Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    1/36

    The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics

    Author(s): Charles Brittain and John PalmerSource: Phronesis, Vol. 46, No. 1, Problems of Matter and Evil in the (Neo)Platonic Tradition(Feb., 2001), pp. 38-72Published by: BRILLStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4182663 .

    Accessed: 21/02/2015 23:03

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

     .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

     .

     BRILL is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Phronesis.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=baphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4182663?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4182663?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=bap

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    2/36

    The New

    Academy's Appeals

    to the Presocratics

    CHARLESBRI1TAIN

    AND

    JOHN PALMER

    ABSTRACT

    Members of the

    New Academy presented

    their

    sceptical position as

    the culmi-

    nation of a progressive development in the history of philosophy,which began

    when certain

    Presocratics

    started to

    reflect on the epistemic

    status

    of their theo-

    retical claims

    concerning

    the natures

    of things. The

    Academics' dogmatic oppo-

    nents accused

    them of misrepresenting

    he early philosophers

    in an illegitimate

    attempt

    to claim respectable

    precedents

    for their dangerous

    position.

    The en-

    suing debate

    over the extent

    to which some

    form of

    scepticism might

    properly

    be attributed

    to the Presocratics

    is reflected

    in various

    passages in

    Cicero's

    Academica.

    In this

    essay, we try to

    get clearer about

    the precise nature

    of the

    Academics'

    historical claim

    and their view

    of the general lesson

    to be

    learned

    from reflection

    on the history

    of philosophy

    down to their

    own time. The

    Academics saw the Presocratics

    as

    providing some

    kind

    of

    support

    for the the-

    sis that things are non-cognitive,or, more specifically, that neither the senses nor

    reason furnishes

    a

    criterion

    of truth. As this

    view is susceptible to both

    'dialec-

    tical' and

    non-dialectical

    readings,

    we consider the prospects

    for each.

    We

    also

    examine the

    evidence for the varied functions

    both of the Academics'

    specific

    appeals

    to individual Presocratics

    and of their collections

    of the Presocratics'

    divergent

    opinions. What

    emerges

    is a better understanding

    of

    why

    the Acad-

    emics were concerned

    with

    claiming

    the

    Presocratics as

    sceptical

    ancestors

    and

    of

    the precise

    mannerin

    which

    they advanced this claim.

    Ever since philosophy

    attained

    a measure of maturity

    as a

    discipline, philoso-

    phers

    have looked

    to the

    great

    figures

    of the

    past

    for

    inspiration

    and,

    equally importantly, have reflected upon the lessons to be learned from

    their

    discipline's history.

    The

    members of the

    New

    Academy

    were no

    exception, and

    the

    past

    few decades

    have

    yielded

    a better understanding

    of some of the ways

    in which they were able plausibly

    to

    present

    them-

    selves as

    true defenders of their Academic

    inheritance.' But the

    Academics

    Accepted September2000

    '

    See

    W.

    Burkert,

    Cicero als Platoniker

    und Skeptiker.Zum

    Platonsverstandnis

    er

    Neuen

    Akademie',

    Gymnasium

    72 (1965),

    175-200;

    H.-J. Kramer,

    Platonismus

    und

    hellenistische Philosophie (Berlin/New York: de Gruyter,1971), 14-107; J. Glucker,

    Antiochus

    and the Late Academy,

    Hypomnemata

    56

    (Gottingen:

    Vandenhoeck

    &

    Ruprecht,

    1978),

    31-64; G.

    Calogero,

    'Socratismo

    e scetticismo

    nel

    pensiero antico',

    (

    Koninklijke

    Brill

    NV, Leiden,

    2001

    Phronesis

    XLVIII

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    3/36

    THE NEW ACADEMY'S APPEALS TO THE

    PRESOCRATICS 39

    also presented their philosophy as the culmination of trends in epistemol-

    ogy that began as

    far

    back

    as Xenophanes.

    This

    claim deserves more

    attention

    than

    it has received,

    not

    only

    because of its importance for

    understanding the sceptical stance

    of

    the New

    Academy,

    but

    also

    because

    it offers

    a

    particularly intriguing example

    of

    how Greek philosophy

    tended

    to develop through reflection on its

    own

    history.2

    The Academics'

    appeals

    to the Presocratics

    also

    made

    for

    a

    lively

    debate with

    their

    dogmatic oppo-

    nents

    over the

    extent

    to

    which some

    form

    of

    scepticism might properly

    be

    attributedto the early Greek philosophers.

    This

    question continues

    to be

    controversial even today; since it arises largely because the interest the

    ancient sceptics took

    in these

    figures proved responsible

    for

    the preserva-

    tion

    of

    a substantial

    portion

    of

    our

    evidence

    for

    Presocratic

    epistemology,

    it seems worth asking what

    the

    sceptics'

    view of the question was.

    Modem

    views

    on the legitimacy of attributing

    some form of scepticism to the

    Presocratics of course vary, but there is general agreement that none of

    the early Greek philosophers subscribed to the radical form of scepticism

    promoted by Arcesilaus. The Academics

    also agreed about this, which

    makes

    it all

    the more

    interesting

    that

    they

    should have used the Presocrat-

    ics in articulating their own sceptical stance.

    in

    G.

    Giannantoni ed.),

    Lo

    scetticismo antico,

    vol.

    1, Elenchos

    6

    (Naples: Bibliopolis,

    1981), 35-46; P. Woodruff, 'The skeptical side of Plato's method', Revue Inter-

    nationale

    de

    Philosophie 40 (1986), 22-37; A. A. Long, 'Socrates in Hellenistic phi-

    losophy', Classical Quarterly 38 (1988), 150-71, repr. with afterward in his Stoic

    Studies

    (Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress, 1996), 1-34,

    at

    1

    1-16;

    J.

    Annas,

    'Platon

    le sceptique', Revue de metaphysiqueet de

    morale

    95 (1990), 267-91; C. Ldvy, 'Platon,

    Arce-silas, Carnmade

    -

    Reponse

    'a J.

    Annas', Revue

    de

    metaphysique

    et de

    morale

    95

    (1990), 293-306; J. Annas, 'Plato

    the

    sceptic',

    Oxford

    Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

    suppl.

    vol.

    1992, 43-72, repr. with afterward in P. A. Vander Waerdt (ed.), The

    Socratic

    Movement

    Ithaca,

    NY:

    Cornell

    University Press, 1994), 309-40;

    C. J.

    Shields,

    'Soc-rates among

    the

    Skeptics',

    in

    Vander Waerdt (1994), 341-66;

    A. M.

    loppolo,

    'Socrate nelle tradizioni accademica e pirroniana',

    in

    G. Giannantoni (ed.), La

    tradizione

    Socratica:

    seminario di studi

    (Naples: Bibliopolis, 1995), 89-123;

    and

    J.

    Glucker,

    'Socrates in the

    Academic books and other

    Ciceronian

    works',

    in

    B.

    Inwood

    and

    J. Mansfeld

    (edd.),

    Assent

    and Argument:Studies

    in

    Cicero's Academic

    Books

    (Leiden/New York/Koln: Brill, 1997), 58-88.

    2

    There has been no previous study devoted specifically to this topic. When the

    more prominent,general works on ancient scepticism mention the subject, they do so

    more or less incidentally and tend towards paraphrase f Cicero or Plutarch.See, how-

    ever,

    D.

    Sedley,

    'The

    motivation

    of

    Greek skepticism',

    in

    M.

    F.

    Burnyeat (ed.), The

    Skeptical

    Tradition

    (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983), 9-29,

    at

    9-10 and

    15-16; and

    M.

    F.

    Burnyeat, 'Antipater and self-refutation', in Inwood

    and

    Mansfeld

    (1997), 277-310, at 295-7.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    4/36

    40 CHARLES BRITTAIN AND

    JOHN

    PALMER

    In trying to understand the Academics' appeals to the Presocratics, we

    shall not be directly concerned with the

    modern question of whether some

    variety of scepticism can properly be

    attributed to any of the early Greek

    philosophers: we shall not be arguing

    that the Academics' engagement

    with the Presocratics tells us something

    significant about the Presocratics

    in

    their

    own right. Our concern

    is

    rather

    with

    sketching

    the

    main features

    of a philosophically significant use

    of

    the Presocratics, regardless of

    its

    historical accuracy,

    in

    the hope

    of

    furthering

    our

    understandingof the

    New

    Academy.

    Nor

    do

    we propose

    to

    discuss

    in any detail

    the

    important role

    played by the Academics in the development of the sceptical strain within

    the

    doxographical tradition,3

    since

    a more

    precise understanding

    of

    the

    philosophical use the Academics made of

    the

    Presocratics seems a neces-

    sary preliminary

    to

    any investigation

    into this

    complex subject.4

    Our

    attempt to understandthis use concentrates

    on Cicero's

    Academica, as

    this

    is the only source that provides detailed and direct information regarding

    the Academics'

    appeals. Proper

    assessment

    of

    any

    further

    evidence

    in

    other

    sources

    will

    have

    to

    depend

    on a

    fuller understanding

    of

    the Academics'

    strategies as represented in this text. Perhaps the most notable case

    in

    point is Plutarch's report that Arcesilaus was accused by certain contem-

    poraries

    of

    attributing

    his own

    views

    regarding epoche

    and

    akatalepsia,

    not

    only

    to

    Socrates and

    Plato,

    but

    to

    Parmenides

    and

    Heraclitus

    as well

    (Col.

    112

    1F-

    122A).

    The more detailed evidence

    of

    the Academica

    sug-

    gests

    this

    report

    needs

    to

    be

    treated

    with a

    fair

    amount

    of

    caution.

    The

    Academics' appeals

    to

    the Presocratics

    as

    represented

    in

    the

    Academica are remnants of four broader

    contexts. What now passes as

    Cicero's Academica are

    in

    fact lengthy

    fragments of

    two

    separate

    and

    complete

    versions

    of

    the

    work

    (Academica II,

    or

    the

    Academica

    Priora,

    is the second book of the two-volume first edition; Academica I, or the

    Academica Posteriora,

    is

    about half

    of the first book of the four-volume

    second

    edition). Behind

    these works lie the

    original

    debates between

    the

    Stoics

    and

    Academics

    over

    the

    history

    of

    philosophy

    and

    their

    continua-

    tion

    by

    Antiochus and

    Philo

    (and

    their

    colleagues),

    which Cicero tried

    to

    summarize

    for

    a Roman audience. Since

    so

    much

    of these

    original

    con-

    texts

    is

    lost

    to

    us, our purpose

    in

    this essay

    is

    modest.

    We

    try

    to

    explain,

    3

    Lactantius informs us that Arcesilaus collected the renowned

    philosophers' con-

    fessions

    of

    ignorance

    as well as their mutual recriminations Inst. 111.4.1 Brandt).

    4

    See, however, J. Mansfeld,

    'Theophrastus and the Xenophanes doxography',

    Mnemosyne 40 (1987), 286-312,

    at 295ff., repr. in his Studies in the

    Historiography

    of Greek Philosophy (Assen/Maastricht:

    Van Gorcum, 1990),

    147-73.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    5/36

    THE NEW

    ACADEMY'S APPEALS TO THE

    PRESOCRATICS 41

    on the basis of the available evidence, why the Academics appealed

    to the

    Presocratics by

    examining

    the

    general

    strategies

    underlying the

    Academics' use of

    the Presocratics in the

    texts and

    by

    setting out

    some-

    thing

    of the

    complexity

    of their

    specific

    appeals

    to individual

    philosophers.

    Rather than

    relying

    on

    speculation

    about the sources of

    the various

    parts

    of Cicero's

    work, or even

    assuming

    at

    the outset that the

    extant

    portions

    of its two

    editions

    provide a

    single

    coherent

    picture,

    we examine

    sepa-

    rately

    the sketch of an

    Academic

    history

    of

    philosophy

    in

    the

    Academica

    Posteriora

    (section

    I)

    and the

    evidence of the

    Academica Priora con-

    cerning the controversial Academic interpretationsof the Presocratics (sec-

    tion

    II)

    before

    attempting

    to draw

    some

    general

    conclusions.

    I. The Academica

    Posteriora

    The

    Presocratics'

    position

    in

    the Academics'

    general picture of the

    lesson

    to be

    learned

    from the

    history of

    philosophical

    inquiry

    is perhaps

    clearest

    in Cicero's

    response to

    Varro's invitation

    to

    explain Arcesilaus's

    'defec-

    tion'

    from

    the Old

    Academy (Acad.

    1.43).

    Cicero

    begins with an

    account

    of Arcesilaus's relation to his predecessors:

    We

    hold that

    Arcesilaus's entire

    struggle with

    Zeno arose not from

    obstinacy or

    rivalry

    ...

    in

    my

    view, at least

    -

    but from

    the

    obscurity of just those

    subjects

    (rerum

    obscuritas) which had

    previously led Socrates

    to his

    confession of

    ignorance

    (confessio

    ignorationis).

    Just

    as, even

    before

    Socrates,

    Democritus,

    Anaxagoras,

    Empedocles,and

    practically all

    the ancients had said

    (A) that

    noth-

    ing could

    be

    apprehended,grasped, or

    known,

    (B)

    that the senses are

    limited,

    our

    minds

    weak,

    our

    lives'

    period

    brief,

    and

    (C)

    that,

    as

    Democritus

    said,

    truth is

    submerged

    in

    an

    abyss,

    everything is

    subject

    to

    opinions and

    customs,

    no truth

    is

    left, and

    everything is

    surroundedby

    obscurity.5Therefore Arcesilaus

    used to

    say that there was nothingthatcould be known- not even that claim itself, which

    Socrates had allowed

    himself

    to know

    -

    so hidden

    in

    darkness

    did

    he

    consider

    everything

    that

    nothing

    could be

    discerned or understood6

    Acad.

    1.44-5).

    The

    successive

    pronouncements attributed to

    the ancients here fall

    natu-

    rally

    into three

    groups, marked

    (A),

    (B), and

    (C)

    above.

    (A) gives vari-

    ous formulations of

    the

    general thesis that all

    things are

    non-cognitive,

    I

    On

    the

    echoes of

    individual Presocratics

    here,

    see Appendix.

    6

    Each view

    Cicero

    attributes o

    Arcesilaus

    echoes a

    view

    attributed o

    the

    Presocratics

    earlier in

    the

    passage:

    negabat

    esse

    quidquam

    quod sciri posset

    (1.45) - nihil sciri

    posse

    (1.44); sic

    omnia

    latere

    censebat

    in

    occulto (I.45)

    =

    rerum

    obscuritate,

    in pro-

    fundo

    veritatem

    demersam,omnia

    tenebris

    circumfusa

    (1.44);

    neque esse

    quidquam

    quod

    cerni

    aut

    intellegi

    posset

    (1.45)

    =

    nihil

    cognosci, nihil

    percipi (1.44).

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    6/36

    42

    CHARLES

    BRITTAIN AND JOHN PALMER

    while (B) and (C) reflect the two aspects of this thesis marked in the

    earlier

    portion

    of the sentence

    as rerum obscuritas and confessio

    ignora-

    tionis.

    The

    principal

    conclusion, that the Presocratics

    support

    the

    akatalep-

    sia thesis (A),

    is

    explicitly justified

    in this

    passage by pointing

    to

    their

    discovery

    of

    the apparent inability

    of either reason

    or the senses to guar-

    antee apprehension

    of the

    nature of

    things (B).

    This leads in turn

    to

    their

    various characterizations

    of their epistemological

    predicament

    (C).

    The

    passage

    is particularly

    valuable for its indication of

    how

    the

    Academics presented their

    own

    refined variety of scepticism

    as the cul-

    mination of a progressive development in the history of philosophy going

    back

    to the time when philosophers

    first

    began

    to reflect on the epistemic

    status of their theoretical

    claims.7

    Their view seems to have

    run

    more or

    less as follows. As ambitious

    in their theorizing and as diverse

    in their

    methods and views as the

    great philosophers

    prior to

    Socrates may

    have

    been,

    they nonetheless appreciated

    their limited ability

    to

    grasp the

    true

    natureof

    things.

    This recognition (A)

    manifested itself

    in

    various unqualified

    assertions to the

    effect

    that all things are non-cognitive

    (B)

    and

    ultimately

    in a dogmatically sceptical

    stance

    regarding

    our relation to truth

    (C).

    Socrates's scepticism introduced a new stage in the history of philosophy,

    which

    was at once

    more reflective

    and

    more moderate. His confession

    of

    ignorance resulted

    not from any theoretical

    beliefs about either

    the nature

    of

    things

    or our cognitive apparatus

    but from his own experience

    in the

    elenctic examination of

    various self-styled

    experts. Socrates

    is

    represented

    as

    dogmatic

    in

    that

    he claimed to know that

    he

    has no

    cognitive

    grasp

    of

    anything,

    but he did not

    go

    so far

    as

    to assert that

    things

    themselves

    are

    non-cognitive

    since he had no further

    views about why

    his

    elenctic exper-

    iments had turned out as they had.

    Arcesilaus's

    innovation

    introduces a

    I

    Although Cicero's

    immediate source

    for our passage may

    have been Philo,

    it

    would

    be a mistake o

    suppose hat he

    historical

    view it presents

    s doctrinallyPhilonian'.

    Acad. 1.44, 'ut

    accepimus',

    indicates that

    what follows

    is a view that has been passed

    down within

    the Academy for

    some time;

    'Cum

    Zenone...

    Arcesilas sibi omne

    cer-

    tamen instituit'

    means that

    he did not, pace

    Varro

    (cf.

    Atad.

    1.43),

    attack the

    mem-

    bers of the

    Old Academy, not

    that

    he only began to

    generate

    his

    philosophical

    ideas

    when

    he locked horns

    with Zeno; 'ut

    quidemmihi

    vide'ur'

    is not an indication

    that

    the historical

    sketch

    represents ust

    Cicero's (or

    Philo's)

    view but is merely

    a polite

    aside as he voices

    disagreement

    with the opposition's charge

    of

    pertinacia (cf.

    Acad.

    11.18).Section II.1 below will show that both Lucullus and

    Cicero (in the Academica

    Priora)

    take somethingvery

    much

    like this to be the

    standard Academic'

    history (i.e.,

    one which does not depend

    on Philo

    -

    see Acad.

    11.12);

    and Acad. 11.15

    and 16

    fur-

    nish good

    evidence

    for supposing

    that its origin stretches

    back to Arcesilaus

    himself

    (cf. infra,

    n. 12).

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    7/36

    THE NEW

    ACADEMY'S APPEALS TO THE

    PRESOCRATICS

    43

    still more moderate position, since he does not even claim to know that

    he

    knows

    nothing. Rather than

    asserting,

    as Socrates had

    done,

    that

    he

    has

    no

    cognitive

    grasp of

    anything,

    he

    merely reports

    that

    it

    appears that

    none of his

    impressions are

    cognitive.

    For all he

    knows,

    however,

    some

    of his

    impressions

    may

    be

    cognitive.

    He is

    just

    in no

    position

    to

    deter-

    mine when this

    might

    be the case. His reaction

    to this situation

    -

    with-

    holding

    assent or

    suspending

    judgement

    (epoche)

    -

    distinguishes

    his

    sceptical

    stance from those of both

    Socrates

    (followed

    by

    Plato,

    Acad.

    1.46)

    and the

    Presocratics. For

    despite

    their

    respectively qualified

    and

    dog-

    matic assertions of akatalepsia, they had nevertheless been willing to en-

    dorse various

    propositions

    they

    admittedly

    did

    not

    know to be

    true.

    Thus

    the Academics' view of

    the

    history

    of

    philosophy

    is

    designed

    to

    present

    their

    own

    advocacy

    of

    epoche

    both as

    something

    new and as the

    culmination

    of a

    gradually more

    reflective

    turn.

    At first

    sight, it

    may

    be

    tempting to dismiss this

    whole

    story

    and

    agree

    with

    Lucullus

    (Antiochus's

    representative in the

    Academica

    Priora)

    that

    the Academics

    are

    simply

    misrepresenting

    the Presocratics

    so as to man-

    ufacture

    respectable

    precedents for their

    own

    sceptical

    innovations. But

    even if, in the end, one might want to side with Lucullus on the accuracy

    of the

    Academics'

    interpretation

    of

    the

    Presocratics, their

    general

    view is

    scarcely the

    implausible

    caricature he

    makes it

    out to be.

    After

    all, the

    Presocratics

    cited

    by

    the

    Academics, engaged

    as they were in

    elaborating

    the distinction

    between

    reality

    and

    appearance,

    took

    the real nature of

    things to be

    quite

    different from how

    things appear to us in

    perception

    and

    thus

    came to

    question the

    veracity

    of

    these appearances.

    Furthermore,

    although

    they

    relied

    primarily upon

    reason in

    constructing their

    accounts

    of the

    nature of

    things,

    at least

    some of them

    came to have

    certain

    doubts

    about whether human reason is in fact capable of providing anything more

    than

    plausible

    speculation

    about how

    things really are as

    opposed to how

    they appear

    to

    us.

    (These

    doubts, of

    course, did

    not prevent

    them

    from

    continuing

    to

    pursue

    their

    various

    physical and

    metaphysical

    inquiries.)

    While

    important

    qualifications

    on

    this basic

    story

    would

    obviously be nec-

    essary

    for

    individual

    thinkers, it

    might

    still

    seem a

    plausible

    enough view

    of the

    position

    of those

    Presocratics

    who reflected

    upon

    the

    epistemic

    standing of their own

    theories.

    What should

    we

    suppose to be the relation

    between

    Arcesilaus's view

    of the Presocratics, as reflected here, and his own sceptical stance?

    Accounts of the

    origins of Arcesilaus's

    scepticism tend to

    focus upon

    two

    principal

    factors:

    his

    debate with

    Zeno

    over

    the

    cognitive

    impression

    and

    his return

    to a

    Socratic style of

    philosophy. The

    conclusion Arcesilaus

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    8/36

    44

    CHARLES BRI'TAIN AND

    JOHN PALMER

    drew, on Cicero's account, from reflectionon philosophy's history- namely,

    that one

    should

    avoid maintaining,

    asserting,

    or

    assenting to

    anything

    (Acad.

    1.45)

    -

    is

    also, of course,

    the conclusion

    of the

    familiar

    Academic

    argument:

    (i) everything

    is non-cognitive;

    (ii) where things

    are

    non-cog-

    nitive,

    one should

    suspend

    judgement;

    therefore

    (iii) one should

    suspend

    judgement

    about

    everything. Arcesilaus's

    conclusion

    in Academica

    1.45

    clearly

    depends

    on the intermediate

    premise

    taken from

    the Stoics

    that

    the

    sage

    will withhold assent in cases

    where

    no cognitive impression

    is avail-

    able (cf.

    Acad. 11.77), and

    the arguments

    for the crucial

    first premise

    are

    usually taken to be drawn from the Academic attacks upon the Stoic doc-

    trine

    of the

    phantasia

    kataleptike.

    Academica

    1.44-5,

    however, represents

    Arcesilaus's

    reflection

    upon (Socrates's

    and) the

    Presocratics'

    epistemo-

    logical quandary

    as having

    led

    him to

    advance

    the premise that things

    are

    non-cognitive:

    'Therefore

    (itaque) Arcesilaus

    used to say

    that

    there was

    nothing that

    could

    be

    known'. Thus

    Cicero's

    reply to

    Varro

    indicates that

    this initial premise

    in the familiar Academic

    argument

    was

    also secured

    by appeal

    to the

    Presocratics,

    and

    it looks

    as if this

    second

    means of secur-

    ing

    the initial premise

    was

    supposed

    to

    be as important

    for Arcesilaus

    as

    the first.8So it seems that Arcesilaus, ratherthan merely seeking to sup-

    port

    his

    position

    by

    claiming

    that

    it was

    prefigured

    to some extent among

    the

    earliest

    philosophers,

    may

    have actually

    developed his position

    in

    part

    by

    a more active

    engagement

    with their

    views.

    It is not yet clear,

    however,

    how

    Arcesilaus's appeal

    to the Presocratics

    supports

    the akatalepsia

    premise

    because

    his appeal

    is

    susceptible

    to

    both

    a 'dialectical'

    and a

    'non-dialectical'

    reading.

    In the first

    place,

    it

    is

    pos-

    sible to

    see the

    appeal

    as functioning

    within

    the context

    of debate with

    the Stoics,

    in such a

    way

    that it

    is

    designed

    to

    rely

    upon

    his

    opponents'

    respect for the ancients. 'Consider those thinkerswhose venerable author-

    ity you yourselves

    acknowledge,

    and

    you

    will find them

    repeatedly

    declar-

    ing

    that neither the

    senses nor reason

    constitutes

    a criterion

    of

    truth.'

    Much

    of the

    more extended debate

    in the Academica

    Priora

    over the lesson

    to

    be

    learned from the

    Presocratics

    does,

    in

    fact,

    depend

    upon

    Antiochus's

    (and

    hence, presumably,

    the Stoics')

    acknowledgement

    of

    their

    authority.

    The non-dialectical

    reading, by

    contrast,

    rests

    on the fact that

    the Aca-

    demics

    themselves seem

    to think more

    highly

    of the Presocratics

    than

    of

    8

    Premise (i), that everything is non-cognitive, is shorthandfor the two distinct

    claims

    to

    the

    effect that

    the

    criterion

    of truth

    is located neither

    in

    the senses

    nor

    in

    reason.

    Section

    II.2-6

    below shows

    that

    the

    specific appeals

    to the

    Presocratics

    n

    the

    Academica

    Priora

    were taken

    by the Academics

    to

    provide

    support

    for both

    claims.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    9/36

    THE

    NEW

    ACADEMY'S

    APPEALS TO THE

    PRESOCRATICS

    45

    any other thinkers apart from Socrates and Plato. This is not merely

    because their

    arguments can be

    seen,

    in

    one

    way

    or

    another,

    to

    lend

    cre-

    dence to the view that

    neither the

    senses nor reason

    furnishes

    a

    criterion

    of

    truth.

    (If this

    were the

    case,

    then

    one

    might

    expect

    the

    Academics to

    be

    less

    dismissive

    of, for

    instance, the

    Cyrenaics' restriction of the

    objects

    of

    perception to

    the

    sensations

    of

    which one

    is

    immediately

    aware.)

    Rather,

    the

    Academics

    seem to

    have

    respected

    the

    Presocratics

    because

    they

    saw

    reflection on

    these

    early

    thinkers as

    having

    had a

    formative

    influence

    on

    Socrates's

    confession of

    ignorance.

    Since

    the

    Academics

    avowedly modeled themselves upon Socrates, they may have been will-

    ing

    to

    present the

    Presocratics'

    dogmatic

    scepticism, which

    they

    saw as

    having

    influenced

    him, as

    also

    influencing their

    own

    somewhat

    different

    position.

    'When

    we

    consider

    those

    thinkers who

    speculated most

    aggres-

    sively about the

    nature of

    things, we find

    that

    even as

    they

    pursued these

    speculations

    they were

    careful to

    qualify

    the epistemic

    status of

    their

    own

    theories

    and to

    admit their

    inability

    to know

    the

    truth of

    their

    claims either

    on the

    basis of

    the

    senses or

    reason.

    While

    we, like

    Socrates, do

    not

    actively pursue

    such

    inquiries

    ourselves, our

    reflection on

    the

    experience

    of those who have done so makes it seem reasonable to us to suppose that

    everything is

    non-cognitive.'

    While it is

    not always

    obvious

    whether the

    Academics'

    general

    appeal to the

    Presocratics is

    or is

    not

    supposed to be

    merely

    dialectical,

    it is

    clear that

    the

    two

    readings

    are

    not

    incompatible.

    On

    either

    interpretation,

    moreover, the

    appeal to

    the

    Presocratics

    in

    sup-

    port

    of

    the

    akatalepsia

    premise

    would

    have

    served the

    Academics as

    one

    way to

    secure the

    premise

    without

    endorsing it

    themselves

    (which

    would

    obviously

    amount

    to a

    dogmatic

    form

    of

    scepticism). We

    can

    thus begin

    to

    see how

    the

    Academics could

    have

    appealed

    to the

    Presocratics, who

    were seen as manifesting a dogmatic variety of scepticism, without equat-

    ing

    this

    earlier

    form of

    scepticism with

    their

    own.

    II. The

    Academica Priora

    1.

    Lucullus's

    Accusation

    and

    Cicero's

    Reply

    In the

    lost first

    book of

    the

    Academica's

    first

    edition,

    Cicero

    presuma-

    bly

    had

    Catulus

    explain

    the

    general nature of

    the

    Academics'

    appeal to

    the Presocratics. What survives in the second book, however, is only

    Lucullus's

    criticism of

    the

    appeal

    (Acad.

    11.13-15) and

    Cicero's

    response

    to that

    criticism

    (11.72-6).

    The

    latter is

    mainly

    taken

    up

    with

    detailing

    and

    defending

    some of

    the

    Academics'

    specific

    appeals to

    individual

    Presocratics

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    10/36

    46

    CHARLES

    BRITTAIN AND JOHN PALMER

    rather than with explaining why the general appeal was made in the first

    place. This loss

    of context raises

    two problems concerning the relation

    between the exposition

    of the Academic view in the

    two editions. The

    first

    is controversial

    but relatively straightforward:

    did both editions originally

    offer the same general historical

    views? It will turn out to be fairly

    straightforwardto show that there

    is good reason to think that the outlines

    and detailed content of the historical

    views were quite similar (if

    not

    absolutely

    identical). The second,

    more

    interesting,

    though generally

    neglected, problem concerns the

    context or motivation for the general

    appeal in the first edition. For even if we come to accept that both edi-

    tions

    offered more or less the same historical

    picture,

    it is still

    possible,

    if

    not likely,

    that it may have been deployed for somewhat

    different ends.

    The history

    in the extant portion of the Academica

    Posteriora is presented

    as a

    way

    of

    explaining

    Arcesilaus's motivation for

    his

    sceptical

    innova-

    tions

    (hence

    the inclination

    towards a 'non-dialectical'

    reading); yet

    it

    is

    also a

    response

    to a critical question posed against

    the

    background

    of Varro's

    own Antiochian version of the history

    of

    philosophy

    (and

    hence allows

    for a 'dialectical'

    reading).

    The lost general history

    of the first edition

    might have been similarly ambiguous, but it may possibly have been more

    clearly

    dialectical or more clearly

    non-dialectical. Our examination

    of

    the

    appeals

    to

    specific

    Presocratics in the extant

    portion

    of the

    Academica

    Priora

    (which

    are without

    analogue

    in the extant portion

    of the Academic a

    Posteriora)

    will at least

    suggest

    that

    we should

    keep

    the dialectical

    option

    open.

    At

    any rate,

    there

    seem to be sufficient reasons to evaluate the

    his-

    torical claims of the

    first edition

    separately.

    The Antiochian

    Lucullus begins his discussion

    of Arcesilaus and

    Carneades

    by

    criticizing

    the Academics' citation

    of the ancient

    philoso-

    phers as precedents for their own subversion of philosophy (Acad. II. 13-

    15).9

    Lucullus is

    willing

    to

    admit that the ancient

    natural

    philosophers

    were liable, on occasion,

    when stuck over

    some difficult

    point,

    to

    give

    vent to their frustration in various aporetic pronouncements

    (Acad. I.14).

    Despite

    these

    occasional

    outbursts, however,

    the natural

    philosophers

    were, on Lucullus's view,

    if

    anything

    too confident

    in their claims to

    I

    He compares

    the Academics to

    seditious

    Romans

    (such

    as his

    contemporary,

    Saturninus)

    who recall famous

    figures of the

    past with seemingly

    popular

    leanings

    so

    as to claim that in their own efforts to throw the republic into turmoil they are fol-

    lowing the

    established

    practice

    of their ancestors.

    The Academics

    are no better,

    he

    charges,

    when

    they

    seek to

    overthrowa well-established

    system

    of

    philosophy

    and,

    in

    so doing, compare

    their own

    audacity

    to the

    modesty (verecundia)

    of the famous

    figuresof

    antiquity.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    11/36

    THE NEW

    ACADEMY'S

    APPEALS TO

    THE

    PRESOCRATICS 47

    knowledge. So Arcesilaus was disingenuous and deceitful when 'he hid

    behind the

    authority

    of those who had denied that

    anything

    could

    be

    known or

    grasped (in

    eorum auctoritate

    delitisceret,

    qui

    negavissent quid-

    quam

    sciri aut

    percipi

    posse)' (Acad. 11.15).

    Lucullus's

    remarks in this section indicate that the

    Presocratics

    ap-

    pealed

    to

    by the Academics included

    (at

    least)

    Empedocles, Anaxagoras,

    Democritus,

    Parmenides, and Xenophanes. His

    summary

    of

    the content of

    the

    Academic

    appeal to these

    figures

    is

    given

    in the remark

    cited above:

    the

    Academics claimed that these Presocratics were

    sceptical

    of the

    pos-

    sibility of achieving knowledge (i.e. they supported the Academic thesis

    of

    akatalepsia). But Lucullus also

    ascribes to them four more

    specific

    'sceptical' theses: 'all

    things are

    hidden,

    we

    perceive

    nothing,

    we

    discern

    nothing with

    the

    intellect,'

    we can discover

    the character of

    nothing at

    all (abstrusa

    esse

    omnia, nihil nos

    sentire, nihil cernere,

    nihil omnino

    quale

    sit

    posse reperire)' (Acad.

    11.14).

    Although one

    might trace

    the first

    and fourth of

    these formulations to

    specific

    source-statements

    by

    individ-

    ual

    Presocratics, neither is a direct

    paraphrase, and the

    generality

    of

    the

    second and third theses

    suggests that

    we have here a set

    of

    claims intended

    to represent the kind of scepticism manifested among these Presocratics

    collectively.

    Taken

    together, these four

    theses outline a

    sceptical-sounding

    argument: because all

    things are concealed

    from us (first

    thesis),

    we are

    Although

    the verb 'cernere'

    does often

    have the

    sense of 'to

    discern with

    the

    eyes' or even

    'to

    perceive with the

    senses', it

    also often has

    the

    sense of 'to

    discem

    with

    the

    intellect'. In the

    Academica,

    the verb

    is more

    often used in

    this latter

    sense;

    see

    1.21,

    30,

    45

    (where 'cerni' is used

    synonymously

    with

    'intellegi'), II.20,

    22

    bis,

    54, 129. J.

    S.

    Reid, M. Tulli

    Ciceronis

    Academica

    (London:

    Macmillan, 1885:

    repr.

    Hildesheim: Olms, 1966), 188 ad loc., notes that 'cernere' in the present passage

    'probably refers

    to

    the mind, as

    sentire to

    the senses'.

    Although it

    remains possible

    that the use of

    'cernere'

    alongside 'sentire' is

    simply

    a

    case

    of

    rhetorical

    variatio

    on

    Cicero's

    part,

    we follow

    Reid in

    supposing it more

    likely

    that Cicero

    draws

    a dis-

    tinction with his

    use of the two

    verbs,

    a

    distinction which is

    perfectly

    appropriateand

    even to be

    expected in this context.

    11

    The first

    thesis may

    seem an

    echo of

    Democritus's

    declaration

    that truth

    s in the

    abyss (Democr.

    ap. D.L. IX.72

    =

    68B117

    DK:

    iT?r4 ?e oU&v

    '16'8rv ?v

    V06 y'ap

    'i

    &XkOeita).

    ontrast,

    however,

    the actual

    paraphrase f Democritus B 117

    at Acad.

    II.32:

    naturam

    accusa, quae

    in

    profundo veritatem ut ait

    Democritus

    penitus

    abstruserit.

    Xenophanes's famous

    'sceptical' fragment

    (Xenoph.ap.

    S.E. M. VII.1

    10

    =

    21B34

    DK)

    might likewise appearto lie behind the final thesis, with its emphasis on the impos-

    sibility of

    discoveringthe

    natureof

    things. But

    'nihil

    omnino quale sit

    posse

    reperire'

    is

    clearly

    not a

    direct

    paraphraseof

    Xenophanes's

    pronouncement.Thus in

    each

    case,

    the echo, if there

    is one, is not meant

    to

    be distinct

    (contrast

    the

    echoes at Acad.

    1.44,

    discussed in the

    appendix).

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    12/36

    48 CHARLES BRITTAIN AND JOHN PALMER

    in no position to apprehend the nature of things by either perception or

    reason (second

    and third theses).

    Since these

    two

    options exhaust our

    cri-

    teria for apprehension,

    we

    are unable to

    discover by any

    means

    the true

    character of

    anything whatsoever

    (fourth thesis).

    As an ordered

    set,

    then,

    these four theses

    constitute

    an argument for

    the conclusion

    that all

    things

    are non-cognitive

    (akatalepsia).

    However,

    this

    will not be a straightfor-

    wardly

    Academic argument,

    since

    its first premise

    depends

    on a dogmatic

    claim about the nature

    of things.

    Cicero's eventual

    response to

    Lucullus's criticism

    of

    the Academics'

    appeal to the Presocratics is to deny that it is disingenuous: 'we Acade-

    mics say

    that we hold the same

    views

    that you yourselves

    admit were

    held

    by

    the most

    noble philosophers' (Acad.

    11.72).

    It

    is natural to suppose that

    Cicero is referring specifically

    to the fourfold thesis

    Lucullus attributed

    to

    the Academics at 11.14.

    In the event, however, it

    becomes clear

    that he

    takes the Academics and

    Presocratics

    to hold the

    same views only

    with

    respect

    to the conclusion

    that everything

    is non-cognitive

    (even

    though

    what

    it means for

    each group to

    'hold' the view

    may

    well be different).

    For the

    specific

    claims Cicero

    goes

    on to make about individual

    Pre-

    socratics show that he takes the Academics and Presocratics to agree about

    little

    else. One general

    reason

    will turn out to be precisely

    because he

    takes the Presocratics' views

    to

    rely

    on

    dogmatic

    theories

    about the real

    nature of things.

    But Lucullus's criticism

    has

    already

    indicated

    a

    second

    crucial

    difference

    (agreed

    by

    all

    parties

    in the

    Academica):

    whether

    or

    not

    the

    Presocratics can

    be seen

    as subscribing

    to some form of the

    akatalepsia

    thesis,

    they plainly

    did not

    conclude,

    as the Academics

    did,

    that

    given

    the

    incognizability

    of

    things

    the best

    course is to

    suspendjudge-

    ment

    universally.

    The significance

    of these

    two

    general

    differences

    will be

    clearer if we make a short detour into Academic history of philosophy as

    presented

    in

    this

    edition of the Academica.

    Although

    the

    historical

    understanding

    from which Cicero's

    claims

    spring

    is not

    pellucid

    in the Academica

    Priora,

    there is sufficient evidence

    to discern

    the

    general picture.

    We can

    begin

    with

    two obvious

    points.

    First,

    it is clear

    that Lucullus's criticisms

    are motivated

    by

    the familiar

    Antiochian view of the history

    of

    philosophy.

    On this

    view,

    Plato's

    estab-

    lishment of a

    'discipline'

    of

    philosophy,

    a

    systematic

    set of

    philosophical

    doctrines,

    marks the

    division between

    'ancient' and 'modern'

    philosophy.

    Hence Lucullus distinguishes the 'veteres' in Academica 11.13-15 - the

    subjects

    of the Academics'

    appeal,

    including

    the

    Presocratics as well

    as

    Socrates

    and Plato

    -

    from the 'moderns'

    in

    IL.16-18

    - those

    belonging

    to

    the

    period

    from Zeno and Arcesilaus

    to Philo and

    Antiochus. Two

    of

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    13/36

    THE NEW

    ACADEMY'S APPEALS TO

    THE PRESOCRATICS

    49

    Lucullus's criticisms of the Academic appeal rely on further distinctions

    of sub-periods within these major

    divisions.

    For in

    II.15

    he criticizes

    Arcesilaus's appeal,

    in

    particular,

    for

    ignoring

    the fact that

    philosophy

    had

    moved

    on since the hesitant first

    steps

    of the natural

    philosophers:

    Plato

    had subsequently established

    a

    'discipline'

    of

    philosophy,

    that

    is,

    the

    sys-

    tematic doctrines

    of the

    Old

    Academy

    and

    Peripatos. Then,

    in

    11.16-18,

    he criticizes Cicero's use of the Academic appeal for ignoring the fur-

    ther developments since Arcesilaus fought Zeno, presumably the sub-

    sequent

    defense of the Stoa

    by Chrysippus

    followed

    by Antipater

    and later

    Antiochus's own 'Academic' recension of Stoicism.'2 Thus Lucullus's pre-

    sentation

    of the Academic

    appeal

    is situated within his own view of

    the

    history of philosophy, which sees a progression from its hesitant birth with

    the Presocratics

    (11.14-15),

    its

    development by (Socrates and)

    Plato

    (11.15),

    and

    its

    maturity,beginning

    with Zeno

    (11.16)

    and

    culminating

    with Antiochus

    (11.17-18). On this view, the Academics' appeal to the Presocratics is quite

    perverse (even

    if

    they

    were

    occasionally 'sceptical'

    in

    some sense).

    Cicero's historical claims in Academica 11.72-8 are a direct

    response

    not

    just

    to Lucullus's

    charge

    of

    disingenuousness

    but also to his

    view

    of

    the history of philosophy. His reply to Lucullus's criticism of Arcesilaus

    shows that the Academic position in this edition of the Academica also

    relied on a

    developmental view of history. For in 11.76-7, after the review

    of the Presocratics'

    sceptical tendencies that comprises the bulk of his

    reply

    to

    Lucullus's

    initial

    charge, he responds to the particular criticism

    by noting

    that it is unclear how much

    philosophical progress has actually

    been

    made, except

    in

    one vital

    respect: Zeno,

    unlike all his

    predecessors,

    had correctly seen that the wise cannot hold opinions.'3 Furthermore, as

    2

    Acad. 11.15:nonne cum iam philosophorumdisciplinae gravissimae constitissent

    tum

    exortus est. . . Arcesilas

    qui

    constitutamphilosophiam everteret et in eorum auc-

    toritate delitisceretqui negavissent

    quicquam

    sciri aut

    percipi posse.

    11. 6: Sed

    fuerint

    illa vetera si voltis

    incognita:

    nihilne est igitur actum, quod investigata

    sunt, postea

    quam Arcesilas

    Zenoni ut putatur obtrectans ..

    conatus est clarissimis rebus tenebras

    obducere. These

    passages show,

    moreover, that there is solid evidence for

    taking

    Arcesilaus himself

    to have introducedthe appeal to

    the Presocratics(i.e., his name is

    not

    just

    a

    metonym

    for 'the

    Academics').

    1'

    Acad. II.77:

    nemo umquam uperiorumnon

    modo expresserat sed ne dixerat qui-

    dem

    posse

    hominem

    nihil opinari,

    nec solum posse sed ita necesse esse

    sapienti. visa

    est Arcesilae cum vera sententia

    tum

    honesta et

    digna sapienti.

    Holding

    no

    opinions

    implies suspendingjudgement universally for Arcesilaus and Cicero, of course, since

    they maintain

    akatalepsia.

    Cf. the discussion

    of Acad. 1.44-5 above

    and also Cicero's

    more Philonian ake

    on 'the most ancientand learned hinkers'at Acad.

    II.7:

    etsi

    enimom-

    nis

    cognitio

    multis est obstructa

    difficultatibuseaque est et in ipsis rebus obscuritas

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    14/36

    50

    CHARLES BRIT7AIN AND JOHN

    PALMER

    Cicero's reply to the second criticism (of his own use of the Presocratics,

    II.16-18) shows, on the

    Academic view, the progress in

    the history of phi-

    losophy culminates with

    Arcesilaus.'4 The claim that the

    Academic

    view

    of the

    history

    of

    philosophy

    centers on the radical change

    which

    occurred

    at the time of

    Arcesilaus (a

    distinction equivalent to

    Lucullus's between

    the ancients

    and moderns) does

    not,

    of

    course, get us very far. It does

    not

    seem to be

    stretching the evidence,

    however, to

    suggest that the Aca-

    demics

    saw

    Socrates and Plato

    (cf. II.74) as

    marking

    a

    major division

    within the

    earlier period. If

    so, the historical picture in the

    background of

    the Academica Priora had three stages, involving the Presocratics, then

    Socrates

    and

    Plato, and

    finally the modem period from

    Arcesilaus. It now

    seems

    likely that

    we can identify the point of this

    philosophical history

    by combining the

    notion of a progression

    culminating

    in Arcesilaus's embrace

    of the

    suspension

    of

    judgement (on

    the

    basis

    of

    the

    akatalepsia

    thesis and

    Zeno's novel

    thesis that the wise cannot hold

    opinions)

    with the philo-

    sophical interpretation of

    the Presocratics as dogmatic

    sceptics (whose

    support for akatalepsia relies on

    theories about

    the

    nature

    of things).

    For

    we can now

    discern a

    progression from dogmatic

    scepticism, through the

    more reflective (and methodological) scepticism of Socrates and Plato, to

    the radical

    scepticism of Arcesilaus.

    This allows

    us to

    make better sense

    of the

    general

    claim

    involved

    in

    the Academics'

    appeal

    to

    the Presocratics:

    far from

    being

    an

    implausible claim of

    identity,

    it

    is

    the measured and

    respectable

    view of the

    history

    of

    philosophy given

    explicitly

    in

    Aeade-

    mica 1.44-5.

    Can we now be more

    precise

    about

    why

    the Academics made their

    gen-

    eral

    appeal

    to the Presocratics in the first

    place, especially

    if

    they

    did not

    claim

    that those

    philosophers

    furnished a direct

    precedent

    for their

    own

    views? Not immediately, since, as for the history at 1.44-5, both dialecti-

    cal and

    non-dialectical

    readings

    of the

    general appeal

    are

    available.

    But

    in the case

    of

    the Academica Priora we have some context

    against

    which

    to situate the

    general appeal:

    the Academics'

    specific appeals

    to individ-

    ual

    Presocratics.

    Since these

    appeals

    show that the Academics' under-

    standing of the Presocratics is more

    complex

    than the

    general

    claim

    et in iudiciis nostris infirmitas,ut non

    sine

    causa

    antiquissimi et

    doctissiml

    invenire

    se posse

    quod

    cuperent

    diffisi

    sint, tamennec illi defeceruntneque nos studium xquirendi

    defatigati relinquemus.

    14

    In Acad. 11.78,Cicero points out that, althoughsome sceptical Academics thought

    that there had been

    a

    significant change since

    Arcesilaus over the

    question

    of

    sus-

    pension

    of

    judgement,

    the basic

    controversy

    with the Stoics remained the same: it was

    still about

    akatalepsia.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    15/36

    THE NEW

    ACADEMY'S APPEALS TO THE

    PRESOCRATICS

    51

    (expressed in Cicero's initial response to Lucullus) suggests, it will be best

    to

    return

    to the

    question of which

    reading of

    that claim is

    preferable after

    examining

    its

    context. For it turns out

    that the Academic

    appeals were not

    always

    offered in

    terms of a collective

    interpretation of the

    Presocratics,

    that their

    appeals

    may

    not have even been

    based on

    general

    interpreta-

    tions of the

    individual

    figures,

    that

    they

    did

    not

    always

    make the same

    appeal to each

    figure,

    and that

    they

    did

    not even claim

    that

    all of them

    were

    sceptical

    in any

    sense. We

    shall follow

    Cicero's

    order in

    Academica

    I1.72-4

    and

    treat in turn

    Anaxagoras,

    Democritus,

    Empedocles, and

    Xenophanes and Parmenides.

    2.

    Anaxagoras

    'Anaxagoras said

    snow is black.

    Would you tolerate me if I

    were to

    say

    the same

    thing? You would not if I

    were even to wonder

    whether it is so.

    Yet

    who is this man?

    Surely no sophist

    (this is what

    people

    who

    prac-

    ticed

    philosophy

    for the sake

    of show or

    profit

    used to

    be called).

    He was

    a man with the

    greatest

    reputation for seriousness

    and

    intellectual

    ability'

    (Acad.

    II.72). Cicero

    clearly does not mean to

    identify

    Anaxagoras's

    asser-

    tion that snow is in reality black

    (given

    that

    water, from which snow

    is

    formed,

    is

    black)

    as

    something the

    Academics

    themselves endorse. It is

    not

    clear that

    Anaxagoras

    is

    represented as

    'sceptical' in

    any

    sense here:

    if he

    doubts the

    reliability

    of

    the

    senses,

    it is

    only

    because he has

    certain

    beliefs about

    how

    things

    are in

    reality.

    Cicero's

    point is that his

    Antio-

    chian

    opponent

    will

    not tolerate an

    appeal

    to a

    universally

    recognized

    au-

    thority like

    Anaxagoras's

    to call into doubt whether snow is in fact

    white.

    The

    strategy

    here is similar

    to that of Sextus

    Empiricus

    when he cites

    Anaxagoras's

    argument

    (that since snow is frozen

    water,

    and water is

    black, snow is therefore black) as something the sceptic may appeal to in

    opposing nooumena to

    phainomena

    (PH

    1.33).

    Cicero

    reports

    that,

    when

    asked whether snow is

    white

    (something which

    might

    seem

    quite

    obvi-

    ously

    the

    case),

    the

    Academic will

    not

    go

    so far as

    Anaxagoras

    and

    deny

    the

    phainomena.

    The Academic

    is

    willing, however, to

    point

    out how

    Anaxagoras's

    dogmatic

    theory

    about the

    nature

    of

    things

    led him to

    deny

    the

    phainomena, and the Academic

    takes this to

    support

    his own unwill-

    ingness

    to

    make

    any

    positive assertion

    regarding the actual character of

    things

    on the

    basis of how

    they appear. We

    might

    call this

    a

    defensive

    '5 Cf. De

    orat.

    III.138,

    Clazomenius ille

    Anaxagoras,

    vir

    summus in maximarum

    rerum

    scientia.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    16/36

    52

    CHARLES BRITTAIN

    AND JOHN PALMER

    appeal to Anaxagoras: when confronted by his opponents with the pur-

    ported absurdity

    of withholding

    assent

    on

    the most obvious

    matters,

    the

    Academic

    introduces a

    figure

    whose authority

    his opponents

    acknowledge

    and who

    goes even

    farther than

    he himself

    is willing to in opposing

    what

    is supposedly so

    obvious.

    The appeal thus

    serves

    in a somewhat

    indirect

    way

    the Academics'

    general position

    that the senses

    do not furnish

    a

    cri-

    terion

    of

    truth.

    With the

    subsequent

    appeal

    to Anaxagoras

    at Academica

    11.100

    the

    Academics go

    on the offensive against

    their dogmatic

    opponents.

    The

    con-

    text is the Academic response to the Stoic apraxia argument. Cicero says

    at 11.98-9 that

    he will draw upon the

    first of Clitomachus's four books

    on

    the means of

    withholding

    assent (de sustinendis

    adsensionibus)

    to clarify

    Carneades's view

    of the differenttypes of

    impressions.

    Carneades

    is

    reported

    to have identified

    two ways

    of classifying

    impressions:

    (i)

    as either cogni-

    tive or non-cognitive

    (quae percipi

    possint

    &

    quae

    percipi

    non

    possint

    =

    KOxtaXlnnllrKaCi

    &KCTaUqxirot),

    nd

    (ii)

    as either plausible

    or implausible

    (probabilia

    & non probahilia

    =

    m0avai

    & ai9Oavot).

    The former repre-

    sents the basic Stoic classification,

    while the

    latter

    is Carneades's alter-

    native. He rejected the existence of cognitive impressions on the grounds

    that, contrary

    to the claims

    of the

    Stoics,

    there

    is no

    impression

    of

    such

    a character that it is

    impossible

    for there

    to be a

    qualitatively

    identical

    impression

    that

    is

    nevertheless

    false. However,

    this does

    not mean that the

    sage

    will have no impressions

    to

    rely upon

    for

    guidance

    in the course

    of

    his

    life,

    for

    he

    is

    perfectly

    able to

    employ plausible

    impressions

    as a

    guide

    for

    living

    as

    long

    as

    nothing

    contradicts

    them. Cicero

    is

    likely

    still

    draw-

    ing

    upon

    Clitomachus 6

    when

    he introduces

    Anaxagoras

    to

    clarify

    the

    sense in which Carneades

    held that the sage

    would be able

    to

    rely

    upon

    such impressions as a guide: 'he will draw his deliberations regardingboth

    action and

    inaction

    from

    impressions

    of this

    type,

    and he will be

    more

    amenable to accepting

    that

    snow is white than

    was

    Anaxagoras,

    who said

    not

    only

    that it was not white,

    but that it did not even appear

    to him to

    be

    white,

    because

    he knew that the

    water out of which

    it was solidified

    was

    black'

    (Acad.

    11.100).

    16

    Reid (1885),

    295, supposes

    that in Acad.

    11.99 Cicero

    is actually

    quoting from

    Clitomachusand that the quotation breaksoff with Etenimcontra nlaturam sset...,

    where Cicero

    resumes speaking

    in his

    own voice.

    It is

    not as clear

    as Reid supposes,

    however,

    that Cicero's

    use

    of Clitomachus

    amounts

    to

    simple quotation;

    and

    there

    seems no

    good reason

    to deny that

    what

    follows regarding

    the use Carneades

    made

    of the

    distinction

    between types

    of impressions

    continues

    to

    depend upon

    Clitomachus.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    17/36

    THE

    NEW

    ACADEMY'S

    APPEALS

    TO THE PRESOCRATICS

    53

    The Academic, that is, does not claim to know whether snow is really

    white or

    black,

    but he does

    grant

    that it appears

    white and claims

    that

    plausible

    impressions

    of this

    type

    furnish

    him with a

    reliable

    enough

    cri-

    terion

    for action.

    Although

    'he does not endorse Anaxagoras's

    argument

    for its being

    in

    reality

    black, he is nevertheless

    willing

    to

    appeal

    to

    this

    argument to

    call into

    question

    whether

    snow really

    is

    as

    it appears

    to

    us

    or perhaps

    has some

    other,

    non-apparent

    character.

    So much

    is already

    implied in the initial

    citation of Anaxagoras

    at

    11.72. The renewed

    appeal

    at

    11.100,

    however, goes

    farther than

    this so as to present

    a

    special

    chal-

    lenge to the Stoic (or any other dogmatist) who is prepared to allow

    his dogmatic, theoretical

    beliefs to undermine

    his reliance upon appear-

    ances. Here the

    Academics

    assimilate the dogmatic

    Stoics to the dogmatic

    Anaxagoras

    in

    such

    a

    way

    that their apraxia

    argument

    redounds

    against

    them. In allowing

    his theoretical beliefs to

    undermine his reliance

    upon

    appearances,

    Anaxagoras

    left himself without

    a viable criterion

    of

    action

    in

    many cases,

    both in

    so far as

    he would have

    fallen into

    apparent

    error

    if he

    had

    attempted

    to

    rely

    upon his dogmatic

    view of things

    as a

    guide

    and

    in so far as he would

    have had

    no

    guide

    at all

    in

    cases

    where he

    admitted his inability to access the real nature of things. This seems clear

    enough

    in the case of Anaxagoras's

    declaration

    that because he

    knows

    that snow is really black,

    it no

    longer

    even appears to

    him white. But such

    also seems to be the point being

    made against

    the equally

    dogmatic Stoics

    when Carneades

    argues

    that even

    the Stoic sage

    will have to

    rely

    in

    many

    cases

    upon probabilia

    when cataleptic impressions

    are unavailable (Acad.

    11.99).

    Thus the first

    thinker on

    Cicero's

    list is a Presocratic

    predecessor

    who is

    not in fact presented

    as a direct

    ancestor.

    It is not

    entirely clear

    that

    Anaxagoras

    is

    supposed

    to be a

    sceptical

    ancestor

    at all. At least when

    we come to the second passage which makes use of his denial that snow

    is

    white,

    his view seems to serve more

    as an

    embarrassing

    parallel

    to the

    unreasonable

    dogmatism

    of the Stoics than as a

    sceptical precedent.

    3. Democritus

    Cicero turns next

    to

    Democritus: 'What should

    I

    say

    about

    Democritus?

    Whom can we

    compare,

    for

    magnitude

    of

    spirit

    as well as

    intellect,

    with

    this man

    who was bold

    enough

    to

    commence with the

    words,

    These

    things

    I

    declare

    concerning

    the universe ?'7

    He

    exempts

    no

    subject

    from

    1

    Haec loquor

    de

    universis. Cf. Democr. ap.

    S.E.

    M. VII.265 = 68B 165

    DK: AfljO6K-

    ptto;

    &

    E

    j

    TA

    6

    ;wvj

    itap&tKaC6pvoa

    ;

    I

    kXyOv

    Tcz8E nEpi

    TdV

    4tugaVTOwV....

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    18/36

    54

    CHARLES BRIUIAIN AND

    JOHN

    PALMER

    discussion, or what cantherebe outsidethe universe?Who does notplace

    this philosopherabove

    Cleanthes,Chrysippus, nd the others of the later

    age,

    who seem to me

    to belong to the fifth class when comparedwith

    him? And yet he does not say what we do, who do not deny that there s

    any truthbut do deny that it can be apprehended.He denies outright hat

    there is anything true, and he does not say that the senses are dim

    (obscuros) but dark (tenebricosos)

    -

    for so he calls them' (Acad. I1.73).18

    With Democritus,as

    with Anaxagoras,partof the Academics' strategy s

    to appeal to a figure

    whose philosophical eriousness

    s

    acknowledgedby

    their Stoic opponents.Democritus s represented s more radicallyscep-

    tical than

    the

    Academics

    themselves,

    and

    the

    particular ppeal

    to him is

    in

    the first place a defensive manoeuverdesignedto force theiropponents

    to admit thattheirown

    more

    moderate

    position

    is also

    respectable.

    The

    appeal

    to

    authority,

    herefore,

    has a

    largely

    dialectical

    force.

    It also

    provides

    the Academics an

    opportunity

    o

    clarify

    their own

    stance

    by contrasting

    t

    with a

    dogmatic

    brand

    of

    scepticism

    with which

    it was in danger of being confused. Rather han introducingDemocritus

    as

    a direct precursor,Cicero states

    plainly

    that 'he does

    not

    say

    what

    we

    do'. What exactly, then, is the positionascribedto Democritusand on

    what basis? Here one

    needs to compareAcademica11.73with the appeal

    to Democritus

    reportedby Lucullus

    at

    11.32.

    Lucullus

    says

    thatdifferent

    Academicsgive different

    esponses

    o the

    objection

    hat

    if

    their

    arguments

    are

    true,

    then all

    things

    will

    be

    uncertainomnia

    ncerta

    =

    irrzvta 18ka).)9

    To this charge,he says, some membersof the Academyreply, 'Whatdoes

    that matter

    o us?

    Is it our

    fault?

    Blame

    nature,which,

    as

    Democritus

    ays,

    has completelyhidden

    truth in an

    abyss'.

    He

    proceeds

    to contrast

    this

    response

    with

    the more

    refined

    response

    of other

    Academics

    who intro-

    duce a distinctionbetween what is incertumor nonevidentand what is

    non-cognitive.

    The identification

    f

    the

    figures

    alluded o

    here has

    proved

    unnecessarily ontroversial.20iven that

    Lucullus

    himself

    has said

    that

    he

    18

    Cf. the passage from Democritus'sCanons

    contrasting

    he 'genuine' cognition

    of

    reason with

    the

    omcoiul

    r 'dark' cognitionof the

    senses (Democr.ap. S.E. M. VII.138-9

    -68Bl1

    DK).

    19

    Cf. Acad. 11.54:Ea dico

    incerta, quae

    oar5xa

    Graeci.

    20

    For a review of the various

    positions on the problem, see

    J. Allen, 'Carneadean

    argument in Cicero's Academic Books', in Inwood and Mansfeld (1997), 217-56, at

    238-9 n.

    21. A. A. Long and D. N. Sedley,

    The Hellenistic

    Philosophers, 2 vols.

    (Cambridge:Cambridge

    University

    Press, 1987), ii, 441, incline

    towards identifying

    this first group

    of 'hard-line Academics' with 'philosophers

    like

    Aenesidemus'.

    But

    Cicero

    nowhere

    mentions Aenesidemus or shows

    any familiaritywith the Pyrrhonian

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    19/36

    THE

    NEW

    ACADEMY'S APPEALS TO

    THE

    PRESOCRATICS

    55

    will dealwith the scepticismof Arcesilausand Carneades Acad.11.1 -12),

    the

    most

    straightforwardption

    is to attribute

    he

    appeal

    to

    Democritus

    o

    Arcesilaus and the more

    refined

    response

    to

    Carneades.

    A

    parallel

    pas-

    sage in

    Numenius,

    drawing

    irtually he

    same

    distinction

    etween

    Arcesilaus

    and

    Carneades

    as Lucullusdraws between

    the

    two classes

    of

    Academics,

    confirms his dentification:

    After

    hese[sc. LacydesandEuander]

    Carneades

    inherited

    he

    school

    and

    established

    he

    Third

    Academy.

    He

    employed

    the

    manner

    of

    argumentation

    hat

    Arcesilaus

    had,

    for he too

    used

    to

    practice

    dialectical reasoning

    and demolish

    the

    statements

    of

    others.

    He

    differed

    from him only in his accountconcerningsuspensionof judgement,say-

    ing

    that

    it is impossible for a

    human being to suspend udgementabout

    everything,

    ut

    hat

    here

    s a difference etween

    what

    s

    non-evident

    a`kXov)

    and

    what is

    non-cognitive (docatacXnrVov),

    and that

    all

    things

    are

    non-cog-

    nitive, but not

    all

    things are non-evident'

    Numen.ap. Eus.

    PE

    XIV.7.15).

    The

    Stoics

    claim

    that the Academics' argumentsagainst the

    criterion

    makelife unlivableandrob us of the naturalactivity of our mind (Acad.

    I1.31). When

    faced with

    the

    charge that this renderseverythingnon-evi-

    dent, Arcesilaus makes

    what

    again appears

    to

    be

    a

    largely

    dialectical

    appealto Democritus.Arcesilaus finds himself in the positionof being

    unable

    to

    judge

    whether

    he

    impressions

    he

    has of

    things

    are

    true or

    false.

    The

    Stoics,

    by contrast,

    feel

    that

    they are

    in

    a

    position

    to

    make such

    judgements,

    and

    they provide

    an elaborateaccount

    of how we

    are put

    in

    contact with

    the

    truth

    of things. Arcesilaus himself has no particular

    account

    to give

    of

    why he

    finds

    himself in the position he does.

    He is

    willing, however, to introduceDemocritus as someone

    who

    appears

    to

    agree

    with

    him

    about

    things

    being

    non-evidentand

    who

    does

    have some

    explanation

    of

    why

    this should

    be the

    case.

    Arcesilausappearsto

    take

    Democritus'sdeclaration hat 'we in realityknow nothing,for truth s in

    an

    abyss' (68B117 DK)

    as

    indicating

    hat there is

    such a

    greatdistance,

    if not

    necessarily

    otal

    separation,

    between our impressions

    of

    things

    and

    their

    real

    nature hat

    we can

    never

    rely upon

    our

    ordinaryexperience

    of

    things

    to

    put

    us

    in

    contact with the

    truth.Democritus hus

    has

    positive

    views

    (however qualified)

    about

    the

    real

    nature

    of

    things

    which lead

    him

    revival. (He

    does

    once

    mention

    'Pyrrhonei'

    at De orat. III.62, but there

    he

    classes

    them togetherwith the Eretrians,Erillians,and Megariansas now extinct schools that

    once claimed

    to

    be upholding

    the

    Socratic legacy.)

    Long and Sedley also identify Philo

    and his followers as the Academics with the more refined

    response. Allen, 218-19 and

    237ff., tentatively suggests that

    all

    the views espoused

    in Acad. 11.32-4 should be at-

    tributed

    o

    Carneades

    himself.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.9.8 on Sat, 21 Feb 2015 23:03:03 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Brittain, Charles, And John Palmer_The New Academy's Appeals to the Presocratics_Phronesis, 46, 1_2001!38!72

    20/36

    56 CHARLES BRITTAIN AND JOHN

    PALMER

    to adopta dogmaticscepticismregarding ppearances.Arcesilaus s will-

    ing

    to

    appeal

    to

    Democritus

    as if

    to say

    to

    the Stoics, 'Don't ask me why

    things are like

    this -

    ask Democritus';and yet he wants to maintain he

    requisitedistance between his own non-dogmatic nd Democritus'sdog-

    matic scepticism. This distinction is not as apparentas it might be in

    Academica 11.32,perhapsbecause the hostile Lucullus is not especially

    interested n keeping it clear;

    but,

    as noted, care is taken to preserve he

    distinction n 11.73.

    Comparing

    he

    two passagespresentsa problem,however,since on the

    face of it they creditDemocrituswithratherdifferentpositions:Academica

    11.32attributeso him the view that naturehas hiddenthe truth rom us,

    whereas n 11.73he is creditedwith what seems the strongerpositionthat

    there is

    nothing

    true

    (ille

    verum

    plane negat esse).

    A

    number

    of

    possible

    ways of dealing with

    this

    apparent ontradiction uggest themselves.One

    option

    would be

    to

    suppose

    hatDemocritushimself said

    conflicting hings

    on

    the subjectand that differentpronouncements

    re

    reflected

    n

    our two

    passages.

    This

    would

    not

    be

    surprising,given

    how

    difficult t

    has

    often

    seemed

    o

    bring

    his various

    emarks

    n

    epistemology

    nto

    a coherentwhole.2'

    Alternatively, he two passages might possiblyreflectappealsby different

    membersof the

    Academy.22 t seems more likely, however,

    that the

    dif-

    ferencebetween

    the

    positions

    attributed

    o

    Democritus

    n the

    two

    passages

    is

    merely superficial.

    Here

    we need to get clearer about the Academics'

    view regarding he extent of Democritus's cepticism.Did they see it as

    extending merely to

    the

    reports

    of the

    senses

    or to

    both

    reason and

    the

    21

    Although we seem

    to

    have no fragment

    in

    which

    he

    goes so

    far as to declare

    that there

    is

    no truth, one should compare our two passages with one

    of

    Aristotle's

    remarkson Democritus n Metaphysicsr.5. There Aristotle reports hree types of argu-

    ment that certain thinkersemployed to demonstrate he impossibilityof deciding which

    among conflicting appearances

    should

    be

    judged true (1009a38-bl1). From

    its

    being

    unclear which of such appearancesare true and which false, these thinkers conclude

    that

    the

    one

    is

    no

    more

    true than

    the

    other but

    that

    both are equally true. Democritus

    is cited by Aristotle as having drawn the ratherdifferentconclusion that 'either noth-

    ing is true, or it is unclear to us

    (6to

    ATlgo.tptto6q

    e

    pnlaiv

    `-ot

    ouOcv

    ?ivai

    &xnloe;

    il

    11gtv

    y'

    a`81Xov)'

    1009bl

    1-12).