9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    1/14

    MANAGEMENT SCIENCEVol. 50, No. 5, May 2004, pp. 561574issn 0025-1909 eissn 1526-5501 04 5005 0561

    informs

    doi10.1287/mnsc.1040.0243 2004 INFORMS

    Anniversary Article

    Decision Analysis in Management ScienceJames E. Smith

    Fuqua School of Business, Duke University, Durham, North Carolina 27708, [email protected]

    Detlof von WinterfeldtSchool of Policy, Planning, and Development, University of Southern California,

    Los Angeles, California 90089, [email protected]

    As part of the 50th anniversary of Management Science, the journal is publishing articles that reflect on thepast, present, and future of the various subfields the journal represents. In this article, we consider decisionanalysis research as it has appeared in Management Science. After reviewing the foundations of decision analysisand the history of the journals decision analysis department, we review a number of key developments in

    decision analysis research that have appeared in Management Science and offer some comments on the currentstate of the field.

    Key words : decision analysis; probability assessment; utility theory; game theory

    1. IntroductionManagement Science (MS) has played a distinguishedand distinctive role in the development of decisionanalysis. As part of Management Science, the deci-sion analysis department has focused on papers thatconsider the use of scientific methods to improvethe understanding or practice of managerial decisionmaking. The current departmental statement reads asfollows:

    The decision analysis department publishes articlesthat create, extend, or unify scientific knowledge per-taining to decision analysis and decision making. Weseek papers that describe concepts and techniques formodeling decisions as well as behaviorally orientedpapers that explain or evaluate decisions or judgments.Papers may develop new theory or methodology,address problems of implementation, present empiri-cal studies of choice behavior or decision modeling,synthesize existing ideas, or describe innovative appli-cations. In all cases, the papers must be based on sounddecision-theoretic and/or psychological principles

    Decision settings may consist of any combinationof certainty or uncertainty; competitive or noncom-petitive situations; individuals, groups, or markets;and applications may include managerial decisions in

    business or government.

    According to Hopps counts (Hopp 2004MS),1 Man-agement Science has published 590 decision analysispapers in the period from 1954 to 2003, accounting

    1 We highlight papers that have appeared in Management Science byincluding MS after the publication year in the in-text citation.

    for 12% of the papers in Management Science and17% of the most-cited papers (those receiving 50or more cites). However, given the interdisciplinarynature of the field, it is difficult to draw sharp bound-aries and determine precisely what counts as deci-sion analysis.

    Following Bell et al. (1988), we can distinguishamong three different perspectives in the study ofdecision making. In the normative perspective, thefocus is on rational choice and normative modelsare built on basic assumptions (or axioms) that peo-ple consider as providing logical guidance for theirdecisions. In the domain of decision making underrisk or uncertainty, the expected utility model of vonNeumann and Morgenstern (1944) and the subjec-tive expected utility model of Savage (1954) are thedominant normative models of rational choice. In thedomain of judgments and beliefs, probability theoryand Bayesian statistics, in particular, provide the nor-mative foundation.

    Thedescriptiveperspective focuses on how real peo-ple actually think and behave. Descriptive studiesmay develop mathematical models of behavior, butsuch models are judged by the extent to which theirpredictions correspond to the actual choices peoplemake. One of the most prominent descriptive modelsof decision making under uncertainty is the ProspectTheory model of Kahneman and Tversky (1979), laterrefined in Tversky and Kahneman (1992). This modelcaptures many of the ways in which people deviatefrom the normative ideal of the expected utility modelin a reasonably parsimonious form.

    561

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    2/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management Science562 Management Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS

    The prescriptiveperspective focuses on helping peo-ple make better decisions by using normative models,

    but with awareness of the limitations and descriptiverealities of human judgment. For example, we might

    build a mathematical model to help a firm decidewhether to undertake a particular R&D project. Such

    a model may not include all of the uncertainties,competitive effects, and sources of value that onemight expect a fully rational individual or firmto consider. It would likely include approximationsand short cuts that make the model easier to formu-late, assess, and solve. Descriptive research on deci-sion making would help the analysts understand,for example, which model inputs (e.g., probabilitiesor utilities) can be reliably assessed and how theseinputs might be biased. Prescriptive models are evalu-ated pragmatically: Do the decision makers find themhelpful? Or, what is more difficult to ascertain, dothey help people make better decisions?

    Decision analysis is primarily a prescriptive disci-pline, built on normative and descriptive foundations.In our review of decision analysis in ManagementScience, we emphasize its prescriptive role, but wealso discuss normative and descriptive developmentsthat have advanced prescriptive methodologies andapplications. We begin in 2 with the early history ofdecision analysis into the late 1960s when the deci-sion analysis department at Management Science wascreated. In 3, we discuss the history of the decisionanalysis department at Management Science, describ-ing the editorial structure from 1970 to the presentand reviewing the number of decision analysis arti-

    cles published. In 4, we discuss some of the decisionanalysis research that has been published in Manage-ment Science, focusing on developments in probabil-ity assessment (4.1), utility assessment (4.2), and ingame theory (4.3). In our discussion of the devel-opments of the field, we highlight specific develop-ments that have appeared in Management Science butdo not strive to discuss all of the decision analysisresearch that has appeared in the journal or decisionanalysis research published elsewhere. Our goal is togive a flavor of the decision analysis research that hasappeared in Management Science in its first 50 yearsand some of the debates that have influenced the

    field. In 5, we conclude and look ahead.

    2. The Early History of DecisionAnalysis2

    The normative foundations of decision analysis canbe traced back at least as far as Bernoulli (1738)

    2 More complete discussions of the early development of the (sub-jective) expected utility framework may be found in Arrow (1951a),Raiffa (1968), von Winterfeldt and Edwards (1986), Wakker (1989,2), and Fishburn and Wakker (1995MS).

    and Bayes (1763). Bernoulli was concerned with thefact that people generally do not follow the expectedvalue model when choosing among gambles, in par-ticular when buying insurance. He proposed theexpected utility model with a logarithmic utility func-tion to explain these deviations from the expected

    value model. Bayes was interested in the revisionof probability based on observations and proposedan updating procedure that is now known as BayesTheorem.

    Ramsey (1931) recognized that the notions of prob-ability and utility are intrinsically intertwined andshowed that subjective probabilities and utilitiescan be inferred from preferences among gambles.Ramseys essays did not have much influence whenthey were published but they are now much appre-ciated: INFORMSs Decision Analysis Society awardsthe Ramsey Medal to recognize and honor lifetimecontributions to the field. DeFinetti (1937) followed a

    similar path by developing a system of assumptionsabout preferences among gambles that allowed him toderive subjective probabilities for events. His interestwas primarily in the representations of beliefs as sub-

    jective probabilities, not in the derivation of utilities.The publication of the Theory of Games and Economic

    Behavior by von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944)attracted a great deal of attention and was a majormilestone in the history of decision analysis and eco-nomics. While the primary purpose of von Neumannand Morgensterns book was to lay the foundationfor the study of games, it also established the founda-tion for decision analysis in the process. Specifically,

    in an appendix to the second edition of the book (pub-lished in 1947) von Neumann and Morgenstern pro-vided an axiomatization of the expected utility model,showing that a cardinal utility function could be cre-ated from preferences among gambles. Their analy-sis took the probabilities in the decision problem asgiven and their axioms led to the conclusion that deci-sion makers should make decisions to maximize theirexpected utility. The decision-making framework ofvon Neumann and Morgenstern is now referred to asthe expected utility(EU) model.

    InThe Foundations of Statistics (Savage 1954), Savageextended von Neumann and Morgensterns expectedutility model to consider cases in which the prob-abilities are not given. While Savage was greatlyinfluenced by the work of von Neumann andMorgenstern, his background was in statistics ratherthan economics, and his goal was to provide a foun-dation for a a theory of probability based on the per-sonalistic view of probability derived mainly from thework of DeFinetti (1937) (Savage 1954, p. 5). Savageproposed a set of axioms about preferences amonggambles that enabled him to simultaneously derivethe existence of subjective probabilities for events

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    3/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management ScienceManagement Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS 563

    and utilities for outcomes, combining the ideas ofutility theory from economics and subjective proba-

    bility from statistics into what is now referred to asthe subjective expected utility (SEU) model.

    Although von Neumann and Morgensterns andSavages EU models have had an enormous impact

    on decision analysis and decision theory, not every-one found their axioms compelling. Allais (1953) pre-sented a now famous example where his preferencesand those of many others, including Savage himself,violated the axioms of utility theory. Savage (1954,pp. 100104) acknowledged the descriptive appeal ofAllais example, but did not concede the normativepoint, writing:

    A person who has tentatively accepted a normativetheory must consciously study situations in which thetheory seems to lead him astray; he must decide foreach by reflectiondeduction will typically be of littlerelevancewhether to retain his initial impression of

    the situation or to accept the implications of the theoryfor it. (Savage 1954, p. 102)

    Savage proposed an alternative way of viewingAllaiss problem that forced him to reconsider his ini-tial impressions in favor of the preferences prescribed

    by EU theory. Examples like these helped clarify thedistinction between the normative, descriptive, andprescriptive roles of the EU model in the 1950s.

    With von Neumann and Morgensterns andSavages utility models providing the normativefoundations, Edwardss The Theory of DecisionMaking (1954) launched the descriptive study ofdecision making as a new research area in psychol-

    ogy. In this paper Edwards surveyed utility con-cepts developed in economics and statistics andmade them accessible to psychologists. Other psy-chologists, including Clyde Coombs at the Universityof Michigan and Duncan Luce at Harvard, joinedEdwards (then at Hopkins, later at Michigan) in thestudy of behavioral decision making, taking the SEUframework as the gold standard or benchmark forcomparison and examining deviations from this ideal.Edwards and Coombs and their students at Michigan(including Sarah Lichtenstein, Larry Phillips, PaulSlovic, and Amos Tversky) studied biases and heuris-tics in judgment and decision making. For example,Edwards and Phillips studied Bayesian inference andfound that people tend to revise their opinion lessstrongly than prescribed by Bayes Theorem (Phillipsand Edwards 1966, Phillips et al. 1966). Other researchon probability biases and heuristics soon followed,spearheaded by Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman(for a summary, see Tversky and Kahneman 1974,Kahneman et al. 1982).

    The 1960s saw the emergence of decision analy-sis, building on the prescriptive power of the SEUmodel and Bayesian statistics. Howard Raiffa, Robert

    Schlaifer, and John Pratt at Harvard, and RonaldHoward at Stanford emerged as leaders in theseefforts. Schlaifer wrote Probability and Statistics forBusiness Decisions (Schlaifer 1959), which espousedBayesian, decision analytic principles for businessdecisions. Raiffa and Schlaifers Applied Statistical

    Decision Theory (1961) provided a detailed mathe-matical treatment of decision analysis focusing pri-marily on Bayesian statistical models. Pratt (1964)made major contributions to the theory of utility formoney, formalizing a measure of risk aversion, study-ing specific forms of utility functions, and consid-ering properties of certainty equivalents (the sellingprice for a risky investment) and the demand forrisky investments as related to this risk-aversion mea-sure. Pratt et al. (1964, 1965) and Howard (1965) pro-vided introductory expositions on statistical decisiontheory aimed at statistics and engineering audiences,respectively.

    Howard first used the term decision analysisin his paper Decision Analysis: Applied DecisionTheory (Howard 1966). Shortly thereafter, Howardpublished a paper The Foundations of DecisionAnalysis (Howard 1968) that laid out a process thathe called the decision analysis cycle for solvingdecision problems. Raiffas book Decision Analysis:Introductory Lectures (Raiffa 1968) provided a detailedand practically oriented introductory text which dis-cussed decision trees, the use of subjective probabil-ities, utility theory, and decision making by groups.About this same time, Howard and James Mathesonfounded the Decision Analysis Group at the Stanford

    Research Institute (later SRI International) which pro-vided decision-analysis-based management consult-ing. This group subsequently spawned many otherdecision analysis consulting firms including StrategicDecisions Group (founded by Howard, Matheson,Carl Spetzler, and others from SRI) and AppliedDecision Analysis.

    3. The Decision Analysis Departmentat Management Science

    In the early years of Management Science, there wereno formal editorial departments focusing on particu-

    lar subject areas and the journal published relativelylittle decision analysis research. When ManagementSciencefirst created departments in 1969, there was adecision theory department with H. O. Hartley serv-ing as department editor (DE). In March of 1970,the name of the department was changed to deci-sion analysis, which reflected the new terminologyadvocated by Howard (1966, 1968) and Raiffa (1968).Howard served as the DE from 1970 until 1981; RobertWinkler then served as DE from 1981 until 1989.In 1989, the decision analysis department adopted a

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    4/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management Science564 Management Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS

    Figure 1 History of Department Editors forManagement Sciences Decision Analysis Department

    1970 1975 1980 1985 1990 1995 2000 2005

    D. von Winterfeldt

    Decision Analysis

    Decision Analysis - Empirical and Behavioral

    Decision Analysis -Theory and Methodology

    J. E. SmithR.F. Nau

    R. A. Howard R. L. Winkler

    M. Weber

    R. T. ClemenI. H. Lavalle

    G. W. Fischer L. R. Keller

    two-DE editorial structure that remains in place today.In the current structure, one DE focuses on theoreti-cal and methodological research and the other focuseson behavioral or empirical research. While behav-ioral work on decision making had previously beenaccepted by the decision analysis department occa-sionally, the new structure explicitly consolidated nor-mative, descriptive, and prescriptive research in deci-sion analysis at Management Science. Prior to 1989,much of the descriptive research on decision making

    appeared in what was then called the organizationanalysis, performance, and design department, whichnow focuses more on organization theory and strat-egy. Similarly, work in game theory and forecastingand other aspects of decision analysis was handled bya department called planning, forecasting and appliedgame theory (or variations thereof), which was closedin 1990. The history of DEs for the decision analysisdepartment is summarized in Figure 1.

    As an interdisciplinary field, decision analysisresearch appears in a variety of different contextsand different academic journals. Operations Researchand the new INFORMS journal Decision Analysis are

    closest to Management Science in their perspective ondecision analysis research, but with more of a focuson applications. Interfaces publishes applications ofOR/MS and has included many decision analysisapplications papers.3 In addition, many other high-quality journals regularly publish decision analysisresearch: Organizational Behavior and Human DecisionProcesses, The Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, The

    Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, Theory and Decision,The Journal of Multi-Criteria Decision Analysis, as wellas journals focusing on particular problem areas, likeRisk Analysis or Medical Decision Making. Many psy-chology, economics, and statistics journals also pub-

    lish articles on decision making and decision theory.Despite the many available outlets, Management Sci-ence has arguably been the top journal for decisionanalysis research. Since 1990, INFORMS DecisionAnalysis Society (DAS) has given an annual publi-cation award recognizing the best decision analysispublication appearing in a given year; the publica-tion may be a book or an article appearing in any

    3 For a detailed discussion on publications of decision analysisapplications, see Corner and Kirkwood (1991) and Keefer et al.(2004).

    journal. Papers appearing inManagement Sciencehavereceived this award six times; three times the awardhas gone to books and five times to papers in other

    journals, withOperations Research (two awards) beingthe only other journal with more than one paper win-ning the DAS publication award. (A list of publicationaward winners may be found at www.informs.org.)

    The number of decision analysis papers publishedin Management Science over time is plotted in Fig-ures 2a and 2b, with the two plots corresponding to

    two different methods of counting. Figure 2a showsHopps (2004) counts, which were prepared by hav-ing a Ph.D. student review each article and place it ina category corresponding to one of Management Sci-ences current departments. Figure 2b was preparedusing the online journal archive JSTOR to find all

    Management Science articles that contained the wordsdecision analysis. The JSTOR database includesall Management Science articles from 19541999. Thepoints in the figures indicate the actual counts and thesolid lines represent five-year centered moving aver-ages of these counts. The differences in counts areeasy to explain: Many articles on decision analysismay not use this terminology, particularly before thelate 1960s when this term was popularized. Con-versely, not all articles that mention decision analy-sis are primarily about decision analysis. However,with either method of counting, the same general pic-ture emerges: Decision analysis research in Manage-ment Science grew substantially from the late-1960sinto the mid-1980s and has declined somewhat sincethen. We will return to consider these trends in theconcluding section (5) after discussing some specificexamples of decision analysis research published inthe journal.

    4. Decision Analysis Research inManagement Science

    In this section we survey some central themes indecision analysis as they have been developed in

    Management Science. As indicated in the introduction,our goal in this discussion is not to provide a compre-hensive review or history of these topics or of every-thing that has appeared in Management Science butto highlight some of the interesting research that has

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    5/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management ScienceManagement Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS 565

    Figure 2 The Number of Decision Analysis Articles inManagement Science

    Hopp's Counts

    0

    5

    10

    15

    20

    25

    30

    1954 1964 1974 1984 1994 2004

    NumberofA

    rticles

    JSTORHitson "DecisionAnalysis"

    0

    5

    10

    15

    20

    25

    30

    1954 1964 1974 1984 1994 2004

    NumberofArticles

    Note. The lines represent five-year centered moving averages of the counts.

    appeared in the journal. We highlight developmentsin the assessment of probabilities in 4.1, the assess-

    ment of utilities in 4.2, and game theory and com-petitive decision making in 4.3.

    4.1. Developments in Probability AssessmentAs discussed in 2, one of the foundations of decisionanalysis is the use of personal or subjective proba-

    bilities. This approach is Bayesian in that probabil-ities are interpreted as measures of an individuals

    beliefs rather than long-run frequencies to be esti-mated from data. One of the central challenges ofdecision analysis is reliably assessing probabilitiesfrom experts, taking into account the psychologicalheuristics that experts use in forming these judgments

    and the potential for biases.Early work on probability assessment was carried

    out by researchers in academia and consulting prac-tice. Spetzler and Stal von Holstein (1975MS) pro-vided an overview of the psychological and practicalissues associated with probability assessment, asunderstood at that time. They describe a probabilityassessment protocol that helps experts express theirknowledge clearly in probabilistic terms, while avoid-ing judgmental biases as much as possible. Thoughpsychological research since the 1970s has greatlyimproved our understanding of heuristics and biases,Spetzler and Stal von Holsteins protocols and varia-tions thereof are still widely used today. Wallsten andBudescu (1983MS) provided a comprehensive reviewof psychological and psychometric work related toprobability assessment. More recent work on proba-

    bility assessment in Management Science has focusedon decomposition (Ravinder et al. 1988MS, Howard1989MS) and the assessment of dependence relationsamong uncertainties (Moskowitz and Sarin 1983MS,Clemen et al. 2000MS).

    A related issue concerns the development of tech-niques for evaluating probabilistic forecasts and/or

    providing incentives for experts to provide their bestforecasts. This literature on scoring rules began

    in the domain of meteorology and statistics (seeMurphy and Winkler 1970 for an early review) butwas subsequently developed in Management Science.Matheson and Winkler (1976MS), Sarin and Winkler(1980MS), and Winkler (1994MS) further developedscoring rules, and Winkler and Poses (1993MS) eval-uated the accuracy of physicians assessments ofsurvival probabilities. In these studies, researchersdistinguish between the calibration of an expert (thecorrespondence between the stated probabilities andactual observed frequencies) and the resolution ofthe expert (the ability to distinguish and assign dif-ferent probabilities to different cases). It is possible

    for an expert to have good resolution and be poorlycalibrated or vice versa. Harrison (1977MS) showedhow uncertainty about the calibration of an expertcan cause significant practical difficulties in decisionanalysis by introducing dependence among eventsthat would otherwise (i.e., without miscalibration) beindependent.

    In many applications of decision analysis, the stakesare sufficiently large that a decision maker will seekthe opinions of several experts rather than rely solelyon the judgment of a single expert or on his or herown expertise. This then raises the question of how tocombine or aggregate these expert opinions to forma consensus distribution to be used in the decisionmodel. Management Science has been a central outletfor research in this area. Winkler (1968MS) was oneof the first to consider the problem and comparedweighted averages and a Bayesian approach basedon the use of natural conjugate distributions. Morris(1974MS, 1977MS) suggested the use of a Bayesianapproach in which the decision maker begins with aprior probability distribution on the event or quantityof interest, and treats the assessments provided by theexperts as observations that lead the decision maker

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    6/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management Science566 Management Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS

    to update his prior probabilities using Bayes rule.This is a normatively sound approach, but requiressome very difficult assessments: The decision makermust specify the probability that an expert will stateeach possible response, conditional on the true stateof the event or value of the uncertain quantity. With

    multiple experts, the decision maker must specify ajoint conditional distribution for all expert responsessimultaneously. Morris (1977MS, p. 687) described theconstruction of general models of expert dependenceone of the future challenges in the field of expertmodeling.

    Subsequent work on expert aggregation in Man-agement Science has focused on developing mod-els for structuring and simplifying the assessmentsrequired in this Bayesian approach. Winkler (1981MS)developed a model that considers dependence in theexperts errors, the differences between the expertsstated mean and the observed outcome. If the errors

    have a multivariate normal distribution with knowncovariance, the consensus distribution is a normaldistribution with a mean that is a linear combina-tion of the experts individual means with weightsreflecting the accuracy of and dependence among theexperts. This result is in contrast with the commonlyused linear opinion pools (see, e.g., Bacharach1975MS, DeGroot and Mortera 1991MS), which resultin a consensus distribution with a density that is aweighted average of the individual experts densi-ties; for example, a mixture of normal distributions.Clemen (1987MS) considered models of dependentexperts in which the experts share some information

    and showed how additional information provided tothe experts may confound the expert opinions andactually make a decision maker worse off.

    Morris (1983MS) proposed an axiomatic approachto the expert combination problem and generated agreat deal of discussion and controversy, includingcomments by Lindley (1986MS), Schervish (1986MS),Clemen (1986MS), French (1986MS), and a rejoinder

    by Morris (1986MS) as well as a summarizing discus-sion by Winkler (1986MS). The axiomatic approachwas intended to complement the Bayesian approachdeveloped in Morris (1974MS, 1977MS) by positing aset of regularity conditions to simplify the modelingproblem and reduce the assessment burden. Morrisaxioms assumed that (a) the consensus distributionshould not depend on who observes a piece of dataif there is agreement on the likelihood function and(b) a uniform prior distribution from a well-calibratedexpert should not change the decision makers opin-ion. Given these assumptions, Morris concluded thatif an expert is well-calibrated, the decision makerhas a (noninformative) uniform prior, and the deci-sion makers and experts opinions are independent,then it is appropriate to elicit probabilities from a

    single expert and use them directly in a decisionanalysis, as most decision makers (and decisionanalysts) do all the time without thinking (Morris1986MS, p. 322). Morris called these conditions quiterestrictive suggesting that this common practice isinappropriate.

    One point of recurring debate in this literature isthe unanimity principle: Given two experts who agreeon the probability of an event (for example, two mete-orologists say that the probability of rain on a givenday is 0.55), should the consensus probability matchthis common probability or should it be a differentnumber? While there was clearly some disagreementabout the interpretation and usefulness of Morrissaxioms, Morris and the others all seemed to agree thatone should approach the expert combination problemthrough the use of Bayesian models and the answer toquestions like this unanimity question should dependon the specifics of a given problem.

    While it is easy to say that the Bayesian modelingapproach represents the solution to the expert com-

    bination problem in principle, in practice there remainmany complex modeling challenges and questionsabout the effectiveness of different combination mech-anisms. Clemen and Winkler (1990MS) describedan empirical test of the unanimity principle andits generalization into the compromise principle(consensus probabilities should lie between differ-ing probability forecasts) and compared the perfor-mance of several Bayesian models using a largedataset of probability of precipitation forecasts. Their

    results illustrated the importance of capturing depen-dence among the expert forecasts when combiningforecasts.

    The expert combination problem remains an inter-esting and active area. Clemen and Winkler (1993MS)described a flexible influence-diagram-based model-ing approach to this problem, and Myung et al.(1996MS) described a maximum entropy approach.Hora (2004MS) presents a study of calibration in lin-ear combination schemes.

    Several application papers have focused on proba-bility assessment. North and Stengels (1982MS) anal-ysis of funding alternatives for the U.S. Department

    of Energys magnetic fusion energy research programfocused on the elicitation of probabilities for researchoutcomes, some of them unforeseeable and far in thefuture. Keeney et al. (1984MS) described the assess-ment of uncertainties about potential adverse healtheffects associated with carbon monoxide emissions.This involved 14 experts and complex dose-responsemodeling. Keefer (1991MS) described a model used todetermine bids for offshore oil and gas leases wherethe dependence among the values of the leases was akey element of the model.

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    7/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management ScienceManagement Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS 567

    4.2. Developments in Utility Modelingand Assessment

    The early developments in utility theory were sum-marized in Management Science in 1968 in a reviewarticle by Peter Fishburn (1968MS). While the earlyfocus had been on utilities for arbitrary consequences

    and for money (as in Pratt 1964), in the 1970s attentionfocused on the assessment of utilities and on multi-attribute utility functions. The work on multiattributeutility functions is discussed in detail in Keeney andRaiffas classic book Decisions with Multiple Objec-tives (1976) and is built on contributions from manyauthors in many fields including research publishedin Management Science (Fishburn 1965MS, 1967MS;Keeney 1972MS). Later, Bell (1979MS) described tech-niques for assessing multiattribute utility functionsthat cannot be decomposed into an additive or mul-tilinear combination of univariate utility functions.von Winterfeldt and Edwards (1986) provided an

    overview of both single and multiattribute utilityassessment as well as a review of the related behav-ioral literature. Huber (1974MS) provided an earlyreview of applications of multiattribute utility. Laterapplications of multiattribute utility theory includeBodily (1978MS), Crawford et al. (1978MS), Ford et al.(1979MS), Golabi et al. (1981MS), Gregory and Keeney(1994MS), and Parnell et al. (1998MS).

    A great deal of behavioral decision research relatedto utility assessment has appeared in Management Sci-ence. Farquhar (1984MS) provided an early review ofutility assessment techniques. Hershey et al. (1982MS)and Hershey and Schoemaker (1985MS) explored

    biases in the two main techniques for assessing utili-ties. In the probability equivalence (PE) method, oneasks what probability in a binary gamble would makethe decision maker indifferent between taking thegamble and receiving a fixed amount for certain. Inthe certainty equivalence (CE) method, one fixes theprobabilities and varies the certain amount instead.If the decision maker or experimental subject trulyfollowed expected utility theory, the two assessmentmethods would yield identical utilities. However, theexperiments of Hershey et al. demonstrated that theassessed utilities depends on the probabilities usedin the assessment gambles, and that the CE methodgenerally yields greater risk taking behavior than thePE method. Such behavior is consistent with sub-

    jects inappropriately weighting probabilities as sug-gested by Kahneman and Tversky (1979). To reducethe impact of this probability weighting, McCord andde Neufville (1986MS) proposed asking subjects tocompare two gambles (rather than a gamble and surething) and showed that their method produced util-ities that depend less on the probabilities used inthe gambles. Johnson and Schkade (1989MS) studiedthese biases in more detail and, later, Wakker and

    Deneffe (1996MS) proposed a more complex trade-offassessment procedure that uses the same probabilitiesin the two gambles and thus circumvents problemsassociated with subjects inappropriately weightingprobabilities. More recently, Bleichrodt et al. (2001MS)used descriptive models to correct biases in utility

    assessments.Behavioral decision research has also affected howdecision analysts define and structure utility func-tions; here we emphasize results on proxy attributesand splitting effects. A proxy attribute is an indirectmeasure of the degree to which some more funda-mental, harder to measure objective is obtained. Forexample, response time measures are often used asproxies for more fundamental measures of emergencysystem performance, like lives saved or fire dam-age averted. Keeney and Raiffa (1976) suggestedthat utilities assessed for proxy attributes may be

    biased because it is difficult for decision makers

    to fully comprehend the relationship between theproxy attribute and the corresponding fundamen-tal attributes. Fischer et al. (1987MS) tested thishypothesis by comparing assessments in a pollu-tion control setting. In one treatment, subjects pro-vided utilities for pollution control costs and thefundamental attribute pollution-related illnesses.In another treatment, subjects provided utilities forcontrol costs and the proxy attribute pollutionemission levels, with a mathematical model relatingemission levels to illnesses. Fischer et al. showed thatsubjects consistently overweighted the proxy attributeemission levels as compared to the implied weight

    for this proxy attribute derived from preferences forthe fundamental attribute illnesses and the modelrelating the proxy and fundamental objectives. Thisresearch suggests that analysts should focus utilityassessments on the fundamental attributes rather thanproxies, but at the cost of increasing the modeling

    burden to capture the sometimes complex and contro-versial relationship between proxy and fundamentalattributes.

    Weber et al. (1988) studied how weights in mul-tiattribute utility assessments change depending onthe level of detail in a hierarchical multiattribute util-ity function. For example, they considered a multiat-tribute job-selection model and compared the weightsassociated with the attribute job security whenit was treated as a single objective and when thesame attribute is decomposed into two componentelements, stability of the firm and personal jobsecurity. Weber et al. found that the level of detailused in the specification greatly impacted the weightassigned to the attribute: Attributes that are decom-posed in more detail received more weight thanthe same attribute with a less detailed decomposi-tion. These results suggest that analysts need to take

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    8/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management Science568 Management Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS

    great care in defining a value hierarchy for utilityfunctions.

    While most of the work in utility has consideredthe perspective of a single decision maker, there hasalso been a significant amount of research in Manage-ment Science on normative models for group decision

    making. Arrows famous Impossibility Theorem(1951b) showed that given arbitrary orderings of con-sequences by individuals in a group, there is no pro-cedure for generating a group order that satisfies aset of seemingly reasonable behavioral assumptions.However, Keeney (1976MS) showed that if we beginwith cardinal utilities (rather than ordinal utilities),we can easily find a group utility function that sat-isfies a suitably reinterpreted version of Arrows rea-sonable assumptions. Under uncertainty and withexpected utilities for individuals and the group, thisgroup utility is a weighted sum of the individual util-ities with the weights reflecting the decision makers

    (a social planner or benevolent dictator) trade-offsbetween the utilities of the group members; this hadbeen shown in Harsanyi (1955). Keeney and Kirk-wood (1975MS) and Dyer and Sarin (1979MS) stud-ied more general forms of group preference functions,the former focusing on decisions under uncertaintyand the latter using strength of preference notionsto study group decisions under certainty. While thesemodels considered aggregating individual utilities,Eliashberg and Winkler (1981MS) considered the casewhere each individuals utility function itself dependson what other members of the group receive.

    A major recurring theme in the literature on group

    decision making is concern with the equity and fair-ness of the group decision and the allocation of thecosts, benefits, and risks associated with the decision.Keeney (1980MS) developed the concept of an equi-table distribution of risk and identified utility func-tions consistent with basic attitudes toward equity.Harvey (1985MS) studied preferences for equity inmore detail, developing notions of inequity neutral-ity and inequity aversion and studying the impli-cations for the form of the group utility function.Fishburn and Sarin (1991MS) focused on dispersiveequity, looking at the distribution of risks amongsubgroups in a population and later studied fair-ness and envy in social risk contexts (1994MS,1997MS).

    One of the more acrimonious debates in Manage-ment Science has concerned the Analytic HierarchyProcess (AHP). The AHP is a decision-making pro-cedure originally developed by Thomas Saaty in the1970s and described in Saaty (1980). Decision ana-lysts have been critical of the AHP saying that it lacksa strong normative foundation and that the ques-tions the decision maker must answer are ambigu-ous. While Saaty (1986MS) provided an axiomatic

    foundation for the AHP, these axioms conflict withthe axioms of expected utility theory and have metwith resistance from decision analysts. Harker andVargas (1987MS) provided a wide-ranging defense ofthe AHP countering some of these criticisms. Dyer(1990MS) summarized the concerns of decision ana-

    lysts and responded to Harker and Vargas: Dyersmain point was that the results produced by the[AHP] are arbitrary (p. 254). Dyer illustrates this bypresenting examples where three alternatives (A, B,and C) are ranked in order B > A > C by the AHP.When we add a fourth alternative, D, that is an exactcopy of Cmeaning it has identical evaluations onall attributesthe alternatives are ranked in the orderA > B > C = D; thus, the introduction of an irrel-evant alternative causes A and B to switch orders!Dyer pointed out that the same phenomenon occurswith near copies as well and suggested a solutionto the flaws of the AHP using techniques from multi-

    attribute utility theory.Saaty (1990MS) and Harker and Vargas (1990MS)both wrote replies to Dyers article addressing manyspecific points and generally not accepting Dyerscomparison to the normative standard of utility the-ory. Reading these replies, however, it is difficult tounderstand whether Saaty and Harker and Vargasintend the AHP to be prescriptive or descriptiveprocedure. They seem to use the AHP as a pre-scriptive procedure in applications, but Saaty writesthat:

    Utility theory is a normative process. The AHP as adescriptive theory encompasses procedures leading to

    outcomes as would be ranked by a normative the-ory. But it must go beyond to deal with outcomes notaccounted for by the demanding assumptions of a nor-mative theory. (Saaty 1990MS, p. 259)

    Our view is that if the AHP is truly intended asa descriptive model, then one should test it to seehow well it describes actual decision-making behav-ior. Though we know of no such tests, we are con-fident that the AHP would not do a very good

    job predicting decision-making behavior, just as theexpected utility model has limited descriptive power.The appeal of the AHP as a prescriptive methodology

    remains matter of disagreement. While many in thedecision analysis community (ourselves included) fol-low Dyer in believing the AHP to be fundamentallyunsound, others (including Saaty, Harker, and Vargas)disagree and the AHP is still widely used in practicetoday.

    4.3. Developments in Game Theory andCompetitive Decision Making

    As indicated in the historical discussion of 2,game theory and decision analysis share commonfoundations: The systematic formal study of game

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    9/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management ScienceManagement Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS 569

    theory and utility theory both began in earnestwith the publication of von Neumann and Morgen-sterns Games and Economic Behavior in 1944. More-over, some of the key figures in decision analysis,notably Duncan Luce and Howard Raiffa, began theircareers working in game theory (see, e.g., Luce and

    Raiffa 1957). Since that time, however, the interestsof decision analysts and game theorists seem to havediverged, but not until after some significant contribu-tions to game theory appeared inManagement Science.

    The most prominent game theory publication inManagement Science is the three-part series by JohnHarsanyi published in 1967 and 1968 (1967MS,1968aMS, 1968bMS), which was the basis forHarsanyis Nobel Prize in Economics in 1994. Con-sistent with the decision analysts focus on decisionmaking under uncertainty, Harsanyi studied games ofincomplete information in which some or all play-ers lack full information about some essential features

    of the game, including perhaps knowledge about theother players payoff function or available actions. AsBayesians, each player assigns subjective probabili-ties over these uncertain features of the game. More-over, Player 1 would be uncertain about the probabil-ities that Player 2 assigns and, as a rational Bayesian,would assign probabilities on Player 2s probabili-ties. Player 2 would do likewise. Player 1 then has toassign another level of probabilities on the probabil-ities that Player 2 would assign to the probabilitiesthat Player 1 assigns. Player 2 would do likewise andthe sequence continues rationally but impractically adinfinitum.

    Harsanyis contribution was the development ofa framework that logically models games of incom-plete information but avoids this infinite regress andreduces the game to a game of complete informa-tion with uncertainty about the types of the playersinvolved in the game. The type of a player containsinformation about all players first-order probabilitiesand payoffs. Harsanyi assumed that there is an exoge-nously given joint probability distribution on thetypes of all players in the game that is interpreted as acommon prior. At the beginning of the game, eachplayer knows his own type but not that of his oppo-nents. The players then update their probabilities onthe other players types using Bayes Theorem basedon this and whatever other information revealed dur-ing the course of the game. Harsanyis first paper inthe three-part series (Harsanyi 1967MS) showed that,given the consistency requirement of a common prioron types, any game of incomplete information can

    be represented in this flattened form. In the secondpaper (Harsanyi 1968aMS), Harsanyi showed that theNash equilibria in the flattened game, which Harsanyicalled a Bayesian equilibria, correspond to the equilib-ria of the original game. In the third paper (Harsanyi

    1968bMS), he studied properties of the distributionon types in the model. Harsanyis Nobel Prize lecture(Harsanyi 1995) provides an overview of this work.

    Games of incomplete information have been usedto analyze negotiation, competitive bidding, socialchoice, the signaling roles of education and adver-

    tising, as well as many other economic phenomena.Nevertheless, game theory has its critics, includingmany in the decision analysis community. HowardRaiffa (1982, p. 2), for example, wrote that gametheory deals only with the way in which ultra-smart, all-knowing people should behave in compet-itive situations and has little to say to Mr. X ashe confronts the morass of his problem. Raiffa, inhis study of negotiations, instead preferred to focuson an asymmetrically prescriptive/descriptive per-spective in which one seeks to help a party competeagainst an opponent whose behavior is not neces-

    sarily assumed to be rational, or alternatively helpsmany parties (not necessarily rational) reach a jointdecision. This perspective has been adopted in muchrecent work in negotiation analysis; in particular, seeSebenius (1992MS). Pratt and Zeckhauser (1990MS)provided a wonderful example of this kind of anal-ysis describing the development and use of a for-mal, decentralized division procedure to fairly andefficiently divide a set of valuable silver heirloomsamong beneficiaries of an estate.

    An important paper in the debate on game the-ory is Kadane and Larkeys Subjective Probabilitiesand the Theory of Games (1982bMS). Kadane andLarkey argued that a Bayesian decision maker needonly take into account his first-order beliefs about hisopponents play at the time he chooses actions, with-out getting caught up in the infinite regress or strongassumptions about the rationality of the opponent.They wrote

    It is true that a subjectivist Bayesian will have an opin-

    ion not only about his opponents behavior, but alsoabout his opponents belief about his own behavior, his

    opponents belief about his belief about his opponentsbehavior, etc. (He also has opinions about the phase

    of the moon, tomorrows weather and the winner ofthe next Superbowl.) However, in a single-play game,

    all aspects of his opinion except his opinion about hisopponents behavior are irrelevant, and can be ignoredin the analysis by integrating them out of the joint

    opinion. (Kadane and Larkey 1982bMS, p. 116)

    Thus, in Kadane and Larkeys view, there is no needfor the hierarchy of beliefs or special structures orrationality assumptions. The various solution con-cepts of game theory provide the basis for assigningparticular prior distributions, but are not necessary

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    10/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management Science570 Management Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS

    for the solution of the decision problem. Harsanyi(1982MS) wrote in a comment

    Kadane and Larkey oppose any use of normativesolution concepts and oppose imposing any rational-ity criteria on players choice of subjective probabili-ties. They do not seem to realize that their approach

    would amount to throwing away essential information,viz., the assumption (even in cases where this is arealistic assumption) that the players will act ratio-nally and will also expect each other to act rationally.Indeed, their approach would trivialize game theory

    by depriving it of its most interesting problem, thatof how to translate the intuitive assumption of mutu-ally expected rationality into mathematically precise

    behavioral terms (solution concepts). (p. 121)Kadane and Larkey have not proposed any viable

    alternative to this approach. All they have proposed isto trivialize game theory by rejecting the basic intel-lectual problem and to replace it by the uninforma-tive statement that every player should maximize his

    expected utility in terms of his subjective probabilitieswithout giving him the slightest hint of how to choosethese subjective probabilities in a rational manager.(p. 123)

    In their reply to Harsanyi, Kadane and Larkey(1982aMS) suggested the use of what we nowcall an asymmetrically prescriptive/descriptive modeof analysis that uses an empirically supportedpsychological theory making at least probabilistic pre-dictions about the strategies people are likely to use,given the nature of the game and their own psy-chological makeup (p. 124). In this response, theyparaphrased remarks in Harsanyis reply, but while

    Harsanyi suggested the need for such a psychologi-cal theory for playing against actually or potentiallyirrational opponents, Kadane and Larkey arguedthat most opponents are in fact actually or poten-tially irrational and such a psychological theoryshould be central in the study of competitive decisionmaking.

    In a follow-up paper titled The Confusion of Isand Ought in Game Theoretic Contexts (1983MS),Kadane and Larkey called the 30+ years of work ingame theory cumulatively useless in that it pro-vides so little of value in instructing people onhow they should behave in conflict situations andin predicting how they do behave in conflict situa-tions (p. 1370). This prompted a comment by anotherprominent game theorist, Martin Shubik (1983MS),who acknowledged that Kadane and Larkey raisegood questions. However, like Harsanyi, Shubik saidthat replacing an n-person game by n parallel one-person games with subjective probability updating

    black boxes solves no problems, it slurs over them(p. 1383).

    In a plenary address given at the 1987 Instituteof Management Sciences meeting called What Is

    an Application and When Is a Theory a Waste ofTime? (Shubik 1987MS), Shubik reconsidered theusefulness of game theory and distinguished betweenthe high-church version of game theory concernedwith formal, mathematical structures and analysis;low-church applications of basic concepts to spe-

    cific problems; and the conversational game theoryconsisting of advice, suggestions and counsel abouthow to think strategically. Shubik acknowledged thatlow-church applications of game theory have beenof some, but nevertheless relatively modest worth

    but that the conversational version of game theory isof considerable worth (p. 1516). However, he notedthat

    Without high church game theory, the concepts, illus-trations and stories of conversational game theorywould hardly exist and certainly would not have asound intellectual basis. Without conversational andhigh church game theory, sponsorship for low church

    game theory would hardly exist.Application is not just calculation and specific prob-

    lem solving. It is also concept clarification, education,and changing modes of thought. (p. 1517)

    Rothkopf and Harstad (1994MS) expressed similarsentiments in their review of the use of game-theoreticmodels of auctions in actual competitive biddingsituations.

    To us, it appears that most decision analysisresearchers have come to prefer the more practicallyoriented asymmetrically prescriptive/descriptive per-spective on competitive decision making advo-

    cated by Raiffa, Kadane and Larkey, and othersto the ultrarational normative/normative perspectiveof high-church game theory. While low-churchapplications of game theory have become quite pop-ular in some areas ofManagement Science, particularlyin supply chain analysis (see, e.g., Cachon and Zipkin1999MS), the decision analysis department has notpublished much in the way of high-church gametheory in recent years. We have however begun tosee considerable activity in behavioral game the-ory where one studies the actual behavior of par-ticipants in various forms of games (see, e.g., Boltonet al. 2003MS). Colin Camerers new book, Behav-ioral Game Theory(Camerer 2003), provides a compre-hensive review of the current state of the art in thisarea.

    5. Concluding and Looking AheadAs we reviewed the decision analysis articles thathave appeared in Management Science, we have beenimpressed with the depth, quality, and sheer volumeof decision analysis research that has appeared inthe journal. In highlighting a few topics and articles

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    11/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management ScienceManagement Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS 571

    here, we have omitted many important articles thatappeared inManagement Sciencebut did not fit clearlyinto the research streams that we chose to empha-size, as well as many important contributions pub-lished elsewhere. Our choice of topics was intended tohighlight how prescriptive decision analysis research

    builds on the foundations of normative and descrip-tive research on decision making.While the number of decision analysis papers

    appearing in Management Science increased dramat-ically from the 1960s through the mid-1980s, wehave witnessed a general decline since that time. We

    believe that this decline in papers does not reflecta decline in the relevance of decision analysis orin related research. Interest in behavioral decision-making research in particular is growing, although itis less likely to use the term decision analysis andless likely to have the managerial and prescriptive ori-entation of Management Science. The Journal of Behav-

    ioral Decision Making and Organization Behavior andHuman Decision Processes now publish a great dealof behavioral decision-making research and top jour-nals in economics and finance now regularly pub-lish work in experimental economics and behavioralfinance. Daniel Kahneman won the Nobel Prize inEconomics in 2002 for his research, much of it withthe late Amos Tversky, on decision-making behaviorunder uncertainty. The prize was shared with VernonSmith who was cited for his laboratory experimentsstudying behavior of humans interacting in differentmarket settings. As editors at Management Science, wewould like to see more work relating these new devel-

    opments in behavioral decision making back to theprescriptive modeling of decision analysis.Prescriptive decision analysis research is also grow-

    ing and appearing in a variety of new settings.As part of a recent study on the viability of thenew journal Decision Analysis, Don Kleinmuntz con-ducted a literature search that looked for articlespublished from 1994 to 1998 that used decisionanalysis in the title, subject key words, or abstract(Keller and Kleinmuntz 1998). The search found atotal of 811 articles in 369 journals. Strikingly, over60% of the articles identified were published in med-ical journals and some 220 different medical journalswere represented. The other 149 journals representedfields such as environmental risk management, engi-neering, artificial intelligence, psychology, as well asmanagement.

    Decision analysis has clearly been recognized asan important tool for the evaluation of major deci-sions in the public sector, particularly in the health-care arena. Although a handful of consulting firmshave demonstrated the value of decision analysis tocorporate clients in evaluating research and devel-opment projects, oil and gas exploration opportuni-ties, and other areas, the use of decision analysis

    methods is not yet widespread in corporations. Tohave a greater impact on corporate decision mak-ing, we believe that decision analysis researchersmust build on and pay more attention to the prin-ciples of corporate finance and the theory of finan-cial markets. Management Science has published some

    papers that integrate finance and decision analy-sis. For example, Wilson (1969MS) used probabilis-tic models of investments and financing decisions todevelop conditions for accepting or rejecting individ-ual projects without considering the entire portfolioof projects. Smith and Nau (1995MS) considered theevaluation of projects where some project risks can behedged by trading marketed securities; their methodsintegrate risk-neutral valuation techniques used tovalue derivative securities with traditional, decision-analytic certainty-equivalent-based notions of valu-ation. However, despite these advances, at presentthere is no consensus on how firms should evaluaterisky cash flows and much research remains to bedone.

    As we have seen, Management Sciencehas played acentral role in the development of the field of decisionanalysis over the last 50 years, particularly during thelast 35 years. We hope that Management Science willcontinue to play a central role in future, along withINFORMS new Decision Analysis journal. In particu-lar, we hope that decision researchers will continue todo research with the prescriptive goal of improvingmanagerial decision making and that they will con-tinue to write up their best work for the broad audi-

    ence at Management Science.

    AcknowledgmentsThe authors thank Bob Clemen, Ralph Keeney, Bob Nau,and Bob Winkler for many helpful comments on thispaper.

    References

    Allais, M. 1953. Le comportement de lhomme rationnel devant lerisque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de lecole americaine.Econometrica21(4) 503546.

    Arrow, K. J. 1951a. Alternative approaches to the theory of choice

    in risk-taking situations. Econometrica 19(4) 404437.Arrow, K. J. 1951b. Social Choice and Individual Values. Wiley,

    New York.

    Bacharach, M. 1975. Group decisions in the face of differences ofopinion. Management Sci. 22(2) 182191.

    Bayes, T. 1763. An essay toward solving a problem in the doctrineof chances.Philosophical Trans. Roy. Soc. London 53 370418.

    Bell, D. E. 1979. Multiattribute utility functions: Decompositionsusing interpolation.Management Sci. 25(8) 744753.

    Bell, D. E., H. Raiffa, A. Tversky. 1988. Decision Making: Descrip-tive, Normative, and Prescriptive Interactions. Cambridge [Cam-

    bridgeshire]; Cambridge University Press, New York.

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    12/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management Science572 Management Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS

    Bleichrodt, H., J. L. Pinto, P. P. Wakker. 2001. Making descriptive useof prospect theory to improve the prescriptive use of expectedutility. Management Sci. 47 14981514.

    Bodily, S. E. 1978. Police sector design incorporating preferencesof interest groups for equality and efficiency. Management Sci.24(12) 13011313.

    Bolton, G. E., K. Chatterjee, K. L. McGinn. 2003. How communica-tion links influence coalition bargaining: A laboratory investi-gation. Management Sci. 49(5) 583598.

    Cachon, G. P., P. H. Zipkin. 1999. Competitive and cooperativeinventory policies in a two-stage supply chain. Management Sci.45(7) 936953.

    Camerer, C. F. 2003. Behavioral Game Theory: Experiments in StrategicInteraction. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

    Clemen, R. T. 1986. Calibration and the aggregation of probabilities.Management Sci. 32(3) 312314.

    Clemen, R. T. 1987. Combining overlapping information. Manage-ment Sci.33(3) 373380.

    Clemen, R. T., R. L. Winkler. 1990. Unanimity and compromiseamong probability forecasters. Management Sci. 36(7) 767779.

    Clemen, R. T., R. L. Winkler. 1993. Aggregating point estimates:A flexible modeling approach.Management Sci. 39(4) 501515.

    Clemen, R. T., G. W. Fischer, R. L. Winkler. 2000. Assessingdependence: Some experimental results.Management Sci. 46(8)11001115.

    Corner, J. L., C. W. Kirkwood. 1991. Decision analysis applicationsin the operations research literature, 19701989.Oper. Res.39(2)206219.

    Crawford, D. M., B. C. Huntzinger, C. W. Kirkwood. 1978. Multiob-jective decision analysis for transmission conductor selection.Management Sci. 24(16) 17001709.

    de Finetti, B. 1937. La prvision: Ses lois logiques, ses sources sub-jectives. Ann. Inst. H. Poincar7 168.

    DeGroot, M. H., J. Mortera. 1991. Optimal linear opinion pools.Management Sci. 37(5) 546558.

    Dyer, J. S. 1990. Remarks on the analytic hierarchy process.Management Sci. 36(3) 249258.

    Dyer, J. S., R. K. Sarin. 1979. Group preference aggregation rules

    based on strength of preference.Management Sci.25(9) 822832.Edwards, W. 1954. The theory of decision making. Psych. Bull. 51

    380417.

    Eliashberg, J., R. L. Winkler. 1981. Risk sharing and group decision-making. Management Sci. 27(11) 12211235.

    Farquhar, P. H. 1984. Utility assessment methods. Management Sci.30(11) 12831300.

    Fischer, G. W., N. Damodaran, K. B. Laskey, D. Lincoln. 1987. Pref-erences for proxy attributes. Management Sci. 33(2) 198214.

    Fishburn, P. C. 1965. Independence, trade-offs, and transformationsin bivariate utility functions. Management Sci. 11(9, Series A,Sciences) 792801.

    Fishburn, P. C. 1967. Methods of estimating additive utilities.Management Sci. 13(7, Series A, Sciences) 435453.

    Fishburn, P. C. 1968. Utility theory. Management Sci. 14(5, Theory

    Series) 335378.

    Fishburn, P. C., R. K. Sarin. 1991. Dispersive equity and social risk.Management Sci. 37(7) 751769.

    Fishburn, P. C., R. K. Sarin. 1994. Fairness and social risk i: Unag-gregated analyses.Management Sci. 40(9) 11741188.

    Fishburn, P. C., R. K. Sarin. 1997. Fairness and social risk ii: Aggre-gated analyses.Management Sci. 43(1) 1526.

    Fishburn, P. C., P. P. Wakker. 1995. The invention of the indepen-dence condition for preferences. Management Sci. 41(7) 11301144.

    Ford, C. K., R. L. Keeney, C. W. Kirkwood. 1979. Evaluatingmethodologies: A procedure and application to nuclear powerplant siting methodologies. Management Sci. 25(1) 110.

    French, S. 1986. Calibration and the expert problem. ManagementSci.32(3) 315321.

    Golabi, K., C. W. Kirkwood, A. Sicherman. 1981. Selecting a port-folio of solar energy projects using multiattribute preferencetheory.Management Sci. 27(2) 174189.

    Gregory, R., R. L. Keeney. 1994. Creating policy alternatives usingstakeholder values. Management Sci. 40(8) 10351048.

    Harker, P. T., L. G. Vargas. 1987. The theory of ratio scale estima-tion: Saatys analytic hierarchy process. Management Sci. 33(11)13831403.

    Harker, P. T., L. G. Vargas. 1990. Reply to remarks on the analytichierarchy process by J. S. Dyer. Management Sci.36(3) 269273.

    Harrison, J. M. 1977. Independence and calibration in decision anal-ysis.Management Sci. 24(3) 320328.

    Harsanyi, J. C. 1955. Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, andinterpersonal comparisons of utility. J. Political Econom. 63(4)309321.

    Harsanyi, J. C. 1967. Games with incomplete information played byBayesian players, iiii. Part i. The basic model. ManagementSci.14(3, Theory Series) 159182.

    Harsanyi, J. C. 1968a. Games with incomplete information playedby Bayesian players, iiii. Part ii. Bayesian equilibrium

    points. Management Sci. 14(5, Theory Series) 320334.Harsanyi, J. C. 1968b. Games with incomplete information played

    by Bayesian players, iiii. Part iii. The basic probability dis-tribution of the game. Management Sci. 14(7, Theory Series)486502.

    Harsanyi, J. C. 1982. Subjective probability and the theory of games:Comments on Kadane and Larkeys paper. Management Sci.28(2) 120124.

    Harsanyi, J. C. 1995. Games with incomplete information. Amer.Econom. Rev. 85(3) 291303.

    Harvey, C. M. 1985. Decision analysis models for social attitudestoward inequity.Management Sci. 31(10) 11991212.

    Hershey, J. C., P. J. H. Schoemaker. 1985. Probability versus cer-tainty equivalence methods in utility measurement: Are theyequivalent? Management Sci. 31(10) 12131231.

    Hershey, J. C., H. C. Kunreuther, P. J. H. Schoemaker. 1982. Sourcesof bias in assessment procedures for utility functions.Manage-ment Sci. 28(8) 936954.

    Hopp, W. 2004. Fifty years of management science. Management Sci.50(1) 17.

    Hora, S. C. 2004. Probability judgments for continuous quanti-ties: Linear combinations and calibration.Management Sci.50(5)597604.

    Howard, R. A. 1965. Bayesian decision models for systems engi-neering. IEEE Trans. Systems Man Cybernetics 1(1) 3640.

    Howard, R. A. 1966. Decision analysis: Applied decision the-ory. Proc. Fourth Internat. Conf. Oper. Res., Wiley-Interscience,New York.

    Howard, R. A. 1968. The foundations of decision analysis. IEEE

    Trans. Systems, Sci. Cybernetics 4(3) 211219.Howard, R. A. 1989. Knowledge maps. Management Sci. 35(8)

    903922.

    Huber, G. P. 1974. Multi-attribute utility models: A review of fieldand field-like studies.Management Sci. 20(10) 13931402.

    Johnson, E. J., D. A. Schkade. 1989. Bias in utility assessments: Fur-ther evidence and explanations. Management Sci.35(4) 406424.

    Kadane, J. B., P. D. Larkey. 1982a. Reply to Professor Harsanyi.Management Sci. 28(2) 124.

    Kadane, J. B., P. D. Larkey. 1982b. Subjective probability and thetheory of games.Management Sci. 28(2) 113120.

    Kadane, J. B., P. D. Larkey. 1983. The confusion of is and ought ingame theoretic contexts.Management Sci. 29(12) 13651379.

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    13/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management ScienceManagement Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS 573

    Kahneman, D., A. Tversky. 1979. Prospect theory: An analysis ofdecision under risk.Econometrica 47 263291.

    Kahneman, D., P. Slovic, A. Tversky, eds. 1982. Judgment UnderUncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge University Press,Cambridge, U.K.

    Keefer, D. L. 1991. Resource allocation models with risk aversionand probabilistic dependence: Offshore oil and gas bidding.

    Management Sci. 37(4) 377395.

    Keefer, D. L., C. W. Kirkwood, J. L. Corner. 2004. Perspective ondecision analysis applications. Decision Anal. 1(1) 422.

    Keeney, R. L. 1972. Utility functions for multiattributed conse-quences. Management Sci. 18(5) 276287.

    Keeney, R. L. 1976. A group preference axiomatization with cardinalutility. Management Sci. 23(2) 140145.

    Keeney, R. L. 1980. Utility functions for equity and public risk.Man-agement Sci. 26(4) 345353.

    Keeney, R. L., C. W. Kirkwood. 1975. Group decision makingusing cardinal social welfare functions. Management Sci. 22(4)430437.

    Keeney, R. L., H. Raiffa. 1976. Decisions with Multiple Objectives.Wiley, New York.

    Keeney, R. L., R. K. Sarin, R. L. Winkler. 1984. Analysis of alterna-

    tive national ambient carbon monoxide standards. ManagementSci. 30(4) 518528.

    Keller, R. L., D. N. Kleinmuntz. 1998. Is this the right time for a newdecision analysis journal? Decision Anal. Soc. Newsletter 17(3).

    Lindley, D. V. 1986. Another look at an axiomatic approach toexpert resolution. Management Sci. 32(3) 303306.

    Luce, R. D., H. Raiffa. 1957. Games and Decisions: Introduction andCritical Survey. Wiley, New York.

    Matheson, J. E., R. L. Winkler. 1976. Scoring rules for continuousprobability distributions.Management Sci. 22(10) 10871096.

    McCord, M., R. de Neufville. 1986. Lottery equivalents: Reductionof the certainty effect problem in utility assessment. Manage-ment Sci.32(1) 5660.

    Morris, P. A. 1974. Decision analysis expert use. Management Sci.20(9) 12331241.

    Morris, P. A. 1977. Combining expert judgments: A Bayesianapproach. Management Sci. 23(7) 679693.

    Morris, P. A. 1983. An axiomatic approach to expert resolution.Management Sci. 29(1) 2432.

    Morris, P. A. 1986. Observations on expert aggregation. ManagementSci. 32(3) 321328.

    Moskowitz, H., R. K. Sarin. 1983. Improving the consistency of con-ditional probability assessments for forecasting and decisionmaking. Management Sci. 29(6) 735749.

    Murphy, A. H., R. L. Winkler. 1970. Scoring rules in probabilityassessment and evaluation. Acta Psych. 34 273286.

    Myung, I. J., S. Ramamoorti, A. D. Bailey, Jr. 1996. Maximumentropy aggregation of expert predictions. Management Sci.42(10) 14201436.

    North, D. W., D. N. Stengel. 1982. Decision analysis of program

    choices in magnetic fusion energy development. ManagementSci. 28(3) 276288.

    Parnell, G. S., H. W. Conley, J. A. Jackson, L. J. Lehmkuhl,J. M. Andrew. 1998. Foundations 2025: A value model forevaluating future air and space forces. Management Sci. 44(10)13361350.

    Phillips, L. D., W. Edwards. 1966. Conservatism in a simple proba-bility inference task.J. Experiment. Psych. 72 346357.

    Phillips, L. D., W. L. Hays, W. Edwards. 1966. Conservatism in com-plex probabilistic inference tasks. IEEE Trans. Human FactorsElectronics7 718.

    Pratt, J. W. 1964. Risk aversion in the small and in the large. Econo-metrica 32(12) 122136.

    Pratt, J. W., R. J. Zeckhauser. 1990. The fair and efficient division ofthe Winsor family silver. Management Sci. 36(11) 12931301.

    Pratt, J. W., H. Raiffa, R. Schlaifer. 1964. The foundations of decisionunder uncertainty: An elementary exposition. J. Amer. Statist.

    Assoc.59(306) 353375.

    Pratt, J. W., H. Raiffa, R. Schlaifer. 1965. Introduction to StatisticalDecision Theory (Preliminary Edition). McGraw-Hill, New York.

    Raiffa, H. 1968. Decision Analysis: Introductory Lectures on ChoicesUnder Uncertainty. Random House, New York.

    Raiffa, H. 1982. The Art and Science of Negotiation. Belknap Press ofHarvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Raiffa, H., R. O. Schlaifer. 1961. Applied Statistical Decision Theory.Harvard University, Boston, MA.

    Ravinder, H. V., D. N. Kleinmuntz, J. S. Dyer. 1988. The reliabil-ity of subjective probabilities obtained through decomposition.

    Management Sci. 34(2) 186199.

    Rothkopf, M. H., R. M. Harstad. 1994. Modeling competitive bid-ding: A critical essay. Management Sci. 40(3) 364384.

    Saaty, T. L. 1980. The Analytic Hierarchy Process. McGraw-Hill,New York.

    Saaty, T. L. 1986. Axiomatic foundation of the analytic hierarchyprocess.Management Sci. 32(7) 841855.

    Saaty, T. L. 1990. An exposition on the ahp in reply to the paperremarks on the analytic hierarchy process. Management Sci.36(3) 259268.

    Sarin, R. K., R. L. Winkler. 1980. Performance-based incentive plans.Management Sci. 26(11) 11311144.

    Savage, L. J. 1954. The Foundations of Statistics. Wiley, New York.

    Schervish, M. J. 1986. Comments on some axioms for combiningexpert judgments. Management Sci. 32(3) 306312.

    Schlaifer, R. 1959. Probability and Statistics for Business Decisions.McGraw-Hill, New York.

    Sebenius, J. K. 1992. Negotiation analysis: A characterization andreview.Management Sci. 38(1) 1838.

    Shubik, M. 1983. The confusion of is and ought in game theoreticcontextsComment. Management Sci. 29(12) 13801383.

    Shubik, M. 1987. What is an application and when is theory a wasteof time. Management Sci. 33(12) 15111522.

    Smith, J. E., R. F. Nau. 1995. Valuing risky projects: Option pricingtheory and decision analysis. Management Sci. 41(5) 795816.

    Spetzler, C. S., C.-A. S. Stael Von Holstein. 1975. Probability encod-ing in decision analysis.Management Sci. 22(3) 340358.

    Tversky, A., D. Kahneman. 1974. Judgment under uncertainty:Heuristics and biases. Science 185 11241131.

    Tversky, A., D. Kahneman. 1992. Advances in prospect theory:Cumulative representation of uncertainty. J. Risk Uncertainty5 297323.

    von Neumann, J., O. Morgenstern. 1944. Theory of Games andEconomic Behavior. Princeton University Press, Princeton,NJ.

    von Winterfeldt, D., W. Edwards. 1986.Decision Analysis and Behav-

    ioral Research. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, U.K.Wakker, P. 1989. Additive Representations of Preferences, a New

    Foundation of Decision Analysis. Kluwer Academic Publishers,Dordrecht, The Netherlands.

    Wakker, P., D. Deneffe. 1996. Eliciting von Neumann-Morgensternutilities when probabilities are distorted or unknown. Manage-ment Sci. 42(8) 11311150.

    Wallsten, T. S., D. V. Budescu. 1983. Encoding subjective probabil-ities: A psychological and psychometric review. ManagementSci.29(2) 151173.

    Weber, M., F. Eisenfuhr, D. von Winterfeldt. 1988. The effects ofsplitting attributes on weights in multiattribute utility mea-surement.Management Sci. 34(4) 431445.

  • 8/12/2019 9 Decision Analysis in Management Science MS04 9099

    14/14

    Smith and von Winterfeldt: Decision Analysis in Management Science574 Management Science 50(5), pp. 561574, 2004 INFORMS

    Wilson, R. 1969. Investment analysis under uncertainty.ManagementSci. 15(12) B650B664.

    Winkler, R. L. 1968. The consensus of subjective probabil-ity distributions. Management Sci. 15(2, Application Series)B61B75.

    Winkler, R. L. 1981. Combining probability distributions fromdependent information sources.Management Sci.27(4) 479488.

    Winkler, R. L. 1986. Expert resolution. Management Sci. 32(3)298303.

    Winkler, R. L. 1994. Evaluating probabilities: Asymmetric scoringrules.Management Sci. 40(11) 13951405.

    Winkler, R. L., R. M. Poses. 1993. Evaluating and combining physi-cians probabilities of survival in an intensive care unit. Man-agement Sci. 39(12) 15261543.