56
Institute of Cognitive Science Albrechtstrasse 28 49069 Osnabrück, Germany Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite Article in German Bachelor Thesis by Maria Cieschinger [email protected] Oct. 12 th , 2006 Supervisors: Prof. Dr. Peter Bosch, Dr. Carla Umbach

Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    1

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

Institute of Cognitive Science

Albrechtstrasse 28 49069 Osnabrück, Germany

Constraints on the Contraction of

Preposition and Definite Article in German

Bachelor Thesis

by

Maria Cieschinger

[email protected]

Oct. 12th, 2006

Supervisors: Prof. Dr. Peter Bosch, Dr. Carla Umbach

Page 2: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

2

Table of Contents

0. Abstract p. 3

1. Introduction p. 4

2. Löbner's Proposal for Definites p. 8

2.1 Noun Types and Concepts p. 9

2.2 Semantic and Pragmatic Definites p. 11

2.2.1 Semantic Definites p. 11

2.2.2 Pragmatic Definites p. 19

2.3 Problems p. 24

3. Contractions in Löbner's Framework p. 28

4. A New Theory of Contractions p. 37

4.1 Motivation p. 38

4.2 Three Different Uses of Definite Descriptions p. 41

4.2.1 The Generalised Use p. 41

4.2.2 The Specific Use p. 44

4.2.2.1 The Small-world Use p. 44

4.2.2.2 The Contextual Use p. 50

5. Conclusion p. 53

6. References p. 56

Page 3: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

3

0. Abstract

In this paper we will try to give an adequate account of preposition-article con-

tractions in standard written German. Löbner (1985) suggests that contractions are

not possible in front of pragmatic definites, but possible if the definite description

is semantically definite. Of course, we have to understand the distinction between

pragmatic and semantic definites that he proposes, before we can test his hypothe-

sis. So, after presenting Löbner's theory in Section 2 we will check his claims with

the help of several examples in Section 3. It will turn out that his claims with re-

spect to contractions are correct for pragmatically used definite descriptions, but

many observations with regard to semantic definites cannot be predicted correctly

by his theory. This is why in Section 4 I will propose a different account of con-

tractions. The use of either the contracted or the un-contracted form appears to be

not a matter of choice, but it is dependent on the way in which the respective defi-

nite description is used. I will suggest a distinction between different uses of defi-

nite descriptions that is inspired by Donnellan's (1966) notion of the referential

and the attributive use of definite descriptions. The two main categories I will

propose are the specific and the generalised use. The specific use roughly corre-

sponds to the referential use of definite descriptions, the generalising use corre-

sponding to some extent to the attributive use in Donnellan's sense. The specific

use can again be subdivided into two subcategories: The small-world and the con-

textual use. Contractions are obligatory if definite descriptions are used in the

small-world use or generalisingly, the un-contracted forms are required by contex-

tually used nominals. It will turn out, that such an approach seems to give an ade-

quate account of contractions.

Page 4: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

4

1. Introduction

In some languages that make use of the definite article, we can find forms that

seem to be contractions of a proposition and the definite article. In Italian, for ex-

ample, the contracted forms are obligatory if the phonological environment allows

a contraction and the non-contacted forms are never used in such environments. In

German, on the other hand, we can find both contracted and non-contracted

forms, even in sentences that have an otherwise identical structure, as in the fol-

lowing example.1

(1) Mary and John are watching a news report about the St.-Marien-Hospital in

Osnabrück. Mary says to John:

(a) Ein Freund von mir arbeitet in dem Krankenhaus.

[A friend of mine works in the hospital.]

(A friend of mine works in that hospital.)

(b) Ein Freund von mir arbeitet im Krankenhaus.

[A friend of mine works CONTR-in-the hospital.]

(A friend of mine works in a hospital.)

As can be seen from the English translations, (1a) and (1b) differ in meaning. In

(1a) Mary states that one of her friends works in a particular hospital, viz. in St.-

Marien-Hospital, whereas (1b) is considered a true statement if and only if one of

her friends works in some hospital or other, but not in St.-Marien-Hospital.2 In

contrast to the first case, here Mary might not even be able to answer the question

which hospital it is that her friend works in and she would still have succeeded in

saying something meaningful, something true iff her friend works in a hospital.

This simple example already indicates that the use of preposition-article contrac-

tions cannot simply be reduced to an optional choice on the part of the speaker, as

suggested by Lyons (1999: 328f). Also Heim's (1991: 488) proposal can be shown

to be inadequate with the help of our example; she claims that it is obligatory to

form preposition-article contractions in the presence of certain prepositions, 1 In the following I will give two translations for the German examples where necessary: The first is a word-by-word translation (in square brackets), the second is idiomatic (in parentheses). CONTR indicates the preposition-article-contraction. In cases where the idiomatic translation is sufficiently close to the German original sentence, I will sometimes use CONTR in these transla-tions, too. 2 The exclusion of St.-Marien-Hospital here is due to the Gricean implicature; if Mary had wanted to state that her friend works in St.-Marien-Hospital, she would have used (1a) instead of (1b).

Page 5: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

5

whereas the demonstrative determiner cannot form contractions in otherwise simi-

lar environments. In (1a) dem is not used as a demonstrative determiner and we

can also find other examples that stand in opposition to Heim's suggestion.

(2) Karl sitzt in dem (*im) Auto, das er letzte Woche im Lotto gewonnen hat.

(Karl is sitting in the (*CONTR-in-the) car that he won in the lottery last

week.)

(3) ... und dann habe ich zu der (*zur) alten Hexe gesagt, sie solle unsere Kinder

endlich in Ruhe lassen.

[... and then have I to the (*CONTR-to-the) old witch said, she should

our children finally leave alone.]

(... and then I told the old witch that she shouldn't harass our children any

more.)

In neither of the two sentences do we find demonstrative determiners, neverthe-

less the contracted forms are not possible.

Lyons' claim is too weak and Heim's explanation for the phenomenon of

contractions in German is too restrictive. In this paper, we are trying to find a the-

ory that comes close to a correct account of the data.

In the course of our investigation we will encounter many different problems that

have to be solved with respect to contractions in German. Our aim is, of course, to

give an adequate account of all of these problems. However, it should be noted

that we are restricting our domain of research deliberately.

First of all, we will not consider all possible preposition-article contrac-

tions that can be found in the German language, rather we will concentrate only

on those forms that have found their way into standard German, i.e. into written

language. By no means are we trying to give reasons or explanations as to why

some forms are considered part of standard German and others are only present in

colloquial language or in certain dialects, and we will not engage in any specula-

tions about possible future inclusions of certain forms into standard German. So

even though contractions in phrases such as umme Ecke ('round the corner), an-

ner Wilmersdorfer Straße (at Wilmerdorfer Straße), inner Schule (in school),

aufer Arbeit (at work) exhibit similar characteristics to contractions in written

Page 6: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

6

German, we will not include such forms into our investigation. The contractions

we are going to consider are only the following: im, am, ins, ans, zur, zum, beim

and vom.

Secondly, in German the use of the definite article in combination with

given names and family names is highly dependent on the dialect of the speaker.

Generally, it can be said that the definite article precedes given names frequently

in Southern German dialects, while its combination with family names seems to

be a phenomenon that is not restricted to Southern German dialects and can also

be found in written language, albeit rather rarely. But since intuitions and judge-

ments of acceptability differ widely with respect to different regions speakers

grew up in, we will exclude this phenomenon from our analysis.

A further restriction to our domain of investigation is that we will not be

concerned with certain collocations that contain contractions. We will take is as

given that phrases like im Vorfeld (in the run-up to something), im Nachhinein

(with hindsight), im Geheimen (in private), im Stillen (inwardly), im stillen Käm-

merlein (when nobody watches you) are considered collocational and hence they

will not be discussed in this paper.

One final remark: The reader may have noticed that I have avoided any reference

to the "inner structure" of contractions. It seems to be a generally accepted fact

that contractions are constructed this way: von + dem > vom, to give just one ex-

ample. Another idea would be that contractions can be ambiguous, i.e. that they

can be constructed with the help of both the definite and the indefinite article. We

would then get something like (von + dem) or (von + einem) > vom. In this paper,

however, we will not be concerned with the inner structure of contractions or with

the morphological processes that build up contractions. We will assume that the

contracted and the un-contracted forms are two different words and we will try to

give an adequate account for the use of either form.

Now that we have seen what we are not going to be concerned with in this paper,

we should turn to what we are going to do. We will start by presenting a theory of

definite NPs that was introduced by Löbner (1985). Löbner distinguishes three

different types of (uses of) nouns: Sortal, relational, and functional nouns. Differ-

ent uses of nouns in different linguistic environments can in turn give rise to sor-

Page 7: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

7

tal, relational, and functional concepts. The meaning of the definite article in Löb-

ner's framework is to indicate that the noun immediately following the definite

article is to be interpreted as a functional concept.3 According to Löbner, the sub-

categorization of uses of nouns enables us to distinguish systematically between

semantic and pragmatic definites. Roughly speaking, the unambiguous reference

of pragmatic definites depends crucially on a particular situation, whereas seman-

tic definites refer unambiguously independent of the particular situation. I will try

to argue, however, that some of the conceptions that are essential for the theory as

such are questionable or at least need more clarification. My main concerns are

the applicability of the classification of uses of nouns and the role of the situation

of utterance in Löbner's framework.

With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con-

tracted and non-contracted preposition-article combinations corresponds directly

to his distinction between semantic and pragmatic definites. So after looking at

the details of his theory, we will test this hypothesis with the help of several ex-

amples and of general observations about contractions. We will see that although

many of our observations can be correctly predicted by Löbner's theory, there

remain some unsolved problems with regard to contractions. It will become clear

that the theory does not make the correct predictions in many cases, that some of

his own examples are not very convincing, and that Löbner's theory seems inca-

pable of handling the use of epithets.

We will then proceed to an analysis of contractions that is inspired by (but

distinct from) Donnellan's (1966) theory of definite descriptions. Since, however,

the theory suggested by Donnellan cannot be applied to contractions in general,

we will need some modifications. These modifications mainly apply to the at-

tributive use of definite descriptions and might change the original theory so

much that we should probably not refer to the result as a result in the sense in-

3 Apparently, Löbner assumes a structure like (a) for complex definite descriptions. Heim & Kratzer (1997: 82f.), on the other hand, point out that a structure like (b) (proposed by Barbara Partee in 1976) is more appropriate for semantic analyses. (a) [[Det N] PP/relative clause/...] (b) [Det [N PP/relative clause/...]] In our analysis we will stick to the second version and we will use the term nominal (NOM) to refer to the constituent [N PP/relative clause/...]. It should be noted, though, that Löbner's termi-nology differs from ours; it seems that he uses the term NP to refer to nominals. Nonetheless, in the discussion of Löbner's proposal I will often use the term nominal instead.

Page 8: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

8

tended by Donnellan any more. The two main distinctions between different uses

of nouns (or of definite descriptions in general) that I want to propose are the gen-

eralised and the specific use. The generalised use roughly corresponds to Donnel-

lan's attributive use in that the speaker makes a statement about something or

other that fits the description used. Generic sentences and nominals will also be

included in this category. The specific use, on the other hand, is inspired by Don-

nellan's notion of the referential use of definite descriptions. All nominals that are

used referentially are classified as specific, but we will also consider nominals as

being used specifically if they show certain syntactic characteristics. As a result of

those considerations we will also find definite descriptions in this class that would

be regarded attributive in Donnellan's theory; we could say that the syntactic

properties can override the semantic properties of definite descriptions.

Definite descriptions that belong to the category of the generalised use will

obligatorily be used with contractions in the presence of the appropriate environ-

ment, while those that belong to the specific category do not exhibit a uniform

distribution with respect to contractions. That is why we will again subdivide this

class, viz. into the small-world and the contextual category. The small-world use

necessarily occurs with the contracted forms, the contextual use uniformly re-

quires the non-contracted forms.

Let us now turn to Löbner's proposal for definite descriptions.

2. Löbner's Proposal for Definites

According to Löbner (1985) the problem of preposition-article contractions in

standard German has already been solved. He claims that "cliticization of the arti-

cle to a preposition as a host [...] is possible if and only if the NP is semantically

definite and not too complex" and that "the contracted forms are not possible in

the same phrases as soon as they are used to refer 'pragmatically' in our sense"

(Löbner 1985: 311f). In order to put ourselves in a position where we can sensibly

decide whether this is right, we must first take a closer look at (the relevant as-

pects of) the theory as it is presented in Löbner (1985) and we have to get ac-

quainted with the necessary terminology.

Page 9: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

9

2.1 Noun Types and Concepts

According to Löbner "nouns have two basic interpretations. Taken in isolation

they can be considered either sortal nouns or relational nouns" (Löbner 1985:

292). As the names suggest, sortal nouns classify objects as belonging to particu-

lar sorts exhibiting certain characteristics, and relational nouns refer to objects that

stand in a specific relation to other objects. Sortal nouns can logically be under-

stood as conjunctions of (one or more) one-place predicates, i.e., as a conjunction

of other sortal nouns. Relational nouns differ from sortal nouns in that they ex-

press relations, i.e. two- (or many-) place predicates, possibly in conjunction with

several one-place predicates. It is not possible to substitute one-place predicates

by many-place predicates and vice versa; that it why sortal nouns cannot be re-

duced to relational nouns or the other way round. Löbner himself uses the nouns

woman and wife to exemplify the distinction between sortal and relational nouns.

The meaning of woman can be understood as a conjunction of other sortal nouns

such as human, adult and female. The meaning of wife differs from that of woman

in that while a wife is also a woman, a wife additionally always is the wife of

somebody, i.e. a wife stands in a particular relation to another object. We can ex-

press this fact with the help of a two-place predicate.

A special case of relational nouns are functional nouns. They also express

relations, i.e. many-place predicates, but here the relation is a function. This

means that an object is related unambiguously to another object, it is a one-to-one

relation. We can use the noun wife again to make this distinction clearer. If we

imagine a society in which a man can be married to more than one woman at a

time, the noun would be relational, i.e. it expresses a one-to-many relation. More

than one person could stand in a wife-relation to a particular person. In a society

that only allows monogamous marriage, however, a particular man can only have

one wife at a time. In that case wife would be a functional noun, because it relates

a person unambiguously to another person. Functional nouns, then, refer unambi-

guously in virtue of their inherent meaning, "they do not allow for more than one

referent" (Löbner 1985: 293). Relational4 and sortal nouns, in contrast, can refer

unambiguously only accidentally. This can happen if by coincidence only one

object satisfies the one-place predicates of a sortal noun or if, for example, a 4 I will use the term relational in the narrower sense from now on. The three types of nouns are: sortal, relational and functional nouns.

Page 10: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

10

woman in a polygamous society happens to be the only and not the, say, third

wife of someone, and the one-to-many relation wife becomes a one-to-one relation

due to the circumstances.

Note, that the reference of the two nouns that we used as examples cru-

cially depends on external factors. We have already seen that the classification of

wife in the polygamous society as a one-to-one or a one-to-many relation differs

under different circumstances. Time also plays an important role for determining

the referents in our examples. As for sortal nouns, an individual might belong to a

certain sort at one time but not at another. A person, let us call her Claire, might

be a woman in the year 2006 (i.e. fulfil the one-place predicates human, adult and

female), but she would not belong to the sort woman in 1983 when she was only

three years old. It is obvious that the reference of a noun depends on various fac-

tors (such as time and location), which we will simply call a reference situation

from now on. This view of course changes the logical properties of the noun types

that we introduced above. Instead of one-place predicates we will now use two-

place predicates for sortal nouns, the first argument being a situation. The same

changes apply to the many-place predicates for relational and functional nouns,

we add a situation as the first argument of the respective relations.

The sortal-relational-functional distinction that Löbner proposes for nouns also

applies to concepts. Concepts are often represented by nouns (Löbner 1985: 295),

but complex definite descriptions can also represent concepts. "They can be un-

derstood as effective mental procedures with a certain input/output characteristic."

(Löbner 1985: 295) But what is an effective mental procedure? It is some kind of

mental process (Löbner remains rather vague here) that maps a situation and ob-

jects to objects (in the case of relational and functional concepts) or situations to

objects (in the case of sortal concepts). Roughly speaking it is a procedure to

evaluate the predicates that are given by the noun. (Sometimes the context of an

utterance has to be consulted in order to be able to form a concept, because some

(or even all) of the arguments of relational and functional nouns might not be

specified explicitly.)

Löbner's discussion of semantic and pragmatic definites heavily relies on

his notion of sortal, relational, and functional concepts. One and the same noun

can express different kinds of concepts in different situations. It should be noted

Page 11: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

11

here that Löbner speaks rather sloppily, and often uses the term noun instead of

concept, a point we will discuss in more detail in Section 2.3. In the rest of this

section I will try to stick to Löbner's distinction between nouns and concepts, but

we will see that, unfortunately, due to Löbner's own phrasing, this distinction will

get a little blurred at times.

2.2 Semantic and Pragmatic Definites

Now that we have introduced Löbner's basic terminology, we can proceed to his

two different uses of definite descriptions as semantic and pragmatic definites.

Semantic definites represent functional concepts and the nominal refers unambi-

guously independently of a particular situation. Pragmatic definites crucially de-

pend on the context of an utterance for unambiguous reference and they have head

nouns that are used relationally or sortal. We will begin with the semantic defi-

nites.

2.2.1 Semantic Definites

Let us first consider functional concepts that have a situation as their only argu-

ment, FC1s as Löbner calls them. Proper names paradigmatically belong to this

class of functional concepts. Löbner claims that "within a certain range of situa-

tions, proper names refer unambiguously to certain objects. They constitute con-

stant functional concepts, as their value does not vary with their possible argu-

ments." (Löbner 1985: 299) Remember that the possible arguments for FC1s are

situations. What the above statement means, then, is that there are (smaller or lar-

ger) sets of situations in which a particular proper name refers unambiguously.

With regard to personal names, the set of situations in which such a name can be

used felicitously is rather small, especially in the case of bare first names. Other

proper names, such as geographical names or dates for example, have a much

larger range of situations in which they yield one and the same value. Phrases that

contain proper names are also considered FC1s; examples from Löbner's text

would be the year 1984, the opera Rigoletto or the number zero. Although sortal

nouns are used here for disambiguation, the phrases are interpreted as functional

concepts, and hence as semantic definites, because of the proper names that are

Page 12: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

12

used.5 Löbner also subsumes under the category of proper names NPs with an

abstract sortal head noun that is specified explicitly by a subordinate clause:

(1) the rumour that Reagan is going to resign

(2) the idea to have pizza now

Unfortunately, he does not give an explanation for this view (and it is very ques-

tionable whether such phrases should be regarded as proper names), but in the

discussion of Löbner's theory of contractions below we will stick to the classifica-

tion of such phrases as semantic definites.

The last group of cases that can be considered as proper names is much

less controversial. Examples for this group are the World Trade Center in New

York, the Tower in London or the Louvre in Paris. Here we have sortal head

nouns, but since the objects that are referred to are unambiguous in a certain lo-

cally restricted domain of situations they can acquire the status of proper names.

A similar line of reasoning lies behind the classification of certain uses of other

sortal nouns as FC1s, though not as proper names. In a locally restricted domain,

say, a particular neighbourhood, we can uses phrases that have sortal head nouns

such as the pub, the supermarket or the playground unambiguously if they per-

form a certain unique role in that domain. Because of the unique role of these ob-

jects in a particular set of situations, the above examples give rise to functional

concepts and are semantic definites. Another important group of FC1s are certain

complex definite descriptions. Sortal or relational head nouns that are combined

with superlatives, ordinals or adjectives such as last, only, next, same or other can

form functional concepts. The head nouns provide a set of alternatives due to their

non-functional status and the adjectives single out a particular member of that set.

So in these cases we again get a one-to-one mapping from (a set of) situations to

objects, i.e. we have semantic definites.

5 Löbner also claims that "definiteness [...] is not a matter of overall reference, but only a matter of the link provided by the noun following the article immediately." (p. 303) However, the link pro-vided, e.g., by the sortal noun year in the definite NP the year 1984 does not seem to provide a one-to-one link, i.e. a functional link. It is not really clear to me how Löbner's conception of defi-niteness in fact applies to the examples cited above, but a detailed discussion of this question would lead us into a direction that is far off the topic of this paper.

Page 13: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

13

Functional concepts that have both a situation and an object as their arguments

(FC2s) are slightly more difficult to analyse in Löbner's framework.6 It should be

noted that FC2s always have functional nouns as heads (Löbner 1985: 302); rela-

tional head nouns, as in some FC1s, do not seem to give rise to FC2s. (Sortal head

nouns are not possible either, because they only have a single argument and hence

cannot be used to build FC2s.) As we have seen above, FC2 nouns yield unambi-

guous values for their respective arguments. Löbner also uses the (more intuitive)

term 'linking' instead of 'returning a value for the given arguments' in his discus-

sion of FC2s. In his words: "FC2s provide one-to-one (i.e. unambiguous, func-

tional) links from arguments to their values. The argument in turn, will be linked

to the situation referred to [...]" (Löbner 1985: 301). We can imagine this idea as

some kind of link-chain in which the value of a noun that gives rise to an FC2-

concept is linked unambiguously to an object and that object is then linked to the

situational argument. (Of course this is a simplistic picture and it is a little unclear

how FC3 nouns could be integrated into this picture, but it might be more intuitive

than functions for some readers.) It is important to notice that the link between the

argument and its value needs to be a one-to-one link, whereas the link between the

situation and the argument can also be a one-to-many link. If all links are func-

tional, the overall reference of the NP will be determined, but if the chain of links

is somehow interrupted (e.g. by a one-to-many link between the situation and the

argument as in the father of one of my friends) the reference of that NP will be

indefinite, even though the definite article is used and the NP is considered defi-

nite. We have to distinguish between two kinds of definiteness here: The definite-

ness of the head noun and the determinedness of the whole NP (Löbner 1985:

303). Löbner is only concerned with the first kind, which is provided by the link

between the argument and its value alone. If and only if that link is unambiguous

(independently of the situation), then the NP will be semantically definite in Löb-

ner's terms.

The cases where all arguments are explicitly given are not that interesting.

We simply check whether the argument and its value stand in a functional rela-

6 Löbner does not include functional three-place predicates in his detailed analysis of semantic definites. Distance, difference, or relationship are examples for the admittedly small group of functional nouns that need two objects as arguments in addition to the situational argument (FC3 nouns). In principle, they should show the same characteristics as FC2 nouns, but we are not going to explore them in more detail.

Page 14: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

14

tion. If the arguments are not given, however, Löbner's theory seems to provide

significant insight into linguistic phenomena such as the "associative anaphoric

use" and the "introductory situational use" (Löbner 1985: 303). In introductory

statements like

(3) This is the clutch.

the implicit argument (most probably a car) is provided by the "immediate physi-

cal environment" (Löbner 1985: 304), it can thus be regarded as an implicit deic-

tic7 argument. According to Löbner, here clutch represents an FC2 and requires an

object as its argument (additional to the situational argument) and a suitable ar-

gument is provided by the situation. Even though the argument is dependent on a

particular situation, the link between the argument and its value (the clutch) is an

unambiguous link and the NP is a semantic definite. According to Löbner, only

functional nouns can be used in introductory statements (Löbner 1985: 304), be-

cause only they represent general functional concepts. Löbner has adopted the

notion of an introductory statement from Hawkins (1978) (Löbner 1985: 303).

Whether or not this notion is sensible, Löbner's prediction that only nouns that are

used functionally can occur in such statements does not seem to be correct. Con-

sider the following examples:

(4) A veterinary has been called to the zoo. He wants to know which tiger it is

that he is supposed to examine. The attendant answers:

This is the tiger.

(5) A group of children are visiting the zoo. Their teacher says:

This is a tiger.

As I understand Löbner, only nouns that are always used functionally, and there-

fore represent general functional concepts, can occur in introductory statements.

In (4), however, it is not at all obvious that the noun tiger represents a general

functional concept, even less an FC2 with an implicit deictic argument. We could,

of course, argue that tiger in (4) is a functional noun, because the referent of that

7 I use the term deictic in Löbner's sense here, i.e., the implicit argument refers to an object that is somehow present in the utterance situation, as opposed to objects that are introduced verbally in a text or a conversation.

Page 15: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

15

noun performs a certain unique function in a locally restricted domain, but this

interpretation does not correspond to Löbner's prediction: In (4) the head noun is

not "a functional noun in its own right" (Löbner 1985: 304). As for sentence (5),

the indefinite article is used, so tiger can obviously not be used functionally, and

hence should not be possible in an introductory statement like (5).

In anaphoric associative uses the implicit argument is usually provided by

the linguistic context of an utterance. Consider the following example:

(6) Fritz read a review about an interesting book he wanted to buy. But when he

arrived at the bookstore he had forgotten the title.

Title is usually used as a functional noun (a title is always the title of something

and that something can only have one title) and the missing argument (an interest-

ing book) is given in the preceding sentence. The link obviously is functional, so

the noun title represents an FC2. This analysis is theoretically appealing because it

does not need to assume discourse referents introduced by an interesting book and

we can do away with speculations about the nature of the relation between a book

and its title according to Löbner. "The crucial condition [for the use of associative

anaphors, von mir eingefügt] is that the head noun [...] provides a general two-

place functional concept for which there is an appropriate argument in the imme-

diate linguistic context." (Löbner 1985: 304)8

Let us now turn to the last class of semantic definites: Configurational uses of

definite descriptions. Configurations are abstract situations that essentially consist

of objects and certain relations between those objects. Such an abstract situation

contains only those objects that are explicitly mentioned in a sentence and the

objects are linked to each other via relations. These relations in turn are func-

tional, i.e., one-to-one relations, because they unambiguously relate the objects to

each other. Consider the following example from Löbner (Löbner 1985: 304):

8 It remains an open question in Löbner's paper, however, how we can recognise 'appropriate' arguments. Do they have to appear in the sentence directly preceding the anaphoric NP? Does the lexical entry of title somehow specify what kinds of arguments it can take? Songs, books, plays, newspapers?

Page 16: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

16

(7) He was the son of a poor farmer.

The relational noun son does not provide a one-to-one link from its arguments to

its value, or, to put it differently, sentence (7) does not imply that the poor farmer

has only one son. Nevertheless, the definite article is used here and according to

Löbner the definite article indicates that the following noun is to be interpreted as

a functional concept (Löbner 1985: 314). So how do we get to an interpretation of

son as an FC2? Löbner suggests that statements like (7) refer to an abstract situa-

tion, to a configuration, instead of referring to a particular situation. In the sen-

tence at hand only one son and one father are explicitly mentioned and, therefore,

the configuration has only those two objects as elements. So, the link provided by

son unambiguously relates the son and the father and is thus a functional link and

the head noun son represents a functional concept.9 That is why the definite article

can be used in this kind of "generic" statements.10 It is obvious that the relations

between objects that are provided by relational or functional nouns play a crucial

role in configurational uses of definite descriptions. This explains why sortal

nouns do not occur in statements that make use of abstract situations: They do not

provide the necessary links between the elements of a configuration. Sentences

like (8) where the relational noun is replaced by a sortal noun are unacceptable.

(8) *He was the man of a poor farmer.11

9 It could be argued that here the link is a one-to-one link only accidentally and not due to the inherent meaning of the noun. The relation provided by son is inherently a one-to-many relation, not a functional relation. So, the noun son is obviously used functionally here, and not relationally. Interestingly, Löbner claims that both relational and functional nouns can occur in configurational statements and that the relational nouns give rise to functional concepts due to the structure of the abstract situation. The distinction between nouns and concepts seems to get rather fuzzy at this point. We will return to this point in Section 2.3 below. 10 The term generic is used by Löbner only to indicate that a statement refers to an abstract instead of a particular situation and should (probably) not be understood as generic in the sense that sen-tences like The whale is a mammal. are generic. We will discuss generic statements and generic nominals in Section 4.2.1. 11 It could be argued that statements like (8) are unacceptable because of the uninterpretability of a phrase like man of x. This interpretation can rather easily be rephrased in Löbner's terms, however: As we saw in Section 2.1, sortal nouns cannot express relations, and man is obviously used as a sortal noun in sentence (8). That is why something like man of x (which is supposed to express a relation) is not interpretable.

Page 17: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

17

So far we have only been concerned with the object-argument and not with the

situation argument of relationally or functionally used nouns. First we need to

distinguish between an abstract situation and a "real" or "actual" situation (Löbner

1985: 306). An abstract situation is a configuration in the sense explicated above

and the real situation is provided by the situational argument of a relational or

functional noun. But how can we connect configurations to actual situations?

Löbner claims the following. "Sentences involving [...] abstract situations convey

the notion that the real situation referred to is of that type [...] configurational de-

finites generate in a first step an abstract situation [...] which then must be an-

chored in one of several possible ways in the actual situation referred to." (Löbner

1985: 306) Anchoring in this sense means that the abstract situation must be a

subsituation of the real situation, i.e. the real situation has to be such that all ob-

jects that are present in a configuration and all their relations to each other must

also be given in the real situation. The relation between the abstract and the real

situation is, of course, indefinite. The configuration is only one possible subsitua-

tion of the actual situation, that is why Löbner claims that it can be anchored in

the real situation in "one of several possible ways". As was the case with FC2s

above, also here the definiteness expressed by the definite article only applies to

the one-to-one link between the argument of the noun immediately following the

article and its value, and not to the determinedness of the reference of a complete

phrase or sentence.

Löbner also wants to include certain sentences that do not contain the

definite article into the class of configurationally used NPs. He claims that state-

ments like (9) and (10) generate abstract situations.

(9) She goes to church.

(10) He came after lunch.

It is not really clear to me, however, in what sense church and lunch are nouns

that can provide the necessary relations in a configuration. With regard to (9) we

could say that the sortal noun church gives rise to a functional concept (an FC1, to

be more precise), because it performs a certain unique function in a locally re-

stricted domain of situations. I am not sure, though, whether this view actually

conforms with the intuitive understanding of (9). The sentence is true iff "she"

Page 18: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

18

goes to some church or other on a regular basis (in order to attend church service).

It is not necessary that the object denotated by church has a certain unique func-

tion in a locally restricted domain of situations. We could easily imagine a street

full of churches and that "she" goes to a different church in that street every Sun-

day. Here, none of the churches performs a unique function, they all have the

same function, viz. that of being a place where mass is held. Another line of rea-

soning would be to point out that the noun church in (9) is used to refer to church

service or mass, and not to a building. Similar problems seem to arise, though. In

a configuration only those objects that were explicitly mentioned are consider,

i.e., she and church in our example. But what could be the functional link that

relates those two objects? Even if we accept that church service or mass are used

functionally here, it is not really clear to me what kind of relation would be estab-

lished by the head noun.

Sentence (10) appears to be even less convincing. Lunch is certainly not

relational or functional; so, again, we seem to have a sortal noun that is supposed

to generate a configuration. We could, of course, argue that the noun lunch has an

implicit argument (a particular date most probably, e.g. May 15th 1974), but this

does not conform to Löbner's idea that only those objects are part of the configu-

ration that have been introduced via explicit mention. And, again, even if we as-

sumed that the noun was used functionally in (10), what kind of relation could be

established by lunch in our example? The only other object that is explicitly men-

tioned is "he", so the relation would have to be an unambiguous relation between

"he" and a lunch. What relation could this be? We could say that the verb provides

a relation between the two objects (Löbner 1985: 315ff), but it is doubtful that a

verb like come really provides two distinct thematic roles which "he" and lunch

could play. We could, of course, claim that there exists some kind of verbal con-

cept like come-after that could provide the necessary thematic roles that would

then relate the two objects by a one-to-many link. But this solution seems rather

ad-hoc and does not correspond to the syntactic structure of the sentence or to the

usual syntactic characteristics of the verb to come. And is it really desirable to

strain the lexicon that much? If we suggest a verbal concept like come-after, we

would also have to propose something like come-before, come-between-x-and-y

and maybe even more concepts. This seems rather redundant to me.

Page 19: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

19

Let us summarise the discussion of semantic definites in Löbner's own words be-

fore we move on to pragmatic definites. In definite descriptions that are semantic

definites the head noun is "always a functional concept, either by virtue of its

lexical meaning plus, occasionally, additional general constraints12, or due to the

restriction to limited abstract configurations within which relational concepts can

be used unambiguously" (Löbner 1985: 307).

2.2.2 Pragmatic Definites

Semantic definites represent functional concepts (and thus refer unambiguously)

independently of a particular situation. Pragmatic definites, on the other hand,

depend on the utterance situation for unambiguous reference and Löbner claims

that they have sortal or relational head nouns, never functional head nouns. Löb-

ner distinguishes three types of pragmatic definites: Endophoric, anaphoric and

deictic definites.

Endophoric definites are nominals that contain a disambiguating attribute. This

attribute can be a relative clause, or an adverbial or prepositional phrase, but in the

following discussion we will restrict ourselves to relative clauses. For the endo-

phoric use of a definite description it is essential that the relative clause provides

an unambiguous link between the object referred to with the help of the head noun

and other objects, i.e. it gives rise to a functional concept. Usually, the functional

concept depends on the thematic roles that are given by the verb, and does not, as

in the case of semantic definites, depend on the inherent meaning of the head

noun, locally restricted domains of situations or abstract situations. Löbner claims

that the thematic roles of a verb directly correspond to functional concepts (Löb-

ner 1985: 315), that it is the inherent meaning of the verb that provides a one-to-

one link between objects and it depends on the particular situation whether the

functional concepts refer unambiguously (Löbner 1985: 317). But also locational

predicates or the time or purpose of an action can provide unambiguous links and

thus give rise to a functional concept (Löbner 1985: 316). The idea behind this

claim is that, with respect to verbs, there usually is one agent of an action and one

recipient, so the relation expressed by a verb is functional. A similar argument can

12 The additional constraints that can help to form functional concepts consist of locally restricted domains of situations in phrases like the pub or certain adjectival attributes like first or next.

Page 20: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

20

be given for locational predicates, for example. An object can normally be found

in exactly one place, and that same place, in turn, cannot be occupied by another

object, hence the functional link between an object and a location.

Let me exemplify the endophoric use of a definite description with an example:

(11) The party John went to last night was boring.

John is linked to a situation and the phrase party John went to last night relates

parties to John via a kind of go-to-relation, i.e. it is a relational concept. If we fur-

ther assume that people usually go to only one party on a particular evening (indi-

cated by the phrase last night), then the nominal phrase actually constitutes a

functional concept, relating John unambiguously to one party. Note, that it is the

thematic roles of the verb that provide the functional interpretation of the definite

description: One person usually goes to one place or event (at a particular time).

Intuitively, one could propose a classification of endophoric definites as FC1s and

hence as semantic definites. According to Löbner, however, this is not possible

due to the inner structure of the NP party John went to last night.13 We can para-

phrase (11) in the following way.

(12) John went to a party last night and the party was boring.

Here, party cannot be considered semantically definite in the sense discussed

above. We have to consider the context of the utterance (i.e. the preceding sen-

tence) in order to determine whether or not the sortal head noun party expresses a

sortal or a functional concept. It is neither the inherent meaning of the noun or

local restrictions of situations, nor an abstract situation that accounts for the func-

tional interpretation of the head noun. So, in that sense we can say that endophoric

uses of definite descriptions depend on a particular situation of utterance for un-

ambiguous reference and should therefore be regarded as pragmatic definites.

13 Löbner also gives a second argument against the classification on endophoric NPs as semantic definites, viz. that the definite article only applies to the immediately following noun and not to the phrase as a whole. This seems a little circular, though. It is Löbner's proposal that suggests such a meaning of the definite article, so I do not think that this is a valid argument at this point.

Page 21: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

21

Anaphoric definites differ from endophoric uses of definite descriptions in that

they do not contain an explicit specification that gives rise to a functional concept

(Löbner 1985: 317). Löbner restricts his discussion to direct anaphors and we will

follow him with respect to this restriction. Direct anaphors refer to an object that

has previously been introduced into the discourse. Let us see what Löbner has to

say about the introduction of discourse referents and the structure of the "universe

of discourse" (Löbner 1985: 317). A universe of discourse can be regarded as a

network which is "a complex abstract situation, in which every constituent – ob-

ject or event – plays a unique role" (Löbner 1985: 317). As we saw above, in an

abstract situation the members of that configuration are related to each other via

functional relations. Remember that only those objects that are explicitly men-

tioned figure in an abstract situation and that this is the reason for the functional-

ity of the links between the objects. The same applies to a discourse-network. The

constituents, i.e. the nodes of the network, are introduced via explicit specification

and the relations between the constituents are one-to-one links. Additionally, each

node is provided with a certain amount of predicative information.

Let us now come to the insertion of nodes into the network. According to Löbner,

the first nodes that constitute the universe of discourse are objects or locations that

are given by the utterance situation. New nodes will be integrated into this uni-

verse by means of explicit mention. Löbner claims that the "introductory situ-

ational use" of definite descriptions as in (3) (This is the clutch.) can be used to

establish new nodes in the network. Also FC2s with semantically definite argu-

ments are capable of first mention use (Löbner 1985: 303), and, of course, nouns

that are preceded by the indefinite article. But there are many more possibilities to

create new nodes. Most endophoric definites are capable of first mention use and

so are FC2s with an implicit anaphoric argument ("associative" anaphors). Con-

figurational uses of definite descriptions as well as FC2s with indefinite argu-

ments can also introduce new nodes. All of these are nodes that refer to objects,

but events are also constituents of the universe of discourse. They are created by

the use of verbs and verbs can also contribute predicative information for object-

nodes (Löbner 1985: 317). The relations between the nodes are established either

by the inherent meaning of semantic definites, configurational uses of NPs and

Page 22: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

22

additional general constraints, or by the thematic roles of verbs or locational or

temporal attributes.

To return to anaphoric definites, a nominal phrase can be used anaphori-

cally if (and only if) it refers to a node already present in the universe of dis-

course. Since the nodes carry predicative information, the sortal or relational con-

tent of the anaphoric phrase can be reduced to a minimum, but they have to be

sufficient to single out a particular discourse referent. Sometimes such additional

information can be used to further specify a given discourse referent and will then

be added to the predicative information already contained in the respective node

or new links between the constituents will be established. To sum up, the sortal or

relational head nouns of anaphoric NPs are pragmatic definites, because the un-

ambiguous reference of these nouns crucially depends on the discourse-network,

i.e. it depends on a particular situation of utterance.

We saw that anaphoric definites refer to previously introduced discourse referents.

Deictic definites, in contrast, refer to objects that are present in the situation of

utterance. At first sight, they appear to be pragmatic definites par excellence, but

not all uses of deictic definites are pragmatic in Löbner's sense. The "immediate

situation use" of deictic NPs is semantically definite. Löbner gives the following

examples for this use.

(13) Beware of the dog!

(14) Harry, mind the table!

In (13) the noun dog represents a functional concept, viz. the dog that belongs to

the house, so the NP is a semantic definite. The implicit deictic argument is pro-

vided by the context of the utterance, but the NP itself is an FC2 and should be

analysed analogously to (semantically definite) FC2s with implicit arguments that

we have discussed above. This seems reasonable, but in my opinion Löbner's sec-

ond example is less convincing. Here, table is supposed to represent a functional

concept, too. It refers to "the table that always stands where it stands" (Löbner

1985: 310) and therefore, according to Löbner, gives rise to a functional concept.

It is not really clear to me, however, how this notion of a functional concept cor-

responds to his earlier characterization of FCs. Furthermore, I do not think it is

Page 23: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

23

necessary that the table always stands at a particular place if (14) is uttered.

Harry's wife could have rearranged the furniture while Harry was asleep and she

might use a sentence like (14) to stop him from running into a table that usually

stood two feet further to the right. In that case Löbner's explanation for the func-

tionality of the concept expressed by table is not applicable.

Or what about sentences like (15), (16) and (17)?

(15) Mind the gap!

(16) Beware of the bugs: Fire ants can kill Americans.14

(14) and (15) have a very similar structure, so the head noun in (15) should also

express a functional concept. It is not really obvious, though, why gap should be

regarded as a functional noun here. Does gap in (15) express a functional concept,

because it is the gap between the platform and the door of the tube, i.e., because it

stands in a certain relation to other object (as does dog to the house in (13))? Or

because it is the gap that always is where it is, similar to Löbner's explanation for

the functionality of table in (14)?15 It is not clear to me, either, in what sense bugs

in sentence (16) could represent a functional concept. Functional concepts usually

express relations, but what kind of relation could be represented by bugs in a sen-

tence like (16)? Do the bugs belong to something or some place, i.e., are they

bugs of something or other? An explanation along the lines of that for (14) does

not seem very probable either. It seems that Löbner's account of what he calls the

"immediate situation use" needs further clarification if we want to be able to han-

dle sentences like (15) and (16) appropriately in his framework.

There is a second use of deictic definites, which is pragmatically definite,

because the unambiguous reference of the head nouns depends on a particular

situation: The "visible situation use" (Löbner 1985: 309). "This use is possible if

one and only one object of the kind belongs to the situation of utterance, if that

object is visible (at least for the addressee) and known to him as such." (Löbner

1985: 310) Löbner proposes not only to include nouns that denote visible objects

14 from http://abcnews.go.com/GMA/Health/story?id=2143091&page=1 15 The speaker of (15) probably assumes that the hearer can recognise the functionality of the head noun, otherwise she would most likely use a different description. But if the hearer knows that the gap is where it always is, then what use would there be in uttering (15)?

Page 24: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

24

into the category of "visible situation use", but also referents of nouns that are

perceived by other organs than the eyes: smell and noise would be examples for

such nouns.

But also here I think that Löbner's theory needs further explication.

(17) Pass me the table!

Imagine that Mary uses an orange box as a table. The noun table then represents a

functional concept, because the object table refers to functions uniquely as a table

(cf. Löbner 1985: 293). Statement (17) is clearly deictic and, hence, the noun is

regarded as being pragmatically definite. The problem is that functional nouns are

not possible in pragmatic definites (Löbner 1985: 307) according to Löbner.

2.3 Problems

Now that I have presented Löbner's proposal for definites, I want to make a few

remarks before we proceed to the application of this theory to contractions in

German. I already hinted at some of the difficulties that I have with Löbner's

ideas. These were of a rather specific nature, but there are also two general prob-

lems to the theory: The distinction between sortal, relational and functional nouns

on the one hand and the role of situations on the other.

As we saw in the above discussion, the three types of uses of nouns have

distinct characteristics. In Table 1 I briefly summarised the most important as-

pects.

Page 25: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

25

Type of Use of

Noun

Characteristics

Sortal nouns - conjunction of one-place predicates

- classify objects

- can represent functional concepts in restricted domains of situations

- often used as head nouns in pragmatic definites

Relational nouns - conjunction of one-place and many-place predicates, i.e., they spec-

ify one-to-many relations between objects

- can generate abstract situations

- often used as head nouns in pragmatic definites

Functional nouns - conjunction of one-place and many-place predicates, they specify

one-to-one, i.e., functional relations between objects

- identify referents

- refer unambiguously independent of utterance situation

- represent functional concepts

- cannot be used as head nouns in pragmatic definites

- are usually not preceded by indefinite article

Table 1: Characteristics of different types of uses of nouns in Löbner's framework.

Sortal nouns are a conjunction of one-place predicates and classify objects (Löb-

ner 1985: 293), they can represent functional concepts in restricted domains of

situations (Löbner 1985: 299f) and are often used as head nouns in pragmatic de-

finites. Relational nouns contain sortal information, i.e. one-place predicates, and

additionally specify one-to-many relations between objects (many-place predi-

cates), they often occur in sentences that generate abstract situations and in prag-

matic definites. Functional nouns are similar to relational nouns in that they pro-

vide relations between objects in addition to sortal information, but here the rela-

tions are functional, i.e. one-to-one relations. They refer unambiguously inde-

pendently of a particular situation of utterance due to their inherent meaning, they

give rise to functional concepts (Löbner 1985: 296), always identify a referent

instead of just classifying it (Löbner 1985: 293) and they cannot appear as head

nouns in pragmatic definites (Löbner 1985: 307). Functional nouns also exhibit

another characteristic which has not been mentioned yet: "They do not allow the

Page 26: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

26

indefinite article as long as it can be presupposed that they have a referent" (Löb-

ner 1985: 297). Roughly speaking, they can appear with the indefinite article only

if it is not certain that they actually refer to something, e.g. in questions about the

existence of some object.

This appears to be a very problematic view. All count nouns can be pre-

ceded by the indefinite article. In particular those that Löbner regards as "the most

perspicuous cases" (Löbner 1985: 294) of functional nouns, viz. nouns that refer

to unique parts of objects like roof or head. Murderer is also considered an obvi-

ously functional noun by Löbner (Löbner 1985: 294). To me, the following sen-

tences are perfectly acceptable.

(18) He fell off a roof yesterday and broke his left leg.

(19) The other day, I found a head in the trash bin.

(20) A murderer was arrested at the airport yesterday.

(18), at a first glance, looks like a sentence that generates an abstract situation

which must then be anchored in the real situation. But what kind of relation

should hold between "he" and a roof? The noun roof obviously does not provide a

relation to "he". We could propose that the thematic roles that are provided by the

verb establish a fell-off-relation. But then the distinction between sentences like

(18) and endophoric definites would get very fuzzy. With respect to endophoric

definites, Löbner argued that they are pragmatic definites mainly on the ground

that the functional relations are not provided by the noun, but by the linguistic

context, i.e. the verb, and that the unambiguous reference of the thematic roles

depends on the particular situation of utterance. Similar thoughts can be invoked

by (19), but the same problems arise. Sentence (20) is also problematic, because

Löbner considers the head noun murderer an obvious case of a noun that is used

functionally (Löbner 1985: 294), nevertheless the indefinite article can be used.

Similar to (18) and (19) we could claim that (20) generates an abstract situation,

but also similar to (18) and (19), it is not clear how or what kind of relations could

be established between the objects that are explicitly mentioned in sentence (20).

But, again, this argument might not be valid, because the head nouns in all the

Page 27: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

27

above examples are not preceded by the definite article and Löbner only consid-

ered configurations that are constructed by means of definite descriptions.16

A different approach to sentences like the above could be to regard the

head nouns as sortal nouns. Löbner concedes that nouns cannot be subdivided in a

strict way and therefore prefers to talk of concepts instead (Löbner 1985: 295).

However, I have the feeling that he does not stick to his own assumptions. If it

depends on the rest of a sentence whether or not a noun is functional, then he

should not use phrases like "[Definite descriptions] with a functional head noun

obviously yield functional concepts" (Löbner 1985: 296) or "Pragmatic definites

[...] have sortal or non-functional relational head nouns" (Löbner 1985: 307). It

seems that a great deal of his account depends on the division of nouns into three

distinct classes, but his argument seems to be somehow circular if this division

really depends on the linguistic environment of a noun. I am not claiming, though,

that Löbner's hypothesis about the meaning of the definite article is inappropriate.

It might well be that the meaning of the definite article is to indicate that the fol-

lowing noun should be interpreted as a functional concept (Löbner 1985: 319). It

is his methodology that I am not really satisfied with.

Let us now turn to the second difficulty that I have with Löbner's theory, the role

of situations.

If I understand Löbner correctly, the situational argument of sortal, rela-

tional or functional nouns refers to the situation of utterance. Locations, objects

and relations between the objects that are present are somehow contained in the

situational argument as well as the time and place of an utterance and information

about the speaker and the audience (and possibly many more aspects, too). The

situation of utterance plays a crucial role for the distinction of semantic and prag-

matic definites. In the case of "'semantic definites' the referent of the definite is

established independently of the immediate situation or context of utterance. [...]

'Pragmatically definite' NPs, on the other hand, are essentially dependent on spe-

16 I think that the same complications arise in a sentence like (21) where the definite article is used. (21) John went to the doctor. Also in this case, the noun doctor does not provide a relation between "John" and a doctor, which is necessary for the generation of an abstract situation. The verb might establish such a relation, but then we run into the same problems as above.

Page 28: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

28

cial situations and contexts for the non-ambiguity [...] of a referent." (Löbner

1985: 298)17 First of all, the classification of a noun as relational or functional

does depend on the situation of utterance. I gave an example for this (the noun

wife) in Section 2.1. It might be the case that a noun has one of the interpretations

in a lot of different situations of utterance that share, say, the time and space as-

pects, and differ with respect to all other situational information. Nevertheless, a

phrase like "independently of the particular situation referred to" (Löbner 1985:

299) seems inappropriate. This becomes even more evident, if we consider simple

FC1s (cf. Section 2.2.1). According to Löbner, sortal nouns, for example, can give

rise to functional concepts in a restricted domain of situations. Also here, the ap-

plicability of the definite article does depend on the situation of utterance. And,

conversely, it is possible to imagine quite a few (if we like even rather similar)

situations in which an NP like the girl (which should be pragmatically definite)

refers unambiguously. The claims Löbner makes about the role of the situation of

utterance are either too strict or to loose. But they surely are not very welldefined.

3. Contractions in Löbner's Framework

In Section 1 we already saw that both contracted and non-contracted form can be

used in German and we are looking for a theory that makes the correct predictions

about the conditions for the use of either form. Löbner proposes a solution that

draws on his distinction between semantic and pragmatic definites. In this section

we will test Löbner's hypothesis with the help of different observations and exam-

ples, assuming, of course, that the theory presented above is free of any unclari-

ties, i.e. we will ignore the doubts mentioned earlier.

Löbner claims the following: "Cliticization of the article to a preposition as

a host [...] is possible if and only if the NP is semantically definite and not too

complex [...] Contracted forms are particularly frequent in configurational uses

[and ...] the contracted forms are not possible [...] as soon as they are used to refer

"pragmatically" in our sense to specific objects" (Löbner 1985: 311f). Let us first

concentrate on those uses of definite descriptions, which do not allow contracted

forms, i.e. pragmatic definites.

17 It is unclear what Löbner means by "context" here (the linguistic environment? the universe of discourse? or are situation and context identical?), but we will ignore this vagueness.

Page 29: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

29

(1) Ich habe mir dieses Buch von dem (*vom) Mann, der nebenan wohnt

ausgeliehen.

(I borrowed this book from the (*CONTR-from the) man, who lives next

door.)

(2) Paul hat sich ein Haus gekauft. Zu dem (*Zum) Haus gehört ein riesiger

Garten.

[Paul has himself a house bought. To the (*CONTR-to-the) house

belongs a huge garden.]

(Paul bought a house. With the house comes a huge garden.)

(3) Pointing to a shop:

In dem (*Im) Laden kann man Wein kaufen.

[In the (*CONTR-in-the) shop can one wine buy.]

(They sell wine in the shop.)

In the examples above the nominals that are interesting for our discussion are

endophoric, anaphoric, and deictic definites, respectively. It is indeed the case that

the contracted forms cannot be used in pragmatic definites, Löbner's theory makes

correct predictions. His claims about contractions in semantic definites, however,

are much less persuasive.

First of all, the "if and only if" in the first sentence of the citation is too

strong. The implication only works in one direction: If a contraction is used, then

the following NP is a semantic definite, but if the following NP is semantically

definite it is not a necessary consequence that contractions can be used. We can

find many examples for semantic definites that cannot be preceded by a con-

tracted form (or that are at least preferably used with the un-contracted forms) if

the referents of the respective nominals are not known to some extent to the audi-

ence.

(4) Fritz hat gestern eine Rezension über ein interessantes Buch gelesen, das er

sich heute kaufen wollte. Von dem (?Vom) Titel hatte er sich allerdings

nur den ersten Buchstaben gemerkt.

(Yesterday, Fritz read a review about an interesting book that he wanted

to buy today. Unfortunately, he could only remember the first letter of the

(?CONTR-of-the) title.)

Page 30: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

30

(5) Bei dem (?Beim) Patienten Müller muss man aufpassen, er ist cholerisch und

gewalttätig.

(You have to be careful with the (?CONTR-with-the) patient Müller, he is

choleric and violent.)

(6) Karl hat diese Informationen von dem (?vom) Bürgermeister einer kleinen

walisischen Stadt bekommen.

(Karl got this information from the (?CONTR-from-the) mayor of a small

town in Wales.)

Sentence (4) is a slightly modified version of one of Löbner's own examples for

FC2s with implicit anaphoric arguments (cf. Löbner 1985: 304). The definite de-

scription is semantically definite, nevertheless the non-contracted form is pre-

ferred. In (5) the phrase corresponding to the patient Müller is also a semantic

definite, it is an FC1 which has a usage that resembles that of a proper name (cf.

Löbner 1985: 299). But also here the contracted form does not seem to be pre-

ferred if the referent of the phrase is not known to some extent. To clarify this

point, consider the following different situations in which (5) could be uttered:

(5a) A nurse starts working in a hospital. She does not know any of the patients

yet and is given a list that contains information about each patient. The

head nurse explains the list and points out that the patient Müller is a

somewhat problematic patient.

(5b) Two nurses work in the same hospital and they know the patients. They talk

about their experiences with different patients. When they come to Mr.

Müller one of the nurses utters (5).

In the second situation the contracted form will most probably be preferred, while

the un-contracted form will be used in a situation like (5a). In both cases the defi-

nite description is used as a semantic definite, and should therefore exhibit the

same characteristics according to Löbner. It is not clear, how the difference in the

use of the contracted and the un-contracted form can be accounted for in Löbner's

framework.18 Similar problems arise in sentence (6). The definite description the

mayor of a small town in Wales is, again, one of Löbner's own examples (Löbner

18 In Section 4 I will propose an account of contractions that gives an explanation for the differ-ence between the use of the definite description in situations like (5a) and (5b).

Page 31: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

31

1985: 302). The phrase expresses an FC2 with an indefinite argument and like in

(5) the contraction appears to be unacceptable in certain contexts, at least to some

speakers of German. If both the speaker and her audience know the person re-

ferred to to some extent, the contraction will probably be used, and the un-

contracted form is usually preferred if the definite description is e.g. used to intro-

duce a new discourse referent that was not known until then. So, also in this ex-

ample we seem to use either the contracted or the un-contracted form, depending

on the knowledge of the speakers about the referents of the respective definite

description. As stated above already, Löbner's proposal does not seem to be able

to account for this difference in use.

Secondly, it should be noted that the formulation "cliticization [...] is pos-

sible" (Löbner 1985: 311) is inappropriate. It implies an optional choice on the

part of the speaker between the contracted and the non-contracted form. However,

it is usually not a matter of choice whether a contraction can be used or not.19 We

have already seen examples for the unacceptability of contractions, but we can

also find instances of NPs that can only occur with contracted forms.

(7) Vom (*Von dem) Nachdenken bekommt Paula immer Kopfschmerzen.

[CONTR-from-the (*from the) thinking hard gets Paula always a head

ache.]

(Thinking hard always gives Paula a headache.)

(8) Im (*In dem) letzten Jahr ist meine Nichte in die Schule gekommen.

[CONTR-in-the (*in the) last year has my niece into school got.]

(My niece started attending school last year.)

(9) Im (*In dem) Irak herrscht Bürgerkrieg.

[CONTR-in-the (*in the) Iraq there is civil war.]

(There is civil war in Iraq.)

(10) Ludwig Erhard war im (*in dem) Deutschland der Nachkriegszeit ein

bekannter Politiker.

[Ludwig Erhard was CONTR-in-the (*in the) post-war Germany a well-

known politician.]

(Ludwig Erhard was a well-known politician in post-war Germany.)

19 There are rather few definite descriptions that appear to always have the same meaning, irre-spective of use of the contracted or the non-contracted form. In the next section I will suggest that this apparent indifference to the contraction is in fact due to the possible over-riding of certain constraints.

Page 32: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

32

In all of the above cases the contracted forms are obligatory. It is not easy to de-

cide whether nominalised verbs like Nachdenken (thinking hard) in (7) are seman-

tic or pragmatic definites. I would tend to regard them as semantic definites,

though. In sentence (7), at least, an abstract situation seems to be generated which

has to be anchored in the real situation. It appears to be generally the case that

nominalised verbs cannot be preceded by un-contracted forms, so the contraction

is not only possible but even obligatory here. The NP corresponding to last year

in (8) is a semantic definite (cf. Löbner 1985: 301) and the contraction is, again,

mandatory. Some, but not all, proper names that refer to regions or monuments

are used with the definite article in German. If such a proper name, i.e. such a

semantic definite, is preceded by an appropriate preposition, the contracted form

has to be used, as can be seen in sentence (9). Interestingly, even those proper

names that usually are not preceded by the definite article require contracted

forms as soon as they are modified in a certain way. If the modified noun phrase

yields a sortal concept in Löbner's sense the contractions are obligatory, as can be

seen in (10). Unmodified proper names of this kind do not allow contracted forms.

(11) Ludwig Erhard war in (*im) Deutschland ein bekannter Politiker.

(Ludwig Erhard was a well-known politician in (*CONTR-in-the) Ger

many.)

I said that modified nominals can yield sortal concepts in Löbner's sense. This

means that a phrase like Deutschland der Nachkriegszeit (post-war Germany) is

not used as a proper name, but it refers to a certain kind (of whatever it is that the

proper name usually refers to). The modified NOM in (19) seems to imply a set of

"different kinds of Germany", including post- and pre-war Germany, Southern

Germany, Germany in the 1840ies, etc, and the definite description is used to refer

to one of the members of that set with the help of the sortal information that is

provided by the respective modifying phrase, der Nachkriegszeit (post-war) in our

example. Whether or not such sortal concepts give rise to FCs that are then either

pragmatic or semantic definites shall not interest us at this point, the reason being

that, if we strictly follow Löbner, it should not be possible that phrases that con-

tain proper names can form sortal concepts in the first place. In Section 2.2.1 we

Page 33: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

33

saw that such phrases are considered as being "very close to proper names" (Löb-

ner 1985: 299) in Löbner's framework and that they are not regarded as sortal

concepts, but as FC1s. I am stressing this point, because, as I already pointed out,

there is linguistic evidence that proper names and certain modified versions of

proper names behave differently.

(12a) Deutschland, Süddeutschland

(Germany, South-Germany)

(12b) Deutschland der Nachkriegszeit, südliches Deutschland, wiedervereinigtes

Deutschland

(post-war Germany, Southern Germany, reunified Germany)

The nouns in (12a) are used as proper names and do not occur with contracted

forms. Those in (12b), on the other hand, refer to a certain kind (of Germany) and

require contracted forms.

Let us briefly examine a few examples that Löbner gives for cases of semantic

definites that are preceded by contractions (Löbner 1985: 312).

(13) im Mai, zur Halbzeit

[CONTR-in-the May, CONTR-at-the halftime]

(in May, at half-time)

(14) Er hat beim Poker 2 Pfund verloren.

[He has CONTR-at-the poker two pounds lost.]

(He lost two pounds playing poker.)

Löbner does not explain his examples any further, so let us assume that he consid-

ers them as obvious cases of semantic definites.

We begin with the phrase zur Halbzeit. I would like to point out that

Halbzeit is not an inherently functional noun, it can be used to refer to either the

first or the second half-time, so the noun does not express a one-to-one relation.

Furthermore, I want to suggest that the phrase zur Halbzeit is an idiom and hence

should not be regarded as an example for semantic definites. If zur Halbzeit is

used without the adjectives erste (first) or zweite (second) it refers to the half-time

break, i.e., it is synonymous to zur Halbzeitpause. In that case, the noun would in

Page 34: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

34

fact express a functional concept. Nonetheless, zur Halbzeit seems to be a rather

misleading example for a semantic definite, because the functionality of the con-

cept expressed by the noun is crucially dependent on the meaning of Halbzeit-

pause, and does not depend on the inherent meaning of Halbzeit.

With regard to im Mai I guess that Löbner considers it an obvious case of a

semantic definite because it requires a year as an argument and that there is al-

ways exactly one May for each year.20 I do not think, however, that Mai (or any

other month) necessarily needs an argument. Consider the following sentences.

(15) Mein Freund hat im Mai Geburtstag.

(My boyfriend's birthday is in May.)

(16) Cäsar starb im März.

(Cesar died in March.)

In both cases the contracted form is obligatory, so the respective phrases should

be semantically definite. But why? Neither noun requires a year as an argument.

My boyfriend's birthday is in May every year. As for (16), the sentence is per-

fectly acceptable without any need for (direct or indirect) reference to the year 44

BC. In my opinion, the uses of May and March, respectively, should again be re-

garded as sortal concepts and it is not at all obvious that they are clear cases of

semantic definites. If that was correct, a recourse to abstract situations would not

explain the semantic definiteness of (15) or (16) either. The nouns are sortal and

hence cannot provide a relation to the subjects. And if we assume that the verbs

provide the needed relations, we run into the same problem as in Section 2.3 with

(14) and (15), viz. that the distinction between semantic and pragmatic definites

would get rather blurred.

With respect to (14), it is a clear case of obligation of the contracted form.

The non-contracted forms are unacceptable in conjunction with the noun Poker.

This, again, shows that the choice between contracted and non-contracted forms is

not optional at all.

20 I chose this interpretation, because regarding Mai as a proper names seems implausible and I could not come up with another explanation for the classification of May as semantic definite.

Page 35: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

35

I do not have much to say about Löbner's claim that contractions occur frequently

in configurational uses. In my opinion, this formulation is so weak that not much

is in fact conveyed by it. And I do not want to repeat my arguments against ab-

stract situations or against the view that nouns like hospital or doctor are non-

sortal yet again.

Before we proceed to a new (and hopefully more adequate) theory of contractions,

let us briefly return to pragmatic definites and the impossibility of contractions in

such uses. Consider the following example from Section 1 repeated here for con-

venience.

(17) ... und dann habe ich zu der (*zur) alten Hexe gesagt, sie solle unsere Kinder

endlich in Ruhe lassen.

[... and then have I to the (*CONTR-to-the) old witch said, she should

our children finally leave alone.]

(... and then I told the old witch that she shouldn't harass our children any

more.)

Epithets are always used as anaphoric NPs21 and cannot be preceded by contracted

forms. As pointed out above, Löbner's claims about contractions and pragmatic

definites seem accurate. Epithets are used anaphorically, are pragmatic definites

and the prediction that they do not occur with contractions seems to be correct. I

do not see a way, though, to give a satisfying account of epithets in general within

Löbner's framework.

Let us, in a few words, recapitulate how the anaphoric link can be estab-

lished according to Löbner. The universe of discourse is a network that is built up

in the course of a discourse. It is an abstract situation, so only those objects,

events and relations are part of the network that are explicitly mentioned. The

21 I could not come up with examples for the deictic or the endophoric use of epithets (but maybe there are some??). In sentences like (18) Do you see the old witch over there? (19) The old witch, who always scared our children, died at last. the definite description appears to be used deictically and endophorically, respectively, in Löbner's sense. However, such sentences seem to be acceptable only if the hearer already has some infor-mation about the referent of the NP, and then I would regard the NP as an anaphoric expression.

Page 36: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

36

predicative information that is associated with each node is provided by the inher-

ent meaning of the nodes or by explicit specification. An NP which is used ana-

phorically refers back to nodes in the universe of discourse and "it is sufficient to

employ some distinctive sortal information in order to refer to the node in ques-

tion" (Löbner 1985: 318). With respect to epithets, however, it seems questionable

whether the information that they supply can ever be sufficient to single out a par-

ticular node in the network.

Let us try to find out what kind of information epithets do provide. If a

phrase like the old witch is used as an epithet it obviously does not have its literal

meaning and I would suggest that nouns that can be used as epithets have an addi-

tional lexical meaning.22 To simplify matters, let us assume that the old witch has

a literal meaning and a non-literal meaning roughly corresponding to the mean

and hateable woman. Interestingly, an epithet does not really provide (possibly

additional) sortal information about the referent, rather it expresses the attitude of

the speaker towards the referent. In a sentence like (17), for example, the person

referred to by the old witch is not necessarily a mean and hateable woman (she

might in fact be a very friendly woman), but the speaker of that sentence consid-

ers her mean and hateable. The problem of analysing epithets in Löbner's frame-

work seems to lie in the difficulty of singling out a particular discourse referent by

means of the sortal information alone. As I understand his conception of the uni-

verse of discourse, the nodes (i.e. objects in our example) that an anaphoric NP

refers to have to fulfil (at least part of) the descriptive content of the anaphoric NP

(cf. Löbner 1985: 309) and the descriptive content, in turn, has to be sufficient to

single out a particular node in the network. It is not at all obvious that the descrip-

tive content of an epithet is really sufficient to establish an unambiguous ana-

phorical link to a previously mentioned object, usually additional information

(e.g. the attitude of the speaker towards the referent) has to be taken into consid-

eration. In Löbner's proposal, however, does not seem to allow for the accommo-

dation of such additional information.

Furthermore, it is not the case that the node that is referred to always

shares at least part of the predicative information that is given by the lexical 22 The adjectives that can precede nouns that are used as epithets do not seem to contribute much to the meaning of the whole phrase. Because of this, I only propose to assign an additional lexical meaning to the nouns and not to the adjectives. (They should be regarded as semantically vacuous in most cases.??)

Page 37: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

37

meaning of an epithet. In (17) the predicate woman, which is part of the lexical

meaning of the epithet, is most probably contained in the predicative information

of the corresponding node. But epithets like the dragon can be used to refer both

to men and to women and the meaning of the epithet does not provide even such

basic predicates as man or woman which could help to single out a particular dis-

course referent. Maybe the thematic roles of the verb could provide an unambigu-

ous link to a previously mentioned object, but I do not think that this solution

would be in Löbner's spirit. "VPs either supply predicative information for exist-

ing nodes or introduce new objects or event nodes." (Löbner 1985: 317) Löbner

apparently does not consider verbs as being able to establish anaphoric links.

In this section we have tested Löbner's hypothesis about contractions with a large

set of examples. Although the theory correctly predicts that endophoric, anaphoric

and deictic NPs cannot be preceded by contracted forms, Löbner's claims about

contractions in front of semantic definites are less convincing. It is not a matter of

choice whether or not contractions are used, phrases like "particularly frequent"

(Löbner 1985: 312) or "cliticization [...] is possible" (Löbner 1985: 311) do not

characterise the use of contracted forms correctly. Furthermore, we have found

examples for semantic definites that cannot be preceded by contractions. Epithets

appear to resist an analysis along the lines of Löbner's theory, too. In short, Löb-

ner's hypothesis seems appropriate for pragmatic definites (with the exception of

epithets), but with respect to semantic definites this hypothesis seems rather in-

adequate. In the following section I will propose a different theory of contractions.

It is inspired by Donnellan's theory of definite descriptions (1966), the primary

reason being that epithets can be dealt with rather easily in Donnellan's frame-

work.

4. A New Theory of Contractions

In this section I want to propose my own theory of contractions. I will introduce

three different uses of NPs: The contextual, the small-world and the generalised

use. The latter two require contracted forms, while the first can only be preceded

by un-contracted forms. The contextual and the small-world use can be subsumed

under the category of the specific use of definite descriptions, which roughly cor-

Page 38: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

38

responds to Donnellan's referential use, the generalised use being somewhat simi-

lar to the attributive use of definite descriptions. We will also see that some at-

tributively used NOMs can occur both with contracted and un-contracted forms.

This is not arbitrary, though, and I will suggest that syntactic characteristics can

override the constraints imposed by the different uses of definite descriptions.

4.1 Motivation

Let me briefly explain why Donnellan's theory of definite descriptions might be a

good starting-point for an analysis of contractions. During the discussion of Löb-

ner's theory we saw that epithets seem to resist a thorough analysis and that ge-

neric statements are not included in Löbner's considerations. In my opinion, both

epithets and generic statements can be dealt with in a rather straightforward fash-

ion in the framework proposed by Donnellan.

As I said earlier, epithets are always used anaphorically. They refer to a

specific object (that has been introduced already). If a definite description is used

to refer to someone particular, it is used referentially in Donnellan's sense. The

descriptive content of the NP is just a tool to enable the audience to pick out the

right referent (Donnellan 1966: 249), it is not necessary that the referent actually

fits that description. As we have seen in Section 3, the information that is pro-

vided by an epithet does not have to be consistent with other sortal information

that is associated with the referent of the NP. The reference to an object can be

successful even if that object does not fit the description provided by the NP

(Donnellan 1966: 249). So, the problems that we ran into earlier in Löbner's

framework, viz. that the meaning (or descriptive content) of the epithet did not

enable us to refer to a particular node in the universe of utterance, do not seem to

arise if we apply Donnellan's analysis. Note, that anaphoric and referential are

not synonymous. The referential use of a definite description does not depend on

previous mention of an object that fits the definite description. Epithets are rather

special in the sense that they are referential expressions that can only be used ana-

phorically.

Before we discuss the three different uses of NPs that I want to propose in detail, I

want to emphasise that the context of utterance is crucial for deciding whether an

NP is classified as small world, contextual or generalised. There are in general no

Page 39: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

39

such things as "contextual nouns", but "a definite description occurring in one and

the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either [of the

three] way[s]" (Donnellan 1966: 247).

(2) Fritz ist beim Arzt.

[Fritz is CONTR-with-the doctor.]

(Fritz is with the doctor.)

(3) Fritz ist bei dem Arzt.

(Fritz is with the doctor.)

Let us now look at different situations in which the above sentences could be ut-

tered.

(2a) Anna, Felix and Fritz live in a small village. There is only one doctor in that

village. Anna asks Felix about Fritz' whereabouts.

(2b) Fritz has been feeling ill for some time already and went to see a doctor.

Felix tells Anna that.

(3a) Anna is at a party and asks her friend Felix where Fritz is. Both Anna and

Felix know that there is one doctor at the party and Felix thinks that Fritz

is talking to that doctor.

The noun Arzt (doctor) in (2) is used rather differently in situations (2a) and (2b).

In (2a) Felix refers to a particular person, viz. the person who is practicing medi-

cine in the village. The definite description is used referentially in Donnellan's

sense. In (2b), on the other hand, the referent of the noun Arzt is not determined. It

is totally irrelevant which doctor it is that Fritz is seeing, but it is essential that the

referent fits the description, i.e. that he is a GP. This use of the NP is similar to the

attributive use of definite descriptions, Fritz is seeing someone or other who fits

the description, i.e. who is a doctor. Sentence (3) has a structure very similar to

that of (2). But, again, the use of the noun Arzt is rather different from those in

(2). The description is used referentially, Felix has a particular person in mind that

he makes a statement about. In that sense, (3) and (2) uttered in the situation (2a)

are similar. However, in (2a) the description is not only a tool to enable the audi-

ence to pick out the right referent, as is the case in (3). It also indicates that the

person referred to plays a unique role in a locally restricted domain, here the

Page 40: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

40

(unique) role of a person who practises medicine in the village. So, even though

(3) and (2) uttered in situation (2a) resemble each other to a large extent, I would

like to distinguish the uses of the respective NPs as the small-world (in (2a)) and

the contextual use (in (3)) of a definite description, because they behave differ-

ently in the presence of a preposition. The contextual use requires the non-

contracted forms, whereas the small-world use (and also the generalised use in

(2b)) can only be preceded by contracted forms.

The threefold distinction between uses of nouns can also be found in the follow-

ing examples.

(4) Anna and Felix are talking about a party some time ago. Anna says:

An dem Abend habe ich mich richtig besoffen.

[CONTR-in-the evening have I got myself really drunk.]

(I got really drunk that night.)

(5) Felix tells Anna about the plans for his wedding next Sunday.

Am Abend gibt es dann noch ein Feuerwerk.

[CONTR-in-the evening there will be also a display of fireworks.]

(There will also be a display of fireworks in the evening.)

(6) Anna talks to Felix about her daily routines and says:

... und am Abend trinke ich ein Glas Rioja und rauche eine Zigarette.

[... and CONTR-in-the evening drink I a glass of Rioja and smoke a

cigarette.]

(... and in the evening I have a glass of Rioja and a cigarette.)

In (4) and (5) the noun Abend (night or evening) is used referentially, in (6) it is

used similarly to the attributive use. The use of the definite description in (5) dif-

fers from that in (4) in that the evening that is referred to plays a unique role in a

small community, viz. the role of being the evening of Felix' wedding. Abend in

(6), in contrast, does not refer to a particular evening, but rather to some evening

or other. And, again, we see that the preposition-article contraction cannot appear

in front of a noun that is used contextually (as in (4)).

To sum up, the occasion of an utterance is crucial for determining the way in

which a definite description is used and a distinction into three different kinds of

Page 41: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

41

uses is motivated by linguistic evidence. Let us now turn to a more detailed de-

scription of the three uses of NPs.

4.2 Three Different Uses of Definite Descriptions

I will begin with the generalised uses of a definite description and then we will

proceed to the specific use, which can again be subdivided into the small-world

and the contextual use of an NP.

4.2.1 The Generalised Use

As stated above, the generalised use of a definite description roughly corresponds

to the attributive use of Donnellan, in the sense that the speaker does not refer to a

particular object, but rather to a set of objects that fit the description or to an insti-

tution or a common (i.e. not necessarily unique) role. Additionally to (2) uttered

in situation (2b) and to (3), all of the following are examples for the generalised

use of a noun.

(7) Mein Freund arbeitet im Krankenhaus.

[My friend works CONTR-in-the hospital.]

(My friend works in a hospital.)

(8) Cäsar starb im März.

[Cesar died CONTR-in-the March.]

(Cesar died in March.)

(9) Anders als beim Menschen, bei dem die Nase aus dem Gesicht ragt, geht beim

Leguan der Kopf einfach in die Schnauze über.23

[Different CONTR-from-the human, whose nose protrudes from the face,

CONTR-at-the iguana the head simply merges with the mouth.]

(In contrast to humans, with their noses protruding from the face, the

iguana's head simply merges with the mouth.)

The identity of the referent of hospital in (7) is irrelevant, what is important is that

the friend works in some place or other that fits the description, i.e. that he works

23 from http://www.green-iguana.net/gruener-leguan/leguan-anatomie.htm

Page 42: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

42

in a hospital.24 The speaker of (7) might not even know which hospital it is that

his friend works in, still the sentence is perfectly acceptable. Also in (8), the

speaker might not even be aware of the fact it was March 44 BC in which Cesar

died, so he is not referring to a specific object, but only to some object that fits the

description. Sentence (9) could be regarded as a statement about a general prop-

erty of iguanas; it is a characterising sentence. The phrase beim Leguan (roughly:

the iguana's) refers to the kind Iguana-Iguana, it is a kind-referring nominal. (cf.

Krifka (1995)). So here we have an example for a generic sentence that contains a

generic NOM and I propose to subsume both of these notions of genericity under

the category of generalisingly used definite descriptions. The idea to regard kind-

referring nominals as being used generalisingly seems to be rather obvious. But

what about object-referring, i.e., non-generic definite descriptions that occur in

characterising sentences? Consider the following example:

(10) Im Winter ist es kalt.

[CONTR-in-the winter it is cold.]

(It is cold in winter.)

(10) is a generic sentence and the noun Winter is not kind-referring. The sentence

does not express "specific episodes or isolated facts, but instead [reports] a kind of

general property, that is, [reports] a regularity which summarises groups of par-

ticular episodes or facts" (Krifka (1995): 2). The nominal does not refer to a par-

ticular object and should therefore be regarded as an instance of the generalised

use.

It is often possible to refer to a particular instance of the kind described by the

NOM, for example with the help of pronouns. Consider the following example.

(11) Anna war gestern beim Zahnarzt. Er hat ihr einen Zahn gezogen.

(Anna went CONTR-to-the dentist yesterday. He pulled one of her teeth.)

24 The indefinite article in the English translation already indicates the non-determinedness of the referent of the nominal. In German, however, the definite article is used, if we assume that the contracted forms are built with the help of a preposition and the definite article.

Page 43: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

43

I suggest that the anaphoric reference to dentist is accomplished by accommoda-

tion. The phrase beim Zahnarzt (roughly: at the dentist) does not introduce a dis-

course referent. Otherwise (12) would not be possible.

(12) Fritz war heute nicht beim Friseur. Es gibt nämlich keinen in dem kleinen

Dorf, in dem er wohnt.

(Fritz did not go CONTR-to-the hairdresser's today, because there is none

in the small village he lives in.)

Admittedly, the sentences are a little awkward, but acceptable. The example

shows that it seems inappropriate to suggest the introduction of a discourse refer-

ent via the phrase beim Friseur (roughly: at the hairdresser's). We can also find

other examples that seem to support the idea that a generalising definite descrip-

tion does not introduce a discourse referent.

(13) Ruth geht morgen zum Zahnarzt. *Der andere Zahnarzt ist im Urlaub.25

(Ruth is going CONTR-to-the dentist tomorrow. *The other dentist is on

vacation.)

A contrast is not permissible, because there is no discourse referent that could be

contrasted by the phrase der andere Zahnarzt (the other dentist).

I said above that it is often possible to refer to a particular instance indi-

cated by the generalised use of a noun. In (14), for example, the pronoun seems

inappropriate (at least according to my intuitions).

(14) Ruth geht morgen zum Zahnarzt. ?Er wohnt in der Lerchenstrasse.

(Ruth is going CONTR-to-the dentist tomorrow. ?He lives in Lerchen-

street.)

Maybe accommodation is only possible if the sentence containing the pronoun

somehow expresses a property that is associated with the concept of the descrip-

tive content of the nominal, the concept of a dentist (whatever that means) in our

25 This example is taken from Bosch (1995).

Page 44: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

44

example (cf. example (11)). But this is just a guess and needs further investiga-

tion.

Nominalised verbs seem to represent a class of nouns that are almost always used

generalisingly. Consider (15), repeated here from Section 3.

(15) Vom Nachdenken bekommt Paula immer Kopfschmerzen.

[CONTR-from-the thinking hard gets Paula always a headache.]

(Thinking hard always gives Paula a headache.)

This might be due to the meaning of such nouns, but this suggestion would need

further examination, too.

For the generalised use of a definite description it is essential that the description

fits. It is not used as a tool for identifying a particular referent, it rather classifies

objects with the help of the descriptive content of the respective nominal. In the

presence of an appropriate preposition the contracted forms have to be used.

4.2.2 The Specific Use

The specific use of a definite description resembles the referential use of NPs in

Donnellan's sense. In the specific use the speaker always has a particular object in

mind that he makes a statement about. It is not always necessary that the descrip-

tion actually fits the object referred to. The specific use of definite descriptions

does not in general exhibit a uniform distribution of contracted or un-contracted

forms. A subdivision of specifically used definite descriptions seems necessary.

4.2.2.1 The Small-world Use

The small-world use of a definite description always requires the contracted

forms. In Section 4.1 we already saw a few examples for the small-world use.

Generally speaking, definite descriptions belong to the small-world category if

they refer to a particular object that has a unique function or role in a regionally

restricted domain or in a small community. There are, however, two different

ways in which small-world nominals can be used: They can be used in bridging

anaphors and as local names. The reference of a nominal that is used in bridging

Page 45: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

45

anaphors is established via accommodation. Local names, on the other hand, are

used to refer to individuals that are unique in a particular community. Let us begin

with the latter kind of nominals that belong to the small-world category.

In certain situations all of the following examples are instances of nominals being

used as local names.

(16) Anna war gestern beim Priester.

[Anna was yesterday CONTR-at-the priest.]

(Anna went to see the priest yesterday.)

(17) Felix hat seinen Rucksack im Rathaus vergessen.

(Felix forgot his rucksack CONTR-in-the town hall.)

(18) Der Sohn vom Bürgermeister wurde am Sonntag verhaftet.

(The son CONTR-of-the mayor was arrested on Sunday.)

Suppose that Anna lives in a village that only has one priest. If (16) is uttered in

such a situation, then the nominal Priester (priest) refers to the village's priest and

we could say that the nominal is used as a name here. Of course, this interpreta-

tion is only possible in a restricted domain, that is why I propose the term local

name for this kind of small-world nominals. The nominal Rathaus (town hall) in

(17) can be understood as referring to the local town hall. In this case the NOM

would, again, be used as a local name. An analogous interpretation can be given

for (18): A city usually has only one mayor and members of a particular commu-

nity can use the nominal Bürgermeister (mayor) as a local name that refers unam-

biguously to a certain person.

In the above examples, the descriptive content of the nominal fitted the

referent. It is not always necessary, though, that the description fits the object that

is referred to.

(19) Das Buch liegt da vorne beim Tisch.

(The book lies over there, CONTR-near-the table.)

(20) Felix wurde gestern vom General zum Essen eingeladen.

(Yesterday, Felix was invited to dinner CONTR-by-the general.)

Page 46: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

46

Sentence (19) is acceptable if the object referred to by Tisch (table) has a unique

function in a locally restricted domain or in a small community. The descriptive

content of the nominal is a tool that enables the audience to pick out the right ref-

erent, in our example it also corresponds to the kind of function that the referent

has. It appears to be a general characteristic of the small-world use of a definite

description that the descriptive content indicates the function or role that a particu-

lar object has. This does not mean, however, that the object necessarily fits the

description. In (19), for instance, the noun table could well be used to refer to an

orange box which happens to function as a table in the situation at hand. So, the

description does not fit the referent, but it indicates the function of the referent

and is used as a local name. Also in (20) the referent of the NOM does not have to

be a general. He might be a man with a pedantic and austere character who never

served in the military. Nevertheless, if he is regarded as performing a unique role

(i.e. the role of being a general) in a small community, the nominal general is

used as a local name. Of course, the same sentence could not be used in the same

way if uttered to someone who is not part of that community, so the use of local

names is restricted to certain social circles or to certain regions.

Nouns that refer to regions or named buildings should also be considered

as local names (even though the community in which such names are used is

rather large). Nouns of this kind which are usually not accompanied by the defi-

nite article belong to this kind of small-world use if they are modified in certain

ways (cf. Section 3). In (21) I have listed a few NOMs that cannot occur with un-

contracted forms.

(21) im Nahen Osten, am Brandenburger Tor, im Deutschland der

Nachkriegszeit, am Mount Everest, im südlichen Italien, beim Olympia-

stadion, am Funkturm, im Berlin der 20er Jahre, im Jüdischen Museum,

zum Kongresszentrum, im Sportpalast

(in the Middle East, at the Brandenburg Gate, in post-war Germany, at

Mount Everest, in Southern Italy, near the Olympic Stadium, at Funk-

turm, in Berlin in the twenties, in the Jewish Museum, to the Kon-

gresszentrum, in the Sportpalast)

Page 47: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

47

It should be noted that in their discussions of contractions Haberland (1985: 86ff.)

and Hartmann (1980: 17f) make use of a notion very similar to local names in our

sense. "Einwohner eines Dorfes können auf Grund ihres allgemeinen Wissens

über den Gemeinderat, die Kirche, den Pastor, die Mittelpunktsschule usw. reden,

Mitglieder einer Familie über den Vater, die Mutter, die Großmutter, die Oma

usw." 26(Hartmann (1980): 18). Both Hartmann and Haberland point out that there

are some German dialects (most notably Fering and the Mönchengladbach-

dialect) that have two different definite articles, one being used with local names,

the other being used with all other nominals. Apparently, contractions can usually

be used in contexts that would allow for the definite article that combines with

local names (Haberland (1985): 89). Unfortunately, I am not very familiar with

the German dialects mentioned, so it is not possible to verify Haberland's and

Hartmann's claims in this paper. Nevertheless, I think their notion similar to local

names is very helpful for analysing contractions.

As stated above, what is referred to as "FCs with implicit anaphoric arguments" in

Löbner's proposal or sometimes as "bridging anaphors" is also an instance of the

small-world use in our sense.

(22) Peter hat neulich sein altes Radio repariert. Am Verstärker war etwas kaputt

gegangen.

[Peter has the other day his old radio repaired. CONTR-at-the amplifier

had something broken.]

(The other day, Peter has repaired his old radio. The amplifier was

broken.)

The referent of the phrase amplifier is established via accommodation. I regard

this use of the definite description as small-world, because the referent has a cer-

tain unique function in the situation of the utterance and the identification of the

referent is only possible in a restricted domain. In our example, the domain is re-

stricted in the sense that outside of the situation of utterance the referent of the

definite description does not perform a unique function.

26 "Due to their general knowledge, inhabitants of a village can talk about the district council, the church, the pastor, the secondary school, etc., member of a family can talk about the father, the mother, the grandmother, the granny, etc." (my translation)

Page 48: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

48

In Section 3 I gave an example similar to (22), repeated here for conven-

ience, in which the un-contracted form was preferred.

(20) Fritz hat gestern eine Rezension über ein interessantes Buch gelesen, das er

sich heute kaufen wollte. Von dem / Vom Titel hatte er sich

allerdings nur den ersten Buchstaben gemerkt.

(Yesterday, Fritz read a review about an interesting book that he wanted

to buy today. Unfortunately, he could only remember the first letter of the

/ CONTR-of-the title.)

Vom Titel (CONTR-of-the title) in (22) can be regarded as an instance of the

bridging-anaphoric use of small-world nominals. The referent of the nominal is

established via accommodation and the contracted form is required. The un-

contracted form, on the other hand, indicates that the nominal is used anaphori-

cally, because anaphoric NOMs do not allow contracted forms. I want to suggest

that the apparent indifference with respect to the contracted or the un-contracted

form in sentences like (22) arises from an ambiguity of the interpretation of the

respective nominal: The nominal being used in a bridging anaphor on the one

hand and the indication of some other kind of anaphoric use (i.e., contextual use

in our sense, cf. Section 4.2.2.2) on the other.

There is a last set of examples that should also be considered as instances of the

small-world use; I am not really sure, though, whether these examples can be sub-

sumed under either of the two different kinds of small-world nominals that I in-

troduced earlier. Maybe we should regard them as yet another kind of small-world

NOMs, viz. as nominals that imply a set of alternatives.

Above I stressed the importance of the occasion of an utterance for the

determination of the use of a particular nominal. But certain syntactic characteris-

tics also have to be taken into account. Ordinals, superlatives, and other prenomi-

nal adjectives that single out a particular object from a set of possible alternatives

(like next, previous, or last) can be used to indicate that a definite description is

used specifically in our sense.

Page 49: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

49

(23) im ersten Moment, beim nächsten Mal27

[CONTR-in-the first moment, CONTR-at-the next time]

(in the first moment, next time)

(24) im letzten Sommer, am dritten Tag, zur nächsten Woche, beim letzten

Treffen, am höchsten Berg

[CONTR-in-the last summer, CONTR-on-the third day, CONTR-to-the

next week, CONTR-at-the last meeting, CONTR-at-the highest mountain]

(last summer, on the third day, until next week, at the last meeting, at the

highest mountain)

(25) Im letzten Monat hat Paula eine Telefonrechnung von 500 Euro gehabt.

(CONTR-in-the previous month, Paula's phone bill was 500 Euros)

I would consider the nominals in (23) and (24) as belonging to the small-world

category because they refer to objects that have a unique function in the situations

at hand in the sense that there can always be only one first moment or one last

meeting. In sentences like (25) the definite description is obviously used specifi-

cally and I want to claim that the object referred to also has a unique function in

the context of the utterance.

Furthermore, the nominal seems to refer to a particular object in a set of

possible alternatives. It was not this month or two months ago that Paula's phone

bill was so high, but it was last month. The same observations can be made in the

following sentences.

(27) Anna asks Fritz whether he enjoyed Felix' wedding. Fritz replies:

Am Abend war mir langweilig.

(I was bored CONTR-in-the evening.)

(28) Intrusion Detection am Beispiel von Snort.28

[Intrusion Detection CONTR-at-the example of Snort.]

(Intrusion Detection exemplified by Snort.)

27 It appears to be the case that the nouns in (23) can only occur with adjectives of the kind men-tioned. An apparent exception can be found in the following sentence. (26) Ich weiß im Moment auch nicht weiter. [I know CONTR-in-the moment not further.] (I am at a loss right now.) I suggest that im Moment is an idiom, since the phrase can be used interchangeably with jetzt gerade (right now). 28 from http://www.pro-linux.de/work/snort/print/index.html

Page 50: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

50

(29) Am Kopf des Toten haben wir eine Schädelfraktur festgestellt.

(We found a skull fracture CONTR-on-the head of the body.)

Fritz' answer in (27) seems to imply that he was bored in the evening, but that he

enjoyed the rest of the wedding day. In (28) am Beispiel (roughly: exemplified by)

indicates that intrusion detection could just as well have been explained with the

help of Network Flight Recorder, but that Snort was chosen instead. The person

who utters (29) implies that the rest of the body was also examined, but that he is

focusing on the head at the moment. To be honest, I have no idea why these im-

plications can arise if a small-world definite description is used, but I think it is an

interesting observation nonetheless.

The small-world use of a definite description requires the contracted forms. In this

use the definite descriptions function referentially, in the sense that a particular

object is referred to. We can distinguish between different kinds of small-world

nominals: Local names and bridging anaphors. The third class consists of nomi-

nals that imply that the referent of the NOM is a particular object in a set of possi-

ble alternatives.

4.2.2.2 The Contextual Use

If a nominal is used contextually, it cannot occur with contractions. Endophoric,

anaphoric and deictic uses of definite descriptions belong to the contextual use.

The identification of the right referent of these nominals is successful if the audi-

ence is able to pick out the right referent of the respective NOMs. The description

of the NP used does not have to fit the referent, neither does it indicate a certain

unique function or role of the referent (as in the small-world use of definite de-

scriptions). Information additional to the purely descriptive content of a nominal

sometimes have to be taken into consideration in order to make the identification

possible. This has become obvious during the discussion of epithets above. Epi-

thets are clearly instances of the contextual use of definite descriptions, they refer

to a specific object and they are used anaphorically.

Occasionally, nominalised verbs can apparently be preceded by un-contracted

forms.

Page 51: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

51

(30) Anna's neighbours are renovating.

Bei dem (*Beim) Geklopfe kann Anna nicht schlafen.

[At the (CONTR-at-the) rapping can Anna not sleep.]

(Anna cannot sleep with all the noise.)

Here, the phrase bei dem Geklopfe (roughly: with all the noise) refers to a particu-

lar object that is part of the utterance situation. In that sense we could regard (30)

as a deictic use in Löbner's sense, and we could claim that deictic uses of definite

descriptions require un-contracted forms, that is why the contracted form beim is

not permissible in (30). A different interpretation seems more adequate, though.

The word dem (the) in (30) is a demonstrative, not a definite determiner. The ap-

parently un-contracted form is in fact a preposition-demonstrative combination

and hence does not really belong to the subject matter of this paper. I gave this

example nonetheless, because it might help to clarify the theory I am proposing.

Some definite descriptions that are used attributively in Donnellan's sense seem to

evade a treatment in the account of contractions presented so far.

(31) In a news report about an unsolved murder.

Am Tatort wurden Fingerabdrücke vom / von dem Mörder gefunden.

(They found fingerprints CONTR-of-the / of the murderer at the crime

scene.)

(32) The host of a teetotalers' party is told that one of the guests is

drinking a martini.

Vom / Von dem Mann mit dem Martini werde ich eine öffentliche

Entschuldigung fordern.

(I will demand a public excuse CONTR-from-the / from the man with the

martini.)

Attributively used definite descriptions do not belong to the category of the spe-

cific use in our sense, they should be classified as generalising uses. This classifi-

cation explains why the contracted forms can be used in the above sentences.

With respect to the un-contracted form I want to suggest an analysis along the

lines of (30). If the sentences (31) and (32) are used anaphorically (i.e. if they re-

Page 52: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

52

fer to a discourse referent that has been introduced earlier via accommodation)29

they are used contextually and hence do not allow the contracted forms.

(33) Der Mörder war verschwunden, aber am Tatort wurden Fingerabdrücke von

dem (*vom) Mörder gefunden.

(The murderer had disappeared, but they found fingerprints of the

(*CONTR-of-the) murderer at the crime scene.)

So, in (31) and (32), the apparent indifference with respect to the contracted or the

un-contracted form can be regarded as an interference of the generalised and the

contextual use of the respective definite description. As soon as an expression is

used anaphorically, endophorically, or deictically, it requires the un-contracted

forms and belong to the category of the contextual use.

The un-contracted forms are obligatory if a definite description is used contextu-

ally, i.e. if it is used as an anaphoric, endophoric or deictic nominal. Even nomi-

nals that are used generalisingly require the un-contracted forms as soon as they

are used anaphorically.

A few open questions remain if we follow the theory that I am proposing: The use

of pronouns to refer to nominals that are used generalisingly (cf. Section 4.2.1),

the reason why nominalised verbs seem to never be used specifically in our sense

(cf. Section 4.2.1), and the mechanisms that underlie the implication of alterna-

tives when certain small-world nominals are used (cf. Section 4.2.2.1).

Nevertheless, the account presented in Section 4 seems to make correct

predictions about the vast majority of the examples that we considered so far, es-

pecially about those cases that could not be handled satisfactorily in Löbner's

framework.

29 The discourse referents can only be established via accommodation. In section 4.2.1 we saw that if a definite description is used generalisingly (as is the case with attributively used NPs), the re-spective phrase does not establish a discourse referent. We can use, e.g., pronouns to refer to in-stances of the kind indicated by the descriptive content, which can then be regarded as discourse referents. So, the discourse referents are introduced via accommodation.

Page 53: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

53

5. Conclusion

In this paper we have been concerned with preposition-article contractions in

German. We saw that Lyon's (1999), Heim's (1991) and Löbner' (1985) accounts

of contractions do not make the correct predictions. We discussed Löbner's pro-

posal in detail and found out that his notion of semantic definites is not suitable

for an adequate analysis of contractions. It is supposed to subsume too many dif-

ferent phenomena to be coherent. That is why I have been proposing a new ac-

count of contractions. Table 2 and 3 summarise the most important aspects of

Löbner's and of my proposal, respectively.

Type of Definite Description Characteristics

Semantic Definites - refer unambiguously independent of the

utterance situation

- proper names, FC1s, FC2s (also with

implicit arguments), configurations

- contracted forms are possible

Pragmatic Definites - depend on the utterance situation for

unambiguous reference

- includes anaphoric, endophoric and the

"visible situation use" of deictic definites

- require un-contracted forms

Table 2: Characteristics of semantic and pragmatic definites in Löbner's framework

Page 54: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

54

Type of Use of

Nominal

Characteristics

Generalised Use - does not refer to a particular object

- the identity of the referent is irrelevant, but the descriptive content

of the nominal has to fit the referent

- used in generic sentences or as generic nominals

- requires contracted forms

Specific Use - refers to a particular object

Small-world Use - used as local names, in bridging anaphors, and sometimes implies

a set of alternatives

- can only be used in a locally restricted domain or in a particular

community

- requires the contracted forms

Contextual Use - includes anaphoric, endophoric, and deictic nominals

- can also include generalising nominals if they are used anaphori-

cally

- requires the un-contracted forms

Table 3: Different types of uses of nominals in the proposal presented in Section 4.

In contrast to Löbner, the distinction between the two main categories, i.e., the

generalised and the specific use of nominals, is based on the kind of reference that

is expressed by the nominals, and not on the (in-) dependence on the context of an

utterance for the unambiguous reference of a definite description. NOMs that are

used specifically refer to a particular object, those that are used generalisingly do

not. Such a distinction seems to be suited much better for an analysis of contrac-

tions than Löbner's distinction between semantic and pragmatic definites.

The subdivision of the specific use into the small-world use and the con-

textual use of a nominal is useful for making the correct predictions. With the help

of these two kinds of specifically used nominals and the notion of the generalised

use we are able to give an adequate account of contractions, which is not possible

in Löbner's framework.

It still remains unclear why nominalised verbs can only be used generalisingly,

why reference to a generalising nominal with the help of pronouns is not always

Page 55: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

55

possible, and why certain nominals that belong to the small-world category seem

to imply a set of alternatives.

Nonetheless, the proposal presented in Section 4 of this paper seems to

make the correct predictions for the use of contracted and un-contracted forms in

the vast majority of examples.

Page 56: Constraints on the Contraction of Preposition and Definite ...CL/download/BSc_thesis_Cieschinger.pdf · With respect to contractions, Löbner claims that the occurrence of con- tracted

56

6. References

Bosch, Peter, 1995: Definiteness & Dynamic Knowledge Representation. Lecture

slides from: Workshop Anaphora and Reference, Nancy.

Carlson, Gregory N. & Pelletier, Francis J. (eds.), 1995: The Generic Book. Uni-

versity of Chicago Press, Chicago.

Donnellan, Keith, 1966: Reference and Definite Descriptions. Reprinted in: Mar-

tinich, Aloysius P. (ed.), 2001: The Philosophy of Language. Oxford

University Press, New York, 2001, pp. 247-259.

Haberland, Hartmut, 1985: Zum Problem der Verschmelzung von Präposition und

bestimmtem Artikel im Deutschen. In: Osnabrücker Beiträge zur Sprach-

theorie 30: 82-106.

Hartmann, Dietrich, 1980: Über Verschmelzungen von Präposition und bes-

timmtem Artikel. In: Zeitschrift für Dialektologie und Linguistik 47: 160-

183.

Heim, Irene, 1991: Artikel und Definitheit (Articles and Definiteness). In: A. v.

Stechow, 1991, pp. 487-535.

Heim, Irene & Kratzer, Angelika, 1997: Semantics in Generative Grammar. An

Introduction. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford.

Krifka, Manfred, F.J. Pelletier, G.N. Carlson, A. ter Meulen, G. Chierchia, & G.

Link, 1995: Genericity: An Introduction. In: Gregory N. Carlson, 1995,

pp. 1-124.

Löbner, Sebastian, 1985: Definites. Journal of Semantics 4: 279-326.

Lyons, Christopher, 1999: Definiteness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,

pp. 326-330.

Stechow, Arnim von & Wunderlich, Dieter (eds.), 1991: Semantik/Semantics. Ein

internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung. An interna-

tional Handbook of Contemporary Research. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin,

New York.