23
“AS BEFITS IT” Ethics and Humanism In Hans-Georg Gadamer’s 0

As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    2

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

“AS BEFITS IT”

Ethics and Humanism In

Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Hermeneutical Philosophy

0

Page 2: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

Andrew SchoutenPhilosophy 4200:

Advanced Topics in PhilosphyFinal Paper

Dr. Daniela Vallega-NeuDecember 16, 2003

A quick review of the history of moral philosophy shows an enduring concern amongst

its participants about how man should be in the world, but it quickly becomes clear that

philosophers are incapable, or do not seem inclined to correctly address the fundamental

questions that underlie the concrete situations of social and political life. Hans-Georg Gadamer

(1900-2002), thinks otherwise, and finds as a result of his formative philosophical encounter

with Aristotle’s ethics, that “the ways of thinking of philosophy” do address the entirety of our

practical lives, and while it cannot settle its fundamental issues, philosophy can help us to better

ask the questions we ourselves must ask as we take care in the world. In his philosophical

hermeneutics, Gadamer deploys from the co-terminal nature of understanding, interpretation and

application, an ethics of humanism that achieves expression as traditionary concepts in the

general repository of our language), which finds it fulfillment in phronesis (“moral knowledge”,

i.e., “ethical know-how”) a sense of what is appropriate for the necessary concretization of

“right” action within a particular situation.

In a short essay published in 1989 entitled On the Political Incompetence of Philosophers

Gadamer considered a commonly-held view of philosophers namely, that while they consider

every issue down to its ultimate generality, they remain woefully immature in relation to their

political and social reality. This unfortunate deficiency, Gadamer says, calls into question the

1

Page 3: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

nature of philosophic knowledge itself.1 Gadamer names two philosophers and discusses their

political mistakes, Plato’s tenure in Syracuse educating its future tyrant, Dionysius II, and Martin

Heidegger’s support for the Nazi regime. In the case of Plato, his latent Pythagoreanism caused

him to see that since morals and politics are changeable they were not genuine knowledge,2

Accordingly, Gadamer notes that Plato’s “Good” was nothing more than an empty generality.3

Thus, when Plato sought to teach the young tyrant his ideas on a just state and equitable ordering

of society, his ignorance of court politics eventually led to his imprisonment during two

successive tenures in Syracuse.4

As for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the

universe, a position afforded to him on the basis of his ability to reason. Instead, man was to be

seen more as a “shepherd of Being,” who in order to transcend to a higher understanding of

Being had to repudiate humanism.5 Thus we can follow Gadamer’s thinking that Heidegger

equated the chaos of the Weimar Republic to man’s ontological deficiency brought on by

modern technology, and seeing this within a grand sweep of human history, he saw a “much

needed, radically fresh start” in the events of 1933.6 In both cases, Plato and Heidegger

privileged a naïve supra-human Good/Being over human knowledge and for that reason, fell

victim to their own political immaturity and myopia. It would fall to their interpreters, Aristotle

and Gadamer, to circumscribe and rehabilitate their mentors’ intellectualisms while legitimizing

humanism, i.e. practical philosophy.7

1 Gadamer, H.G. “On the Political Incompetence of Philosophy”, Diogenes, Summer 1998 v46 il82.2 Gadamer, H.G. “The Ideal of Practical Philosophy” (1994), In J. Weinsheimer (Ed.), Praise of Theory, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1998, p. 51.3 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 312.4 Attributed to Diogenes Laertius, from Smillie, W.M., Plato: Life, Retrieved December 7, 2003, from Carroll College, Philosophy Department web site, http://web.carroll.edu/msmillie/bios/platobio.htm5 Grondin, J. “Gadamer on Humanism” (1992), The Philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer, Chicago: Open Court, 1997, p. 160.6 Gadamer, “On the Political Incompetence of Philosophy”, Diogenes, 1998. 7 C.f. Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 312, and Grondin. “Gadamer on Humanism”, p. 161.

2

Page 4: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

Gadamer himself acknowledges his relationship to Aristotle, when he observes that

“hermeneutic philosophy is the heir of the older tradition of practical philosophy whose chief

task is to justify this way of reason and defend practical and political reason against the

domination of technology based on science.”8 Practical philosophy like the human sciences

(Geisteeswissenschaften), concerns themselves with praxis – changeable, temporal issues, such

as politics, economics, and laws – such that “the purpose of practical philosophy is not

comprehension of the thing-in-itself but learning to how relate to things.”9 This begs the

question, how does hermeneutics teach us to relate to things?

Much like traditional hermeneutics, hermeneutic philosophy is grounded upon three

subtleties, subilitas intelligendi (understanding), subilitas explicandi (interpretation), and

subilitas applicandi (application). The term subilitas (subtlety) is itself significant, implying “a

sophisticated skill and distance from purely intellectual method.”10 Hermeneutics sees

understanding as being a primarily historical phenomenon; insofar as how understanding is

changed by historical momentum and demands a skilled interpretation in order for knowledge to

be applied to the current situation. Unlike its traditional counterpart, hermeneutic philosophy

sees these subtleties in a unitary fashion, i.e., they are inseparable.11 We can see this by turning

to the example of legal hermeneutics.

Within legal hermeneutics, the jurist is concerned with understanding the law in terms of

the present case, for the present case. For this to occur, the judge must concern himself with the

law itself, and its historical relevance within the continuity of the law from inception to the

8 Gadamer, Hermeneutics and Social Sciences, quoted in Bernstein, R.J. “From Hermeneutics to Praxis” (1982), In B.R. Wachterhauser (Ed.), Hermeneutics and Modern Philosophy, Albany: State University of New York Press, 1986, p. 88 (internal quotes omitted).9 Dobrosavljev, D. “Gadamer’s Hermeneutics as Practical Philosophy”, Facta Universitatis: Series Philosophy, Sociology and Psychology, vol. 2, No 9, 2002, p. 606.10 Ibid., p. 64.11 Gadamer, Truth and Method, pp. 307-308.

3

Page 5: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

current day.12 While Napoleonic and Common law systems differ somewhat on the vehicle of

continuity (codified statue vs. precedent), a law’s relevance can never be determined

dogmatically, i.e., it is never a circumstance of subsuming the particular under the universal.

Thus, a legal jurist is concerned with the historical origins of a law and the particular instances of

its application, only insofar as it enables him to interpret the significance of the law.13 By

coming-to-an-understanding on the law vis-à-vis a legal issue, he “concretize[s] the law in each

specific case – i.e., it is a work of application.”14

Deliberating on the sache lies at the heart of jursiprudence. We can see this in the

German word’s deep meaning, when it correspondence with the Roman legal concepts of both

res (thing) and causa (matter, or “issue before the court”). In the Roman tradition, the disputed

thing was placed between the litigating parties until a decision was reached regarding it, thus

symbolically ensuring that the proceeding abjured partiality toward either party. For the jurist,

this emphasis toward equity and away from arbitrariness is also repeated, not by physical

proximity to the item in question, but by limiting his findings to an interpretation of the law. 15

Unlike a silver-tongued advocate, both the jurist and the philosopher must “not try to argue the

other person down, but that one really considers the weight of the other’s opinion.”16 What is

presupposed here is that the interpreter, to gain a sense of the sache, must keep himself open to

what the law says, by asking questions, in a specific way.

This orientation toward openness is found in dialogue, and in the dialectical logic of

question and answer. When one asks a question, it means to bring the sache into the open;

12 Ibid., pp. 324-327.13 Ibid., p. 328.14 Ibid., p. 329 (original emphasis).15 Gadamer, “The Nature of Things and the Language of Things”, Philosophical Hermeneutics, trans. and ed. by Linge, D.E. (Berkeley: UC Press, 1976), p. 71.16 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 367.

4

Page 6: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

insofar as the answer is undetermined – the matter is not yet settled. What is gained through this

play is the “revealing [of] the questionability of what is questioned.”17 This is the art of

questioning, the dialectic of Plato: to place into the open the sache as well as all of its fluid

possibilities. As we saw earlier, for both legal and philosophical questions, the practice of

dialectic consists,

[N]ot in trying to discover the weakness of what is said, but in bringing out its real strength. It is not the arguing (which can make a strong case out of the weak one) but the art of thinking (which can strengthen objections by referring to the subject matter).

This strengthening, furthermore, occurs in the process of transforming what is said about the

sache in the dialectic into the “uppermost possibilities” of its truth, over and against attempts to

“limit its validity.”18 Moreover, conversations are more than mere arguments; they are also the

“forming of concepts” accomplished “through working out a common meaning”. By

participating in the give-and-take, question-and-answer of spoken dialogue in language, the

partners share in the production of meaning. Bringing the sache is to presence in language, is

precisely equivalent to finding the significance of the law in legal hermeneutics.19

For Gadamer, we find that language is a medium, one where substantive understanding

and agreement can take place between two people, as seen in the phenomenon of conversation.20

Language’s medial character comes from its inherent metaphoricity: metaphor (Meta-phrein)

means “to carry-over”, and it is through metaphorical transference that meaning arrives. Thus,

the focus of languages is what comes into meaning in verständigung (“shared-coming-to-an-

understanding”). Verständigung presupposes that language is itself, a life process in which the

community of life is lived out. 21

17 Ibid., p. 363.18 Ibid., pp. 367-368.19 Ibid., p. 368.20 Ibid., p. 384.21 Ibid., pp. 445-446

5

Page 7: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

On this point, Gadamer is in perfect correspondence with Aristotle, who classifies the

nature of man as the living being who has logos, i.e. language.22 Like animals, humans are able

to make themselves known to each other. Unlike animals, man has a variability of expression

within language, enabling him to speak about matters of fact, best exemplified by the world.

From this factualness in the relation of language and world, man is able to recognize, within his

relationship to the other, that the other is an independent other.23 Thus, we see that language is

not a system of representation, sign, and meaning, but a self-forgetting, communal, and all-

encompassing aspect of being; whose operation is not one of cognitive reference, but of

interpretation.24 For this reason linguistic fact has the value of truth – the basic correspondence

of knowledge to an object – which reveals to us the true being of things. Within this relationship,

objects are not simply objects; they bring themselves to expression in language,25 addressing us

as a Thou.

A relationship to the Thou implies, first and foremost, a moral position. Gadamer

compares and contrasts three such relations to the Thou. First, we can attempt to derive patterns

“human nature” from seemingly empirical observations on the behavior of other men, and

attempt to make predictions based on those observations, much like Rousseau attempted.26 Such

a view, according to Gadamer, is self-regarding and “contradicts the moral definition of man,”

ultimately reducing man to nothing more than a means for an end.27 Second, we can relate to the

22 Gadamer, H.-G., “Man and Language”, Philosophical Hermeneutics, p. 59.23 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 445.24 Gadamer, H.-G. “Man and Language”, Philosophical Hermeneutics (UC Press, 1976), trans. and ed. by Linge, D.E . pp. 64-66, 68.25 Gadamer, “The Nature of Things and the Language of Things”, Philosophical Hermeneutics, p. 77.26 This is easily seen in Rousseau’s polemics against the excessive dislocations caused by the Enlightenment. Rousseau contrasts the noble savages from “the warmer climes” with the northern people, who subject as they are to harsh conditions, “are easily irritated; everything that happens around them worries them,” and accounts for their violent nature; and thus reduces man to an ugly caricature for the sake of his argument, and his legacy of misanthropic environmentalism. Rousseau, J.J., Essay on the Origins of Langauge, trans. and ed. by Victor Gourevitch (New York: Harper & Row), p. 274.27 Gadamer, H.-G., Truth and Method, p. 358.

6

Page 8: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

Thou via a dialectic grounded in self-consciousness, much as Hegel and the Hegelian Left

attempted. Instead of speaking with one another, each effectively reflects himself out of their

relation as a means for self-recognition as well as mastery of the other, and in doing so, robs the

other’s claim to legitimacy.28 Although reflective philosophy also evidenced a “formal

superiority,” their claims were self-refuting as they inappropriately describe immediate relations

with analyses intrinsic to reflective activity. When combined with the denial of the other’s

legitimacy, theses self-refuting claims of reflective philosophy constituted the ultimate act of

philosophical self-abolition.29

The third way, however, points the way toward genuine human community. As found in

the dialogue, this is a comportment characterized by openness, and constitutes the universal task

of reaching out to the other person, whose result is “the actual relationship of men to each

other.”30 For Gadamer, this is the most important thing in human relations: to genuinely

experience the Thou as a Thou, and by strongly considering his claim, thereby come-into-

agreement with him.31 Hence, in coming-to-agreement man finds the common ground of his

kinship, i.e., the bonds of community that ground the relationships of praxis, i.e., social life,

political constitution, and economics,32 Gadamer emphasizes that within praxis, the ability to

come-to-agreement by virtue of the logos, is a kind of practical knowledge. Since it is performed

through social life, practical knowledge corresponds precisely to Aristotle’s phronesis. 33

Expressly developed in opposition to Plato’s “empty generalities” of the Good, Aristotle

restores the value of moral knowledge as an intrinsically humanly good in terms of human 28 Ibid., pp 359-360.29 Ibid., p. 344. After the conclusions of dialectical materialism (the result of the transformation of Hegelian thought into a political theory) failed to account for real transformation of the world, intellectuals within the Hegelian-left tradition became dogmatists, working to “reconcile” the world to the “formal supremacy” of their reflective theory, even as the adherents of Marxism robbed others (non-Marxists) of the legitimacy of their lives, rationalizing theft and mass-produced slaughter in the name of “social justice”. 30 Gadamer, “The Universality of the Hermeneutical Problem”, Philosophical Hermeneutics, p. 17.31 Ibid., p. 361 C.f. Risser J. “Shared Life”, Seattle University, 2003, pp. 5-7.32 Gadamer, H.-G., “Man and Language”, Philosophical Hermeneutics, p. 60.33 Risser J. “Shared Life”, p. 4.

7

Page 9: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

action. Differentiating between theoretical knowledge and moral knowledge, he finds in his

“moral sciences” (ethics) the need to answer what knowledge is proper to govern our action.34

Thus, ethics means precisely a combination of praxis and ethos.35 The philosophical issues

contained within ethics arise from the fact that the “person acting must view the concrete

situation in light of what is being asked of him in general.” Moreover, as seen in the cases of the

Plato, Heidegger, Rousseau, and Marx, these difficult methodological questions gain moral

relevance; especially when one considers that under these conditions a misreckoning of either the

concrete situation or of the general moral principles can obfuscate the sache with tragic

consequences.36 Finding that serious philosophical and moral questions arise from the

misunderstanding of ethics, we must now turn the raison d'être of its study: phronesis.

As the founder of philosophical ethics, Gadamer feels deeply indebted to Aristotle’s

architectonic treatment of phronesis. Of the latter’s achievements, Gadamer says,

“[He] succeeded, however, in rendering the nature of moral knowledge so clear that … is covers just as much the subjectivity of judges in the case of conflict as the substance of law and custom which determines its moral knowledge and its particular choices. His analysis of phronesis recognizes that moral knowledge is a way of moral being itself…”37

Through Gadamer’s reading of the Magna Moralia, as well as the Nichomachean and Eudemian

Ethics, we see that Aristotle defines phronesis in contradistinction to techne, as both seem to

indicate an art, a skill, i.e., a real knowledge of how to make something, involving the “same task

of application,” but they are , in fact, very distinct. Techne can be learned as well as forgotten,

phronesis, on the other hand, is not something that we can acquire. Instead, as we are always

34 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 314.35 Praxis: “Points to the totality of our practical life, all our human action and behavior, the self-adaptation of the human being as a whole in this world” and Ethos: “Living network of common convictions, habits, and values” from, Gadamer, “Practical Philosophy”, Gadamer in Conversation, , trans. and ed. Robert E. Palmer, by New Haven: Yale University Press, 2001.36 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 313.37 Gadamer, H.-G, “On the Possibility of a Philosophical Ethics” (1963), In J. Weinsheimer (Ed.), Hermeneutics, Religion, and Ethics, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999, pp. 28-29.

8

Page 10: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

already acting in the world, we “must already possess and be able to apply moral knowledge.” 38

This implies a fundamental distinction between techne and phronesis with regard to the

implementation of an intended plan toward the production of a artifact A craftsman possesses

the image of that which he wishes to craft, whereas “what is right … cannot be fully determined

of the situation that requires right action.” The images of what a man has of what he ought to be

namely, the virtues, are by no means absolutely determined. Aristotle advances a subtle

explication of natural law as a critical example to show that, even something like law which

prima facie, seems to exist in a perfect state, remains in a strained relationship with concrete

action, because it “cannot contain practical reality in its full concreteness” and, consequently

does not allow for a simple application of the law.39

Thus, in the case of a judge true wisdom in jurisprudence comes not from a strict, literal

application of the law, but an appropriate application of the schemata of the law, i.e., its

significance, proportionate to the concrete situation of the sache before him. It is the same with

moral principles (arche): they are “concretized only in the concrete situation of the person

acting.” They exhibit the character of convention, although the principles correspond to the

nature of the sache, even as the arche is determined by the use the moral consciousness makes of

them in each and every individual case.40 This entails the second fundamental aspect of

phronesis.

Unlike technical knowledge, which is particular and serves particular ends, phronesis has

no particular end, but instead, concerns itself with right living in general. And, although techne

does concern itself with particular ends, it is not mutually exclusive from moral knowledge, one

beginning where the other ends. We see this because the latter necessarily demands a “kind of

self-deliberation”, and as such, is not knowledge in the manner of a techne. There is no a priori 38 Ibid., p. 316.39 Ibid., pp. 317-318.40 Ibid., p. 320.

9

Page 11: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

knowledge of means and ends, and by virtue of the fact that right ends are not objects of

knowledge, they cannot be taught. Consequently, Aristotle’s theory of virtues discusses the

general forms of right action, as well as the knowledge that is guided by these forms in

actionable response to concrete situations; it is a “knowledge-for-the-sake-of-oneself.”41

Furthermore, in the act of deliberation of means – which is “itself a moral consideration” – the

“moral rightness of the end” is concretized. The application in phronesis necessarily employs

knowledge of a particular situation in order. Thus phronesis enjoins both means and end and

attests to the self-knowledge at its core: an experience (erfahrung) of the finitude of man namely,

that “all foresight is limited and all plans uncertain.”42

The realization that moral knowledge contains an experience of self-relation, confirms a

third aspect namely, that it has the ontic characteristic of “being-with-an-other.” Aristotle

acknowledges this by introducing phronesis’ correlate sunesis (sympathetic understanding),

which as a capacity for moral judgment, presupposes a relationship with other beings.

Unequivocally, this is the concretion of moral knowledge in a particular situation, which is

neither technical knowledge nor its application in the production of a good.43 Moral self-

knowledge, finds its acme in friendship, when, two people acknowledges themselves in the

other, and behave in a reciprocal manner with one another in accordance with commonly-held

forms of right action. This attests not to only to good will or disposition, but “a real embedding

in the texture of communal human life.”44

41 Ibid., pp. 321-322. Here Gadamer also notes that Aristotle’s definitions of phronesis have an element of uncertainty contained in them because, although he stresses that it is concerned with the means and not the ends, the capacity to determine the right means also sees the end toward which the human aims.42 Ibid., pp. 322, 357.43 Ibid., p. 323.44 Gadamer, H.G. “Friendship and Self-Knowledge: Reflections on the Role of Friendship in Greek Ethics” (1985), In J. Weinsheimer (Ed.), Hermeneutics, Religion, and Ethics, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999, p. 139.

10

Page 12: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

So then, what can we say is the proper ontology of ethos? As we can see from the

example of natural law, ethos has the characteristic of a natural, typical form.45 From Aristotle,

Gadamer sees three kinds of concepts: universal, general (née natural), and particular. Universal

concepts are like scientific concepts, standing forever; while particular concepts are specific to

one event. Gadamer distinguishes natural concept formation by its accidental quality: natural

concepts begin to take form when a person speaks, and are firmly situated within a particular

event, such that everything he says “acquires a share” in the particularity of the concrete

situation. This means that these linguistic concepts are essentially alive. Moreover, by virtue of

the fusing recombination of concept-bearing linguistic tradition and experience that further

informs these concepts; the results do greater justice to concrete situations than particular or

universal claims, as they are concretized into further actions in a way that universals and simple

particulars are not.46 To illustrate this, Aristotle uses the allegory of an army in flight – suddenly,

the army comes to “stand” just as general concepts do – much like ethos is born along in

tradition, i.e., the historical realization of these linguistic forms, that is always “coming to a

stand.”47

In his treatment of the Geisteeswissenschaften (human sciences) Gadamer advances an

outline for a contemporary curriculum based on linguistic concepts in tradition for the

development of phronesis, and its ultimate product the phronimos – “a person imbued with

practical wisdom who is able” to fuse both his own life-situation and the communal shared life.48

Part of this occurs via socialization, as “we integrate ourselves into society though education and

45 Gadamer, Truth and Method,46 Gadamer, Truth and Method, pp. 428-429.47 Gadamer, “The Universality of the Hermeneutical Problem”, Philosophical Hermeneutics, p. 17.48 McGee, M.C. Phronesis in the Habermas vs. Gadamer Debate. Retrieved 12/07/03, from (f)ragments, http://www.mcgees.net/fragments/essays/archives/Phronesis.in.the.Habermas.vs.Gadamer.Debate.htm

11

Page 13: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

the control exercised by life within the family,” and later on through language.49 But phronesis

is more fully developed in the moral-practical disciplines of the Geisteeswissenschaften, which

can help to “elucidate the distinctive type of knowledge and truth that is realized when we

authentically understand.”50

We can see this in his treatment of the “guiding concepts” of the humanist tradition

namely, Bildung, Sensus Comunus, Judgment, and Taste. 51 Their order is not accidental,

presupposing each other in their respective order from former to latter, even as they develop each

other in the opposite direction: bildung, a rough cognate of education, indicated a constant state

of cultivation with no goals outside itself;52 sensus comunus, i.e., common sense which connotes

a moral and ethical dimension;53 judgment, the sense of proper application;54 and taste, the true

sense– an immediate, yet sufficiently distant disposition-toward the common agreement – of a

community.55 Thus, the cultivation of the person in the Geisteeswissenschaften, perfectly echoes

the schemata of ethics, leading to what Balthasar Gracián called “un hombre en su punto”56 –

who is able to “evaluate the object in relation to a whole in order to see whether it fits in with

everything else – that is, whether it is fitting” – in other words, capable of interpretation.57

49 Gadamer, H.G. “On the Political Incompetence of Philosophy,” 1998. 50 Bernstein, R.J. “From Hermeneutics to Praxis” (1982), p. 88 (original emphasis).51 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 9.52 Ibid., p.13. Bildung is seen as the proper way of developing the whole self, leads to a character which can “reconcile itself with itself, to recognize oneself in other being. 53 Ibid., pp. 22-23. Sensus Communus is a synonym of phronesis, “an element of moral and social being,” devoted to the “common good”and living within a community.54 Ibid., p. 31. As we have seen, in its thematic operation in legal hermeneutics, judgment has no given principle to guide it, as is developed for concrete situations on a case-by-case basis.55 Ibid., p. 34. Also p. 38, from Gracián: “It follows that taste knows something—though admittedly in a way that cannot be separated from the concrete moment in which that object occurs and cannot be reduced to rules and concepts” Since it is concerned precisely with the evaluation of general, natural concepts, “taste is in no way limited to what is beautiful in nature and art, judging it in respect to its decorative quality, but embraces the whole realm of morality and manners.”56 This translates literally from Spanish as “Man at his peak”, akin to “pinnacle” and “acme”, signifying “excellence” and “mountain top”, and figuratively with the Greek phronimos.57 Ibid., 38 (internal quotes omitted).

12

Page 14: As Befits It -- Ethics and Humanism in Gadamer's ...  · Web viewAs for Heidegger, he wanted to call into question the centrality of the human being in the universe, a position afforded

In the final analysis, Aristotle’s ethics of mean and Gadamer’s hermeneutical philosophy

are “always hos dei or hos ho orhtos logos. What can be taught in the practice ethics is logos

also, but not akribes (precise) beyond a general outline. The decisive thing is finding the right

nuance.”58 To that end, ethics is concerned with three inseparable facets, the seamless

application in concrete situations of our understanding of the factuality of convictions, values,

and habits that we all share.59 The purpose of hermeneutics and the Geisteeswissenschaften alike

is the return of “practical philosophy to its ancient privilege of not merely recognizing the good,

but demanding it as well.”60 In this fashion as Aristotle once said, we may come to know what is

right, “as befits it.”61

58 Gadamer, Truth and Method, footnote p. 4059 Gadamer “The Ideal of Practical Philosophy”, Praise of Theory, 1998, p. 58.60 Gadamer, H.-G, “The Ethics of Value and Practical Philosophy” (1963), In J. Weinsheimer (Ed.), Hermeneutics, Religion, and Ethics, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999, p. 116.61 Gadamer, “On the Possibility of a Philosophical Ethics”, Hermeneutics, Religion, and Ethics, p.29.

13