Daniel a. Dombrowski, Rethinking the Ontological

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/29/2019 Daniel a. Dombrowski, Rethinking the Ontological

    1/2

    Int J Philos Relig (2007) 62:171172

    DOI 10.1007/s11153-007-9130-0

    Daniel A. Dombrowski, Rethinking the Ontological

    Argument: A Neoclassical Theistic ResponseNew York: Cambridge University Press, 2006, 172 pp, Hb, US$ 70.00

    Donald Wayne Viney

    Received: 12 May 2007 / Accepted: 14 May 2007 / Published online: 20 July 2007 Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2007

    In numerous books and articles, Daniel Dombrowski has explored nearly every aspect of

    Charles Hartshornes thought. This book discusses the contribution for which Hartshorne

    himself is most widely credited, namely, the rehabilitation of the ontological argument. Begin-

    ning with his dissertation in 1923, Hartshorne defended the argument as part of a cumulative

    case for Gods existence. (Dombrowski rightly emphasizes that Hartshorne never considered

    it as a proof sufficient in itself.) In articles in Philosophical Review (1944, vols. 53 and 54), he

    answered the challenge to give a non-fallacious syllogistic statement of the argument. Sevenyears before Norman Malcolms Anselms Ontological Arguments, Hartshorne made the

    same point in Philosophers Speak of God(1953). He identified one version of the argument

    in Proslogion chapter II that had been attacked by philosophers from Gaunilo to Russell, and

    a second version in chapter III, that had been ignored by nearly all of those just mentioned.

    The argument ofPros. II presupposes that existence is a perfection, but Pros. IIIs argument

    presupposes that modality of existencespecifically, necessary existenceis a perfection.

    The second argument, unlike the first, does not confuse the existential quantifier with a pred-

    icate. Hartshorne further clarified Anselms reasoning in a notice of Malcolms article in The

    Journal of Philosophy (1961, vol. 58) and in The Logic of Perfection (1962) by expressing it in

    the formalism of Lewiss S5 modal logic. These developments occasioned a refreshing shift

    in the literature from rehearsing Kantian objections to debating the metaphysics of modality.

    Dombrowskis aim is to reconsider the neoclassical case for the modal argument in light

    of reactions both to Hartshornes work and, more generally, to the ontological argument as

    a paradigm of metaphysical reasoning. The intent is not to give an exhaustive survey of the

    critical literature but to respond to representative trends of thought about the argument. The

    discussion is wide-ranging, competently bringing together disparate thinkers, from decon-

    structive postmodernists to mainstream analytic philosophers. These groups are often not

    very good at talking to each other, but Dombrowski at least manages to put them in dialogue

    with Hartshorne and to make the case for his distinctive approach to the argument and to

    D. W. Viney (B)

    Department of Social Sciences/Philosophy, Pittsburg State University,

    412 G Russ Hall, Pittsburg 66762, KS, USA

    e-mail: [email protected]

    123

  • 7/29/2019 Daniel a. Dombrowski, Rethinking the Ontological

    2/2

    172 Int J Philos Relig (2007) 62:171172

    metaphysical inquiry as an open-ended search for necessary truths about existence. A curious

    lacuna is that, despite an opening chapter on the history of the argument, none of Hartshornes

    formalizations of the argument are included, save a position matrix which is less an argument

    than a list of options (119).

    Hartshornes neoclassical defense of the modal argument is the centerpiece for arguing,against Richard Rorty (chapter 2) and Mark Taylor (chapter 3), for the very possibility of

    metaphysics in a postmodern context. Rorty is famous for declaring philosophy otiose. He

    eschews the projects of getting things right and of seeking certainty about eternal veri-

    ties. Hartshorne meets Rorty half-way by emphasizing the fallibility of our knowledge of

    metaphysical necessities. Moreover, the truths in question do not transcend time but are the

    everlasting features of process. Dombrowski shows that Hartshornes metaphysics is less an

    attempt to mirror reality (to use Rortys metaphor) than to accurately interpret it, analogous

    to the way a map can represent a landscape while leaving out a wealth of detail. An illustra-

    tion is Hartshornes insistence that, at most, the argument shows the necessary existence of

    God, not the actual states in which God exists. Dombrowski claims that it is precisely this

    point that Taylor misses in his critique of the viability of philosophy (62f). By focusing

    on Hegels use of the argument, Taylor wrongly concludes that metaphysics negates divine

    alterity. Hartshorne, on the contrary, denies that one can infer any contingent state of God

    from the necessary truth that God exists.

    Nearly a third of the book (chapters 4 and 5) is devoted to replying to Graham Oppy, who

    Dombrowski honors as the ontological arguments greatest contemporary critic (26). He

    accusesOppy, however, of operatingwith a truncated conception of the theistic alternativesto

    classical theism and thereby failing to do justice to Hartshornes neoclassical variety(8889).

    Therelevance of this criticism forthe ontological argumentis twofold. First, Oppy, like Taylor,treats existence and actuality as roughly synonymous (116). This gives the false impression

    that Hartshorne thinks one can deduce a concrete reality from an abstract definition. Second,

    Oppy does not attend to Hartshornes semantics for modal operators. For Hartshorne, the

    temporal-causal matrix provides the anchor for all discourse about modality. Necessity upon

    contingent conditions is what must be, given the actual past; unconditional necessity is what

    must be, given any actual past. Combining these points one can say that divine existence

    can only be unconditionally necessary whereas divine actuality can only be necessary upon

    contingent conditions (96f). Making these discriminations also provides an answer to the

    various parodies of the argument: for example, Gaunilos perfect island can be necessary,

    at most, upon contingent conditions, like erosion, sea level, tectonic movements, etc.In the last chapter, Dombrowski engages a triad of philosophers who are favorably dis-

    posed towards Anselms reasoning: Thomas Morris, Katherin Rogers, and Alvin Plantinga.

    They accept that God cannot exist contingently, but they resist Hartshornes view that God

    must exist with some world or other. As they see it, this compromises divine sovereignty and

    aseity. Dombrowski does not here enter (as he has elsewhere) this thicket of philosophical

    theology. He simply registers his doubts about the coherence of classical theism. If he (and

    Hartshorne) are correct, then, barring a workable alternative such as neoclassical theism, the

    ontological proof becomes an ontological disproofGods existence would be an impossi-

    bility. This fact shows that Oppy is mistaken to view debates over the concept of God asunimportant (139).

    Dombrowski expertly shows the intimate link between Hartshornes defense of the modal

    argument and his dipolar theism. Moreover, his measured assessment is a welcome

    counter-point to Oppys strident declaration that ontological arguments are completely

    worthless (5). No one expects religious conversion from a philosophical argument, but the

    intelligibility it may bring to the religious life is value enough.

    123