Discussion on Legal Positivism

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/13/2019 Discussion on Legal Positivism

    1/5

    Legal Positivism

    Legal positivism is the thesis that the existence and content of law depends on social

    facts and not on its merits. The English jurist John Austin formulated it thus: The

    existence of law is one thing; its merit and demerit another. hether it !e or !e not is

    one in"uir#; whether it !e or !e not conforma!le to an assumed standard$ is a different

    in"uir#.%&

    Legal positivism has a long histor# and a !road influence. 't has antecedents in ancient

    political philosoph# and is discussed$ and the term itself introduced$ in medieval legal

    and political thought.(

    The modern doctrine$ however$ owes little to these for!ears. 'ts

    most important roots lie in the conventionalist political philosophies of )o!!es and

    )ume$ and its first full ela!oration is due to Jerem# *entham whose account Austin

    adopted$ modified$ and populari+ed.

    Jerem# *entham is a legal philosopher primaril# ,nown for this -tilitarian theor#. )e

    proposes that man is governed !# pain and pleasure and that ever# act made !# man

    will result in either of the two. -tilit#$ for *entham$ is simpl# that part in an# act or

    omission that results to happiness. )e proposes that an# act or omission that results to

    pleasure is good and an# act or omission that results to pain is !ad. )e goes on to sa#

    that it is the legislators responsi!ilit# to !e a!le to measure and determine$ !ased on

    several factors including intensit#$ duration$ certaint#$ remoteness$ num!er of people

    affected and etc.$ what the predominant result would come from an act or omission.

    'f the act or omission results in a predominantl# pleasura!le tendenc#$ the act/omission

    is considered as good. 'f the act or omission results in more pain than pleasure$ the act

    or omission is !ad. Even if the act/omission is contrar# to morals$ customs$ and

    traditions$ as long as the result is more pleasura!le than painful$ then the act/omission is

    good.0

    &

    Austin$ John 1&20(3. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Ed. .E. 4um!le$

    &556. 7am!ridge: 7am!ridge -niversit# 8ress

    (9innis$ John 1&553. The Truth in Legal 8ositivism$% in The Autonomy of Law$ ed.

    4o!ert 8. eorge. .

    0Bentham, Jeremy 1748-1832).An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation.Ed. 1789. Oxford: Clarendon re!!

  • 8/13/2019 Discussion on Legal Positivism

    2/5

    John "#!t$n%! &on&e't of la( ha! the follo($n element!:

    1. *a( $! a &ommand $!!#ed +y the r#l$n !oere$n

    2. Command $! $en to the !#+e&t! for them to o+ey

    3. oere$n ex'e&t! the &ommand to +e ha+$t#ally o+eyed +y h$! !#+e&t! +#t doe!

    not ha+$t#ally o+ey anyone el!e.

    "#!t$n 're!#''o!e! that the relat$on!h$' +et(een the !oere$n and the !#+e&t +ody $!

    one that $! of !oere$nty and !#+e&t$on / !oere$n ex'e&t! ha+$t#al o+ed$en&e from the

    !#+e&t +ody +#t doe! not ne&e!!ar$ly and ha+$t#ally o+ey anyone el!e. 0he !oere$n $!

    the one that $! $nde'endent and #'on (h$&h the !#+e&t +ody $! de'endent on.

    't is important to note that Austin !elieved that onl# the sovereign could issue laws.

    Austin adheres to *enthams proposition that an# command issued !# the sovereign is

    deemed valid and thus must !e o!e#ed !# the su!ject !od# so the# will not suffer

    conse"uences for an# violation thereof. A law is onl# valid if it was issued from the

    proper authorit#. Austins test of validit# of a law was its source.

    'n ever#$ or almost ever#$ independent political societ#$ there are principles or

    maxims which the sovereign ha!ituall# o!serves$ and which the !ul, of societ#$ or

    !ul, of its influential mem!ers$ regard with feelings of appro!ation. ?ot infre"uentl#$

    such maxims are expressl# adopted$ as well as ha!ituall# o!served$ !# the

    sovereign or state. @ore commonl#$ the# are not expressl# adopted !# the

    sovereign or state$ !ut are simpl# imposed upon it !# opinions prevalent in the

    communit#. hether the# are expressl# adopted !# the sovereign or state$ or are

    simpl# imposed upon it !# opinions prevalent in the communit#$ it is !ound or

    constrained to o!serve them !# merel# moral sanctions.

  • 8/13/2019 Discussion on Legal Positivism

    3/5

    9or much of the next centur# an amalgam of their views$ according to which law is the

    command of a sovereign !ac,ed !# force$ dominated legal positivism and English

    philosophical reflection a!out law. *# the mid=twentieth centur#$ however$ this account

    had lost its influence among wor,ing legal philosophers. 'ts emphasis on legislative

    institutions was replaced !# a focus on law=appl#ing institutions such as courts$ and its

    insistence of the role of coercive force gave wa# to theories emphasi+ing the s#stematic

    and normative character of law. The most important architects of this revised positivism

    are the Austrian jurist )ans elsen and the two dominating figures in the anal#tic

    philosoph# of law$ ).L.A. )art and Joseph 4a+ among whom there are clear lines of

    influence$ !ut also important contrasts. Legal positivismBs importance$ however$ is not

    confined to the philosoph# of law. 't can !e seen throughout social theor#$ particularl# in

    the wor,s of @arx$ e!er$ and Cur,heim$ and also 1though here unwittingl#3 among

    man# law#ers$ including the American legal realists% and most contemporar# feminist

    scholars. Although the# disagree on man# other points$ these writers all ac,nowledge

    that law is essentiall# a matter of social fact. Dome of them are$ it is true$ uncomforta!le

    with the la!el legal positivism% and therefore hope to escape it. Their discomfort is

    sometimes the product of confusion. Law#ers often use positivist% a!usivel#$ to

    condemn a formalistic doctrine according to which law is alwa#s clear and$ however

    pointless or wrong$ is to !e rigorousl# applied !# officials and o!e#ed !# su!jects. 't is

    dou!tful that an#one ever held this view; !ut it is in an# case false$ it has nothing to do

    with legal positivism$ and it is expressl# rejected !# all leading positivists. Among the

    philosophicall# literate another$ more intelligi!le$ misunderstanding ma# interfere. Legal

    positivism is here sometimes associated with the homon#mic !ut independent doctrines

    of logical positivism 1the meaning of a sentence is its mode of verification3 or sociological

    positivism 1social phenomena can !e studied onl# through the methods of natural

    science3. hile there are historical connections$ and also commonalities of temper$

    among these ideas$ the# are essentiall# different. The view that the existence of law

    depends on social facts does not rest on a particular semantic thesis$ and it is

    compati!le with a range of theories a!out how one investigates social facts$ including

    non=naturalistic accounts. To sa# that the existence of law depends on facts and not on

    its merits is a thesis a!out the relation among laws$ facts$ and merits$ and not otherwise

  • 8/13/2019 Discussion on Legal Positivism

    4/5

    a thesis a!out the individual relation. )ence$ most traditional natural law% moral

    doctrines==including the !elief in a universal$ o!jective moralit# grounded in human

    nature==do not contradict legal positivism. The onl# influential positivist moral theories are

    the views that moral norms are valid onl# if the# have a source in divine commands or in

    social conventions. Duch theists and relativists appl# to moralit# the constraints that legal

    positivists thin, hold for law.6

    A positivist account of the existence and content of law offers a theor# of the validit# of

    law in one of the two main senses of that term.elsen sa#s that validit# is the specific

    mode of existence of a norm. An invalid marriage is not a special ,ind of marriage having

    the propert# of invalidit#; it is not a marriage at all. 'n this sense a valid law is one that is

    s#stemicall# valid in the jurisdiction == it is part of the legal s#stem. This is the "uestion

    that positivists answer !# reference to social sources. 't is distinct from the idea of

    validit# as moral propriet#$ i.e. a sound justification for respecting the norm. 9or the

    positivist$ this depends on its merits.

  • 8/13/2019 Discussion on Legal Positivism

    5/5

    fairness == so there is no o!ligation to unfair or pointless laws. 24a+ goes further still$

    arguing that there isnBt even a prima facie dut# to o!e# the law$ not even in a just state. 5

    The peculiar accusation that positivists !elieve the law is alwa#s to !e o!e#ed is without

    foundation. )artBs own view is that an overweening deference to law consorts more

    easil# with theories that im!ue it with moral ideals$ permitting an enormous

    overvaluation of the importance of the !are fact that a rule ma# !e said to !e a valid rule

    of law$ as if this$ once declared$ was conclusive of the final moral "uestion: F Philosophical !eview$ pp. &6=

    5&.

    54a+$ Joseph 1&553. The Authority of Law.