Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    1/10

    The Psychologies ofStructure,

    Function,and Development

    A . CHARLES CATANIA New York University

    1

    The nineteenth century closed with the promise of

    an

    integrated science

    of

    psychology

    (Titchener,

    1898).

    In the twentieth century,

    that

    promise has

    yet to be

    fulfilled. Students

    of

    psychology still

    are

    asked to choose theoretical sides.

    They

    see

    functional

    accounts of operant behavior pitted

    against

    ethological accounts

    of

    behavioral struc-

    ture,

    analyses

    of

    reinforcem ent contingencies p itted

    against theories

    of cognitive

    processing,

    and de-

    scriptions

    of

    language

    as

    verbal behavior pitted

    against psycholinguistic formulations of language

    competence. Behaviorism continu es to clash with

    phenomenology,

    and empiricism with nativism.

    Psychologists are not yet even agreed on whether

    theirs is a science of behavior or a science of

    menta l life.

    The

    development

    o f

    these controversies

    ha s

    been

    described in terms of paradigm clash (e.g., Katahn

    & Koplin, 1968; N eisser, 19 72 ; Segal &Lachman,

    1972) ,

    as if

    psychology were

    in the

    midst

    of the

    kind of scientific revolution described by Kuhn

    ( 1 9 6 2 ) .

    The

    student, whether

    hi s

    mentor

    be

    cog-

    nitive

    psychologist or behaviorist, is led to believe

    that

    one or the

    other paradigm

    will

    emerge victori-

    ous from th e

    confrontat ion

    of incompatible intel-

    lectual positions. But this characterization may be

    misleading, because it is not clear that the contro-

    versies have grown

    out of

    incompatible treatments

    of comm on problems. The present account argues

    that

    th e

    important d imensions

    of

    psychology

    are

    different from those ordina rily consideredwhen

    th e

    history

    of

    psychology

    is

    interpreted

    in

    terms

    of

    para digm clashes, and that these dim ensions have

    Prepara t ion

    o f

    this article

    w as

    s u p p o r t ed

    in

    p a r t

    b y

    Nat ional Institutes of Heal th Grant MH-18506 to New

    York Univers i ty .

    Reques t s

    fo r

    repr in t s should

    be

    sent

    to A .

    Char les

    Catania , who i s now at D epar tment of Psychology, Uni -

    vers ity of Ma ryland Bal t imore C oun ty , 5401 Wi lkens

    Av en u e , Baltimore, Maryland 21228.

    been emerging through evolution over

    the

    past cen-

    tury rather than through revolution in the past

    decade.

    Titchener s

    Psychologies

    Let us

    re tu rn

    to

    Titchener's position

    at the

    tu rn

    of

    th e

    century (Titchener, 1898, 1899a, 1899b):

    Psychology was a single science that, like biology,

    contained

    lines

    of

    division. Biology included

    a

    science of structure called morphologyor anatomy,

    a science of

    function

    called physiology, and a sci-

    ence of

    growth

    or

    development called embryology

    or morphogenesis. By analogy, Titchener saw psy-

    chology divided into structural,

    functional ,

    and de-

    velopmental components. (He also noted a similar

    division at the

    level

    of the

    analysis

    of

    species, wh ich

    included the

    sciences

    of

    taxonomy, bionomics

    or

    ecology, and paleontology or evolutionism, and

    even

    suggested the possibility

    that this type

    of

    classification could

    be

    extended

    to the

    study

    of

    cultures.) Titchener

    (1899a)

    described

    the

    divi-

    sions

    of

    psychology

    in the following w a y :

    we see at once t h a t th e psychology of our defini t ion is

    (1 ) a structural psychology, an a n a t o m y or morphology

    of mi n d . Mind is a mass of tangled processes. Our prob-

    le m

    is to

    dissect this complex,

    and to

    discover,

    if we

    can ,

    it s

    plan

    of

    a r r an g emen t .

    But we may

    also regard mind

    . . .

    as a

    system

    of func t ions . The

    mi n d

    does

    things

    for us,

    or

    enables us to do things. W e shal l then have

    ( 2 )

    a

    functional psychology. And we

    may, fur ther , discuss

    th e

    m a k e u p

    and working of the chi ld 's mind, and the way in

    which

    it

    passes over into

    th e

    adul t mind .

    W e

    shall then

    have a menta l emb ryology . Our psychology has become

    (3 )

    th e

    s tudy

    of

    psychogenesis [pp.

    21- 22] .

    The present arg um ent , simply, is that Titchener's

    classification

    of

    psychological problems,

    appropriate

    in

    his time, remains appropriate today . The criti-

    cal

    point

    is that

    Titchener recognized

    the

    three

    psychologies

    as

    complementary,

    not

    incompatible.

    Titchener (1899a) went

    on to

    say:

    No one of

    434 MAY 1973 A M E R I C A N P S Y C H O L O G I S T

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    2/10

    these three psychologies is

    'better' psychology

    psychology in a more real sense of the wordthan

    any

    other

    [p . 22]. Psychologists,

    however, per-

    haps including Titchener, seem not to have

    taken

    sufficient note

    of the

    statement.

    The

    present

    ac-

    count

    will

    take it as a point of depa rture. In

    elaborating on it, we will first concentrate on the

    distinction

    between structural and functional psy-

    chologies, because this distinction seems to lie at

    the root of the conflict

    between

    cognitive and be-

    havioral psychologies. W e will later have occasion

    to consider the place of psychogenesis.

    Structure and

    Function

    In biology, th e distinction between structure and

    function

    was so

    well

    established

    that

    it supported a

    division of the field into such separate departments

    as anatomy and physiology. The line between

    anatomical research

    and

    physiological research

    was

    sometimes difficult to draw, and it remains so to-

    day. But it is at least clearly recognized

    that

    studies

    of biological structure and studies of bio-

    logical

    function

    are concerned with different em -

    pirical questions. To say what an organ

    does,

    it

    m ay

    help

    to

    know

    how it is

    constructed;

    yet its

    function

    is not studied in the same way as its

    structure.

    While the analogous distinction is made in psy-

    chology, it is sometimes

    difficult,

    as in biology, to

    draw

    the line. Neve rtheless, there exist some

    bodies of research predominantly concerned with

    analyzing stimulus structure

    or

    response structure,

    an d other bodies of

    research predominantly con-

    cerned with analyzing behavioral

    function.

    A n

    analysis

    of the

    distinctive

    features of a

    stimulus,

    for example, is concerned with a different problem

    than

    the analysis of the

    conditions

    that

    motivate

    the organism's continu ed attention

    to

    those distinc-

    tive features.

    The

    relation between these

    different

    kinds

    of

    psychological

    problems has

    typically been obscured

    by

    different

    languages

    of

    psychology.

    These

    d i f -

    ferences have developed as consequences of histori-

    ca l

    accident,

    the

    influence

    of

    everyday discourse

    on

    technical

    vocabulary,

    and the various research

    strategies that

    are

    appropriate

    to

    specific experi-

    me ntal issues. Str uct ura l research tends

    to be de-

    scribed

    in the

    cognitive

    or

    mentalist vocabulary,

    and functional research in the behaviorist vocabu-

    lary.

    But the

    correlation between these research

    concerns

    and

    these vocabularies

    is not a

    necessary

    one. A cognitive psychologist can be concerned

    with

    functional problems (e.g.,

    in

    distinguishing

    betweenparallel an dserialprocesses, cf . Sternberg,

    1 9 7 0 ) jus t as a behav ioral psychologist can be

    concerned with structural ones (e.g.,

    in

    analyzing

    the stimulus dimensions to which an organism re -

    spondsin a

    color-matching task,

    cf .

    Wright

    &

    Gum-

    ming, 1971) . In fact, a major argument of the

    present account is that psychological controversy

    ha s often originated because the dichotomy between

    structure and function ha s been confused with

    that

    between mentalism and behaviorism. (An instruc-

    tive comparison is with the history of anatomy and

    physiology in

    biology,

    in

    which

    the

    respective con-

    cerns with structure and with function were not

    so

    highly correlated withvitalistic and mechanistic

    positions.)

    The point demands a concrete example, and one

    ha s

    been chosen

    that

    may at f irst

    seem frivolous:

    consider what a psychologist might do if he were

    interested

    in

    ana lyzing baseball pitching.

    He

    might

    begin

    by concerning himself with the coordination

    of the pitch. Throu gh slow-motion photography

    or electromyographic recording, he could examine

    the sequential pa tterning of muscle movem ents, and

    he

    could analyze

    th e

    relation between

    the

    early

    and

    the late parts of the

    performance.

    He might

    be

    able to

    specify

    the interaction

    between

    the

    ball's

    speed and trajectory as it leaves the pitcher's hand

    and the

    magnitude

    and

    form

    of the

    pitcher's fol-

    low-through. He might even ven ture a mathe-

    matical formulation in which fast

    balls

    and curves

    were distinguished

    by parameters of his equations,

    and his analysis could conceivably provide clues

    about what to emphasize in

    giving

    instruction to

    a novice pitcher. If he were reasonably successful,

    to the

    point,

    fo r

    example,

    that he

    could

    predict the

    properties of a given pitch

    from

    the early com-

    ponents of muscle activity, he might be tempted to

    claimthat

    an

    exhaustive account

    of the

    critical fea-

    tures

    of

    pitching

    was

    realizable

    at

    least

    in principle

    i f

    not

    attainable

    in

    practice.

    Yet no

    matter

    ho w

    exhaustive

    hi s analysis of the s truc tureof the pitch,

    this psychologist would not be in a position to

    deal with the circumstances

    that

    determine when

    and at what the pitcher throws the

    ball.

    Such an

    account wou ld requ ire, instead,

    an

    analysis

    of the

    functional properties of the pitch: its relation to

    antecedent stimulus conditions and subsequent

    stimulus

    consequences.

    A M E R I C A N P S Y C H O L O G I S T MAY 1973

    43 S

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    3/10

    The

    example

    m ay

    seem tr ivial .

    Yet it is

    precisely

    paralleled

    by

    contemporary developments

    in the

    psychology

    of

    language

    and

    il lustrates

    the different

    strategies tha t have

    led to

    conflict

    between cogni-

    tive and

    behavioral form ulation s. Studies

    of

    both

    gramm ar and phonology (e.g. , Chom sky & M iller ,

    1 9 6 3 ; Liberman, 1970)have dealt specifically with

    the stru ctu re of language and speech. Tran sfor-

    mational analyses have been concerned with the

    complex coordinations necessary

    to

    generate gram-

    matical sentences orcomprehensible phonetic utter-

    ances. Recognizing

    that the way a

    sentence

    or

    utterance

    ends

    interacts

    with

    characteristics of the

    earl ier

    parts of the

    sentence

    or

    ut terance

    is not so

    very different from recognizing that

    the

    follow-

    through interacts with

    th e

    w i n d u p

    and the

    delivery

    even though it occurs after th e ball has left th e

    pitcher's han d. Such analyses can beelaborated at

    various levels of complexity; fo r example, the hier-

    archical organization of units such as phonemes,

    words,

    and

    grammatical

    forms is

    explicit ly fea-

    tured in accounts of grammat ical s t ructure .

    Structural analyses of grammar and speech, how-

    ever, cannot tell

    us

    when

    a

    person will decide

    to

    speak, or what he

    will

    talk about. It is precisely

    these latter questions that are the concern of a

    functional

    analysis

    of

    langua ge. This

    is

    i l lust ra ted

    even by some of those materialsthat are taken as

    critical examples of the primacy of a structural ac-

    count. The written sentence

    Dropping

    bombs can

    be dangerous has one of two structures, depending

    on

    whether

    th e

    speaker

    is

    concerned with

    th e

    people in the air or those on the ground . There is

    no debate about whether these five words in this

    particular order can consti tute two

    different

    sen-

    tences.

    But the

    structural account cannot help

    us

    to choose between

    the two

    structures.

    The

    choice

    must be based on

    functional

    considerations: the

    conditions under which

    th e

    sentence

    is

    generated.

    But sa y

    instead that

    th e

    words

    are

    spoken.

    N ow

    the twosentences can be distinguished by different

    pat terns of stress. Once both phonological and

    grammatical

    analyses

    are available, an account can

    be given of the relation between the two types of

    structure. The problem is not surmou nted, how-

    ever

    ;

    even

    at

    this point,

    th e

    structural account can-

    not

    tell

    us

    about

    th e

    circumstances under which

    a

    sentence with one or the other structure will be

    ut tered .

    T h a t issue

    is

    again

    functional .

    It is surprising that such relations are so often

    overlooked.

    Y et

    failures

    to

    note them

    ca n

    easily

    be

    documented.

    The

    controversy over

    th e

    psycho-

    linguistic account

    of

    gramm atical struc ture versus

    the

    functional

    analysis of verbal behavior has been

    both persistent and prominent in psychology. The

    chronology includes, among others, Skinner

    ( 1 9 5 7 ) ,

    Chomsky ( 1 9 5 9 ) , Lenneberg

    ( 1 9 6 7 ) ,

    Dixon and

    Hor ton (1968 ) ,

    MacCorquodale

    ( 1 9 7 0 ) , a n d

    Premack ( 1 9 7 0 ) . The two sides of the controversy

    were at most t imes simply co ncerned with two di f-

    ferent

    k i nds

    of

    problems: problems

    of

    st ructure

    and

    problems

    of

    function (or , equivalently, problems

    of

    competence and problems of performance, cf . Mc-

    Neill,

    1970,

    p.

    146) .

    But the

    accounts were

    couched

    in

    languages

    and

    contexts that were suffi-

    ciently

    different

    that th e different problems

    each

    was addressing typically went unrecognized (c f.

    Catania , 1972) .

    A

    Behavior

    Paradigm

    Although

    we are

    arguing that

    th e

    development

    of

    contemporary psychology

    is not

    properly inter-

    preted

    in

    terms

    of

    paradigm clashes, paradigms

    can

    be

    useful.

    We may

    recall

    that a

    paradigm

    is a

    model that exhibits essential relations among th e

    phenomena that it

    represents.

    W e should not be

    surprised if neither a cognitive nor a behavioral

    psychologist could come

    up

    with

    a

    paradigm

    on

    which

    his respective colleagues could universally

    agree. Nevertheless,w e

    shall introduce

    a

    paradigm

    here to il lustrate some of the properties of struc-

    tural

    and

    functional accounts.

    T he paradigm takes th e form S ' ^ R i S

    0

    ) , where

    S represents a s t imulus and R represents a re-

    sponse.

    The

    superscripts,

    in

    S

    D

    and

    S,distinguish

    between two kinds of st imuli: a disc riminative st im-

    ulus, S

    D

    , which is a st imulus denned in terms of

    th e

    events

    that

    ca n occur in its presence, and a

    contingent st imulus,S

    r

    ,which is a stimulus

    defined

    in

    terms

    of its

    consequential relation

    to

    responses.

    The expression

    ( R : S )

    represents th e relation of

    responses to consequences. This relation is called

    a

    contingency

    and can be translated,

    the

    effect

    of

    response R on the probabi l i ty of st imulus S

    c

    .

    Thus, the paradigm as a whole represents a con-

    tingency that operates

    in the

    presence

    of a

    dis-

    criminative st imulus.

    The

    paradigm

    is not

    exhaus-

    t ive ;

    it does not inc lud e, for example, responses

    that may be

    elicited

    by the

    contingent st imulus.

    A

    more detailed account of the paradigm has been

    presented elsewhere (Catania,

    1 9 7 1 ) ;

    the point of

    436 MAY

    1973

    A M E R I C A N P S Y C H O L O G I S T

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    4/10

    using it here is not to argue the precedence of a

    behavioral terminology, b ut rather to illustrate

    some

    structural

    and

    funct ional dimensions

    of

    prob-

    lems

    in

    psychology.

    Let us consider the scope of the para digm . The

    contingency represents the way in which behavior

    can

    affect environmental events.

    If the

    contingent

    s t imulus is a food pellet delivered to a hungry rat,

    for

    example, the

    rat's

    various responses may make

    the

    delivery

    of a

    pellet more likely

    or

    less likely,

    or

    might have no effect on pellet delivery. Let us

    sa y tha t the lever press makes the pellet delivery

    more likely, or, in other words,

    that

    the lever press

    produces a pellet; we call this an instance of posi-

    tive reinforcement. But if the lever press makes

    the pellet delivery

    less

    likely, or, in other words,

    prevents

    thepellet

    delivery,

    wespeak of the

    proce-

    dure as omission trainin g. Finally, if the lever

    press

    has no

    effect

    on the

    likelihood

    of a

    pellet

    de-

    livery, we

    speak

    of

    pellet deliveries

    as

    response

    independent.

    But each of these contingencies might operate

    only in the presence of some discriminative stimu-

    l u s , such as a light. Such cases provide various

    examples

    of

    discrimination procedures.

    If, in the

    presence

    of a

    light, lever presses produce food pel-

    lets,

    we

    speak

    of an

    operant discrimination.

    If, in

    the presence of a light, lever presses prevent the

    delivery

    of food pellets, we speak of discriminated

    omission train ing. A nd if, in the presence of a

    l ight,

    food

    pellets

    are

    delivered independently

    of

    leverpresses, we speak of a respondent or Pa vlovian

    conditioning procedure: in the presence of a light,

    food

    pellets

    are

    delivered, just

    as food was

    delivered

    in

    th e

    presence

    of

    various stimuli

    to Pavlov's

    dogs.

    The

    contingent stimulus, however,

    can be

    aver-

    sive

    instead

    of

    appetitive.

    If the

    contingent stimu-

    lu s

    were electric shock,

    fo r

    example,

    th e

    three cases

    would include

    punishment,

    when lever

    presses

    pro-

    duce

    shock;

    avoidance

    or

    escape, when lever presses

    prevent

    or

    remove

    shock; and

    response-independent

    shock, when lever presses have

    no effect on the

    likelihood

    of

    shock

    delivery.

    These

    contingencies,

    too,

    ca n

    operate

    in the

    presence

    of a

    discriminative

    stimulus. In

    such cases,

    we

    classify

    the

    procedures

    as

    discriminated punishment, discriminated avoid-

    ance

    or

    escape,

    an d

    respondent defensiv e condition -

    i n g , respectively.

    Finally,

    th e

    contingent stimulus

    can be effec-

    tively neutral.

    If a rat's

    lever press produces

    or

    removes a

    stimulus such

    as a

    click

    or a

    light,

    we

    can ask about the extent to which the rat learned

    about the contingency relation between its lever

    press and this stimulus by later pairing the stimu lus

    with someappetitive

    or

    aversive event.

    W e

    speak

    of learning

    so

    demonstrated

    as

    latent learning.

    But

    relations between responses and such simple events

    typically occur in certain settings, and so it is

    appropriate to speak of discriminative stimuli fo r

    these con tingencies also.

    In the

    presence

    of

    certain

    visual,

    tactile, and other stimuli, the rat moves

    about and encounters various

    parts

    of its environ-

    men t: its mo vemen ts are responses

    that

    have cer-

    tain consequences, and these relations are also ex-

    amples

    of

    contingenc ies. Thus, procedures

    in

    sensorimotor

    learning can be encompassed by

    such a paradig m. There may be, in addition, some

    neutral events that

    reliably

    occur independently

    o f

    th e

    rat's

    responses. Suppose, for example,

    that

    in

    the presence of a tone, a light consistently flashes;

    i f

    we find,

    through later procedures

    in

    which

    we

    pair th e tone or the light with other events,

    that

    the rat had learned something about the relation

    between these tw o stimuli, we refer to the initial

    procedure as an instanceof sensory preconditioning.

    Thus,

    all of the

    basic lea rning procedures

    ca n

    be

    incorporated into

    this

    paradigm.

    The

    essential

    fea ture

    of the

    analysis

    of

    contingencies

    is in

    fact

    th e

    description

    of the

    functional

    relations among

    stimuli an d

    responses. Some stim uli, which

    we

    call

    discriminative,

    are

    stimuli

    denned

    in terms of the

    events

    that ca n occur in their presence. Othe r

    stimuli ,

    which

    we

    call contingent,

    are

    stimuli

    de-

    fined in

    terms

    of

    their consequential relation

    to

    responses. Our intere st in behav ior encompasses

    both the circumstances under which responses can

    occur and the

    ways

    in

    which

    they ca n modify th e

    likelihood

    of

    environmental events.

    Structural

    and

    Functional

    Research Strategies

    Consider how we

    proceed

    if we are

    interested

    in

    funct ional questions.

    We can

    study various con-

    tingencies, ( R : S

    C

    ) , b y

    varying

    a

    response's

    effect

    on the

    probability

    of

    some contingent stimulus

    or

    by

    varying

    th e

    nature

    of the

    contingent stimulus.

    For

    example, when

    we

    study

    th e

    transition

    from

    reinforcement

    to extinction, we change

    from

    a con-

    t ingency

    in which a response produces a

    reinforcing

    s t imulus

    to one in which the response no longer

    produces

    that reinforcing

    stimulus; when we study

    A M E R I C A N P S Y C H O L O G I S T MAY 1973 437

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    5/10

    th e

    effects

    ofsatiation,we

    change

    from a

    procedure

    in

    which

    th e

    contingent stimulus

    is

    reinforcing

    to

    one in

    which

    th e

    contingent stimulus

    is no

    longer

    reinforcing. Or we can

    study

    th e

    stimulus control

    acquired by a

    discriminative

    stimulus, S

    D

    ,by

    vary-

    ing the

    contingencies

    on

    which

    th e

    st imulus

    is

    superimposed

    or by

    changing

    the

    relation

    of the

    s t imulus

    to a contingen cy. For examp le, when we

    compare the

    roles

    of

    stimuli

    in

    operant

    and re-

    spondent conditioning,

    we

    change

    th e

    contingency

    that

    operates in the presence of a discri min ative

    s t imulus from one in which a response produces a

    contingent stimulus

    to one in

    which

    a

    response

    ha s

    no

    e f f e c t

    on presentations of a contingent stimulus;

    when

    weexamine stimulus control in complex rein-

    forcement

    schedules

    or in

    types

    of

    delay condition-

    ing, we vary the temporal separation between the

    discriminative stimulus and the operation of a con-

    tingency.

    (W e

    could

    now

    transfer this account

    to

    th e baseball pitcher of our earlier example. W e

    could

    a rgue

    that a

    given batter

    at a

    particular point

    in a

    game represents

    a

    discriminative stimulus,

    S

    D

    ,

    in th e

    presence

    of

    which

    a

    particular pitch,

    R , will

    be

    likely

    to

    have

    a

    particular consequence,

    S. The

    tran slatio n is simple enough. To illustrate how

    th e

    paradigm

    bears on

    structural

    and

    functional

    questions,

    however, we might better

    apply

    it to

    more

    traditional psychological materials.)

    Each of the functional questions in the preceding

    examples concerns relations among various terms

    in th e

    paradigm.

    Let us now

    consider structural

    analyses, which deal with

    th e

    distinguishing proper-

    ties

    of

    individual terms when

    th e

    relation among

    terms is held constant. For example, if a particula r

    contingency operates in the presence of a particular

    discriminative stimulus, we can vary the stimulus

    an d

    ask

    questions about

    it s

    critical features.

    This

    is our strategy in psychophysical experim ents with

    both

    human

    and

    animal

    subjects, but it is also

    applied when the stimulus features are more com-

    plex. Thus, in a study of how children learn to

    read,

    we can try to identify

    properties

    of the

    letters

    o f

    th e

    alphabet

    that are critical to learning, and

    we

    might

    find,

    among

    th e

    features

    tha t w e

    examine,

    that the child can be taugh t to disting uish between

    up-down reversals of letters more easily than be-

    tween

    left-right reversals (c f. Gibson,

    1965) .

    The

    questions

    are

    about stimulus structure,

    or, as

    Pylyshyn ( 1 9 7 2 )

    put it, about the struc ture of

    th e percept :

    The quest ion of the n a t u r e of a

    menta l

    representat ion

    is real ly a quest ion about which aspects of the

    pa t t e rn

    of

    incoming data

    a re

    perceived, learned,

    and

    retained

    fo r

    potent i a l

    fu t u r e

    use. How ever, . . . these aspects that

    are

    dist inguished an d retained and that

    play

    a f u n c t i o n a l

    role

    in

    cognit ion need

    not be

    simple classes

    of

    physical

    propert ies of the st imulus pat tern. They of ten a re ra ther

    abst rac t propert ies

    whose relat ion to the physical features

    of

    th e

    s t imulus

    may b e qu i t e

    obscure . . .

    [p .

    548].

    The account is reminiscent of the distinction be-

    tween sensation and perception, and we may recall

    the extent to which the field of perception has in-

    volved

    structural concerns.

    On the other hand, we might be interested in

    studying differences among

    the classes of responses

    that can be

    learned. Again,

    th e

    relations among

    terms

    of the paradigm are held constant, but

    this

    t ime we vary the response rather than the discrimi-

    native stimulus. W ecould examine simple response

    properties, such as the force or topography of a

    rat 's

    lever

    press, or we could study the

    differenti-

    ation of

    motor skills

    in

    hum an subjects. Similar

    questions, however, can be addressed to more com-

    plex modeso f responding. In the four decades be-

    tween

    Guilford's

    ( 1 9 2 7 ) The Role of Form in

    Learning and Johnson's (196 8) The

    Influence

    of

    Grammatica l

    Uni ts

    on

    Learning,

    our

    experimental

    sophistication has changed, but the basic

    problem

    has rema ined the same : at issue is the stru ctur e of

    complex responses. A n u m be r of

    areas

    in the con-

    temporary

    psychology

    of

    human verbal learning

    (e.g.,

    sub jective organization

    in

    free recall; Tulving,

    1 9 6 2 )

    can be regarded as concerned with the stru c-

    tur al properties of complex responses. (To extend

    the account to contingent stimuli, we might even

    argue

    that

    concern

    in

    motivat ion with

    th e

    factors

    that influence th e effectiveness of

    contingent stim-

    u l i ,

    as in the analysis of incentives, is a structural

    problem in the present sense.)

    Hierarchical

    Organization of

    Stimuli

    and Responses

    Some

    might argue

    tha t

    this kind

    of an

    account

    misses the point, because an

    analysis

    of stimulus

    s t ruc ture

    alone or of response structure alone will

    necessarily omit the complex interaction between

    organism and environment tha t must take place

    dur ing

    cognitive processing (c f. Neisser, 196 7) .

    But

    each

    stage of

    such

    an

    interaction must involve

    th e organism's responses to particular features of

    the environm ent. The resolution, therefore, ma y

    438 MAY

    1973

    A M E K I C A N

    P S Y C H O L O G I S T

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    6/10

    lie

    with

    an

    account

    of the

    hierarchical organization

    of

    stimuli and responses.

    Estes ( 1 9 7 1 )

    stated the

    issue

    as follows:

    If

    one who is

    a t tempt ing

    to describe and

    predict

    the

    behavior of an adult human learner fails to take account

    o f these behavioral organizations, and a t tempts to con-

    struct an account in

    terms

    only of

    individual stimulus-

    response units,

    the

    principles

    of

    operation

    of

    rewards

    an d

    punishments may appear to be

    qui te

    different from

    those

    revealed

    in

    simpler

    experiments with animals or immature

    hum an learners. Actually, it may be that the principles

    of

    operation of these factors are the same in all cases an d

    tha t th e difference lies in the

    na tur e

    of the behavioral

    units whose probabilitiesare being modified as a result of

    the experiments with various types of

    outcomes

    [p .

    23].

    The tendency to select on e response

    strategy rather

    than

    another

    in a given

    situation

    must itself be modified by

    past experience with rewarding or punishing outcomes. A

    strategic question

    which must

    be

    fundamenta l

    to the

    f u r -

    ther development

    of theory in this

    area

    is tha t of

    whether

    the laws and mechanisms of reinforcement are the same

    for these higher-order

    behavioral

    units as for the more

    elementary

    responses

    studied in most laboratory experi-

    ments

    [p .31].

    We

    may too

    often

    think of responses as single

    and discrete events,

    fail ing

    to regard their struc-

    tural properties as also included among their de-

    fining features . (W e

    have similar problems when

    we

    talk about

    stimuli

    when we mean to ta lk about

    stimulus properties.) Not simply the closure of a

    switch

    by a lever press, but perhaps also the gram-

    maticality

    of a

    sentence that

    is

    uttered

    or the ap-

    propriateness

    of a

    strategy

    that

    is

    applied

    can be

    regarded as

    denn ing

    properties of those response

    classes that

    ca n

    enter into

    funct ional

    relations.

    Take Harlow's (1949) learning

    set

    exper iment

    as an exam ple. A t one level of analysis, the choice

    of

    one or another s t imulus is the response of

    interest .

    But at a

    hierarchically more complex

    level,

    the acquisit ion of learning set is denned in

    terms

    of the

    subst i tu t ion,

    fo r

    many separate choices

    in different problems, of a single, more general re -

    sponse

    class that can be

    described

    in the

    following

    te rms: if the stimulus choice produced

    food this

    t ime,

    contin ue to choose it; if it did n ot, choose

    the other s t im ulu s; more economical ly , we m ay

    speak

    of

    win-stay,

    lose-shift. It is fruitless to

    debate w hether this perform anc e should be spoken

    of

    in

    terms

    of a

    complex response class

    or in

    t e rms

    of

    a

    strategy;

    in

    either case,

    the

    point

    is that the

    analysis concerns behavioral struc ture. Questions

    about the nature of this structure are orthogonal to

    funct ional questions, such

    as

    that

    of

    whether rein-

    forcementwas a

    learning

    or a

    performance var iab le

    in

    these procedures. (This does

    not

    imply

    that an

    analysis

    of

    s t ruc tu re

    will

    necessarily

    be

    irrelevant

    to an

    analysis

    of funct ion, or vice versa; if st ruc-

    ture

    and

    function

    interact in learning, fo r example,

    it

    is all the more impor t an t to be clear about the

    difference between st ructural

    and

    funct ional

    quest ions. )

    The fol lowing accoun t (F i sche r , 1972 ) of m a z e

    l e a rn ing

    p rov ides ano the r i l l u s t r a t ion :

    After . . .

    familiarizing

    yourself with one of the more

    complete structural

    systemsperhaps Chomsky's g ra m m a r

    you might even be able to begin to write tha t structural

    analysis of

    children's

    maze performance. While other psy-

    chologists were

    explaining th e

    performance

    by

    reducing

    it

    to some lowest common factor like reinforcement or a t ten-

    t ion,

    you

    would

    be searching for key pat terns and for

    rules tha t

    would relate those

    pat terns to

    each other.

    In

    a w a y ,it w ould be like

    writing

    a grammar fo r maze per-

    formance .

    You w ould need a set of

    grammatical

    categories

    to

    describe

    th e phrasest ructure of the children'sbehavior

    in the maze and a set of transformation rules for relating

    different

    types

    of phrase

    structures.

    With

    this

    kind of

    structural description, yo u could account for the particu-

    lars

    of maze performance to an extent

    t ha t

    is

    probably

    impossible

    fo r

    explanations t h a t

    merely reduce

    behavior

    to

    fac tors

    like reinforcement and a t tent ion [pp. 330-3311.

    According

    to this account,

    Krechevsky

    ( 1 9 3 2 )

    w as

    wr i t ing a pre l imin ary gramm ar of maze learn-

    in g

    when

    h e

    carried

    out his

    experiments

    on

    hypoth-

    eses in rats. A nd this form ula tion is reasona ble,

    because Krechevsky's concern, l ike Fischer's, was

    with

    th e s t ruc tu re of the maze pe r fo rmance . Y et

    neither

    th e

    child

    nor the rat will

    necessarily move

    through

    the

    maze, even

    if the

    maze

    has

    been

    thoroughly mastered, on the basis of a maze gram-

    mar alone.

    W e ma y

    recal l Tolman 's (1948 ) ra t ,

    said to be lost in thought at the choice point . The

    cognit ive map provided a way of describing the

    effective

    st imulus s t ructure

    of the rat's

    wor ld .

    B ut

    a rat with a cognitive map must have occasion to

    use it, and procedures that get the rat to perform

    and thereby demonst rateits map are funct ional . In

    psycholinguistics, we can simi lar ly imagine Chom-

    sky's speaker lost in thought, capable of grammati-

    cal

    speech

    but

    with noth ing

    to

    say:

    In the

    case

    of linguistic

    concepts, such

    as

    grammaticali ty,

    such

    procedures are called

    generative

    gramm ars. Such

    grammars do not describe how people go a bo u t

    under-

    standing or generating sentences, but they do describe the

    abstract relation tha t

    holds

    between strings of words and

    such concepts as

    grammatical

    sentence [Pylyshyn,1972,

    p.

    550].

    AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST MAY 1973 439

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    7/10

    If we wish to understand how the thinker comes to

    speak, we mus t be able to provide a

    functional

    as

    well as a structural account of language.

    Explanation and

    Description

    Let us

    suppose, however, tha t

    we had

    provided

    both

    a

    structural

    and a

    functional

    account

    of

    lan-

    guage

    or of

    maze learning.

    To

    what extent would

    we have explained th e per formance? In his quota-

    tion above, Fischer contrasted functional fac tors

    like

    reinforcement

    and

    attention with structural

    factors like transformation rules as waysof explain-

    ing or

    account ing

    for the

    maze performance.

    But

    we m ay question whether either a s truc tura l or a

    functional account, or even both in com bin ation ,

    can ever have the power of exp lana tion. The pres-

    ent

    view

    is that both s t ruc tura l and

    funct ional

    analyses

    a re

    descriptive rather than explanatory .

    Consider

    th e

    following commentary

    by

    Black

    (1970) on the

    psycholinguistic account

    of

    lan-

    guage in terms of deep s t ruc tures and generative

    grammars :

    Whatever their value, Kepler 's laws do not explain th e

    planetary motions, in any useful sense of expla in : they

    replace a crude and unsystema tic descript ion ( those orbi ts

    out there ,

    or

    the orb i t s confo rmin g

    to

    these readings )

    by

    another descript ion concisely present ing some m a t h e -

    matical propert ies of the orbi ts . The

    same

    applies,

    mutatis

    mutandis to the rules constituting a specific generative

    g r ammar . O ur ini t ial crude

    intuitions

    as to what should

    c o u n t as

    grammat ica l

    or the

    reverse

    ar e

    replaced

    by a set

    of precise

    an d

    explicit rules that (approximately

    and

    with

    ideal izat ion) generate a corresponding classificat ion. This

    provides valuable insight into structural connect ions: it

    ma y be

    said

    to

    provide intelligible reasons

    fo r w h a t w e

    previously seemed

    to be

    doing

    b y a

    kind

    of

    inst inct .

    B ut

    explanat ion hardly seems th e right ta g [pp.

    454455].

    Fu nctional terms like reinforcem ent, too, have

    typically been regarded

    as

    explanatory.

    Y et

    rein-

    forcement is simply a name for a certain set of

    functional relations.

    If a

    response

    in a

    given class

    produces a s t imulus ,a nd responses in that class are

    strengthened by virtue of its production of that

    stimulus,we say

    that

    we

    have observed

    an

    instance

    o f

    the

    process

    of

    reinforcement .

    We may

    wish

    to

    relate this process

    to

    other b ehavioral processes,

    or to

    characterize

    the

    properties

    of

    stimuli that

    ca n

    have this reinforcing effect, but tha t does not

    change

    th e

    na ture

    of the

    term.

    It

    rema ins

    a

    name,

    to

    be

    applied when

    it is

    appropriate like

    any

    other

    name (Catania , 1973) . Thus, we can talk about

    st imulus properties

    and

    about response properties

    at various hierarchical levels of complexity, and we

    can outline the kinds of functional relations that

    ca n

    exist

    among them. A t each level, our concern

    is descriptive, and the question of what kind s of

    functional relations

    different

    s t imuli or responses

    ca n

    enter into is an empirical one.

    Much emphasis ha s recently been given to the

    l imits

    of

    learning (e.g., Breland

    &

    Breland, 1961;

    Revusky

    &

    Garcia, 1970; Rozin

    &

    Kala t , 1 9 7 1 ;

    Sel igman, 1970) : limits

    on the

    kinds

    of

    responses

    that can be learned, on the kinds of stimuli that

    can act effectively on an organism, and on the kinds

    o f relations tha t can be established between par-

    t icular

    s t imuli

    and

    particular responses.

    But

    analyses

    of the

    s t ruc ture

    of

    effective s t imuli ,

    or of

    the differentstructures of

    those

    responses that can

    be

    more

    or

    less easily learned,

    are different from

    analyses of how s t imuli and responses function in

    behavior .

    And if

    some

    functional

    relations turn

    out to be less general than was once believed, it

    does

    not follow

    that their names should

    be

    changed

    or

    that they no longer have the status of functional

    relations.

    Distinguishing

    the Structure-Function

    Dimension from the Behavior-

    Cognition Dimension

    According to the present view, questions of stimu-

    lus

    s truc ture

    and

    response structure

    a re

    orthogon-

    ally related to questions of behavioral funct ion.

    This

    is not to say

    tha t information about s t ruc ture

    will never bear

    on the

    analysis

    of

    funct ion ,

    or

    vice

    versa. But to the extent that these relations can

    be clarified to

    show that various research

    areas in

    psychology comp lement rather than conflict with

    each other, controversy

    m ay

    give

    way to

    more pro-

    duct ive interac t ion.

    For

    example, applications

    of

    psychology to education are often divided between

    those concerned wi th the cognitive org aniza tion of

    th e subjec t mat ter and those concerned with be-

    havioral methodology in classroom management.

    Yet to

    teach

    effectively, it is

    essential

    to

    know

    bothhow a subjec t mat ter iss truc tured, as s t imulus

    in th e teacher 's presentation and as response in

    the student 's mastery,

    and how the

    teacher

    and

    th e

    s tudent

    ca n

    function

    in a

    classroom.

    W e

    mus t

    give a t tent ion

    to

    cognition

    in

    both s t ruc tura l

    and

    functional

    senses: structurally in the extent to

    which cognitive strategies can be regarded as ways

    440 MAY 1973 A M E R I C A N P S Y C H O L O G I S T

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    8/10

    of describing the structural properties of complex

    stimuli, and

    functionally

    in the analysis of both

    the

    circumstances under which strategies

    are ap-

    plied and the consequences of these strategies . A t

    issue is the question of whether cognitive and

    behavioral approaches

    are

    inappropriately inter-

    preted, respectively, as structural and

    functional

    psychologies.

    The evolution of psychology over the

    past

    cen-

    tury has included the successive elaboration of

    various structural

    and

    functional psychologies.

    Th e

    properties

    of

    these

    different

    psychologies have

    changed in detail over the years. Gestalt psychol-

    og y wasclearly structural, just as the analysisof

    contingencies in schedules of reinforcement was

    clearly

    functional . B ut

    structural

    and functional

    psychologies complement each

    other;

    they need

    not

    stand in opposition.

    Some

    of the

    differences

    have been differences in

    language. The clash between the vocab ulary of

    mentalism and the vocabulary of behaviorism is

    readily evident.

    It is not

    unfashionable these

    days to be a

    mental is t ;

    only dualism is reprehen-

    'sible.

    But the deba te between mentalism and be-

    haviorism has

    been along different dimensions than

    those of structure and function. The major be-

    haviorist argument has been against

    causal,

    not

    descriptive, mentalism , and to argue that mental

    events are not causes of behavior is not to argue

    that private events

    do not

    exist.

    In

    fact,

    th e

    pos-

    sibility

    of an

    internally consistent mentalism

    is

    implicit in the notionthat a behavioral translation

    of mental

    or

    cognitive vocabularies

    is

    feasible.

    The choice of vocabularies will rest with the

    effectiveness with which their proponents

    apply

    them. On the side of the men tal or cognitive

    vocabulary, it might be argued that it lies closer

    to everyday talk than some behaviorist languages,

    but on examination, th e language of

    information

    storage

    and

    retrieval,

    fo r

    example,

    is no

    less eso-

    teric than the language of reinforce men t contingen-

    cies.

    On the

    side

    of the

    behaviorist vocabulary,

    it mightbeargued thatitprovidesgreater precision

    and less risk of contamination by everyday pre-

    conceptions,

    but

    behaviorists have

    yet to

    discount

    the possibility of an internally consistent and ef-

    fective m entalist vocabulary (c f . Bolles, 19 67 ).

    A s the

    arguments

    are

    marshaled

    onboth sides, the

    tide shifts: epistemological difficulties in behavior-

    ism are balanced by accounts of its relevance to

    phenomenology (Day,

    1969),

    while

    the

    expanding

    front

    of

    cognitive research

    is

    tempered

    by its

    philosophical limitations (Malcolm, 1971) . These

    clashes,

    in any

    case,

    may be

    mere epiphenomena;

    the distinction between structure and function is

    critical to either v iewpo int, and progress will de-

    pend more

    on

    results than

    on

    discussion.

    The Place of

    Psychogenesis

    Let us now turn back to Titchener's

    formulation.

    W e

    have seen

    ho w

    various problems

    of

    psychology

    can be interpreted as problems of structure or of

    function.

    It rem ains to relate these two subdivi-

    sions

    to

    problems

    of

    development: what Titchener

    called psychogenesis. Superficially, it is tempting

    to

    equate this area with developmental

    psychology,

    and in one sense such an equation would be cor-

    rect. Yet to place the area in its proper perspec-

    tive, we must be clear about the kind of develop-

    ment

    that is to be studied. Certainly, we may be

    interested in the development, through maturation,

    of the capacity to

    respond

    to

    various complexes

    of

    stimuli

    or to

    engage

    in new

    responses

    an d

    apply

    different strategies.

    But

    whether

    we say we are

    concerned with

    the

    development

    of

    behavior

    or

    with that of the mind, our psychogenesis must in -

    clude

    the

    psychology

    of

    learning.

    If

    embryology

    deals with the development of the organism, and

    evolution with the development of a species, then

    psychogenesis must deal with the development of

    th e organism's behavioral or mental capacit ies; this

    is

    what

    the

    psychology

    of

    learning

    is

    supposed

    to

    be about .

    The

    view resolves some paradoxes.

    In the

    analy-

    sis of behavior, the functional analysis of con-

    tingencies,

    as in the

    study

    of

    reinforcement sched-

    ules

    (Ferster & Skinner,

    1957) ,

    created

    conflict.

    The operant analysis of steady-state performances

    was not

    seen

    as

    relevant

    to

    some problems

    in the

    psychology of learning. This was as it should have

    been: on the one hand, the analysis was more con-

    cerned

    with

    functional

    relations in the

    steady-state

    maintenance of behavior than with developmental

    relations in its acquisition; on the other, it might

    have been anticipated that the study of develop-

    ment, too, would divide into functional and struc-

    tura l

    components (e.g., respectively, Bijou &Baer ,

    1966;

    Piaget &Inhelder,

    1969).

    According to the present view, it was appropriate

    for these various

    parts

    of psychology to proceed

    in

    different

    ways.

    It is

    only unfortunate that they

    A M E R I C A N P S Y C H O L O G I S T

    MAY

    1973

    441

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    9/10

    have

    often

    been seen

    as

    incompatible.

    Progress in

    these areasstructure, function, and development

    h as

    constituted the evolution in psychology over

    th e

    past

    century.

    It has

    typically been uncoordi-

    nated, and there is much left to be settled. The

    detailed character

    of

    each area changes

    from

    time

    to time. The areas m ay variously merge and

    separate again,

    but

    they

    are at

    least

    as

    indepen-

    dently viable as are divisions of the biological

    sciences. Ho pefully , they

    will

    not become totally

    isolated

    from

    each other.

    Paradigms

    and

    Clashes

    We have argued here

    that

    psychology is not in the

    midst

    of a par adig m clash. Tru e parad igm clashes

    require points of conta ct. In the clash between

    the

    astronomies

    of

    Kepler

    and of

    Ptolemy,

    the

    sub-

    ject matter stayed

    th e

    same while

    the

    point

    of

    view

    changed;

    literally, as

    well

    as figuratively, the center

    did not

    hold.

    Different

    schools

    of

    psychology, how-

    ever, have been concerned with different problems.

    This is not to say

    that

    th e

    evolution

    of

    psychologi-

    cal concepts has never involved conflict. Rather ,

    it

    is to say

    that

    the

    clashes have

    not

    been along

    an y simple dimension of psychological problem s.

    The m ultip licity of issues m ay generally d istinguish

    clashes in the

    life

    sciences

    from

    those in the

    physi-

    cal sciences. A strong case for

    this

    view has been

    made

    in Mayr ' s ( 1 9 7 2 )

    analysis

    of the

    Darwinian

    revolution:

    It is now evident that the Darw inian revo lution does

    not conf o rm to the simple model of a scientific revolut ion

    a s described, fo r instance, b y T . S .

    K u h n .

    . . . It is actually

    a complex movement t h a t started nearly 25 0 years a g o ;

    i t s many major components were proposed a t different

    t imes, and became victorious independently of each other.

    E ve n t hough

    a

    revolut ionary c l imax occurred unquest ion-

    ably in 1859, the gradual acceptance of evolutionism, with

    all of its

    ramifications, covered

    a

    period

    of

    nearly

    250

    years . . . [p .

    988].

    Neither is the revolutionin psychology a revolution

    o f a decade.

    We have argued

    that

    Titchener's insight into

    th e

    organization of psychology is relevant today. Yet

    we

    m ay

    wonder

    why

    Titchener,

    in his structural

    account, contributedto an opposition between struc-

    turalism and functio nalis m that has persisted for

    most

    of

    this century. Part

    of the

    answer probably

    lies in what it was possible to do in each of these

    separate areas

    in Titchener 's

    time.

    A s

    Titchener

    (1899a, p. 22) noted, structural psychology had

    made more progress in his day than either of the

    other two psychologies, But it is the progress in

    structural , functional,

    and

    developmental accounts

    that constitutes psychology's evolution and revolu-

    tion.

    It is

    reassuring

    to

    note that Boring (1969)

    detected signs that Titchener, near the end of his

    career, was gradually moving toward behaviorism;

    Boring's grounds

    were

    simply

    that

    Titchener 's

    theory of meaning was changing into a functional

    account . And from that development, too, both

    structural is ts and

    functionalists

    can learn.

    REFERENCES

    BIJOU, S. W., & B A E R , D. M . Operant methods in child

    behavior a nd development . In W. K . Honig

    ( E d . ) ,

    Operant

    behavior:

    Areas

    of

    research

    an d

    application.

    N ew

    Y o r k : Ap p l e t o n - Cen t u r y - Cr o f t s , 1966.

    B L A C K , M .

    C o m m e n t .

    In R.

    B or ge r

    & F .

    C i o f f i ( E d s . ) ,

    Explanation

    in the behavioural

    sciences. C a mbr i dge :

    Cambridge University Press, 1970.

    B O L L E S , R. C. The syntax of the mi nd . Psychological

    Reports 1967, 21,493^99.

    B O R I N G ,

    E . G .

    Ti tchener , meaning

    an d

    be ha v i o r i sm.

    In

    D. L . Krantz ( E d . ) , Schools of psychology: A sym-

    posium.

    Ne w Y or k : A pp l e t on- C e n t ur y- C r of t s , 1969.

    B R E L A N D , K ., & B R E L A N D , M. The misbehavior of or-

    ganisms. American

    Psychologist,

    1961, 16 ,

    681-684.

    C A T A N I A ,

    A. C . Elicitat ion, re inforcement , and s t imulus

    contro l . In R. Glaser (Ed.) , Th e nature o f

    learning.

    N ew Y o r k : A ca de m ic Press, 1971.

    C A T A N I A , A. C . Chomsky's

    f o rm a l

    analysis of na t u r a l

    l anguages : A

    behavioral translation. Behaviorism 1972,

    1, 1-15.

    C A T A N I A ,

    A. C. The

    n a t u r e

    of

    learning.

    In J . A.

    Nevin

    G. S.

    Reynolds (Eds . ) ,

    The study of behavior: Learn-

    ing,

    motivation emotion an d instinct.

    Glenview, 111.:

    Scot t ,

    Foresman, 1973.

    CHOMSKY,

    N .

    Review

    of B. F.

    Skinner 's

    Verbal

    behavior.

    Language, 1959,

    35 ,

    26-58.

    CHOMSKY,

    N ., &MILLER, G. A . I n t r oduc t i on to the formal

    analysis

    of

    na tura l l anguages .

    In R. D.

    Luce,

    R. R.

    Bush , & E.

    Galanter ( E d s . ) , Handbook of mathematical

    psychology. Vol .

    2 . New

    York: Wiley, 1963.

    D A Y , W. F .

    Radical behaviorism

    in

    reconcil iat ion with

    p h en o men o l o g y .

    Journal

    of the

    Experimental Analysis

    o f Behavior 1969, 12 , 315-329.

    D I X O M , T.

    R .,

    & M O R T O N , D. L. (Eds . )

    Verbal behavior

    and general

    behavior

    theory. Englewood Cliffs, N.J . :

    Prentice-Hall, 1968.

    ESTES, W. K. Reward in hum an lea rning: Theoret ica l i s -

    sues and

    strategic choice points.

    In R.

    Glaser

    ( E d . ) ,

    Th e

    nature

    of

    reinforcement.

    N ew

    York: Academic

    Press, 1971.

    F E R S T E R ,

    C.

    B.,

    &

    SKINNER,

    B. F. Schedules

    of

    reinforce-

    ment. New York: Ap ple ton-Century-Crofts , 1957.

    FISCHER,

    K. W.

    Structuralism

    fo r

    psycho logists. Review

    of

    M . Lane ( E d . ) ,

    Introduction to structuralism.

    Con-

    temporary Psychology, 1972,

    17 ,

    329-331.

    G I B S O N , E. J.

    Learning

    to

    read.

    Science,

    196 5, 148, 1066-

    1072.

    442 MAY

    1973

    A M E R I C A N P S Y C H O L O G I S T

  • 8/10/2019 Catania (1973) the Psychologies of Structure, Function and Development

    10/10

    G U I L F O R D , J. P. The role of form in lea rning. Journal of

    Experimental Psychology,

    1927, 10, 415-423.

    H A R L O W , H. F. The formation of learning sets.

    Psy-

    chological Review 1949, 56, S1-6S.

    J O H N S O N ,

    N. F. The

    influence

    of gr a mma t i ca l un i t s on

    learning. Journal

    of

    Verbal Learning

    an d

    Verbal

    Be-

    havior, 1968, 7, 236-24 0.

    K A T A H N , M ., &

    KOPLIN,

    J. H. Paradigm clash: Com men t

    on Some recent cri ticisms of behaviorism an d learning

    theory with special reference to Breger a nd M cGa ugh

    an d to

    C homsky . Psychological

    Bulletin

    1968,

    69 ,

    147-148.

    K R E C H E V S K Y , I.

    Hypotheses

    in

    ra ts .

    Psychological Re-

    view

    1932,

    39 ,

    516-532.

    KUHN, T. S. The

    structure

    of scientific

    revolutions.

    Chi-

    cago: Univers i ty of Chicago Press, 1962.

    L E N N E B E R G , E. H. Biological foundations

    of

    language.

    N ew

    Y ork: Wiley, 1967.

    L I B E R M A N , A. M. The gr a mma r s of speech and language .

    Cognitive Psychology, 1970, 1, 301-323.

    M A C C O R Q U O D A L E , K. On

    Chomsky's review

    of

    Skinner 's

    Verbal behavior. Journa l of the Experimental Analysis

    o f

    Behavior 1970, 13, 83-99.

    M A L C O L M , N. The m y t h of cognit ive processes and s t ruc-

    tures.

    In T.

    Mischel

    (Ed.),

    Cognit ive development and

    epistemology. New Yo rk: Academic Press , 1971.

    M A Y R , E. The n a t u r e of the Da r w i n i a n r e vo l u t i on .

    Sci-

    ence,

    1972, 176,

    981-989.

    McNEiLL,

    D. The acquisition of

    language.

    New Y o r k :

    Ha r pe r

    & Row, 1970.

    NEISSER,

    U . Cognit ive psychology. N ew York: Appleton-

    C e ntu ry -C rof t s ,

    1967.

    N E I S S E R ,

    U. A

    pa r a d i gm

    shift in

    psychology. Review

    of

    A . Richardson,

    Mental imagery; S. J .

    Segal

    ( E d . ) ,

    Imagery:

    Current cognit ive approaches;

    and A. Paivio,

    Imagery a nd verbal processes. Science,

    19 72, 176, 628-

    6 3 0 .

    P I A G E T , J.,

    &

    I N H E L D E R ,

    B.

    The

    psychology

    of the

    child.

    (Trans,

    by H. W eaver ) New York: Basic Boo ks, 1969.

    P R E M A C K , D. A

    funct iona l analysis

    of

    language.

    Journal

    o f

    the

    Experimental Analysis

    of Behavior 1970, 14 , 107-

    1 2 5 .

    P Y L Y S H Y N , Z . W. Com petence and psychological reali ty.

    American Psychologist , 197 2, 27, 546-552.

    R E V U S K Y , S., & G A R C I A , J. Learned associations over long

    delays . In G. H. Bower (Ed .) ,

    Th e

    psychology

    of

    learning and

    motivation. Vol . 4 . New Yo rk: Academ ic

    Press, 1970.

    ROZIN,

    P., & K A L A T , J . W.

    Specific

    hunge r s and poison

    avoidance as adap tive specializations in learning .

    Psy-

    chological Review 1971, 78,

    459-486.

    S E G A L , E . M ., & L A C H M A N , R.

    C ompl e x be ha v i o r

    or

    higher

    men t a l process:

    Is

    there

    a

    paradigm

    sh i f t? American

    Psychologist, 1 9 7 2 ,

    27 , 46-55.

    S E L I G M A N ,

    M. E. P. On the

    generality

    of the

    laws

    of

    learn ing . Psychological Review 1970, 77,

    406-418.

    SKINNER, B. F, Verbal behavior. N ew York: Appleton-

    Century-Crof t s , 1957.

    S T E R N B E R G , S. Mem ory-scan ning: Menta l processes re -

    vealed by reaction-time experiments. In J. S. Antrobus

    ( E d . ) ,

    Cognit ion

    and a f f e c t Boston: Li t t le , Brown,

    1 9 7 0 .

    TITCHENER,

    E. B. The

    postulates

    of a

    structural psychol-

    o g y . Philosophical Review

    1898,

    7,

    449-465.

    T I T C H E N E R ,

    E. B.

    A n outline of psychology.

    New

    Y o r k :

    Macmillan, 1899.

    (a)

    T I T C H E N E R , E. B. S t r uc t u r a l and funct iona l psycho l ogy .

    Philosophical Review 1899, 8, 290-299. (b )

    T O L M A N , E . C. Cognitive map s in rats and men . Psy-

    chological Review 1948, 55,

    189-208.

    T U L V I N G , E. Subject ive organiza t ion in free recall of un-

    related words. Psychological Review 1962,69 , 344-354.

    W R I G H T ,

    A. A., &

    CUMMING,

    W. W.

    C ol or - na mi ng func-

    tions for the pigeon.

    Journal of the Experimental Analy-

    sis

    of

    Behavior 1971,

    15,

    7-17.

    A M E R I C A N P S Y C H O L O G I S T

    MAY

    1973

    443