1
BOOK REVIEW In Making Sense of Life, Evelyn Fox Keller enquires into what consti- tutes knowledge and explanatory theory in the biological sciences. In attempting to answer this vast question, Keller limits herself to the dis- cipline of developmental biology and the processes by which a fertil- ized egg grows and becomes patterned as one of the multitude of biological forms which we see around us today. Keller does not make any presumptions about what a suitable explanation is. Instead, she looks at a range of explanations of how an organism comes to be and then discusses whether these explanations are, or ever were, valid, and if so, why. Making Sense of Life is chronologically divided into three sections. In the first, Keller evaluates various mathematical and physical models that were used to explain development in the first half of the twentieth cen- tury. She examines Stephane Leduc’s attempt to explain the develop- ment of an organism by the synthesis of artificial organisms out of inorganic chemicals. She then evaluates D`Arcy Thompson’s On Growth and Form, which again aims to explain biological development by using only physical and chemical principles. Finally, Keller focuses on the his- tory of mathematical biology using Alan Turing’s model of embryogen- esis as an example. Keller is disappointed that mathematical biology has never caught on with biologists and questions why this is the case. In the second section, Keller looks at the role that experimental genetics has had in addressing biological development. Here the author argues that the process of constructing explanations of devel- opment from genetic data is primarily a ‘linguistic’ activity, in that it relies on the evolution of ‘novel metaphors’. Taking such terms as ‘gene action’, ‘genetic program’, ‘feedback’ and ‘positional information’, Keller claims that these ‘novel metaphors’ name phenomena about which very little is known and, thereby, inspire, help and focus researchers in a given field. In the final segment of her book, Keller evaluates the function of machines, particularly computers, recombinant DNA and molecular imaging, in the recent history of developmental biology. Using such examples as Eric Davidson’s model for the regulation of gene activity and Christopher Langton’s program of artificial life, Keller discusses what these new additions to the biologist’s tool kit have meant for con- temporary developmental biology. A primary theme of this book is that profound epistemological differences distinguish the theoretical and the experimental biolo- gist. To the experimental biologist of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, seeing was believing. This view contrasts with that of the mathematical biologist, for whom pure reasoning is what matters most. Now, with molecular imaging, belief in that direct observation has re-emerged. Keller’s thesis is that an explanation has value if it meets the needs of the people to whom it is explaining the given phenomenon. These needs will vary, depending on the attitudes, understanding and cul- ture present in that community at that time. My only criticism is that by limiting her enquiry to the field of development, with its particu- lar set of processes and mechanisms, she may not be taking into account very different epistemological goals or scientific methods that occur in other areas of biology. By extending her enquiry to mol- ecular or evolutionary biology, she might be able to make this con- clusion more secure. The author concludes that the natural world is so complex and diverse that biologists need a multiplicity of explanatory styles to even attempt to understand nature. This far, I agree. But Keller finds it diffi- cult to envision that natural selection could engineer a mental appara- tus that could understand the natural world. But surely an organism possessing a mental apparatus that could fully comprehend itself and everything around it would have a huge selective advantage. I admire Keller for the task that she undertakes with this book. The scientific explanations are set out clearly, their historical and cultural contexts explained in detail and their philosophical value discussed at length. Being a student of biology and not a fan of philosophy, how- ever, I found some of the discussions in this book far too exhaustive. If an explanation accurately and thoroughly explains a given process, that is good enough for me. The lengthy analysis of explanations of processes that have since been proven false, found in the first section of this book, were rather tiresome. The descriptions of the current explanations were of interest to me, and my understanding of these and of their predictive implications in developmental biology is cer- tainly now wider. This book is packed with developmental biology, and newcomers to this field might find it hard going. I feel that this focus limits the acces- sibility and breadth of appeal of the book, and ultimately it was not for me. But for those with a keen interest in the philosophy and history of science and some understanding of developmental biology, this book will be a rewarding read. Lynne M. Harris is at Balliol College, Oxford OX1 3BJ, UK. e-mail: [email protected] A rich biodiversity of explanations Making Sense of Life: Explaining Biological Development with Models, Metaphors, and Machines by Evelyn Fox Keller Harvard University Press, 2002 388 pp. paperback 2003, $17.95 ISBN 0-674-01250-X Reviewed by Lynne M Harris NATURE GENETICS VOLUME 36 | NUMBER 4 | APRIL 2004 317 © 2004 Nature Publishing Group http://www.nature.com/naturegenetics

A rich biodiversity of explanations

  • Upload
    lynne-m

  • View
    217

  • Download
    3

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: A rich biodiversity of explanations

B O O K R E V I E W

In Making Sense of Life, Evelyn Fox Keller enquires into what consti-tutes knowledge and explanatory theory in the biological sciences. Inattempting to answer this vast question, Keller limits herself to the dis-cipline of developmental biology and the processes by which a fertil-ized egg grows and becomes patterned as one of the multitude ofbiological forms which we see around us today. Keller does not makeany presumptions about what a suitable explanation is. Instead, shelooks at a range of explanations of how an organism comes to be andthen discusses whether these explanations are, or ever were, valid, andif so, why.

Making Sense of Life is chronologically divided into three sections. Inthe first, Keller evaluates various mathematical and physical models thatwere used to explain development in the first half of the twentieth cen-tury. She examines Stephane Leduc’s attempt to explain the develop-ment of an organism by the synthesis of artificial organisms out ofinorganic chemicals. She then evaluates D`Arcy Thompson’s On Growthand Form, which again aims to explain biological development by usingonly physical and chemical principles. Finally, Keller focuses on the his-tory of mathematical biology using Alan Turing’s model of embryogen-esis as an example. Keller is disappointed that mathematical biology hasnever caught on with biologists and questions why this is the case.

In the second section, Keller looks at the role that experimentalgenetics has had in addressing biological development. Here theauthor argues that the process of constructing explanations of devel-opment from genetic data is primarily a ‘linguistic’ activity, in that itrelies on the evolution of ‘novel metaphors’. Taking such terms as ‘geneaction’, ‘genetic program’, ‘feedback’ and ‘positional information’,Keller claims that these ‘novel metaphors’ name phenomena aboutwhich very little is known and, thereby, inspire, help and focusresearchers in a given field.

In the final segment of her book, Keller evaluates the function ofmachines, particularly computers, recombinant DNA and molecularimaging, in the recent history of developmental biology. Using suchexamples as Eric Davidson’s model for the regulation of gene activityand Christopher Langton’s program of artificial life, Keller discusseswhat these new additions to the biologist’s tool kit have meant for con-temporary developmental biology.

A primary theme of this book is that profound epistemologicaldifferences distinguish the theoretical and the experimental biolo-gist. To the experimental biologist of the eighteenth and nineteenthcenturies, seeing was believing. This view contrasts with that of themathematical biologist, for whom pure reasoning is what mattersmost. Now, with molecular imaging, belief in that direct observationhas re-emerged.

Keller’s thesis is that an explanation has value if it meets the needsof the people to whom it is explaining the given phenomenon. Theseneeds will vary, depending on the attitudes, understanding and cul-ture present in that community at that time. My only criticism is thatby limiting her enquiry to the field of development, with its particu-lar set of processes and mechanisms, she may not be taking intoaccount very different epistemological goals or scientific methodsthat occur in other areas of biology. By extending her enquiry to mol-ecular or evolutionary biology, she might be able to make this con-clusion more secure.

The author concludes that the natural world is so complex anddiverse that biologists need a multiplicity of explanatory styles to evenattempt to understand nature. This far, I agree. But Keller finds it diffi-cult to envision that natural selection could engineer a mental appara-tus that could understand the natural world. But surely an organismpossessing a mental apparatus that could fully comprehend itself andeverything around it would have a huge selective advantage.

I admire Keller for the task that she undertakes with this book. Thescientific explanations are set out clearly, their historical and culturalcontexts explained in detail and their philosophical value discussed atlength. Being a student of biology and not a fan of philosophy, how-ever, I found some of the discussions in this book far too exhaustive. Ifan explanation accurately and thoroughly explains a given process,that is good enough for me. The lengthy analysis of explanations ofprocesses that have since been proven false, found in the first sectionof this book, were rather tiresome. The descriptions of the currentexplanations were of interest to me, and my understanding of theseand of their predictive implications in developmental biology is cer-tainly now wider.

This book is packed with developmental biology, and newcomers tothis field might find it hard going. I feel that this focus limits the acces-sibility and breadth of appeal of the book, and ultimately it was not forme. But for those with a keen interest in the philosophy and history ofscience and some understanding of developmental biology, this bookwill be a rewarding read. �

Lynne M. Harris is at Balliol College, Oxford OX1 3BJ, UK.e-mail: [email protected]

A rich biodiversity of explanationsMaking Sense of Life:Explaining Biological Developmentwith Models, Metaphors,and Machines

by Evelyn Fox Keller

Harvard University Press, 2002388 pp. paperback 2003, $17.95ISBN 0-674-01250-X

Reviewed by Lynne M Harris

NATURE GENETICS VOLUME 36 | NUMBER 4 | APRIL 2004 317

©20

04 N

atur

e P

ublis

hing

Gro

up

http

://w

ww

.nat

ure.

com

/nat

ureg

enet

ics