6
DEMONSTRATIVE REASONING 201 quickness, and, at the same time, with caution; in other words, to examine subjects, and to do it with expedition. In this way they have acquired exceeding readiness in all their mental acts. The consequence of this is, that the numerous minute circumstances, involved more or less in all subjects of difficult inquiry, are passed in review with such rapidity, and are made in so very small a degree the objects of separate attention, that they vanish and are for- gotten. Hence these persons, although the conclusion to which they have come be satisfactory, are unable to state to others all the subordinate steps in the argument. Everything has once been distinctly and fairly before their own minds, although with that great rapidity which is always implied in a habit ; but their argument, as sta- ted in words, owing to their inability to arrest and imbody all the evanescent processes of thought, appears to others defective and confused. CHAPTER X. DEMONSTRATIVE REASONING. <) 185. Of the subjects of demonstrative reasoning. In the remarks which have hitherto been made, the subject of reasoning has been taken up in the most gen- eral point of view. The considerations that have been proposed are applicable, in the main, to reasoning in all its forms. But it is necessary, in order to possess a more full and satisfactory conception of this subject, to exam- ine it under the two prominent heads of Moral and De- monstrat ve. There are various particulars in which moral and de- monstrative reasoning differ from each other j the consid- eration of which will suggest more fully their distinctive nature. Among other things, demonstrative reasoning differs from any other species of reasoning in the subjects about which it is employed. The subjects are abstract ideas, and the necessary relations among them. Those

Demonstrative Reasoning

  • Upload
    caphil

  • View
    217

  • Download
    3

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Thomas Upham

Citation preview

Page 1: Demonstrative Reasoning

DEMONSTRATIVE REASONING 201

quickness, and, at the same time, w i th caut ion; in other words, to examine subjects, and to do i t w i th expedition. I n this way they have acquired exceeding readiness in all their mental acts. The consequence of this is, that the numerous minute circumstances, involved more or less in all subjects of difficult inquiry, are passed in review wi th such rapidity, and are made in so very small a degree the objects of separate attention, that they vanish and are for­gotten. Hence these persons, although the conclusion to which they have come be satisfactory, are unable to state to others al l the subordinate steps in the argument. Everything has once been distinctly and fair ly before their own minds, although w i th that great rapidity which is always implied in a habit ; but their argument, as sta­ted in words, owing to their inabil ity to arrest and imbody all the evanescent processes of thought, appears to others defective and confused.

CHAPTER X.

DEMONSTRATIVE REASONING.

<) 185. Of the subjects of demonstrative reasoning.

In the remarks which have hitherto been made, the subject of reasoning has been taken up in the most gen­eral point of view. The considerations that have been proposed are applicable, in the main, to reasoning in all its forms. But it is necessary, in order to possess a more full and satisfactory conception of this subject, to exam­ine it under the two prominent heads of Moral and De-monstrat ve.

There are various particulars in which moral and de­monstrative reasoning differ from each other j the consid­eration of which will suggest more fully their distinctive nature. Among other things, demonstrative reasoning differs from any other species of reasoning in the subjects about which it is employed. The subjects are abstract ideas, and the necessary relations among them. Those

Page 2: Demonstrative Reasoning

202 DEMONSTRATIVE REASONING.

ideas or thoughts are called abstract which are represent­ative of such qualities and properties in objects as can be distinctly examined by the mind separate from other qualities and properties with which they are commonly united. And there may be reckoned, as coming within this class of subjects, the properties of numbers and of geo­metrical figures ; also extension, duration, weight, veloci­ty, forces, & c , so far as they are susceptible of being accu­rately expressed by numbers or other mathematical signs. But the subjects of moral reasoning, upon which we are to remark hereafter more particularly, are matters of fact, including their connexion with other facts, whether con­stant or variable, and all attendant circumstances.—That the exterior angle of a triangle is equal to both the inte­rior and opposite angles, is a truth which comes within the province of demonstration. That Homer was the au­thor of the Iliad, that Xerxes invaded Greece, & c , are inquiries belonging to moral reasoning.

§ 186. Use of definitions and axioms in demonstrative reasoning.

In every process of reasoning, there must be, at the commencement of it, something to be proved; there must also be some things, either known or taken for granted as such, with which the comparison of the propositions begins. The prehminary truths in demonstrative reason­ings are involved in such definitions as are found in all mathematical treatises. I t is impossible to give a dem­onstration of the properties of a circle, parabola, ellipse, or other mathematical figure, without first having given a definition of them. Definitions, therefore, are the facts assumed, the f i r s t principles in demonstrative reasoning,. from which, by means of the subsequent steps, the conclu­sion is derived.—We find something entirely similar in respect to subjects which admit of the application of a different form of reasoning. Thus, in Natural Philosophy, the general facts in relation to the gravity and elasticity of the air may be considered as first principles. From these principles in Physics are deduced, as consequences, the suspension of the mercury in the barometer, and its fall when carried up to an eminence.

We mast not forget here the use of axioms in the dem-

Page 3: Demonstrative Reasoning

DEMONSTRATIVE REASONING. 203

Fc

onstrations of mathematics. Axioms are certain self-ey ident propositions, or propositions the truth of which is discovered by intuition, such as the fo l lowing: " Things equal to the same, are equal to one another;" " F r o m equals take away equals, and equals remain." W e gen­erally find a number of them prefixed to treatises of ge­ometry, and other treatises involving geometrical princi-les; and i t has been a mistaken supposition, which has

ong prevailed, that they are at the foundation of geomet­rical and of al l other demonstrative reasoning. But axioms, taken by themselves, lead to no conclusions. W i t h their assistance alone, the truth, involved in proposi­tions susceptible of demonstration, would have been be­yond our reach.

But axioms are by no means without their use, although their nature may have been misunderstood. They are properly and originally intuitive perceptions of the t ru th ; and whether they be expressed in words, as we gen­erally find them, or not, is of but l itt le consequence, ex­cept as a matter of convenience to beginners, and in giv­ing instruction. But those intuitive perceptions which are always implied in them are essential helps; and i f by their aid alone we should be unable to complete a demonstration, we should be equally unable without them. We begin wi th definitions; we compare together suc­cessively a number of propositions; and these intuitive perceptions of their agreement or disagreement, to which, when expressed in words, we give the name of axioms, attend us at every step.

i 187. The opposites of demonstrative reasonings absurd.

I n demonstrations we consider only one side of a ques­tion ; i t is not necessary to do anything more than this. The first principles in the reasoning are g iven; they are not only supposed to be certain, but they are assumed as such; these are followed by a number of propositions in succession, all of which are compared together; i f the conclusion be a demonstrative one, then there has been a clear perception of certainty at every step in the train. Whatever may be urged against an argument thus con­ducted is of no consequence •, the opposite of it w i l l a!-

Page 4: Demonstrative Reasoning

204 DEMONSTRATIVE REASONING.

ways imply some fallacy. Thus, the proposition that the three angles of a triangle are not equal to two right angles, and other propositions, which are the opposite of what has been demonstrated, wi l l always be found to be false, and also to involve an absurdity; that is, are in­consistent with, and contradictory to, themselves.

But it is not so in Moral Reasoning. And here, there­fore, we find a marked distinction between the two great forms of ratiocination. We may arrive at a conclusion on a moral subject with a great degree of certainty; not a doubt may be left in the mind; and yet the opposite of that conclusion may be altogether within the limits of possibility. We have, for instance, the most satisfactory evidence that the sun rose to-day, but the opposite might have been true, without any inconsistency or contradic­tion, viz., That the sun did not rise. Again, we have no doubt of the great law in physics, that heavy bodies de­scend to the earth in a line directed towards its centre. But we can conceive of the opposite of this without involv­ing any contradiction or absurdity. In other words, they might have been subjected, i f the Creator had so deter­mined, to the influence of a law requiring them to move in a different direction. But, on a thorough examination of a demonstrative process, we shall find ourselves unable to admit even the possibility of the opposite.

<J 18S. Demonstrations do not admit of different degrees of belief.

When our thoughts are employed upon subjects which come within the province of moral reasoning, we yield different degrees of assent; we form opinions more or less probable. Sometimes our belief is of the lowest kind; nothing more than mere presumption. New evidence gives it new strength; and it may go on, from cne de­gree of strength to another, t i l l all doubt is excluded, and all possibility of mistake shut out.—It is different in dem­onstrations ; the assent which we yield is at all times of the highest kind, and is never susceptible of being regard­ed as more or less. This results, as must be obvious on the slightest examination, from the nature of demonstra­tive reasoning.

In demonstrative reasonings we always begin with

Page 5: Demonstrative Reasoning

DEMONSTRATIVE REASONING. 205

certain first principles or truths, either known or taken for granted; and these hold the first place, or are the found­ation of that series of propositions over which the mind successively passes unti l i t rests in the conclusion. I n mathematics, the first principles, of which we here speak, are the definitions.

We begin, therefore, w i th what is acknowledged by all to be true or certain. A t every step there is an in tu i ­tive perception of the agreement or disagreement of the {)ropositions which are compared together. Consequent-y, however far we may advance in the comparison of

them, there is no possibility of fal l ing short of that degree of assent w i th which i t is acknowledged that the series commenced.—So that demonstrative certainty may be judged to amount to this. Whenever we arrive at the last step, or the conclusion of a series of propositions, the mind, i n effect, intuitively perceives the relation, whether i t be the agreement or disagreement, coincidence or want of coincidence, between the last step or the conclusion, and the conditions involved in the propositions at the commencement of the series; and, therefore, demonstra­tive certainty is virtually the same as the certainty of in« tuition. Although i t arises on a different occasion, and is, therefore, entitled to a separate consideration, there is no difference in the degree of belief.

§ 189. Of tha use of diagrams in demonstrations.

In conducting a demonstrative process, i t is frequently the case that we make use of various kinds of figures or diagrams.—The proper use of diagrams, of a square, cir­cle, triangle, or other figure which we delineate before us, is to assist the mind in keeping its ideas distinct, and to help in comparing them together w i th readiness and correctness. They are a sort of auxiliaries, brought in to the help of our intellectual infirmities, but are not abso­lutely necessary; since demonstrative reasoning, where-ever i t may be found, resembles any other k ind of reason­ing in this most important respect, viz., in being a com­parison of our ideas.

In proof that artificial diagrams are only auxiliaries, and are not essentially necessary in demonstrations it

S

Page 6: Demonstrative Reasoning

206 MORAL REASONING.

may be remarked, that they are necessarily all of them imperfect. I t is not within the capability of the wit and power of man to frame a perfect circle, or a perfect tri­angle, or any other figure which is perfect. We might argue this from our general knowledge of the imperfec­tion of the senses; and we may almost regard it as a matter determined by experiments of the senses them­selves, aided by optical instruments. " There never was," says Cudworth, " a straight line, triangle, or circle, that we saw in all our lives, that was mathematically exact; but even sense itself, at least by the help of microscopes, might plainly discover much unevenness, ruggedness, flex-uosity, angulosity, irregularity, and deformity in them."*

Our reasonings, therefore, and our conclusions, wil l not apply to the figures before us, but merely to an imagined perfect figure. The mind can not only originate a figure internally and subjectively, but can ascribe to i t the attri­bute of perfection. And a verbal statement of the prop­erties of this imagined perfect figure is what we under­stand by a definition, the use of which, in this kind of reasoning in particular, has already been mentioned

CHAPTER XL

MORAL REASONING.

§ 190. Of the subjects and importance of moral reasoning.

Moral reasoning, which is the second great division or kind of reasoning, concerns opinions, actions, and events; embracing, in general, those subjects which do not come within the province of demonstrative reasoning. The subjects to which it relates are often briefly expressed, by saying that they are matters of f a c t ; nor would this defi­nition, concise as it is, be likely to give an erroneous idea of them.

Skill in this kind of reasoning is of great use in the formation of opinions concerning the duties and the gen-

* Treatise concerning Im-mitable Morality, bk. iv., ch iii.