R. H.Yaxley. Language Comprehenders Mentally Represent

    the Shapes of Objects. Psychological Science13.2 (2002): 16871.

    412 . Two Dogmas of Neo-Empiricism

    Blackwell Publishing 2006 Philosophy Compass 1/4 (2006): 398412, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00030.x