Benjamin - The Theory of Criticism

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/31/2019 Benjamin - The Theory of Criticism

    1/3

    The Theory of Criticism

    The unity of philosophy-its system-is, as an answer, of a higher orderthan the infinite number of finite questions that can be posed.1 It is of ahigher kind and a higher order than that to which the quintessence of allthese questions can lay claim, because a unity of the answer cannot beobtained through any questioning. The unity of philosophy therefore be-longs to a higher order than any single philosophical question or problemcan claim.-If there were questions that nevertheless called for a unifiedanswer, their relation to philosophy would be fundamentally different fromthat of philosophical problems generally. In responses to such problems,there is a constant tendency to ask further questions-a tendency that hasled to superficial talk to the effect that philosophy is an infinite task. Theyearning for a unity that cannot be arrived at by questions turns, in itsdisappointment, to the alternative that could be called a counterquestion.This counterquestion then pursues the lost unity of the question, or seeks asuperior question, which would simultaneously be a search for a unifiedanswer.-If such questions-questions that seek a unity--did exist, theanswers to them would permit neither further questioning nor counterques-tioning. But no such questions exist; the systemof philosophy as such cannotbe interrogated. And to this virtual question (which can be inferred onlyfrom the answer) there could obviously be only one answer: the system ofphilosophy itself. Nevertheless there are constructs that bear the deepestaffinity to philosophy, or rather to the ideal form of its problem, withoutconstituting philosophy themselves--even though they are not the answerto that hypothetical question, or hypothetical, or even the question. Theseconstructs, which are thus actual, not virtual, and are neither questions nor

  • 7/31/2019 Benjamin - The Theory of Criticism

    2/3

    218 The Theory of Criticismanswers, are works of art. Works of art do not compete with philosophy assuch. They do, however, enter into the profoundest relation with it throughtheir affinity to the ideal of its problem. The ideal of the philosophicalproblem is an idea that can be called an ideal, because it refers not to theimmanent form of the problem but to the transcendent content of itssolution, even though only through the concept of the problem and thusthrough the concept that it possesses a unified answer to the problem.According to a lawfulness that is probably grounded in the essence of theideal as such, the ideal of the philosophical problem can be represented onlyin a multiplicity (just as the ideal of pure content in art is to be found inthe plurality of the Muses). Therefore, the unity of philosophy can inprinciple be explored only in a plurality or multiplicity of virtual [this wordwas subsequently crossed out-Ed.] questions. This multiplicity lies im-mured in the multiplicity of true works of art, and their promotion is thebusiness of critique. What critique basically seeks to prove about a work ofart is the virtual possibility of the formulation of its contents as a philo-sophical problem, and what makes it call a halt-in awe, as it were, of thework of art itself, but equally in awe of philosophy-is the actual formula-tion of the problem. For critique arrives at its formulation on the assumption(which is never made good) that interrogating the philosophical system assuch is possible. In other words, critique asserts that, if the system werecomplete, it would turn out to have been interrogated during the investiga-tion of one problem or another. Critique makes the ideal of the philosophicalproblem manifest itself in a work of art, or enter into one of its manifesta-tions; if, however, critique wishes to speak of the work of art as such, it cansay only that the artwork symbolizes this ideal. The multiplicity of worksof art is harmonious, as the Romantics perceived, and, as the latter alsosuspected, this harmony does not stem from a vague principle peculiar toart and implicit in art alone. Rather, it arises from the fact that works ofart are ways in which the ideal of the philosophical problem makes itselfmanifest.

    When we assert that everything beautiful somehow relates to the true andthat its virtual place in philosophy is determinable, this means that a mani-festation of the ideal of the philosophical problem can be discovered in everywork of art. And we should add that such a manifestation may be assignedto every philosophical problem as its aura [Strahlenkreis], so to speak. Atevery point the hypothetical approach to the unity to be interrogated isavailable, and the work of art in which it is contained is therefore relatedto certain authentic philosophical problems, even though it may be preciselydistinguished from them.

    Corresponding to this manifestation of the true as well as of the individualtruth in the individual work of art is a further manifestation of the beautifulin the true. This is the manifestation of the coherent, harmonious totality

  • 7/31/2019 Benjamin - The Theory of Criticism

    3/3

    The Theory of Criticism 219of the beautiful in the unity of the true. Plato's Symposium, at its climax,deals' with this topic. Its message is that beauty achieves this virtual mani-festation only within the truth as a whole.

    What remains to be investigated is the common ground for these tworelations between art and philosophy.(The true: unity.The beautiful: multiplicity assembled into a totality.)(Perhaps there is a virtual relation between other realms, too. Can'tmorality appear virtually in freedom?)Comparison: Suppose you make the acquaintance of a young person whois handsome and attractive, but who seems to be harboring a secret. It wouldbe tactless and reprehensible to try to penetrate this secret and wrest it fromhim. But it is doubtless permissible to inquire whether he has any siblings,to see whether their nature could not perhaps explain somewhat the enig-matic character of the stranger. This is exactly how the true critic inquiresinto the siblings of the work of art. And every great work has its sibling(brother or sister?) in the realm of philosophy.Just as philosophy makes use of symbolic concepts to draw ethics andlanguage into the realm of theory, in the same way it is possible for theory(logic) to be incorporated into ethics and language in symbolic form. Wethen see the emergence of ethical and' aesthetic critique.Fragment written in 1919-1920; unpublished in Benjamin's lifetime.Translated by Rod-ney Livingstone.

    Notes1. Benjamin uses the term "criticism" (Kunstkritik: literally "art criticism") as the

    general designation for all criticism of literature, art, music, etc. In this text, aswell as in The Concept of Criticism in German Romanticism and "Goethe'sElective Affinities," the term "critique" (Kritik) usually designates a specific,philosophically informed aspect of criticism.- Trans.