21
1 ยฉ philosophy.org.za Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations Most of what counts for Science or indeed Humani- ties cannot be expressed solely in terms of the predicate calculus we have learned so far. This is because these disciplines proceed by discovering relations among things. A relation then, is a connec- tion that one (or more) things or phenomena have to others. In the case that they involve two objects, they can be expressed by, so called, binary predi- cates (with two subjects) that represent the relation that subsists between them. Thus: John loves Sarah Even though โ€œSarahโ€ is the grammatical object of the sentence above, both โ€œJohnโ€ and โ€œSarahโ€ are regarded as the subjects of the binary predicate โ€œโ€ฆ lovesโ€ฆโ€. Of course some relations like love can relate to themselves, such as: John loves himself Quite naturally speaking, there are several triadic or even tetradic predicates that relate three or for subjects respectively. E.g. George is between Cape Town and Port Elizabeth. and Jack traded his cow to the peddler for some magic beans. Examples of polyadic predicates involving many subjects do exist but tend to result from longer lists of subjects rather than naturally spoken relations; although sentences such as the following are the exception: Jean and Murray played Diane and Ben at bridge over a bowl of popcorn. As Copi (p. 117) observes, relations enter into arguments in various ways, such as: Al is older than Bill. Bill is older than Charlie. Therefore, Al is older than Charlie. This is simply a relational argument in which other relational predicates could have featured, such as โ€œโ€ฆis taller than..,โ€ โ€œโ€ฆis wiser than..,โ€ โ€œโ€ฆ is heavier thanโ€ฆโ€ etc. Consider the following, slightly more complex argument involving quantification: Helen likes David. Whoever likes David likes Tom. Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz, (1646 - 1716 ) More Often Remembered for his Independent Invention of Calculus, was also a Philosopher and Logician of Note. Seen here in a Portrait housed at the Regional Library of Hannover.

Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    1

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

1

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic

of Relations

Most of what counts for Science or indeed Humani-

ties cannot be expressed solely in terms of the

predicate calculus we have learned so far. This is

because these disciplines proceed by discovering

relations among things. A relation then, is a connec-

tion that one (or more) things or phenomena have

to others. In the case that they involve two objects,

they can be expressed by, so called, binary predi-

cates (with two subjects) that represent the relation

that subsists between them. Thus:

John loves Sarah

Even though โ€œSarahโ€ is the grammatical object of

the sentence above, both โ€œJohnโ€ and โ€œSarahโ€ are

regarded as the subjects of the binary predicate โ€œโ€ฆ

lovesโ€ฆโ€. Of course some relations like love can

relate to themselves, such as:

John loves himself

Quite naturally speaking, there are several triadic or even tetradic predicates that relate three or for

subjects respectively. E.g.

George is between Cape Town and Port Elizabeth. and

Jack traded his cow to the peddler for some magic beans.

Examples of polyadic predicates involving many subjects do exist but tend to result from longer lists

of subjects rather than naturally spoken relations; although sentences such as the following are the

exception:

Jean and Murray played Diane and Ben at bridge over a bowl of popcorn.

As Copi (p. 117) observes, relations enter into arguments in various ways, such as:

Al is older than Bill. Bill is older than Charlie. Therefore, Al is older than Charlie. This is simply a relational argument in which other relational predicates could have featured, such as

โ€œโ€ฆis taller than..,โ€ โ€œโ€ฆis wiser than..,โ€ โ€œโ€ฆ is heavier thanโ€ฆโ€ etc. Consider the following, slightly more

complex argument involving quantification:

Helen likes David. Whoever likes David likes Tom.

Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz, (1646 - 1716 )

More Often Remembered for his Independent

Invention of Calculus, was also a Philosopher and

Logician of Note. Seen here in a Portrait housed at

the Regional Library of Hannover.

Page 2: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

2

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

Helen likes only good-looking men. Therefore, Tom is a good-looking man. The following more complex relational argument employed by Copi (l.c.) meanwhile involves

multiple quantification.

All horses are animals. Therefore, the head of a horse is the head of an animal. Fortunately, no novel methods of proof, other than those already encountered in Critical Reasoning

11, are required to prove the validity of such arguments. However we must pay particular attention

to the way we symbolise relational propositions.

Symbolising Relations

So far, we have used only one-place predicates of the form ๐น๐‘ฅ to represent โ€œ๐‘ฅ is fastโ€. Now we can

expand this notation to represent predicates of the form:

๐‘ฅ is taller than ๐‘ฆ as: ๐‘‡๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ and

๐‘ฅ is between ๐‘ฆ and ๐‘ง as: ๐ต๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ๐‘ง.

Although other publications follow the convention of symbolising binary or dyadic as โ€œ๐‘ฅ๐‘‡๐‘ฆโ€ and so

on, we shall stick with Copiโ€™s notation, if only for consistency.

Just as we regarded different substitution instances of the same predicate โ€œ๐น๐‘ฅโ€, as representing

different propositions, so we may regard different substitution instances of the same polyadic

predicate e.g. โ€œ๐ต๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ๐‘งโ€, as representing different propositions. Note that the order of substitution is

very important here. If the predicate โ€œ๐‘ฅ taught ๐‘ฆโ€ is substituted in terms of โ€œ๐‘ฅโ€ for โ€œSocratesโ€ and

โ€œ๐‘ฆโ€ for โ€œPlatoโ€, the proposition:

๐‘‡๐‘ ๐‘ is true,

whereas the proposition:

๐‘‡๐‘๐‘  is false.

According to the meaning of a proposition, we may be required to use either existential or universal

quantification, either singly or in combination, when symbolising it. Either way we should pay

especial heed to which variables are free and which are bound (see Critical Reasoning 11 p.6) as well

as the scope of our quantifiers. Do they extend across the whole expression or only part of it? The

following examples were compiled from lecture notes as well as Copi (p. 119 ff.) Where the meaning

of an expression may not be immediately apparent, a paraphrasal is suggested.

1. Something is taller than everything.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)๐‘‡๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ

Paraphrasal: There exists an ๐‘ฅ, such that for all ๐‘ฆ, ๐‘ฅ is taller than ๐‘ฆ.

Page 3: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

3

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

2. George is between Cape Town and something or other.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐‘”๐‘๐‘ฅ

3. There is something between Cape Town and Port Elizabeth.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐ต๐‘ฅ๐‘๐‘

4. There is something, such that that George is between that thing and Port Elizabeth.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐‘”๐‘ฅ๐‘

5. Everything attracts everything.

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)( โˆ€๐‘ฆ)๐ด๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ

Paraphrasal: For any ๐‘ฅ and for any ๐‘ฆ, ๐‘ฅ attracts ๐‘ฆ.

6. Everything is attracted by everything.

(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)๐ด๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ

Paraphrasal: For any ๐‘ฆ and for any ๐‘ฅ, ๐‘ฅ attracts ๐‘ฆ. (The passive voice of 5, above)

7. Something attracts something.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)๐ด๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ

8. Something attracts nothing.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)~๐ด๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ

9. Alice is attracted by something.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐ด๐‘ฅ๐‘Ž

10. Nothing attracts Bert.

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐ด๐‘ฅ๐‘

11. Something is attracted by itself.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐ด๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ

12. Nothing attracts itself.

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐ด๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ

Exercise: Now that we have seen how some common relations are symbolised, you may wish to try

your hand at symbolising some of the more challenging sentences provided by Copi, section 5.1 part

II (p. 128). The first ten are reproduced below.

1. Dead men tell no tales.

2. A lawyer who pleads his own case has a fool for a client.

Page 4: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

4

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

3. A dead lion is more dangerous than a live dog.

4. Uneasy lies the head that wears the crown.

5. If a boy tells only lies, none of them will be believed.

6. Anyone who consults a psychiatrist ought to have his head examined.

7. No one ever learns anything unless he teaches it to himself.

8. Delilah wore a ring on every finger and had a finger in every pie.

9. Any man who hates children and dogs cannot be all bad.

10. Anyone who accomplishes anything will be envied by everyone.

Solutions: The following solutions, some of which are not the same as Copiโ€™s, were provided by

Professor Peter Suber in the form of a hand-out. The full set of 45 translations is available here. They

are reproduced below with additional paraphrasals. Note that the format adopted by Suber is known

as โ€œprenex normal formโ€. Accordingly, โ€œall the quantifiers in a formula are stacked at the left end,

none is negated, and the scope of each extends to the end of the whole formula.โ€ (l.c.) This is not

the only preferred form. Indeed many logicians do not follow a consistent format, preferring to

preserve the form of natural language wherever possible.

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐ท๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‡๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ~๐‘‡๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ]

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ and for all ๐‘ฆ, such that if ๐‘ฅ is dead and ๐‘ฅ is a man and ๐‘ฆ is a tale,

then ๐‘ฅ does not tell ๐‘ฆ.

2. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐ฟ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (๐ถ๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐น๐‘ฆ)]

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ and for all ๐‘ฆ, such that if ๐‘ฅ is a lawyer and ๐‘ฅ pleads ๐‘ฅโ€™s case (i.e.

his own), then ๐‘ฆ has ๐‘ฅ as a client and ๐‘ฆ is a fool.

Note that the meaning of the proposition is preserved in this formulation, however we

only appreciate the wit when we realise that the lawyer and client are the same person.

This can be made explicit as follows: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[(๐ฟ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (๐ถ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐น๐‘ฅ)]

3. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(~๐ด๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ฟ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ด๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐ท๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ]

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ and for all ๐‘ฆ, such that if ๐‘ฅ is not alive and ๐‘ฅ is a lion and ๐‘ฆ is alive

and ๐‘ฆ is a dog, then ๐‘ฅ is more dangerous than ๐‘ฆ.

4. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[(๐ป๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ถ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ˆ๐‘ฅ]

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ and there exists a ๐‘ฆ, such that if ๐‘ฅ is a head and ๐‘ฆ is a crown and ๐‘ฅ

wears ๐‘ฆ, then ๐‘ฅ lies uneasy.

5. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)(โˆ€๐‘ข){[๐ต๐‘ฅ โ€ข (๐‘‡๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐ฟ๐‘ฆ)] โŠƒ (๐‘‡๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐ต๐‘ข๐‘ง)}

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ, ๐‘ฆ, ๐‘ง and ๐‘ข, if ๐‘ฅ is a Boy and if ๐‘ฅ tells ๐‘ฆ such that ๐‘ฆ is a lie, then if ๐‘ฅ

tells ๐‘ฆ then ๐‘ข will not believe ๐‘ง.

6. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘†๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ถ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ]

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ and there exists some ๐‘ฆ, then if ๐‘ฅ is a person and ๐‘ฆ is a

psychiatrist and ๐‘ฅ consults ๐‘ฆ then ๐‘ฅ ought to have his head examined.

Page 5: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

5

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

7. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ~๐ฟ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ~๐‘‡๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ]

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ and there exists some ๐‘ฆ, such that if ๐‘ฅ is a person and ๐‘ฅ did not

learn ๐‘ฆ, then ๐‘ฅ did not teach ๐‘ฆ to ๐‘ฅ (himself).

8. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[(๐น๐‘ฅ๐‘‘ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ] โ€ข (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐น๐‘ฅ๐‘‘ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐ผ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ]

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ and there exists some ๐‘ฆ, such that ๐‘ฅ is a finger of Delilahโ€™s and ๐‘ฆ is

a ring then ๐‘ฆ is on ๐‘ฅ, and there exists some ๐‘ฅ and for all ๐‘ฆ, such that ๐‘ฅ is a finger of

Delilahโ€™s and ๐‘ฆ is a pie, then ๐‘ฅ is in ๐‘ฆ.

Note that this is a conjunction between two quantified statements. Unlike the prenex

normal form, none of the quantifiersโ€™ scope extends across the whole formula.

9. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘€๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ถ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ง โ€ข ๐ป๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ป๐‘ฅ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ~๐ต๐‘ฅ]

Note: Copi treats โ€œ๐‘ฅ is all badโ€ as a predicate so there is no need to quantify badness.

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ, ๐‘ฆ and ๐‘ง such that if ๐‘ฅ is a man, ๐‘ฆ is a child and ๐‘ง is a dog and ๐‘ฅ

hates ๐‘ฆ and ๐‘ฅ hates ๐‘ง, then ๐‘ฅ is not all bad.

10. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข ๐ด๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐ธ๐‘ง๐‘ฅ]

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ and there exists some ๐‘ฆ and for all ๐‘ง such that if ๐‘ฅ is a person and

๐‘ง is a person and ๐‘ฅ accomplishes ๐‘ฆ, then ๐‘ง envies ๐‘ฅ.

Note that Copiโ€™s sentence allows that any and every thing that is accomplished will

result in the accomplisher being envied by all persons, including themselves.

Arguments Involving Relations

As mentioned, no new techniques are required in dealing with arguments involving relations. The

four quantification inferences learned in Critical Reasoning 11 now take on the following forms:

Universal Instantiation (UI) Universal Generalisation (UG)

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅ ๐น๐‘ฅ โˆด ๐น๐‘ฅ โˆด (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅ Existential Instantiation (EI) Existential Generalisation (EG)

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅ ๐น๐‘ฆ ๐น๐‘ฅ โˆด (โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)๐น๐‘ฆ โ‹ฎ ๐‘ โˆด ๐‘ Unlike the previous quantification rules, here we do not require that ๐œ‡ and ๐œˆ be different variables.

Instead we can simply instantiate with respect to the same variable in a premise. Of course the other

restrictions apply, such as the correct nesting of assumptions. Similarly, where we have two

premises (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅ and (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)~๐น๐‘ฅ we begin our instantiation of one by simply dropping the quantifier,

Page 6: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

6

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

then we must instantiate the other in terms another letter if it is within the scope of the first

instantiation. (Copi, p. 131)

Consider, by way of example, the following proofs of validity from Copi (Ex II p. 133-4) again

provided by Professor Suber (available here.)

2. All circles are figures. Therefore all who draw circles draw figures.

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ฅ] /โˆด (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ)] 2. ๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ 3. ๐ถ๐‘ฅ 2 Simp. 4. ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ 2 Simp. 5. ๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ฅ 1 UI 6. ๐น๐‘ฅ 5,3 M.P. 7. ๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ 6,4 Conj. 8. (๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) 2-7 CP 9. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ)] 8 UG 10. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ)] 9 UG

5. Whoever belongs to the Country Club is wealthier than any member of the Elks Lodge. Not

everyone who belongs to the Country Club is wealthier than anyone who does not belong.

Therefore, not everyone belongs to either to the Country Club or the Elks Lodge.

Paraphrasal: For all ๐‘ฅ and for all ๐‘ฆ such that if ๐‘ฅ belongs to the Country Club and ๐‘ฆ belongs

to the Elks Lodge then ๐‘ฅ is wealthier than ๐‘ฆ. There exists an ๐‘ฅ and there exists a ๐‘ฆ such that

๐‘ฅ belongs to the Country Club and ๐‘ฆ does not belong to the Country Club such that ๐‘ฅ is not

wealthier than ๐‘ฆ. (I.e. At least one member of the Country Club is not wealthier than at least

one non-member.) Therefore, there exists an ๐‘ฅ that is neither a member of the Country Club

nor a member of the Elks Lodge.

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ธ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ] 2. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ~๐ถ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ~๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) /โˆด (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(~๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ~๐ธ๐‘ฅ) 3. (โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ~๐ถ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ~๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) 4. ๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ~๐ถ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ~๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ 5. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ธ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ] 1 UI 6. (๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ธ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ 5 UI 7. ๐ถ๐‘ฅ 4 Simp. 8. ~๐ถ๐‘ฆ 4 Simp. 9. ~๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ 4 Simp. 10. ~(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ธ๐‘ฆ) 6,9 M.T. 11. ~๐ถ๐‘ฅ v ~๐ธ๐‘ฆ 10 De M. 12. ~๐ธ๐‘ฆ 11,7 D.S. 13. ~๐ถ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ~๐ธ๐‘ฆ 8,12 Conj. 14. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(~๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ~๐ธ๐‘ฅ) 13 EG 15. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(~๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ~๐ธ๐‘ฅ) 3,4-14 EI 16. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(~๐ถ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ~๐ธ๐‘ฅ) 2,3-15 EI

7. Everything on my desk is a masterpiece. Anyone who writes a masterpiece is a genius.

Someone very obscure wrote some of the novels on my desk. Therefore, some very obscure

person is a genius.

Page 7: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

7

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ท๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฅ) 2. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐บ๐‘ฅ] 3. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) /โˆด (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฅ) 4. (โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) 5. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ 6. ๐ท๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฆ 1 UI 7. ๐ท๐‘ฆ 5 Simp. 8. ๐‘€๐‘ฆ 6,7 M.P. 9. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ 5 Simp. 10. ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ 5 Simp. 11. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ 9,8,10 Conj. 12. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐บ๐‘ฅ] 2 UI 13. (๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐บ๐‘ฅ 12 UI 14. ๐บ๐‘ฅ 13,11 M.P. 15. ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ 5 Simp. 16. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฅ 9,15,14 Conj. 17. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฅ) 16 EG 18. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฅ) 4,5-17 EI 19. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฅ) 3,4-18 EI

Jon Ross has provided more proofs to this and further exercises in Copiโ€™s text. The interested reader

can find the relevant introduction and links here or direct links to the remaining chapters as follows :

chapter 5, chapter 7, and Chapter 8.

Some Attributes of Binary or Dyadic Relations

Relations themselves have several interesting attributes, some of which may enter into proofs. For

now we shall confine ourselves to binary or dyadic relations, however there is no upper limit on the

number of attributes of polyadic relations.

1. Symmetry: A relation is symmetrical if the following is true: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ)

Paraphrasal: If ๐‘ฅ has a relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ฆ, then ๐‘ฆ has relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ฅ.

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is next to ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ is married to ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘Ž is the twin of ๐‘โ€ etc.

On the other hand, a relation is asymmetrical if the following is true (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ)

Paraphrasal: If ๐‘ฅ has a relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ฆ, then ๐‘ฆ does not have a relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ฅ.

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is older than ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ is North of ๐‘ฆโ€ etc.

Meanwhile, a relation is non-symmetrical if it is neither symmetrical nor asymmetrical.

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is a sister of ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ loves ๐‘ฆโ€ etc.

2. Transitivity: A relation is transitive if the following is true: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ง]

Paraphrasal: If ๐‘ฅ has a relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ฆ and ๐‘ฆ has the same relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ง, then ๐‘ฅ has the same

relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ง.

Page 8: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

8

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is North of ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ is larger than ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘†1 predates ๐‘†2โ€ etc.

On the other hand, a relation is intransitive if: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ง]

Paraphrasal: If ๐‘ฅ has a relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ฆ and ๐‘ฆ has the same relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ง, then ๐‘ฅ cannot have the

same relation ๐‘… to ๐‘ง.

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is the father of ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ weighs exactly twice as much as ๐‘ฆโ€ etc.

Meanwhile, a relation is non-transitive if it is neither transitive nor intransitive.

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ loves ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ has a different mass to ๐‘ฆ"

3. Reflexivity: A relation ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ is reflexive if: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ v ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ]

Paraphrasal: ๐‘ฅ has a relation ๐‘… to itself if there is some ๐‘ฆ such that either ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ or ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ.

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is the same age as ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ is a contemporary of ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ has the same eye colour as ๐‘ฆโ€ etc.

As a special case, a relation ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ is totally reflexive if the following is true that: ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is identical to itselfโ€

Meanwhile, a relation ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ is irreflexive if it is true that: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ

Paraphrasal: ๐‘ฅ cannot have a relation ๐‘… to itself.

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is North of ๐‘ฆ", or โ€œ๐‘ฅ is married to ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ > ๐‘ฆ for Real numbersโ€

Finally, a relation is non-reflexive if it is neither totally reflexive, reflexive nor irreflexive.

E.g. โ€œ๐‘ฅ loves ๐‘ฆโ€, or โ€œ๐‘ฅ hates ๐‘ฆโ€ etc.

Note: Most binary or dyadic relations have more than one property or attribute. E.g. the relation:

โ€œโ€ฆ weighs more thatโ€ฆโ€ is at the same time asymmetrical, transitive and irreflexive, while that of โ€œโ€ฆ

weighs the same asโ€ฆโ€ is symmetrical, transitive and reflexive. (Copi, p. 136) See if you can identify

the attributes in the following relations.

1. ๐‘ฅ is uncle of ๐‘ฆ. 2. ๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฆ 3. ๐‘ฅ is as big as ๐‘ฆ. 4. ๐‘ฅ is a sister of ๐‘ฆ.

Solutions:

1. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is uncle of ๐‘ฆโ€ is at the same time:

(a) asymmetrical: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘ˆ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘ˆ๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) (b) intransitive: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘ˆ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ˆ๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ~๐‘ˆ๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] and (c) irreflexive: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘ˆ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ

Page 9: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

9

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

2. โ€œ๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฆโ€ is at the same time:

(a) symmetrical: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ (๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ)] (b) transitive: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง){[(๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฆ) โ€ข (๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ง)] โŠƒ (๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ง)} and (c) totally reflexive: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฅ)

3. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is as big as ๐‘ฆโ€ is at the same time:

(a) symmetrical: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ต๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐ต๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) (b) transitive: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐ต๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ต๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐ต๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] and (c) reflexive: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)(๐ต๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ v ๐ต๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐ต๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ]

4. โ€œ๐‘ฅ is a sister of ๐‘ฆโ€

(a) non-symmetrical: neither symmetrical nor asymmetrical - no symmetrical relation (b) transitive: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘†๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] (c) irreflexive: (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ

Copi (p. 136) points out furthermore, that some attributes entail the presence of others, such as that

all asymmetrical relations must also be irreflexive. This he derives as follows:

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) Definition of asymmetry 2. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) 1 UI 3. ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 2 UI 4. ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ v ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 3 Impl. 5. ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 4 Taut. 6. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 5 UG

This last line, as can be seen, is the definition of irreflexivity and so the proof is complete.

Note: When using models to prove invalidity, such as those introduced in Critical Reasoning 11, we

must be cautious when assessing arguments that involve relational attributes. We cannot, for

example, consistently begin with a model ๐‘Ž containing only one object when a relation of

irreflexivity, (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ obtains. There must be at least two non-identical objects. Similarly with the

relation of transitivity, (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] a potentially consistent model must

contain at least three non-identical objects.

Enthymemes

One problem with relational attributes is precisely that they are assumed and therefore unstated. In

Critical Reasoning 01 we called such arguments enthymemes. Where premises are supressed or

โ€œunderstoodโ€ we shall have to take them into account when considering validity. (Copi p. 136-137)

Consider the argument on page 1 above: Al is older than Bill. Bill is older than Charlie. Therefore, Al is older than Charlie.

Page 10: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

10

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

Technically it is invalid as it stands, but we account it valid just the same because the relationship of

โ€œโ€ฆ being older thanโ€ฆโ€ has the obvious, but unstated, attribute of transitivity. Sometimes however

the missing or auxiliary premise may be about factual linguistic assumptions. Consider:

All dogs are tame. Therefore, Fido is tame. Clearly we are assuming that Fido is a dog (๐ท๐‘“) and so we have:

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ท๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘‡๐‘ฅ) /โˆด ๐‘‡๐‘“ 2. ๐ท๐‘“ (auxiliary premise) 3. ๐ท๐‘“ โŠƒ ๐‘‡๐‘“ 1 UI 4. ๐‘‡๐‘“ 3,2 M.P. Even within the same relatively simple argument we might make multiple assumptions about

relations and matters of fact, as in the following example by Copi (p. 138-139).

Any horse can outrun any dog. Some greyhounds can outrun any rabbit. Therefore, any horse can outrun any rabbit. Here we are making the assumption that the relation โ€œโ€ฆ can outrunโ€ฆโ€ is a transitive one and the

fact that all greyhounds are dogs. This makes the argument only a little longer to state but more

lengthy to prove. Here is Copiโ€™s proof of the same:

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[๐ป๐‘ฅ โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ท๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ)] 2. (โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[๐บ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐‘…๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง)] /โˆด (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[๐ป๐‘ฅ โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐‘…๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง)] 3. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] (auxiliary premise of transitivity) 4. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐บ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐ท๐‘ฆ) (auxiliary premise that all greyhounds are dogs) 5. ๐ป๐‘ฅ 6. ๐‘…๐‘ง 7. ๐บ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐‘…๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) 8. ๐บ๐‘ฆ 7 Simp. 9. ๐บ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐ท๐‘ฆ 4 UI 10. ๐ท๐‘ฆ 9,8 M.P. 11. ๐ป๐‘ฅ โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ท๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) 1 UI 12. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ท๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) 11,5 M.P. 13. ๐ท๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ 12 UI 14. ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ 13,10 M.P. 15 (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐‘…๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) 7 Simp. 16. ๐‘…๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง 15 UI 17. ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง 16,6 M.P. 18. ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง 14,17 Conj. 19. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] 3 UI 20. (โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] 19 UI 21. (๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘‚๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง 20 UI 22. ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง 21,18 M.P. 23. ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง 2,7-22 EI 24. ๐‘…๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง 6-23 C.P. 25. (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐‘…๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง) 24 UG 26. ๐ป๐‘ฅ โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐‘…๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง) 5-25 C.P. continued over pageโ€ฆ

Page 11: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

11

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

27. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[๐ป๐‘ฅ โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐‘…๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ง)] 26 UG Exercise: If you have a copy of Copiโ€™s textbook at hand you may wish to try and prove a selection of

some of the enthymemes from the exercise at the end section 5.3 on pages 139-140. Otherwise,

here are the first two. The solutions below were provided by John Ross.

1. A Cadillac is more expensive than any low-priced car. Therefore, no Cadillac is a low-priced

car. (๐ถ๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is a Cadillac. ๐ฟ๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is a low-priced car. ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ: ๐‘ฅ is more expensive than ๐‘ฆ.)

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ฟ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ)] /โˆด (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ~๐ฟ๐‘ฅ) 2. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ (auxiliary premise of irreflexivity) 3. ๐ถ๐‘ฅ 4. ๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ฟ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) 1 UI 5. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ฟ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) 4,3 M.P. 6. ๐ฟ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 5 UI 7. ~๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 2 UI 8. ~๐ฟ๐‘ฅ 6,7 M.T. 9. ๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ~๐ฟ๐‘ฅ 3-8 C.P 10. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ~๐ฟ๐‘ฅ) 9 UG

2. Alice is Bettyโ€™s mother. Betty is Charleneโ€™s mother. Therefore, if Charlene loves only her

mother, then she does not love Alice. (๐‘Ž: Alice. ๐‘: Betty. ๐‘: Charlene. ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ: ๐‘ฅ is mother of ๐‘ฆ.

๐ฟ๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ: ๐‘ฅ loves ๐‘ฆ.

1. ๐‘€๐‘Ž๐‘ 2. ๐‘€๐‘๐‘ /โˆด (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ฟ๐‘๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘) โŠƒ ~๐ฟ๐‘๐‘Ž 3. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ~๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] (auxiliary premise of intransitivity) 4. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ฟ๐‘๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘) 5. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ~๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] 3 UI 6. (โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ~๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] 5 UI 7. (๐‘€๐‘Ž๐‘ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘๐‘) โŠƒ ~๐‘€๐‘Ž๐‘ 6 UI 8. ๐ฟ๐‘๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘ 4 UI 9. ~๐‘€๐‘Ž๐‘ โŠƒ ~๐ฟ๐‘Ž๐‘ 8 Trans. 10. (๐‘€๐‘Ž๐‘ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘๐‘) โŠƒ ~๐ฟ๐‘Ž๐‘ 7,9 H.S. 11. ๐‘€๐‘Ž๐‘ โ€ข ๐‘€๐‘๐‘ 1,2 Conj. 12. ~๐ฟ๐‘Ž๐‘ 10, 11 M.P. 12. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ฟ๐‘๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘€๐‘ฅ๐‘) โŠƒ ~๐ฟ๐‘๐‘Ž 4-12 C.P.

Identity

The special relation of identity, symbolised by the โ€œ=โ€ sign merits special treatment, both because of

its importance and ubiquity. According to the Identity of Indiscernibles or Law of Identity1, two

entities are identical if and only if they have all their properties in common; thus:

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฆ) โ‰ก (โˆ€๐น)(๐น๐‘ฅ โ‰ก ๐น๐‘ฆ)]

1 The term โ€œLeibnizโ€™ lawโ€ is confusing because it may also refer to the โ€œproduct ruleโ€ or the โ€œgeneralized product ruleโ€ in calculus.

Page 12: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

12

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

This formulation of identity is much stronger that of our informal use of the term when, for example

referring to โ€œidenticalโ€ twins. Even if two twins, say Bobby and Joe, are truly indiscernible even by

their parents, one would have the property of having one name, the other another. One may have

the property of standing on the left, the other on the right. One may have the property of having

been born minutes before the other, and so on. Therefore, they are not logically identical.

We should also pause here to point out that quantifying over properties as we have done here is

regarded as illegitimate by a significant proportion of philosopher-logicians for reasons that will take

us too far from the present topic. Suffice it to say that you may regard the Identity of Indiscernibles

and what follows as given, until such time as you have developed your own reasoned position on the

matter.

Rules of Identity (Id.)

ฮฆ๐œ‡ ฮฆ๐œ‡ ๐œˆ = ๐œ‡ ๐‘ ๐œˆ = ๐œ‡ ~(ฮฆ๐œˆ) โˆด ๐œ‡ = ๐‘ฃ โˆด ๐œ‡ = ๐œ‡ โˆด ฮฆ๐œˆ โˆด ~(ฮฝ = ฮผ) Consider the following instances of use of the rules of identity, left to right:

1. Dollar Brand is a musician. Dollar Brand is Abdullah Ibrahim. Therefore, Abdullah Ibrahim is a

musician.

1. ๐‘€๐‘‘ 2. ๐‘‘ = ๐‘Ž /โˆด ๐‘€๐‘Ž 3. ๐‘€๐‘Ž 1,2 Id.

2. Dollar Brand is talented. Phil is not talented. Therefore, Dollar Brand is not Phil.

1. ๐‘‡๐‘‘ 2. ~๐‘‡๐‘ /โˆด ๐‘‘ โ‰  ๐‘ 3. ๐‘‘ โ‰  ๐‘ 1,2 Id.

3. Dollar Brand is Abdullah Ibrahim. Therefore, Abdullah Ibrahim is Dollar Brand.

๐‘‘ = ๐‘Ž /โˆด ๐‘Ž = ๐‘‘ (Identity is symmetrical.)

4. If Dollar Brand is identical to himself, then Phil is South African. Therefore, Phil is South

African.

1. (๐‘‘ = ๐‘‘) โŠƒ ๐‘†๐‘ /โˆด ๐‘†๐‘ 2. ๐‘‘ = ๐‘‘ 1. Id. (Identity is totally reflexive.) 3. ๐‘†๐‘ 1,2 M.P. Note that in the above examples identity is not used on only part of line. Also observe the shorthand

๐œˆ โ‰  ๐œ‡ for ~(ฮฝ = ฮผ).

Examples of sentences involving the identity predicate: ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is a person; ๐‘—= Jane; ๐‘‡๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ: ๐‘ฅ is taller than ๐‘ฆ.

1. Jane is taller than anyone else.

Page 13: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

13

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘—) โŠƒ ๐‘‡๐‘—๐‘ฅ]

2. There is someone who is taller than any other person. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ){๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ฆ โ‰  ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘‡๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ]}

3. Jane is the only intelligent person. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฅ = ๐‘—] or (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘—) โŠƒ ~๐ผ๐‘ฅ]

4. There is only one intelligent person. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ){(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ฅ) โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ]}

Note that the left hand side of the โ€ข with the largest scope ensures that there is at least one

such person, while the expression to the right ensures that there is at most one.

5. There are exactly two intelligent persons. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ){(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ฆ) โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ง) โŠƒ (๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ฆ)]}

Note again, how in similar fashion, the left hand side of the โ€ข with the largest scope insures

that there are at least two such persons, while the expression to the right ensures that there

are at most two. There is no upper limit on how logic can โ€œcountโ€ in this way, except to

observe that the expressions very quickly become increasingly cumbersome.

6. Al is on the team and can outrun anyone else on it. (๐‘Ž = Al; ๐‘‡๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is on the team. ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ: ๐‘ฅ can

outrun ๐‘ฆ) If, in this example by Copi, (p. 143) we were to write: ๐‘‡๐‘Ž โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐‘‡๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘Ž๐‘ฅ), it

would entail that Al can outrun himself, whereas we know that being able to outrun is an

irreflexive relation. What we have to capture is the meaning of the word โ€œelseโ€, hence:

๐‘‡๐‘Ž โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[(๐‘‡๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘Ž) โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘Ž๐‘ฅ] Arguments Involving Identity Consider the following examples of proofs involving identity before trying your own hand at nos. 5,

6, 9 and 10 from the exercise at the end of section 5.4 of Copi (p. 150):

1. Bill is Smith. Smith is taller than Jones. Therefore, Bill is taller than someone or other. (Note

that the โ€œisโ€ in the first premise is one of identity not predication.)

1. ๐‘ = ๐‘  2. ๐‘‡๐‘ ๐‘— /โˆด (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐‘‡๐‘๐‘ฅ 3. ๐‘‡๐‘๐‘— 1,2 Id. 4. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐‘‡๐‘๐‘ฅ 3 E.G.

2. 1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ) 2. โˆผ ๐‘…๐‘๐‘ 3. ๐‘Ž = ๐‘ฅ /โˆด ๐‘Ž โ‰  ๐‘ continued over pageโ€ฆ

Page 14: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

14

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

4. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘Ž = ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘…๐‘Ž๐‘ฆ) 1 UI 5. ๐‘Ž = ๐‘ โŠƒ ๐‘…๐‘Ž๐‘ 4 UI 6. ~๐‘…๐‘Ž๐‘ 2,3 Id. 7. ๐‘Ž โ‰  ๐‘ 5,6 M.T.

3. 1. ๐น๐‘Ž 2. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐บ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘Ž = ๐‘ฅ) /โˆด (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฅ) 3. ๐บ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘Ž = ๐‘ฅ 4. ๐‘Ž = ๐‘ฅ 3 Simp. 5. ๐น๐‘ฅ 1,4 Id. 6. ๐บ๐‘ฅ 3 Simp. 7. ๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฅ 5,6 Conj. 8. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฅ) 7 E.G. 9. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฅ) 2,3-8 EI

4. Only Jane is intelligent. Someone who is intelligent is tall. Therefore Jane is tall. 1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ผ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘ฅ = ๐‘—) 2. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐ผ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‡๐‘ฅ) /โˆด ๐‘‡๐‘— 3. ๐ผ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘‡๐‘ฅ 4. ๐ผ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘ฅ = ๐‘— 1 UI 5. ๐ผ๐‘ฅ 3 Simp. 6. ๐‘ฅ = ๐‘— 4,5 M.P. 7. ๐‘‡๐‘ฅ 3 Simp. 8. ๐‘‡๐‘— 7,6 Id. 9. ๐‘‡๐‘— Selected Solutions to Copi (p. 150)

5. All entrants will win. There will be, at most, one winner. There is at least one entrant.

Therefore, there is exactly one entrant. (๐ธ๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is an entrant; ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ will win)

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ธ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ) 2. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘Š๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ] (note the standard translation for โ€œat most oneโ€)

3. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐ธ๐‘ฅ /โˆด (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)[๐ธ๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ)] (and for โ€œthere is exactly oneโ€) 4. ๐ธ๐‘ฅ 5. ๐ธ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ 1 UI 6. ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ 5,4 M.P. 7. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘Š๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ] 2 UI 8. (๐‘Š๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘Š๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ 7 UI 9. ๐‘Š๐‘ฅ โŠƒ (๐‘Š๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ) 7 Exp. 10. ๐‘Š๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ 9,6 M.P. 11. ๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘Š๐‘ฆ 1 UI (having used UI on 5, we must now use ๐‘ฆ) 12. ๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ 11,10 H.S. 13. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ) 12 UG 14. ๐ธ๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ) 4,13 Conj. 15. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)[๐ธ๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ)] 14 EG 16. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)[๐ธ๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ)] 3,4-15 EI

Page 15: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

15

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

9. There is exactly one penny in my right hand. There is exactly one penny in my left hand.

Nothing is in both my hands. Therefore there are exactly two pennies in my hands. (๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is

a penny; ๐‘…๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is in my right hand; ๐ฟ๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is in my left hand.)

1. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ){๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ]} 2. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ){๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ฟ๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ฟ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ]} 3. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(~๐‘…๐‘ฅ v ~๐ฟ๐‘ฅ) /โˆด (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ) โ€ข (๐‘…๐‘ฆ v ๐ฟ๐‘ฆ) โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง){[๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ง v ๐‘…๐‘ง)] โŠƒ (๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ฆ)}] 4. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ข โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ข โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ข] 5. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ฟ๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ฟ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ] 6. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ข 4 Simp. 7. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ 5 Simp. 8. ๐‘…๐‘ข 4 Simp. 9. ๐ฟ๐‘ฅ 5 Simp. 10. ๐‘…๐‘ข v ๐ฟ๐‘ข 8 Add. 11. ๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ 9 Add. 12. ~๐‘…๐‘ข v ~๐ฟ๐‘ข 3 UI 13. ๐‘…๐‘ข โŠƒ ~๐ฟ๐‘ข 12 Impl. 14. ~๐ฟ๐‘ข 13, 8 M.P. 15. ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ข 9,14 Id. 16. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ข 7,6 Conj. 17. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ข โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ) 16,11 Conj. 18. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ข โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ) โ€ข (๐‘…๐‘ข v ๐ฟ๐‘ข) 17,10 Conj. 19. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ข โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ) โ€ข (๐‘…๐‘ข v ๐ฟ๐‘ข) โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ข 18,15 Conj. 20. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ง v ๐‘…๐‘ง) 21.(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ข] 4 Simp. 22.(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ฟ๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ] 5 Simp. 23. (๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘ง = ๐‘ข 21 UI 24. (๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข ๐ฟ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ 22 UI 25. (๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข ๐ฟ๐‘ง) v (๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ง) 20 Dist. 26. [(๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข ๐ฟ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ] โ€ข [(๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ง) โŠƒ ๐‘ง = ๐‘ข] 24,23 Conj. 27. ๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ข 26,25 C.D. 28. [๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ง v ๐‘…๐‘ง)] โŠƒ (๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ข) 20-27 C.P. 29. (โˆ€๐‘ง){[๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ง v ๐‘…๐‘ง)] โŠƒ (๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ข)]} 28 UG 30. ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ข โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ) โ€ข (๐‘…๐‘ข v ๐ฟ๐‘ข) โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ข โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง){[๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ง v ๐‘…๐‘ง)] โŠƒ (๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ข)} 19,29 Conj. 31. (โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ) โ€ข (๐‘…๐‘ฆ v ๐ฟ๐‘ฆ) โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง){[๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ง v ๐‘…๐‘ง)] โŠƒ (๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ฆ)}] 30 EG 32. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ) โ€ข (๐‘…๐‘ฆ v ๐ฟ๐‘ฆ) โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง){[๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ง v ๐‘…๐‘ง)] โŠƒ (๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ฆ)}] 31 EG 33. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ) โ€ข (๐‘…๐‘ฆ v ๐ฟ๐‘ฆ) โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง){[๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ง v ๐‘…๐‘ง)] โŠƒ (๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ฆ)}] 2,5-32 EI 34. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐‘ฆ)[๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘…๐‘ฅ) โ€ข (๐‘…๐‘ฆ v ๐ฟ๐‘ฆ) โ€ข ๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง){[๐‘ƒ๐‘ง โ€ข (๐ฟ๐‘ง v ๐‘…๐‘ง)] โŠƒ (๐‘ง = ๐‘ฅ v ๐‘ง = ๐‘ฆ)}] 1,4-33 EI

Page 16: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

16

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

Russellโ€™s Theory of Descriptions

What is the meaning of the word โ€œtheโ€? Despite

โ€œtheโ€ being the most commonly used word in the

English language, very few of us (who havenโ€™t done

a course in Linguistics or the Philosophy of Lan-

guage) are likely to know. True, we know how to

use it and pace Wittgenstein, for whom meaning is

use, it was not until Bertrand Russellโ€™s 1905, now

classic paper โ€œOn Denotingโ€ (available here) pub-

lished in the journal โ€œMindโ€ that most Philosophers

were in agreement about the logical structure and

semantics of expressions involving denoting

phrases.

Consider the following sorts of expressions:

1. phrases that fail to denote, such as โ€œthe

current King of Franceโ€;

2. phrases which do denote one object, such

as โ€œthe President of the United statesโ€

which refers unambiguously to one known

individual; or โ€œthe tallest spyโ€ which refers unambiguously to one unknown individual;

3. phrases which denote ambiguously, such as โ€œan aardvarkโ€. (Wikipedia: Theory of

descriptions)

Russellโ€™s theory of descriptions is regarded as a paradigm of Analytic Philosophy because it

apparently solved three problems simultaneously, namely:

โ€ข the problem of empty names;

โ€ข how words attach to things, i.e. reference, and

โ€ข truths (or falsehoods) that fail to refer.

In On Denoting (1905) Russell considers the sentence: โ€œThe current King of Face is baldโ€. Clearly the

sentence has a meaning that we understand but it fails to refer to anybody. So how it possible for it

to be either true or false? Russell analyses the sentence into the following components:

1. There is an ๐‘ฅ such that ๐‘ฅ is the current King of France.

2. For every ๐‘ฅ and ๐‘ฆ such that if ๐‘ฅ and ๐‘ฆ are current Kings of France then ๐‘ฅ is ๐‘ฆ (i.e. there is at

most one current King of France).

3. Anything that is a current King of France is bald.

Thus, any definite description of the form โ€œthe ๐น is ๐ตโ€ can be expressed as:

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)[๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐น๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฆ) โ€ข ๐ต๐‘ฅ]

According to Russell, this immediately solves two problems. Firstly, the sentence: โ€œThe current King

of Face is baldโ€ is straightforwardly seen to be false because there are no entities of which the

Bertrand Russell in 1916

Page 17: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

17

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

predicate โ€œโ€ฆ is the current King of Franceโ€ is true. In fact, all instances of โ€œ๐‘ฅ has the property ๐นโ€ are

false for all ๐‘ฅ, without ๐‘ฅ having to refer to any mysterious non-entity. Secondly, this solves Gottlob

Fregeโ€™s problem of informative identities; the identity of the โ€œmorning starโ€ and the โ€œevening starโ€

being just such a case. Both have different meanings but the same referent i.e. โ€œThe planet Venusโ€.

Instead of treating a sentence like, โ€œThe morning star rises in the morningโ€ as having a subject-

predicate form, Russell analyses it as โ€œthere is one unique thing such that it is the morning star and it

rises in the morningโ€ which is not semantically the same as โ€œthere is one unique thing such that it is

the evening star and it rises in the eveningโ€, even though both expressions ultimately have the same

referent. (Wikipedia: Theory of descriptions)

Although few linguists would say that Russell has โ€œsolvedโ€ the question of reference, his theory of

descriptions has recast such questions in terms of descriptions with which we may become familiar,

rather than entities with which we are acquainted. Thus, I may learn about the existence of a special

point, the centre of gravity of the Solar System, by its definite descriptions. Similarly, I might know

about the not existence of other entities by their definite descriptions.

As far as indefinite descriptions are concerned, we know that the sentence โ€œSome dog is annoyingโ€

is true, not because we are acquainted with the subject-predicate โ€œ๐ด๐‘‘โ€, but because of the

existentially quantified conjunction of two descriptions:

1. There is an ๐‘ฅ such that ๐‘ฅ is a dog, and

2. ๐‘ฅ is annoying.

In symbols: (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(๐ท๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ด๐‘ฅ) (Wikipedia: Theory of descriptions)

Paraphrasal: There exists an ๐‘ฅ such that ๐‘ฅ is a dog and ๐‘ฅ is annoying.

Arguments Involving Definite Descriptions

Some of the exercises at the end of Copiโ€™s section 5.4 involve definite descriptions, introduced by

the article โ€œtheโ€. Try first to symbolise, and then prove nos. 1-4 (p. 149-150) Again, the solutions

below were provided by John Ross. E.g.

1. The architect who designed Tappan Hall designs only office buildings. Therefore, Tappan Hall

is an office building. (๐ด๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is an architect. ๐‘ก: Tappan Hall. ๐ท๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ: ๐‘ฅ designed ๐‘ฆ. ๐‘‚๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is an

office building.)

1. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ){๐ด๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฅ๐‘ก โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐ด๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ก) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ] โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐ท๐‘ฅ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ง)} /โˆด ๐‘‚๐‘ก 2. ๐ด๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฅ๐‘ก โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐ด๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐ท๐‘ฆ๐‘ก) โŠƒ ๐‘ฆ = ๐‘ฅ] โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐ท๐‘ฅ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ง) 3. (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐ท๐‘ฅ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ง) 2 Simp. 4. ๐ท๐‘ฅ๐‘ก โŠƒ ๐‘‚๐‘ก 3 UI 5. ๐ท๐‘ฅ๐‘ก 2 Simp. 6. ๐‘‚๐‘ก 4,5 M.P. 7. ๐‘‚๐‘ก 1,2-6 EI

3. The smallest state is in New England. All states in New England are primarily industrial.

Therefore, the smallest state is primarily industrial. (๐‘†๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is a state. ๐‘๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is in New England.

๐ผ๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is primarily industrial. ๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ: ๐‘ฅ is smaller than ๐‘ฆ.

Page 18: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

18

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

1. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ){๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘†๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ฆ โ‰  ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ] โ€ข ๐‘๐‘ฅ} 2. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[(๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐ผ๐‘ฅ] /โˆด (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ){๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘†๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ฆ โ‰  ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ] โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ฅ} 3. ๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘†๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ฆ โ‰  ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ] โ€ข ๐‘๐‘ฅ 4. ๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘๐‘ฅ 3 Simp. 5. (๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐ผ๐‘ฅ 2 UI 6. ๐ผ๐‘ฅ 5,4 M.P. 7. ๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘†๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ฆ โ‰  ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ] 3.Simp. 8. ๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘†๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ฆ โ‰  ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ] โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ฅ 7,6 Conj. 9. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ){๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘†๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ฆ โ‰  ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ] โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ฅ} 8 EG 10. (โˆƒ๐‘ฅ){๐‘†๐‘ฅ โ€ข (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘†๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘ฆ โ‰  ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐‘†๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ] โ€ข ๐ผ๐‘ฅ} 1,3-9 EI Predicate Variables and Properties of Properties So far we have been employing a first order calculus in which the Roman letters โ€œ๐นโ€, โ€œ๐บโ€, โ€œ๐ปโ€ etc.

(but not the Greek letters โ€œ๐œ™โ€ and โ€œ๐œ“โ€) have been treated as constants. Therefore we have treated

an expression like โ€œ(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅโ€ as a proposition, capable of being true or false, since it contains no free

variables. On a second order calculus a predicate letter like โ€œ๐นโ€ is treated as a variable. Therefore,

on a second calculus, the expression โ€œ(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅโ€ is considered to be a propositional function,

incapable of being true or false because it is incomplete, containing the free variable, โ€œ๐นโ€. To

become a proposition, the expression would have to be written:

(โˆƒ๐น)(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅ or (โˆ€๐น)(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅ.

Some standard translations of second order propositions (Copi, 151-152):

1. Socrates has all properties.

(โˆ€๐น)๐น๐‘ 

2. Plato has some attribute.

(โˆƒ๐น)๐น๐‘

3. Everything has every attribute.

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐น)๐น๐‘ฅ

4. Everything has some property or other.

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐น)๐น๐‘ฅ

5. Something has every property.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐น)๐น๐‘ฅ

6. Every property belongs to something or other.

(โˆ€๐น)(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅ

7. Some property belongs to everything.

(โˆƒ๐น)(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)๐น๐‘ฅ

Page 19: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

19

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

8. Something has some property or other.

(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐น)๐น๐‘ฅ

Although such expressions are meaningful to us, it is a highly contentious question as to whether

they could refer to anything in the external world outside our own mental constructs. There would

almost certainly be no properties in a universe devoid of beings to think about them. Like Hume on

causality, (Classic Text 04) we should be ontologically sceptical. However for example, we speak

almost naturally about classes of particles having certain properties in common, or even being

defined by their properties. Given that we do, a second order calculus must admit the possibility of

properties having properties. Indeed it has to admit of the possibility of sentences such as the

following (with second order predicates in bold):

1. All useful attributes are desirable.

(โˆ€๐น)(๐‘ผ๐น โŠƒ ๐‘ซ๐น)

2. Some desirable attributes are not useful.

(โˆƒ๐น)(๐‘ซ๐น โ€ข ~๐‘ผ๐น)

3. Nothing which possesses every rare attribute has any ordinary attribute.

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[(โˆ€๐น)(๐‘น๐น โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐บ)(๐‘ถ๐บ โŠƒ ~๐บ๐‘ฅ)]

4. Nothing has all attributes.

~(โˆƒ๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐น)๐น๐‘ฅ or (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆƒ๐น)~๐น๐‘ฅ

5. Some attribute belongs to nothing.

(โˆƒ๐น)(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐น๐‘ฅ

6. Napoleon had all the attributes of a great general.

(โˆ€๐น)[(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐บ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ๐น๐‘›]

Second order expressions involving the identity predicate can also be quantified. As Copi (p. 152)

shows beginning with a purely symbolic definition of the identity, i.e.

(๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฆ) = ๐‘‘๐‘“ (โˆ€๐น)(๐น๐‘ฅ โ‰ก ๐น๐‘ฆ)

from which it follows that,

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘ฅ = ๐‘ฆ) โ‰ก (โˆ€๐น)(๐น๐‘ฅ โ‰ก ๐น๐‘ฆ)]

which will be recognised as Leibnizโ€™s law. Consider the following two examples.

7. Any two things have some common attribute.

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[๐‘ฅ โ‰  ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ (โˆƒ๐น)(๐น๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐น๐‘ฆ)]

8. Jones and Smith share all their good qualities but have no bad quantities in common.

Page 20: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

20

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

(โˆ€๐น)[๐‘ฎ๐น โŠƒ (๐น๐‘  โ‰ก ๐น๐‘—)] โ€ข (โˆ€๐น){๐‘ฉ๐น โŠƒ [(๐น๐‘  โŠƒ ~๐น๐‘—) โ€ข (๐น๐‘— โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ )]}

Finally, we can use the method of conditional proof learned in Critical Reasoning 09 to prove the

following tautologies involving attributes or properties:

1. If circles are ellipses then circles have all the properties of ellipses.

(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐ธ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐น)[(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐ถ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ง)]

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐ธ๐‘ฅ) 2. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ฆ) 3. ๐ถ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐ธ๐‘ง 1 UI 4. ๐ธ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ง 2 UI 5. ๐ถ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ง 3,4 H.S. 6. (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐ถ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ง) 5 UG 7. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐ถ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ง) 2-6 C.P. 8. (โˆ€๐น)[(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐ถ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ง)] 7 UG 9. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(๐ถ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ๐ธ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐น)[(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐ธ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ฆ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ง)(๐ถ๐‘ง โŠƒ ๐น๐‘ง)] 1-8 C.P.

2. All asymmetrical binary relations are irreflexive.

Recall that for binary or dyadic relationships the relationship is asymmetrical if (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) is true and irreflexive if (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ

is true. If we connect these as a conditional statement and then universally quantify over both we shall arrive at the desired translation: (โˆ€๐‘…)[(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ]

1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) 2. (โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) 1 UI 3. ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 2UI 4. ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ v ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 3 Impl. 5. ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 4 Taut. 6. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 5 UG (legitimate use of UG because ๐‘ฅ is bound in 1) 7. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 1-6 C.P. 8. (โˆ€๐‘…)[(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ] 7 UG Task Because most of the exercises at the end of Copi 5.5 (p. 155-156) have been used as examples in the

text above, we ask you to attempt only two more by way a task:

I. Symbolise the following propositions:

Page 21: Critical Reasoning 14 - The Logic of Relations

21

ยฉ philosophy.org.za

10. Everyone has some unusual attribute or other. It would be an unusual person who had no unusual attributes. (๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ: ๐‘ฅ is a person; ๐‘ˆ๐‘ฅ: is an unusual individual; ๐‘ผ๐น: ๐น is an unusual attribute)

II. Prove the following:

7. All intransitive binary relations are irreflexive. Feedback These solutions were again provided by John Ross.

10. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[๐‘ƒ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ (โˆƒ๐น)(๐‘ผ๐น โ€ข ๐น๐‘ฅ)] and

(โˆ€๐‘ฆ){[๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข (โˆ€๐บ)(๐‘ผ๐บ โŠƒ ~๐บ๐‘ฆ)] โŠƒ ๐‘ˆ๐‘ฆ} or (โˆ€๐‘ฆ){[๐‘ƒ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ~(โˆƒ๐บ)(๐‘ผ๐บ โ€ข ๐บ๐‘ฆ)] โŠƒ ๐‘ˆ๐‘ฆ} 7. 1. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] (definition of intransitivity) 2. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)[(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ] 1 UI 3. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)[(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ] 2 UI 4. (๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ) โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 3 UI

5. ๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 4 Taut. 6. ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ v ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 5 Impl. 7. ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 6 Taut. 8. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 7 UG 9. (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ 1-8 C.P. 10. (โˆ€๐‘…){(โˆ€๐‘ฅ)(โˆ€๐‘ฆ)(โˆ€๐‘ง)[(๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฆ โ€ข ๐‘…๐‘ฆ๐‘ง) โŠƒ ~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ง] โŠƒ (โˆ€๐‘ฅ)~๐‘…๐‘ฅ๐‘ฅ} 9. UG

Reference

COPI, I.M. (1979) Symbolic Logic, 5th Edition. Macmillan: New York

SUBER, P. (1997) Answers to Copiโ€™s Translation and Derivation Exercises: Polyadic Predicate Logic.

http://legacy.earlham.edu/~peters/courses/log/answers4.htm

Ross, J. (2010) Unfortunately this link has expired or has been moved elsewhere.

Acknowledgement: Unless otherwise acknowledged in the text, the bulk of explanations and

examples above have been compiled from lecture notes on Symbolic Logic presented by the

University of Cape Town by Professor Ian Bunting. The section on definite descriptions and the

meaning of โ€œtheโ€ were reconstructed from notes on the Philosophy of Language by Professor David

Brooks at the same institution.

The next Critical Reasoning study unit concerns hypothesis testing.