Behavioural Economics - Week 1

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/13/2019 Behavioural Economics - Week 1

    1/3

    BE101x: Behavioural Economics in ActionUnit 1.3.3 The Axioms of Rational Choice

    DILIP SOMAN: Now when you push through the math behind this formulation-- andthe formulation behind something called the expected utility theory, which is the

    cornerstone of rational choice-- it turns out that there are a number of what we callaxioms that actually underlie this theory. I'm going to spend a few minutes goingthrough these axioms one by one.

    The first axiom is something called completeness. It says something very simple. Itsays that if I give you the choice between x and y, you should be able to do one ofthree things. You should be able to choose x over y, or y over x, or you should be

    perfectly indifferent between the two. But you cannot say, gee, I don't know, becausethe moment you say that, you are unable to compute a utility, and therefore you haveno basis for making a choice. So, rational choice theory says people have the ability tomaximize something called utility, and that completeness means they can either prefer

    x, or y, or both equally.

    The second is perhaps one of the more important axioms of choice, and it is calledtransitivity. It seems fairly obvious, but let's think through this for a minute.Transitivity says if I like x over y, and I like y over z, I should like x over z. It makes

    perfect sense. If I'm going to give you $50 versus $100, you're going to choose $100.If I'm going to give you $100 versus $200, you're going to choose $200. If I give you$200 versus $50, you should choose $200, no arguments.

    But it turns out that there are many situations in which transitivity is violated. Here'sone example. Let's imagine you're recruiting for a job. You're looking for an assistant,you're looking for a research assistant. Three people apply, Mr. A, Mr. B, Mr. C.You've got information on to attributes, the IQ and the number of years of experiencethey have in doing their job. What you see in this chart is that you've got three peoplewith IQs of 120, 110, and 100, but the one who has the highest IQ has only one year'sworth of experience, followed by two, followed by three.

    Now you also know from all of your years of being a professor or being a researcherthat, in fact, the IQ measure isn't very stable. And in fact, there's very little to choose

    between someone who has an IQ of 100 and 110 because the error on the scale isabout 10 or 15 points. And so the idea is very simple, is you really can't tell the

    difference between 100 and 110, but you can tell the difference between 100 and 120.So here's my rule. I want to choose the smartest guy, but if they're equally smart, thenI'm going to choose the one with the greater experience.

    How do I handle this choice? Again, I'm going to look at A, B, and C. If I look at Aversus B, A and B have about the same IQ. B has more experience than A. I'll chooseB.

    Likewise if I look at B versus C, about the same IQ. C has more experience than B. Ichoose C.

    So I choose B over A. I choose C over B. I should choose C over A. But if I have Cand A in the same room, now I know that A is smarter than C, and I will pick A.

  • 8/13/2019 Behavioural Economics - Week 1

    2/3

  • 8/13/2019 Behavioural Economics - Week 1

    3/3

    So in sum, there are four C's that drive rationality, but as we go through this course,we'll see that there are many other facets of rationality that tend to get violated overtime, and that's what makes human beings a fascinating set of people to study.