Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    1/12

    Critical infrastructures and responsibility:A conceptual exploration

    Koos van der Bruggen *,1

    Delft University of Technology, Faculty of Technology, Policy and Management, Department of Philosophy, Jaffalaan 5,

    2628 BX Delft, The Netherlands

    Received 13 December 2006; received in revised form 8 May 2007; accepted 14 June 2007

    Abstract

    In this article some considerations are presented as a starting point for judging responsibility for infrastructural systemsfrom a moral point of view. Infrastructural systems are essential for present day high-tech society. Without good workinginfrastructural systems people would hardly be able to survive. The importance and relevance of good working criticalinfrastructures for states and other public authorities are illustrated with some examples. Next, the meaning of the conceptof responsibility in relation to infrastructural systems is developed. Outcome responsibility and remedial responsibility developed in philosophy of law and political philosophy are elaborated as useful concepts for dealing with responsibilitiesin infrastructural systems. This analysis is applied to the players on the infrastructural field: governments and other public

    authorities, non-state institutional actors and last but not least individual agents. In a last paragraph some conclusions aredrawn, which can be applied for apportioning responsibility for infrastructures in practice. 2007 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

    Keywords: Critical infrastructure; Outcome responsibility; Remedial responsibility; Operation; Management; Safety

    1. Introduction

    In ethical literature a lot has been written on (moral) responsibility. It certainly is one of the key issues inethical theory. In this article I will present some considerations that can be a starting point for judging respon-

    sibility for infrastructural projects and activities from a moral point of view.First, attention will be given to infrastructures. What are the so-called critical infrastructures? What is theirimportance? What is their function in present day society? What place do they have and what place shouldthey have in social and political arrangements?

    Next, the meaning of the concept of responsibility regarding the management and operation of criticalinfrastructures will be further developed. What does responsibility mean in relation to critical infrastructures?

    0925-7535/$ - see front matter 2007 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

    doi:10.1016/j.ssci.2007.06.003

    * Present address: Leiden University/Campus The Hague, Lange Houtstraat 5-7, 2511 CV DEN HAAG. Tel.: +31 70 3021070.E-mail addresses: [email protected], [email protected], [email protected]

    1 Tel.: +31 15 27 85143.

    Available online at www.sciencedirect.com

    Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148

    www.elsevier.com/locate/ssci

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]
  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    2/12

    Whose responsibility is at stake? Do all players in the field have the same responsibility? What are the practicalor theoretical problems in defining and applying responsibility for infrastructures? Outcome responsibility andremedial responsibility will be elaborated as useful concepts for dealing with responsibilities in infrastructuralsystems.

    A third paragraph will be devoted to the players on the infrastructural field. These are in the first place gov-

    ernments and other public authorities. Furthermore, non-state institutional actors: infrastructural companiesand organizations. And last but not least the individual actors in these fields. What are their roles and theirresponsibilities?

    In a last paragraph some conclusions will be drawn, which can be applied for apportioning responsibilityfor critical infrastructures in practice.

    2. Critical infrastructures

    Infrastructures can be described as the basic facilities, services, and installations needed for the function-ing of a community or society, such as transportation and communications systems, water and power lines,and public institutions including schools, post offices and prisons (http://www.thefreedictionary.com/infrastructure).

    This is a rather broad definition, including schools, prisons, etc. So, the concept is not limited to technicalsystems alone, but it leaves no doubt that the technical basis is essential for many infrastructural systems. Inthis article attention will be limited to the so-called critical infrastructures that have a (strong) technical com-ponent. The safety and reliability of technical provisions are important if not necessary conditions for thefunctioning of most infrastructural systems. This implies a special responsibility for the people and the insti-tutions that are in charge of the task to design and apply the technical artefacts that are part of an infrastruc-tural system.

    The concept of critical infrastructures has become a key concept in recent discussions. Since a few yearsthere is a Journal for Critical Infrastructures. This journal defines critical infrastructures as networks forthe provision of telecommunication and information services, energy services (electrical power, natural gas,oil and heat), water supply, transportation of people and goods, banking and financial services, government

    services and emergency services

    . (http://www.inderscience.com/browse/index.php?journalCODE=ijcis). Thisis a limitative definition, which covers infrastructures so vital that their incapacitation or destruction wouldhave a debilitating impact on defense or economic security, as it is described in a report for the US govern-ment (Moteff et al., 2003; Critical Infrastructures: What Makes an Infrastructure Critical?Report to Congress).

    Western societies have become more and more dependent of these critical infrastructures, but at the sametime we are witnessing a paradoxical development (De Bruijne, 2006, p. 11). De Bruijne shows that on theone hand critical infrastructures are increasingly interconnected into a single system of unimaginable propor-tions. But on the other hand these large-scale infrastructures have become institutionally fragmented. Thereis no longer any single organization (be it public or private) that can compel others to act.

    This fragmentization has also occurred within the separate infrastructural sectors, such as telecommunica-tion and energy, where many competitive actors are playing a role. Moreover, these actors are no longer actingwithin one country, but cross-national: German ICT-operators have taken parts of the market in France, andDutch railways are active in Poland.

    Another development that De Bruijne describes is the interconnectedness of critical infrastructures (DeBruijne, p. 12). The functioning of all infrastructures becomes more and more dependent from ICT-perfor-mance and from the electricity system. The threatening slogan of the labour unions for Dutch railways-work-ers in the beginning of the 20th century is more true than ever before: this whole cogwheels system will falldown if you want it to happen. Nowadays, a simple computer failure can lead to the laming of railway traffic,so safety cannot be guaranteed anymore. This happened more than once in the Netherlands in the past fewyears.

    Disturbances in the ICT-system or in the energy net indeed can lame a society, not only at a national scalebut also across borders. Well known examples are the fall-out in great parts of the North-East of the UnitedStates and in Canada in August 2003, due to a chain reaction in powerplants. The same happened in parts of

    Germany, The Netherlands, Belgium, France and even Spain, Portugal and Italy in November 2006. A

    1138 K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148

    http://www.thefreedictionary.com/infrastructurehttp://www.thefreedictionary.com/infrastructurehttp://www.thefreedictionary.com/infrastructurehttp://www.thefreedictionary.com/infrastructure
  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    3/12

    disturbance in Germany here also leads to a chain reaction. These developments show that the functioning ofinfrastructural systems no longer is a case for national governments alone. This means that questions ofresponsibility also get more and more an international character.

    Without good working infrastructural systems as electricity, water supply, railways, and ICT-telecom peo-ple would hardly be able to survive in our high-tech society! This leads to an interesting paradox: the better

    infrastructural systems are working, the more dependent we are from these systems and the less we are able tocope with the ever more exceptional failures of the system (Rathenau Instituut, 1994). In many so-called ThirdWorld countries it is normal that electric power is interrupted a few times a week. People are prepared for itand go on with their daily work. But if in our society the electric power system is disturbed, life comes to astandstill, as was recently (2005) seen in Haaksbergen (The Netherlands) where electric power had fallen downduring more than 48 h because of heavy snow and storm. It almost led to a state of emergency.

    Because of the crucial importance of critical infrastructures, it is no coincidence that in times of war oftenassaults are planned on infrastructural systems as electric power plants, airports or railways nodes. Rememberin the Yugoslavia war the destruction of the famous Mostar bridge (belonging to the Cultural Heritage ofHumanity) in 1993 and in the Kosovo war (1999) the bombing of television studios in Beograd. It is hopedto destabilize a country with such assaults. For the same reason the conflict between Russia and Ukrainein the beginning of 2006 on gas prizes was seen as a very serious threat for the state of Ukraine and even

    for some EU countries such as Poland, because their gas was delivered via Ukraine.So, again, it leaves no doubt that infrastructural systems are essential for the daily life of citizens. But an

    even stronger statement can be made: nowadays, critical infrastructures belong to the constitutive elements ofa society or even a nation as such. Is it still possible to speak of a state or a society if the most important infra-structures have fallen down? Schneider and Jager refer to Herbert Kruger who wrote that there is no statewithout infrastructures (Schneider and Jager, 2003, p. 15). And indeed, if state authorities cannot provide directly or indirectly by private or semi-public companies infrastructural services and products as energy ordrinking water a state of anarchy and chaos is very near. Reasoning from the other way around it can beargued that society or nation building is greatly helped or perhaps even only made possible by the devel-opment of infrastructures. By using the metaphor of the sovereign (state) as the Leviathan (Hobbes) infra-structures sometimes are labelled as the nerves and blood circulation of the state.

    This can be illustrated with some examples. It is a well known fact that water boards are the eldest dem-ocratic political institutions in The Netherlands, elder than parliament. These water boards were needed toarrange the (infrastructural) water system. Nowadays, the famous Dutch polder model still reminds tothe narrow relationship between infrastructures and a good functioning democratic system.2

    The initiating and constitutive role of infrastructures in the development of political institutions can also beshown at the cross-national level of European cooperation and integration. Already in the 19th century inter-national regulations regarding the Rhine were developed. And the starting point of European integration can-not be untied from the first intergovernmental organization with an infrastructural task: the European Coaland Steel Community (ECSC). The ECSC Treaty creates a framework of production and distributionarrangements for coal and steel and sets up an autonomous institutional system to manage it. Although itsremit is limited to the two branches of industry, the ECSC has had a crucial impact on major economicand political developments in Europe for almost fifty years (http://www.eu.int/ecsc/results/indexen.htm).The success of ECSC contributed a few years later to the foundation of the European Community of sixnations, which became the starting point of the present day European Union.

    A third painful illustration of the importance of (critical) infrastructures for the political system is thesaying that whatever was wrong in the Germany of Hitler and the Italy of Mussolini trains were departingand riding on schedule. And it was the Nazis who developed the famous German highway infrastructure. His-tory shows that a government that succeeds in taking good care for infrastructures, gets appreciation for this,despite its policy in other fields (such as human rights).

    2 The Dutch word polder refers to a part of land that is won from the sea. It is lying below sea level and is protected by dykes.All inhabitants have to work together to protect the land from the sea. This working together and looking for consensus also is a

    characteristic of the political system in the Netherlands. So the name of polder model.

    K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148 1139

  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    4/12

    The importance of good working critical infrastructures as a fundamental (even constitutive) condition forstates and other public authorities has not been given as much attention as other essential state duties, but itsurely is endorsed by political theorists. One of them is perhaps surprisingly Adam Smith. He writes thatbesides defence and judiciary tasks the third and last duty of the sovereign or commonwealth is that of erect-ing and maintaining those public institutions and those public works, which, though they may be in the high-

    est degree advantageous to a great society, are, however, of such a nature, that the profit could never repay theexpense to any individual or small number of individuals, and which it therefore cannot be expected that anyindividual or small number of individuals should erect or maintain. (Smith, 1812 [1776], pp. 570571). Care-fully reading these quotes one learns that there is some ambiguity in it. On the one hand Smith talks about aduty of the sovereign or commonwealth (= public authority), but on the other hand the reason is that noprofit is to be expected from these activities. Implicitly, this means that if profit is a possible result of erectingand maintaining infrastructural works, these can also and perhaps in his liberal view should be undertaken byindividuals or private organizations.

    Since the 19th century taking care of infrastructural systems has become more and more a state task.Schneider and Jager summarize that public responsibility for infrastructures is based on the following argu-ments (Schneider and Jager, 2003, p. 15; Hermes, 1998, p. 271):

    (a) Technical efficiency aspects: This relates to, e.g. standardization or coordination. State commitment isnot necessary here. A private monopoly is also an option, but if that does not work, state has tointervene.

    (b) Military, state and integrationist motives: National security is an important argument for state involve-ment in infrastructures.

    (c) The demand of state resource expropriation rights and fiscal motives: Direct involvement or ownership bythe state can be profitable for the state budget.

    (d) Correction of market failure and public control: State involvement is often justified with the argument thatit makes infrastructural provisions accessible and payable for all groups in society.

    (e) Guarantee of extensive supply (socio-political motives): The state should take care of the supply of publicinfrastructural goods that are scarce.

    (f) Democracy political, legal and environmentalist considerations: Some basic rights and basic needs aremore or less dependent from infrastructural systems (e.g. communication). State commitment can benecessary to guarantee these basic rights.

    Of course it is possible to amend or comment most of these arguments. Partly, they have an empirical char-acter: they refer to how and why decisions have been taken in more and less recent history. But certainly thereis a reference to normative arguments also: that management, organization and possession of infrastructuresshould be in the hands of the public sector (politicians and government), because of the crucial importance ofthese infrastructure for this public domain.

    There is one more argument to be added, which is only partial and indirectly captured by Schneider andJager: guaranteeing the security and safety of infrastructures is in last resort also a responsibility for a publicauthority. In theory, but more important in practice many things can go wrong. Most failures belong toone of the following categories:

    Malfunctioning of the system: electricity breakdown, delay or falling out of trains or buses, no water supply,pollution of water, breakdown of telephone or Internet systems, etc.

    Accidents: fires, explosions, collisions, floods, etc. Shortage of resources: shortage of fuel, shortage of water. Personal problems: shortage of labour force, not enough well educated staff, strikes. Vulnerability for criminal or terrorist attacks: bombing of power plants, poisoning water sources, spam-

    ming, spreading computer viruses, assaults on planes and/or trains, etc.

    How responsibility for the maintenance, functioning, safety and security of critical infrastructures should

    be defined and apportioned to different actors will be elaborated in the next paragraphs.

    1140 K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148

  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    5/12

    3. Concepts of responsibility

    David Miller states that in moral and political philosophy few concepts are more slippery than that ofresponsibility (Miller, 2001, p. 455). In this paragraph some slippery aspects, which are relevant in the dis-cussion on responsibility for critical infrastructures, will be elaborated. By way of introduction a story, told by

    H.L.A. Hart: As captain of the ship, X wasresponsible

    for the safety of his passengers and crew. But on hislast voyage he got drunk every night and was responsible for the loss of the ship with all [others] aboard. It wasrumoured that he was insane, but the doctors considered that he was responsible for his actions. Throughoutthe voyage he behaved quite irresponsibly, and various incidents in his career showed that he was not a respon-sible person. He always maintained that the exceptional winter storms were responsible for the loss of the ship,but in the legal procedures brought against him he was found criminally responsible for his negligent conduct,and in separate civil proceedings he was held legally responsible for the loss of life and property. He is still aliveand he is morally responsible for the deaths of many women and children (Hart, 1968, p. 11, my italics) (Table1).

    In this story the following meanings of responsibility can be discerned (Bovens, 1998, pp. 2426):

    1. Being the cause of a situation or an event (the captain was responsible for the loss of the ship).

    2. Having the capacity to initiate or prevent a situation or an event (he was responsible for his actions).3. Being accountable or liable for something that has happened (he was found legally and criminally

    responsible).4. Having to fulfil a task or obligation (he was responsible for the safety of his passengers).5. Having (or not having) a personal virtue (he was not a responsible person).

    What is the relevance of each of these aspects of responsibility in relation to infrastructural systems? Respon-sibility as task or obligation (4) surely has a high relevance. In this paper the position is taken in line withSchneider and Jager that taking care of critical infrastructures belongs to the tasks of public authorities: itis a public responsibility. But that is not the same as to say that public authorities should have a direct involve-ment in the operation and management of infrastructural systems. Of course also having the capacity (2) is an

    important aspect. It should be evident that people and organizations possess the capacities to perform theirinfrastructural tasks conform the valid guidelines and rules. Responsibility as (not) having a personal virtue(5) may become relevant as far as individual persons have to execute operational and or managerial tasks. Lastbut not least responsibility in the sense of accountability or liability (3) surely also is a relevant aspect in relation

    Table 1Definitions of responsibility and related concepts

    Responsibility

    Being the cause of a situation or an eventHaving the capacity to initiate or prevent a situation or an eventBeing accountable or liable for something that has happenedHaving to fulfil a task or obligation

    Having (or not having) a personal virtueOutcome responsibility

    Being responsible for the good and the harm we bring about by what we do

    Remedial responsibility

    Having a special obligation to put a bad situation right

    Accountability

    A relationship between an actor and a forum, in which the actor has an obligation to explain and to justify his or her conduct, theforum can pose questions and pass judgment, and the actor may face consequences

    Liability

    Duty, obligation, debt, responsibility, or hazard arising by way of contract, tort or statute

    Strict liability

    Legal doctrine that makes persons responsible for damages their actions or products cause, regardless of any fault

    on their part

    K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148 1141

  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    6/12

    to the management and operation of infrastructures. It should be clear who is accountable or liable when thingsgo wrong (which is not necessarily the same as having causal responsibility (1)).

    A problem in all complex organizations and systems, and thus also in critical infrastructures, is that it is notalways easy to find out who is or who are responsible. This is known as the many hands problem. The problemhas been described by Dennis Thompson in 1980: Because many different officials contribute in many ways to

    decisions and policies of government, it is difficult, even in principle to identify who is morally responsible forpolitical outcomes (Thompson, 1980, p. 905). Thompson is writing about responsibility in political processes,but this is also a problem in managing and operating infrastructural systems. Bovens (1998) makes a comparisonwith developments in law to treat or even to solve the many hands problem. In law legal bodies or legal per-sonals (which are not identical with natural persons) exist who have legal rights and duties. He defends the anal-ogy that these organizations then also have moral rights and duties: indeed there is such a thing as (moral)corporate accountability (Bovens, 1998, p. 53). In his view not all moral categories are applicable to organiza-tions, but some such as responsibility as accountability or liability are (Bovens, 1998, p. 57). Accountabilityand liability are related but not identical concepts. Accountability can be defined as a relationship between anactor and a forum, in which the actor has an obligation to explain and to justify his or her conduct, the forum canpose questions and pass judgment, and the actor may face consequences (Bovens, 2006, p. 7). The forum towhich accountability is directed can be of different characters: a parliament, a board, colleagues or mass media.

    Liability is a broad term including almost every type of duty, obligation, debt, responsibility, or hazardarising by way of contract, tort or statute (Encyclopedia Brittanica online). A special form of liability is strictliability. Strict liability is a legal doctrine that makes persons responsible for damages their actions or productscause, regardless of any fault on their part (http://injury-law.freeadvice.com/strictliabilty.htm ). Strict liabil-ity can be described in if, then terms: if someones activities lead to damage for others (be it on purpose ornot on purpose), then that person is unconditionally obliged to restore the damage. Zandvoort is an advocateof applying the principle in discussions on technological risks: Actors are unconditionally required to repairor fully compensate for any damage to others that may result from their actions, unless those who suffer thedamage had given their informed consent to the activities causing the damage (Zandvoort, in press, p. 3).According to Zandvoort the principle of self-determination is the most important ethical basis for strict lia-bility. Self-determination implies the right to be safeguarded for the consequences of another ones actions

    (Zandvoort, 2000, p. 249).In line of these arguments I will further elaborate the concept of responsibility as accountability or (strict)

    liability with two concepts that were developed recently in the fields of philosophy of law and political philos-ophy: outcome responsibility and remedial responsibility. I will argue that these concepts are useful tools inelaborating and applying the different kinds of responsibility for the operation and management of criticalinfrastructures.

    3.1. Outcome responsibility

    The concept of outcome responsibility has been developed by Honore: Outcome responsibility meansbeing responsible for the good and the harm we bring about by what we do. By allocating credit for the good

    outcome of actions and discredit for bad ones, society imposes outcome responsibility (Honore, 1999, p. 14).The article in which he elaborates this concept starts with a provoking sentence: Being responsible in law andin ordinary life is not the same as being at fault or to blame. This view makes outcome responsibility relevantfor judging the operation and management of critical infrastructures, because it is not in the first place blamingand punishing that matter when the functioning of infrastructures is at stake. What matters is that criticalinfrastructures work as they should do. In other words: it is the outcome that matters. Honore introducesthe concept of outcome responsibility as an argument from a moral point of view in order to apply givencertain conditions such a severe rule as that of strict liability. Honore states that a system of outcome respon-sibility can be defended as fair if some necessary conditions are met. It must be impartial, reciprocal and overa period beneficial. (Honore, 1999, p. 26).3 If that is the case, outcome responsibility is the basic type of

    3 This conditions guarantee that outcome responsibility does not lead to an absolute utilitarian interpretation.

    1142 K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148

    http://injury-law.freeadvice.com/strictliabilty.htmhttp://injury-law.freeadvice.com/strictliabilty.htm
  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    7/12

    responsibility in a community: more fundamental than either moral responsibility as generally understood,which requires fault, or legal responsibility, which requires either fault or special danger (Honore, 1999, p.27). The last sentence in the paragraph where he elaborates the concept of outcome responsibility again is pro-voking: Finally, it is outcomes that in the long run make us what we are. (Honore, 1999, p. 31). It does notseem strange to replace us in this sentence by critical infrastructures. The concept of outcome responsi-

    bility may be developed by Honore

    for applications at the individual level, but applications at broader levelsare legitimate and defensible and perhaps even more suited than at the individual level, as is shown by Miller(2004).

    Miller elaborates the concept of outcome responsibility at the level of nations. In line with the definition ofHonore, he describes outcome responsibility as follows: When we say that an agent is outcome responsiblefor the consequences of her action, we are attributing those consequences to her in such a way that, otherthings being equal, the resulting benefits and burdens should fall to her. If the consequences include harmto others, then outcome responsibility may, depending on the case, entail liability to compensate for thatharm (Miller, 2004, pp. 244245).4 According to Miller outcome responsibility is a narrower notion than cau-sal responsibility (Miller, 2004). This means that someone may be causal responsible, but not outcome respon-sible. This can be the case if outcomes arise in bizarre and unpredictable ways (p. 245). Miller gives thisexample: If I toss an orange pip over the edge of a cliff and in doing so precipitate a rock fall, I am causally

    responsible, but not outcome responsible, for the damage that ensues. So outcome responsibility indicatesthat a person or an institution knows or should know what possible consequences of their actions are. Out-come responsibility is related to foreseen and unforeseen consequences of actions. Of course it is a point ofdiscussion of what is the difference between bizarre and unpredictable consequences on the one handand unforeseen consequences on the other hand.

    Let me try to make the difference clearer by giving some examples in the sphere of infrastructures. In TheNetherlands heavy earthquakes are very rare phenomena. When building a nuclear plant the earthquake resis-tance of the plant does not have to be that strong as when it would be built in e.g. California. Should an earth-quake or something comparable happen anyhow (e.g. because a meteor has struck the region), this couldbe seen as a bizarre and unpredictable situation, in which there is no outcome responsibility as defined byHonore and Miller. But this does not mean that there is no responsibility at all. In these cases there may

    be remedial responsibility

    (see below).Miller points out that outcome responsibility is less stringent than moralresponsibility as that term is usu-

    ally understood. To be morally responsible for the consequences of an action, you must be outcome responsi-ble, but the converse does not hold (Miller, 2004, p. 246). Moral responsibility has to deal with the assessmentsof praise and blame, meeting or breaking obligations, etc. That is not necessarily the case when there is onlyoutcome responsibility. Be it remarked here that Miller uses the concept morality (as usually understood)in a rather narrow sense by coupling it to the assessments of praise and blame. It can be defended that the con-cept of outcome responsibility is also a moral concept. If someone is outcome responsible for a result he or she ismorally obliged to compensate the damage, even if he or she is not to blame for a fault.

    In relation to the operation and management of infrastructures outcome responsibility is an important con-cept, because the outcome (result, product, safety) is the most important criterion for judging infrastructuralsystems. And in that respect it often is less relevant who is, e.g. causal responsible for a malfunctioning infra-structure. Of course it has to be examined who has caused the malfunctioning, but first of all it is importantthat the outcome is realized! And if this should not be possible, the option of remedial responsibility becomesrelevant.

    3.2. Remedial responsibility

    The concept of remedial responsibility has been elaborated by Miller (2001): To be remedially responsiblefor a bad situation means to have a special obligation to put the bad situation right (Miller, 2001, p. 454). In

    4 This formulation implies that the harm can be compensated. In the case of irreversible harm, there still is outcome responsibility, butby definition the harm cannot be compensated. Dependent on the character of the damage the outcome responsible person or organization

    can be compelled to help, e.g. survivors or to pay a financial debt.

    K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148 1143

  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    8/12

    practice this means that agents should be held remedially responsible for situations when, and to the extentthat, they were responsible for bringing those situations about (Miller, 2001, p. 455). At first sight this con-cept seems closely related to that of outcome responsibility. But according to Miller remedial responsibilitydoes not always follow immediately from outcome responsibility. This is most obviously in the case wherethat agent cannot now remedy the harm in question (Miller, 2004, p. 266).5 This is the case if the government

    of a country has because of bad policy contributed to the poverty of its inhabitants, but does not have thepossibility to prevent a famine. In such a situation the international community has a remedial responsibilityto help these people, although there is no outcome responsibility. Also in the case of natural disasters as anearthquake or a tsunami no one is to be blamed (except perhaps for not building earthquake resistant houses).But there will not be many people who will say that in these cases there is no obligation to help victims and torestore damage. This moral obligation does not coincide with moral responsibility that is directly linked toaccountability and liability. So, remedial responsibility entails more than restoring the damage that is causedunder the umbrella of outcome responsibility. Because of that remedial responsibility can be seen as a variantof responsibility as a task or obligation.

    What is the practical relevance is of the principle of remedial responsibility? Applied to infrastructuresremedial responsibility means that non-functioning or malfunctioning infrastructures need to be restored orreplaced as soon as possible, regardless of who caused the damage. This is also the case when because of

    bizarre and unpredictable consequences a failure of the critical infrastructure has occurred. So, even afteran earthquake in the Netherlands there is the remedial responsibility to restore the damage and to help thepeople who are dependent of this infrastructure. It must be realized that this is a very demanding interpreta-tion of responsibility, which perhaps not always can be realized. For instance, how realistic is it to ask thepublic authorities or the energy company for restoring the energy supply, if in times of war all power plantsof a country have been damaged or destroyed.

    It should be recognized that there are difficulties in applying the concept of remedial responsibility in prac-tice. But applying the concept to the management and operation of infrastructures shows the importance ofinfrastructures for society. The next question is who should be the bearers of this responsibility.

    4. Responsibility for the management and operation of infrastructures

    Until now attention has been paid to the meaning of the concept of responsibility, and more specificallyoutcome and remedial responsibility, in the context of infrastructural systems. But who is or should be out-come and/or remedial responsible for the functioning of critical infrastructures? How far does the responsibil-ity of public authorities as politicians and civil servants go? And what does it mean for the responsibility ofother actors, such as private companies, because these undoubtedly have their own (part of) responsibility?And last but not least: what do outcome and remedial responsibility mean for individual actors?

    4.1. Responsibility of public authorities

    As infrastructural systems are so important maybe even constitutive for a society it is almost evidentthat in last resort public authorities are responsible for infrastructural projects and activities that take placewithin their jurisdiction. A generally shared conclusion in most societies indeed is that the good functioningof critical infrastructures is a public responsibility. Politicians and broader the public sector can and mustbe held responsible for the operation and management of infrastructures. More specific this public responsi-bility for infrastructural projects is at stake in different kinds of arrangements.

    5 Miller gives this example: . . .showing that there are instances in which nations that lack sufficient resources to keep all of theirmembers above a poverty line are themselves responsible for that lack, by virtue of policies pursued in the recent past, or features of thenational culture that have prevented sufficient resources from being generated, does not entail that other nations should not now step in(Miller, 2004, p. 266). If remedial responsibility is accepted in these cases it will always be a point of discussion how far this remedialresponsibility goes. What may and should be asked of people with remedial responsibility. Should St. Martin of Tours have given the

    beggar only half of his mantle?

    1144 K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148

  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    9/12

    The government (or a local/regional public authority) is partially or totally the owner of the infrastructuralsystem.

    Until the 1980s the common situation in most Western European countries was that public authorities(local, regional and/or national) were the owner of almost all infrastructural systems. At the end of the

    19th and in the beginning of the 20th century most infrastructural projects were initiated or taken over bylocal, regional or national authorities. To give some examples from the Netherlands: regional organizations(most coinciding with provinces) for electricity supply were founded. And the different private railways com-panies came together in one state owned national railways company. This development was strengthened afterthe Second World War, when all over Western Europe the concept of the welfare state (or the Rhinelandmodel) was adopted. This model is based on a rather strong government intervention in economic affairs.In the Netherlands this welfare state model led to the above mentioned polder model. In this model great gov-ernmental influence on critical infrastructures was the generally accepted policy line. Of course there were spe-cialized organizations that took care of the daily operation and management tasks, but these were owned andruled by public authorities. The people who worked for these organizations were civil servants. And althoughpoliticians were not involved directly or often even indirectly in the management and operation of criticalinfrastructures, they were and should be approachable and responsible for these matters. If something went

    wrong, politicians were accountable for it.

    The government has made explicit legal, financial or policy arrangements with the owner of the infrastruc-tural system.

    In the past 1520 years the Rhineland model lost ground in favour of the so-called Anglo-Saxon model,which favours only limited government intervention (Bolkestein, 1998). A consequence was the liberalizationof most infrastructural systems. It was no longer thought necessary that the local, regional or national gov-ernment should own and control the performance of the infrastructural system directly. Private companiesbought the rights and/or the ownership of infrastructural services and systems. Also old players showed upin a new appearance of privatized or semi-public state companies. But this new situation does not imply that

    politics should no longer bear any responsibility for the management and operation of infrastructural systems.The state and other public institutions still are or should be important actors in a direct and an indirect way.

    Instead of the formal ownership of infrastructural systems by public authorities new relations have grownbased on legal, financial and policy arrangements with the (new) owners of the infrastructural system. Thesearrangements are meant to guarantee the good functioning of the infrastructural systems. On the one hand thearrangements describe the obligations of the owners to maintain the operation and management of theirinfrastructural systems. On the other hand also the obligations and tasks of the public authorities such asfinancial and legal support are described. These public tasks give the governmental institutions a directresponsibility in those situations where they are no longer the formal owner of the infrastructure.

    An example from the Netherlands is TenneT. TenneT is the transmission system operator (TSO) that man-ages the Dutch transmission grid. We do this by making our transmission grid available impartially for elec-tricity transmission and by ensuring the necessary balance between supply and demand in the Netherlands.Seen that the transport of electricity doesnt stop at our borders, TenneT cooperates with European TSOs.Since October 2001, the State has been the sole shareholder in TenneT (http://www.tennet.nl/wie).

    Also in other important infrastructural sectors government often have a majority or even all of the shares.This guarantees government the possibility to influence the policy of the infrastructural company, for instanceif the arrangements that are made with the owners do not have the aimed results. In the words of Honore andMiller: government or broader, the public sector accepts its outcome responsibility for infrastructural systems.

    The government has obligations to the people who are dependent on the infrastructural system.

    Even if a public authority is no owner or does not have any formal arrangements with owners of infrastruc-tural facilities, politicians still have an outcome responsibility for the adequate operation and management of

    the infrastructures, if only because infrastructural provisions are essential for the good functioning of society.

    K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148 1145

  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    10/12

    The legitimacy of a public authority that is not able to guarantee these provisions is at stake, even if otherpublic tasks are performed well (although that will not be the case very often). In such a situation the capacityto take responsibility for infrastructural systems has to be restored as soon as possible. If the public authorityis a city council or a regional authority, higher authorities (regional, national, perhaps even international) haveto take their responsibility by assuming power until the lower authority is capable again to take the

    responsibility.Things are even more serious of course if a national government is not able to guarantee good workinginfrastructures. If this is only temporarily and can be explained because of extraordinary circumstances,e.g. a flood or an earthquake, the situation can be restored with international support. But if the failinghas a more structural character, more drastic measures may be necessary. One solution can be that internallyanother (stronger) government is chosen or appointed. From a legal point of view this in fact is the onlyoption. Another more controversial option is an intervention in the failing state by foreign countries. Thisintervention can be economical, political and in last resort military. In political, ethical and legal circles a lot ofdebates were held in the past few years about the question under which circumstances a (humanitarian) mil-itary intervention can be justified. Until now there is no international consensus. But if there is a kind of agree-ment growing, then it concentrates on the opinion that intervention could be allowed only if the human rightsare severely violated (e.g. by genocide). The malfunctioning of infrastructures is of course not comparable with

    such a terrible event.A last remark: most of the time it is far more easy to say that politicians have or should have outcome

    responsibility than to say what that responsibility entails in practice. Agreement exists about one very specifictask as a responsibility for public authorities: inspecting and evaluating the way private or semi-public infra-structural organizations are performing their management and operational tasks. Most countries have createda structure of evaluating, controlling and inspecting infrastructural organizations. It is an institutionalizedway to perform a duty that is based on the concept of outcome responsibility.

    4.2. Responsibility of infrastructural companies

    Another important group of actors on institutional level that bear responsibility for infrastructures are the

    organizations and companies that manage and govern the daily operations of these systems. These can be pub-licprivate cooperation institutions, profit and non-profit organizations. The outcome and remedial responsi-bility of involved organizations is more direct and more specific than that of public authorities. Theresponsibility is immediately related to the task of managing and operating infrastructures in daily practice.In fact this means no more and no less than assuring and guaranteeing that the critical infrastructure doeswhat it should do: delivering electricity, delivering clean water, guaranteeing telecommunication-traffic, driv-ing trains and buses according to appointed time schedules, etc. And this should not only be guaranteed whenthe sun is shining, but also in bad weather (both literally and figuratively). Related to this task is the obligationto prevent failures from happening. And if accidents should happen, the damage needs to be restored as soonas possible. Outcome responsibility includes remedial responsibility: restoring and correcting failures of thesystem as soon as possible as well as to have emergency measures prepared so that services can temporarilybe taken over, for instance generators for electricity in essential places (like hospitals) or buses that replacetrains. This remedial responsibility also exists if the infrastructural company does not have any accountabilityfor an accident or incident that has caused the failure of the system.

    In most cases the infrastructural organizations have to perform these tasks themselves. It is not seen as anexecutive task of the political authorities. An exception is the employment of police or military forces in thecase of a security threat. But this happens only if there is an acute threat that cannot be countered by internalsecurity measures of the organization.

    In most institutions and companies executive tasks are allocated or delegated to lower levels in the organi-zation. In this paper no attention will be paid to these different organizational, legal and financial arrange-ments that exist on this level of infrastructural institutions. All these different arrangements are ways totake care of outcome and remedial responsibility. The main point of the argument is that this outcome andremedial responsibilities exist, irrespective of the way how tasks and responsibilities are shared and/or distrib-

    uted within an organization. In practice this can lead to a situation in which it is not clear who is responsible

    1146 K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148

  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    11/12

    for a failure or that more people or groups are co-responsible. This is the earlier mentioned problem of themany hands. But this many hands problem can never be used as an excuse for the malfunctioning of infra-structures. Of course that does not mean that the many hands problem is not relevant. Every organizationshould try to prevent, solve or reduce that problem.

    4.3. Responsibility of individual persons

    Often the problem of many hands is literally linked to real hands, or better people of flesh and blood! Thethird layer in the ladder of responsibility for critical infrastructures is the responsibility of individual persons,be it that most of these persons are part of either public authorities or infrastructural organizations. Indepen-dent from views on the (im)possibility of collective or shared responsibility, fact is that in a public authority orin an infrastructural organization individual persons do have their own responsibility as a politician, a civilservant, a designer, an engineer, a manager, a user but also as a consumer. The kinds of individual responsi-bility differ according to the function or role that individual persons are performing. An engineer does haveanother responsibility than a manager, a driver or a politician.

    Again, an example can make this clear. Suppose there is a derailment of a train. Who on a personal level can be involved? At least the following persons and roles can be identified: the train engine driver, the

    engineers who are responsible for the construction of the train, the engineers who are responsible for themaintenance of the train, the engineers who developed the rail track, the people who are responsible forthe maintenance of the rail track, the traffic controller, the director/manager of the railway company, thedirector/manager of the rail track company, the civil servants of the Railways Department, the Ministerwho has railways in portfolio.

    But although it can be stated that all of these persons possibly have a personal responsibility, this does notyet mean that they all have the same responsibility. Some are liable and because of that responsible becauseof their action or omission that caused the accident; others perhaps have an administrative or organizationalaccountability: they have organized the train planning or the personal duties. And in last resort the Ministerhas outcome responsibility or perhaps better in this case political responsibility.

    In some cases there is at least at first sight no doubt about the individual responsibility for accidents. If

    someone as has happened in 2005 in the Netherlands throws a heavy lorry on the rail track, this person and nobody else is responsible for the accident that follows. But even in these clear cases there is room for asecond thought. How could this happen? Why did this person have access to the rail track? Could or shouldnobody have stopped him? These questions certainly arise if these kinds of incidents take place more than onceand thus cannot be qualified as bizarre and unpredictable. In that case there is an outcome responsibility forthe authorities, and this again leads to executive responsibilities at the individual level.

    So, whatever responsibility public authorities and infrastructural companies have in managing and operat-ing infrastructures, in last resort individual responsibilities are extremely important. Because of that it is a pri-mary task of infrastructural companies and public authorities to carry out a policy that leads to putting theright people on the right place. And the right people themselves have the obligation to perform their dutiesoptimally. Arrangements have to be developed to evaluate and control the performance of individual techni-cians, staff members, etc., and to punish or even replace them if they fail. This should lead to a chain of respon-sibilities that can be different in various infrastructural systems (such as water management andtelecommunications systems).

    5. Conclusions

    In this article it has been argued that critical infrastructures are of great importance for each modern soci-ety. A good working infrastructural system can even be viewed as a conditio sine qua non for modern statesand societies. Because of that public authorities at the national, regional and local level do have a responsi-bility for the operation and management of infrastructures, also if the management and/or ownership of infra-structures are in private hands.

    The divergent multitude of different individual and corporate responsibilities in the operation and manage-

    ment of infrastructures make it difficult to decide who is responsible if accidents or incidents happen. Practice

    K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148 1147

  • 7/30/2019 Critical Infrastructures and Responsibility

    12/12

    shows that involved parties try to shift the responsibility to other organizations, as happened frequently in theNetherlands in the railway sector. Politicians blamed the railway company and vice versa. The same patronwas repeated during a great breakdown of electricity supply in November 2005. In this article the positionis defended that in last resort public authorities have the outcome and remedial responsibility for the infra-structural systems in their country, because these systems are vital for the functioning of society. This respon-

    sibility does in practice extend to critical infrastructures. If something goes wrong politicians almost alwaysare asked for their responsibility as well for the outcome as for the remedial activities. Politicians cannotescape by telling that what has happened is not their responsibility but, e.g. that of the company that runsthe infrastructural system. Of course this company has its own responsibility, but that does not eliminatethe responsibility of politicians.

    By introducing the concepts of outcome responsibility and remedial responsibility the relevance of thedirect (causal and perhaps moral) responsibility for incidents can become less important. It is the outcomeand remedial responsibility for infrastructures that matters! Arguments and considerations should be directedat pointing out what political and institutional arrangements guarantee the best possible realization of out-come and remedial responsibility and because of that an optimal operation and management of infrastruc-tures. This analysis can be applied in concrete infrastructural systems to decide what political andinstitutional arrangements will lead to a better, more reliable and more safe outcome for society.6

    References

    Bolkestein, F., 1998. The Model of Consent The Dutch Experience, Lecture of the President of the Liberal International. Helsinki, 1998.Bovens, Mark, 1998. The Quest for Responsibility. Accountability and Citizenship in Complex Organisations. Cambridge University

    Press, Cambridge.Bovens, Mark, 2006. Analysing and Assessing Public Accountability. A Conceptual Framework, European Governance Papers

    (EUROGOV) No. C-06-01 (January 16, 2006). .De Bruijne, M.L.C., 2006. Networked Reliability. Institutional Fragmentation and the Reliability of Service Provision in Critical

    Infrastructures. Febodruk BV, Enschede.Encyclopedia Brittanica. .Hart, H.L.A., 1968. Punishment and Responsibility. Essays in the Philosophy of Law. Clarendon Press, Oxford.Hermes, Georg, 1998. Staatliche Infrastrukturverantwortung. Rechtliche Grundstrukturen netzgebundener Transport und Ubertragungs-

    systeme zwischen Daseinsvorsorge und Wettbewerbsregulierung am Beispiel der leitungsgebundenen Energieversorgung in Europa.Mohr Siebeck, Tubingen.

    Honore, Tony, 1999. Responsibility and luck. In: Honore, Tony (Ed.), Responsibility and Fault. Hart, Oxford, pp. 1440.Miller, David, 2001. Distributing responsibilities. The Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (4), 453471.Miller, David, 2004. Holding nations responsible. Ethics 114 (2), 240268.Moteff, John, Copeland, Claudia, Fischer, John, 2003. Critical Infrastructures: What Makes an Infrastructure Critical? Report to

    Congress, Washington DC.Rathenau Instituut, 1994. Stroomloos Kwetsbaarheid van de samenleving; gevolgen van verstoringen van de elektriciteitsvoorziening.

    Rathenau Instituut, Rathenau Institute.Schneider, Volker, Jager, Alexander, 2003. The privatisation of infrastructures in the theory of the state: an empirical overview and a

    discussion of competing theoretical explanation. In: Wubben, Emiel M., Hulsink, Willem (Eds.), On Creating Competition andStrategic Restructuring, Regulatory Reform in Public Utilities. Edward Alger, Cheltenham, UK/Northampton, MA, USA, pp. 101137. . Here the websiteversion has been used.

    Smith, Adam 1812 [1776]. Wealth of Nations. Ward, Lock & Co., London.Thompson, Dennis, 1980. Moral responsibility of public officials: the problem of many hands. American Political Science Review 74, 905

    916.Website European Union. : information about history ECSC.Website Journal for Critical Infrastructures. .Website TenneT. .Zandvoort, H., 2000. Controlling technology through law: the role of liability. In: Brandt, D., Ernetic, J. (Eds.), Preprints of Seventh

    IFAC Symposium on Automated Systems based on Human Skill, Joint Design of Technology and Organisation, June 2000, Aachen,Germany. Duesseldorf, pp. 247250.

    Zandvoort, H., in press. Risk Zoning and Risk Decision Making. International Journal of Risk Assessment and Management.

    6 For example: does public or private ownership of the railways, or splitting or not splitting up energy companies lead to optimal results?

    1148 K. van der Bruggen / Safety Science 46 (2008) 11371148

    http://www.connex-network.org/eurogov/pdf/egp-connex-C-06-01.pdfhttp://www.britannica.com/search?query=liability&submit=Find&source=MWBOXhttp://www2.hu-berlin.de/CompPol/Mitarbeiter/JAEGER%20Veroeffentlichungen/schneiderjaeger2003.pdfhttp://www.eu.int/ecsc/results/indexen.htmhttp://www.inderscience.com/browse/index.php?journalCODE=ijcishttp://www.tennet.nl/wiehttp://www.tennet.nl/wiehttp://www.inderscience.com/browse/index.php?journalCODE=ijcishttp://www.eu.int/ecsc/results/indexen.htmhttp://www2.hu-berlin.de/CompPol/Mitarbeiter/JAEGER%20Veroeffentlichungen/schneiderjaeger2003.pdfhttp://www.britannica.com/search?query=liability&submit=Find&source=MWBOXhttp://www.connex-network.org/eurogov/pdf/egp-connex-C-06-01.pdf