2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    1/26

    The Desecuritisation of Illegal Migration:

    The Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    Paper prepared for the PhD-seminar/EUROPA workshop,

    Department of Political Science and Public Management,

    University of Southern Denmark,

    Odense, 26 October 2004

    Rens van Munster

    PhD-student

    University of Southern Denmark

    Dpt. of Political Science and Public Management

    Campusvej 55

    5230 Odense M

    Email: [email protected]

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    2/26

    1

    There is a certain joy in listening to [security] stories. But what

    is joy on closer reflection than our hidden sorrow unmasked.

    Perhaps we listen, read, and believe security stories only to

    alleviate a deeper pain managing somehow to live

    meaningfully, more comfortably, and even with a smile, within

    our boundaries of violence

    Costas Constantinou

    What we need more is a certain violence against ourselves

    Slavoj iek

    1 Introduction

    Since the introduction of the internal market and, more recently, the establishment of the EU as an

    area of freedom, security and justice the topic of illegal migration is increasingly interpreted as a

    security problem.1 Over the last two decades the issue of illegal has been gradually but consistently

    uncoupled from humanitarian and economic frames and has instead been re-inscribed as a stake in

    the administrative field of security.2

    In this latter field

    the phenomenon of illegal migration is not

    first and foremost considered in the utilitarian terms of economics or in the cosmopolitan terms of

    humanitarianism but as a highly charged socio-political risk to the functioning of the EU and its

    member states. Conceptually as well as institutionally, the issue of illegal migration is now viewed

    as a risk on a European security continuum that also includes transversal issues such as organised

    1

    See for instance Bigo (1994), den Boer (1995), Huysmans (2000b), Albrecht (2002), Green and Grewcock (2002),Berman (2003) and Geddes (2003).2 See Bigo (1996), Carr (1996) and Benyon (1996).

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    3/26

    2

    crime, terrorism, drugs trade and human trafficking. Moreover, the issue of illegal migration has

    started to function as the point of convergence or the common currency with which politicians,

    policy-makers, security professionals and the (sensational) press communicate their misgivings and

    fears to each other and the wider public.3

    As a consequence, the view of illegal migrants as a threat

    to security is now largely taken for granted and security measures taken by the EU to control the

    inflow of illegal migrants are considered to be neutral policy responses to this objective threat. If

    one accepts such a view, the obvious research question for security analysts is a problem-solving or

    instrumental one: how best secure or defend the EU against the inflow of migrants? This paper

    resists such a problem-solving perspective, however. It is not so much interested in the instrumental

    question of how best to manage illegal migration. Instead, it focuses on the more explicit ethico-

    political question of the ways in which the securitisation of illegal migration organises and

    structures the ways in which the EU relates to itself and to outsiders. In doing so, this paper hooks

    up with the linguistic turn in social theory in general and IR-theory more specifically. Departing

    from the by now well-known insight that language is not merely a neutral medium that mirrors an

    extra-discursive realm but also has a constitutive bearing upon that reality, this paper claims that the

    enunciation of security mediates a specific form of belonging that constructs the antagonistic

    identities of friend and enemy.4 In this view, the enunciation of illegal migration as a security

    problem is a practice that seeks to settle the question of belonging and inclusion and exclusion.

    In addressing the securitisation of illegal migration, the purpose of this paper is to show that

    security is not a necessary response to the question of illegal migration but a particular way oforganising belonging that integrates society around the construction of a dangerous other. In an

    attempt to move away from a politics of belonging that functions by turning the other into a threat,

    3 As a result, illegal migration is increasingly made visible in public discourses as the cause for all social anxieties such

    as unemployment, the deterioration of the quality of life in urban areas, petty crime, prostitution and concerns about

    national and cultural identities images which often rely on shaky but nevertheless popular and sticky presumptions.

    See Wacquant (1999), Bigo (2002), Ceyhan and Tsoukala (2002), Albrecht (2002), Bigo (2002), Ceyhan and Tsoukala(2002) and Pickering (2004).4 See, inter alia, Wver (1995), Campbell (1998b) and Weldes et al. (1999).

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    4/26

    3

    this paper seeks to open up for alternative ways of politicising illegal migration and the question of

    belonging in the emerging European polity. That is, it seeks to undo the representation of illegal

    migration as a threat against which the emerging EU community should be defended.5 In an attempt

    to outline a strategy of desecuritisation, this paper turns to deconstruction. Whereas the realm of

    security is essentially a conservative discourse that seeks to defend the status quo through control

    and policing, deconstruction has always been explicitly concerned with opening up what is

    generally taken for given in an attempt to bring marginalised and excluded voices into the picture.

    Insofar as desecuritisation is about the unmaking of security by re-imagining the question of

    illegal migration, there is indeed a close resemblance in the objectives of deconstruction and

    desecuritisation.6 Critically evaluating the deconstructivist strategy of desecuritisation (section 3),

    this paper moves on to formulate a strategy of desecuritisation that rethinks the boundaries of

    belonging from the point of the securitised other as most excluded (section 4). In the more concrete

    context of the securitisation of illegal migration in the EU, this requires a restructuring of belonging

    on behalf of the illegal migrants as the abject of the emerging European polity (section 5). What this

    may entail more concretely will be illustrated by referring to the sans-papiers struggle for the

    regularisation of all undocumented migrants in Europe. However, before inquiring deeper into the

    possibilities of a desecuritisation of social relations and what such a desecuritisation might entail for

    5 From a constructivist perspective, this begs the obvious but essential question whether one in criticising the

    securitisation of illegal migration does not implicitly contribute to these securitising processes. The reason behind this is

    that referring to the issue of illegal migration in terms of security (even critically!) re-enforces and re-inforces the social

    perception of the latter as a security issue (cf. Constantinou, 2000; Wver, 1999). For instance, Guiraudon (1998) has

    warned that it can be difficult to untie the migrant from its strong negative connotations and, hence, trying to do so

    would only help sustaining the social image of migrants as a force corroding the social edifice. But if speaking is a

    problem, silence is not an option either once confronted with an issue that is already heavily securitised. Although the

    normative dilemma of writing security seems inescapable, Huysmans (2002) has argued that it nevertheless can be

    mitigated if one focuses on the governing work on security and its structuring effects on social relations. While this

    does not solve the dilemma, it at least opens up the possibility for unmaking security by pointing out the political workthat security performs.6 On the connection between deconstruction and desecuritisation, see also Huysmans (1995) and Hansen (1997: 377).

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    5/26

    4

    European belonging, it is first necessary to specify in some detail the ways in which security orders

    belonging.

    2. The EU and Illegal Migration: Security as a Politics of Belonging

    Security is a specific way of politicising an issue: to put illegal migration on the security agenda

    means that migrants become staged as actors in a security drama. Security politics does not simply

    function by pointing out pre-existing threats. It is a performative activity that renders societal issues

    such as illegal migration visible as a threat: The process of securitization is what in language

    theory is called a speech act. It is not interesting as a sign referring to something more real; it is the

    utterance itself that is the act. By saying the words, something is done (Buzan et al., 1998: 26). But

    what does it mean more precisely to securitise issues such as illegal migration? What exactly is

    done when issues are framed as security issues? And in which ways does a security drama differ

    from other dramas?

    Arguably, these questions have been addressed most explicitly in the research of Ole Wver

    and the Copenhagen school of security.7 In the view of the Copenhagen school, a security story

    differs from other types of stories because it is structured by the logic of war, which Wver views

    through the lens of national security: To the extent that we have an idea of a specific modality

    labelled security it is because we think of national security and its modifications and limitations,

    and not because we think of the everyday word security (Wver, 1995: 48-9, emphasis inoriginal). Thus while the notion of war is generally restricted to the realm of national security,

    Wver proposes to study the ways in which the national security problematique is present outside

    the immediate context of military conflict between states: [T]he logic of war of challenge-

    7 One sympathetic critic of the Copenhagen school refers to their research as possibly the most thorough and

    continuous exploration of the significance and implications of a widening security agenda (Huysmans, 1998b: 186).

    Also, many of the current debates on the nature of the security drama are framed in relation to the Copenhagen school.See for instance Huysmans (1998a; forthcoming), Doty (1998/99), McSweeney (1999), Hansen (2000), Aradau (2001),

    Eriksson (2001) and Williams (2003).

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    6/26

    5

    resistance (defense)-escalation-recognition/defeat could be replayed metaphorically and extended

    to other sectors ... When this happens, however, the structure of the game is still derived from the

    most classical of classical cases: war (Wver, 1995: 56). In accordance with the traditional

    Clausewitzian view of war, then, security can be defined as the end point of politics. When normal

    politics fail, it gives way to security politics, which inserts issues with a sense of priority and

    urgency that legitimise politicians and policy-makers to take extraordinary measures to secure the

    survival of a political community: When a specific issue is turned into a test case, everything

    becomes concentrated at one point, since the outcome of the test will frame all future questions

    (Wver, 1995: 53). In the extreme case of war, a government is not longer bound by the rules that

    govern normal social relations (e.g. political transparency, public decision-making and respect for

    civil rights), but free to take the decisions that can guarantee the survival of the community (without

    which there would be no politics).8

    While there is little doubt that acts of securitisation can take the exceptional character of war,

    the securitisation of societal issues in the EU and liberal democracies in general rarely (if ever)

    takes such an extreme form. Although the EU considers illegal migration a threat to the internal

    market, the securitising process to which illegal migrants are subjected is less intense than the

    metaphor of war suggests. In fact, to focus too narrowly on securitisation as an act runs the risk of

    ignoring processes of securitisation that stop short of this extreme point (Williams, 2003). For this

    reason, Hansen suggests that one should not just focus on the exceptionality of a security discourse

    but also on the ways in which these discourses inscribe subjectivity and identity: Security is notonly a speech act, but embedded in the production of particular subjectivities which then form the

    basis for what can be articulated as threat and threatened (Hansen, 2000: 306). In a similar critique

    Bigo has argued that it would be better not to distinguish too strictly between politics and security,

    8 Hence the Copenhagen school argues that securitisation is an exceptional discourse in which an actor by means of an

    argument about the urgency of an existential threat breaks free of the normal political procedures (Buzan et al., 1998:

    26, 25; see also Wver, 1995). Hence, various authors have observed that there are certain intellectual similaritiesbetween the Copenhagen school of security on the one hand and Carl Schmitts work on the other. See Huysmans

    (1998a), Williams (2003) and van Munster (2005).

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    7/26

    6

    normalcy and the exception. Rather, he points at the importance of determining the positions of

    authority from which a security continuum of different risks and threats are constructed and, in

    doing so, close off for alternative ways of framing the issue (Bigo, 2001).

    Nevertheless, the metaphor of war can still function as a useful analogy even for less intense

    forms of securitisation. For whether or not a securitising process reaches the limit point of war,

    security always refers to a situation in which the existence of the self is politicised as being

    dependent on the neutralisation of a dangerous other. Thus, while security need not always take the

    extreme form of war, the ordering function security performs is still the sovereign power of

    exclusion through which friends are delineated from enemies (even if their dangerousness is a

    matter of degree).9 Although the degree of exclusivity and the measures to counter societal dangers

    thus may vary, security discourses are united insofar as they mediate a politics of belonging that

    separate a sphere of trust between friends from the enemy who is thought to introduce fear, chaos

    and instability into the social order.

    Mediating belonging through practices of security thus impinges upon how a community

    acts towards itself and outsiders. Two things stand out. First, security radicalises the opposition

    between self and other by transforming this relation into a dialectics between friend and enemy.

    Although it is true that different group can exist alongside each other and interact in a meaningful

    way, the drama of security turns the other party into a threat or enemy with which there is no shared

    understanding or common symbolic ground. Indeed, when viewed through the lens of security, the

    relation between self and other looses its multiple dimensions and is reduced to an antagonisticrelationship of enmity. The transformation of the self/other relation into the friend/enemy relation

    turns the discursive space into two camps in which interaction turns into a zero-sum struggle for the

    good life (cf. Wver, 1995). To a large degree, this dynamic also underpins the EUs relationship to

    9 This is also illustrated by the war-related metaphors invasion of migrants, Fortress Europe, flankingmeasures,

    warorfightagainst illegal migration that are often deployed. Also, metaphorical links to other wars (e.g. Cold Warand Trojan War) are replayed in public discourses on illegal migration. For instance, migrants have been called a fifth

    colon and a Trojan horse.

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    8/26

    7

    illegal migration since the abolishment of internal borders and the development of the EU as an area

    of freedom, security and justice (see, amongst others, Huysmans, 2000b; Geddes, 2003; Boswell,

    2003). Here, illegal migration is mainly portrayed in negative terms as something that disrupts the

    proper conduct of freedom within the EU and, for that reason, needs to be restricted, controlled and

    deterred.10 This is well-captured in article 2 of the EU-treaty which defines that one of the core

    objective of the EU is to maintain and develop the Union as an area of freedom, security and

    justice, in which the free movement of persons is assured in conjunction with appropriate measures

    with respect to external border controls, asylum, immigration and the prevention and combating of

    crime.

    Secondly, framing migration in the negative terms of security increases the distance between

    self and other to the point where the very visibility of the other is enough to trigger a security

    response from the community that feels insecure. As Huysmans observes: Since the migrant is a

    threat because he/she is an alien, increasing the visibility of his or her alienness increases the

    presence of the threat (Huysmans, 1995: 64). Framing migration as a security problem thus risks

    becoming a self-sustaining dynamic in the sense that the production of security knowledge about

    migration renders the latter more visible, which means that new security measures are needed,

    which in turn will increase the visibility of the threat and so on. Looking at the EU, the framing of

    migration as a security problem seems indeed to have become something of a self-sustaining

    dynamic where the visibility of a threat triggers new security measures that in turn make the threat

    more visible. For instance, Boswell argues that despite more intensive attempts to control externalborders, the problem of illegal entry is in many ways far more of a popular concern in many EU

    countries than it was in the first half of the 1990s, before EU and Schengen cooperation had really

    gained momentum (Boswell, 2003: 102). Also, the continuous decrease in immigration since the

    10 Also, representing migrants as an urgent problem to the proper functioning of the internal market and the stability of

    the EU-polity more generally indirectly sustains the more openly xenophobic discourses on the far right (cf. Huysmans,2000b). While the European Union actively fights racism and xenophobia, the casting of migrants as a security problem

    can have the opposite effect, as it adds to the radicalisation of the self/other relationship.

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    9/26

    8

    1990s has not led to less control. To the contrary, at recent meetings in Tampere, Laeken and

    Seville the EU and its member states agreed to step up the fight against illegal migration, amongst

    others by making the question of illegal migration a key policy issue in the Unions external

    relations with non-member states.11

    Generally, these security policies are not articulated as a choice but as a necessary and

    inevitable response to the abolishment of internal borders. In this view, cooperation on migration

    and border control was born out of necessity, as what one could term a spillover from another

    area of EC cooperation: the Single European Act (SEA) of 1986, which set the goal of achieving the

    freedom of movement of goods, capital and workers between EC states by 1992 (Boswell, 2003:

    100). However, what at first sight may seem a question of security and necessity is in the end also a

    political question of who is allowed access to the social fabric of society and how society should be

    structured (Huysmans, 1998a: 570). To speak of migration in security terms is also to articulate a

    particular politics of belonging that risks imposing an organic conception of society in which there

    is no place for difference and alternative ways of imagining the good life. As a way of mediating

    belonging, security measures are by definition reactionary and conservative insofar as they always

    seek to restore the normal order of things. However, to bring things back to normal implies that

    political imagination is confined to the status quo as the benchmark against which other forms of

    political identification are judged deviant or even subversive. Security mediates belonging by

    distributing trust within society, but it does so at the expense of difference and ambiguity. As

    Constantinou argues:

    Securitization as a discursive practice works by synchronizing security, safety, and certitude. It

    depicts all three as co-temporal occurrences. To be secure is to be safe is to be sure. To secure is to

    protect from danger is to know the danger and how to go about doing the protection. This

    constitutes the security problematique automatically and exclusively a question of providing safety

    11 For example through readmission agreements, liaisons officers, VISA policy and the introduction of transit camps at

    the outer borders of the EU.

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    10/26

    9

    and producing knowledge. Thus [security] experts are able to continue with these totalizations,

    identifying threats in uncertainty, and confidently naming the enemy, assuming the endangered,

    and prescribing the deterrence (Constantinou, 2000: 288).

    However, unlike in pre-modern times the endangered can no longer be assumed. In the words of

    Rawls: We must abandon the hope of a political community if by such a community we mean a

    political society united in affirming a general and comprehensive doctrine (quoted in Mouffe,

    1993: 64). The Dutch political theorists Herman van Gunsteren speaks in this context of a

    community of fate, meaning that different groups with different historical, religious, cultural and

    political backgrounds have no choice but to live together and negotiate in a pragmatic sense the

    practical terms of their coexistence (van Gunsteren, 1998). This, however, presupposes a common

    ground between different groups and it is exactly this ground that the exclusionary logic of security

    denies to the other. Instead, security starts from the assumption that a harmonious society can be

    created if threats are hold at bay: The discourse reproduces the political myth that a homogenous

    national community or western civilization existed in the past and can be re-established today

    through the exclusion of those migrants who are identified as cultural aliens (Huysmans, 2000b:

    758). If one agrees, then, that securitisation is undesirable because it is a violent ordering practice

    that integrates a community through staging an existential threat, the question becomes one of how

    to challenge, re-order or simply desecuritise a society premised upon the exclusionary logic of

    security.

    3. Deconstruction and the Impossible Ideal of Desecuritisation

    Deconstructivists generally analyse security practices not as managerial responses to threats but as

    core practices through which units construct their identity. Insofar as desecuritisation seeks to

    unmake the security representations and the forms of belonging they give birth to, its objective is

    similar to that of deconstructivism, which is concerned with articulations of belonging that express

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    11/26

    10

    responsibility towards otherness. Therefore, from a deconstructivist perspective securitisation is

    considered an undesirable way of mediating belonging, because it contributes to the closure and

    naturalisation of a community at the expense of plurality and difference. The starting point of a

    deconstructivist strategy of desecuritisation would therefore be to argue for ways of identity

    formation that do not turn other human beings into a threat. In doing so, deconstructivists usually

    proceed from the assumption that binary divides such as friend/enemy, inside/outside,

    native/migrant, trust/fear, and Europeans/non-Europeans that structure Western metaphysical

    thought are not so much oppositions as hierarchies in which the first term is privileged over the

    second. The critical move of deconstructivism exists in taking sides with the marginalised side of

    the opposition in an attempt to overturn and transgress these hierarchies. It is important to notice

    that deconstructivists do not simply seek to reverse the hierarchy (as this would just lead to a new

    hierarchical relationship) but want to point out that the first term of the hierarchy can only exist and

    is always already contaminated by the presence of the second term. In other words, they seek to lay

    bare that the existence of the self depends on the negating presence of the other.

    The deconstructivist insight that identity requires difference has enabled them to expose an

    important paradox of security policy, namely that security policy seeks to secure the survival of a

    community by eliminating the dangerous other upon which the very identity of that community

    depends. In an oft-quoted passage Campbell eloquently expresses this paradox:[T]he inability of

    the state project of security to succeed is the guarantor of the states continued success as an

    impelling identity. The constant articulation of danger through foreign policy is thus not a threat toa states identity or existence: it is its condition of possibility (Campbell, 1998b: 12-3). Because of

    this paradox inherent to security policy, transcending a security problem cannot happen through

    framing the issue in terms of security. Both security and insecurity share the same logic and are cast

    in terms of the threat-defence sequence. As Wver remarks: Security signifies a situation marked

    by the presence of a security problem andsome measure taken in response. Insecurity is a situation

    with a security problem and no response. Both conditions share the security problematique. There

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    12/26

    11

    are obviously situations other than these, characterized by a-security or non-insecurity (Wver,

    1995: 56, emphasis in original).12 By pointing out that security politics cannot be the answer to a

    security problem, deconstructivists have sought to show that the critical task of security analysts it

    point out, in concrete situations, that only if it is recognised that security cannot be the answer to

    insecurity it will be possible to imagine less exclusive ways of mediating belonging.

    There is one crucial problem with the deconstructivist position, however. For while

    deconstructivism embraces the objective of desecuritisation, its theoretical maxim that identity is

    always constituted in the dialectics between two opposing terms which function as each others

    negation hampers them in reaching this goal. For if one accepts, if only tacitly, that identity is

    always constituted through an antagonistic relationship with the other, it becomes unclear how one

    can envisage desecuritised ways of mediating belonging between self and other (cf. Fierke, 2001;

    Hansen, 1997).13 Indeed, the theoretical maxim that identity always requires a constitutive outside

    logically entails that only the particular contents of a specific friend/enemy figuration can be

    questioned, but never the antagonistic logic itself (see e.g. Norval, 2000). If identity presupposes

    otherness, then every positive articulation of identity will automatically lead to the

    institutionalisation of a new, yet equally absolute, difference. Thus although deconstructivists are

    right to stress the principle openness of all articulations of belonging, they have so far not

    adequately theorised the reverse move from deconstruction to the decision as an ethical act. But

    without a theory of how to break free from the us/them dichotomy, there is nothing to guarantee that

    the deconstruction of a security story will contribute to political forms of identification that are less

    12 In his excellent 1985 novel The New York Trilogy. City of Glass, Ghosts, The Locked Room, Paul Auster makes a

    similar comment with regard to food (security) and eating (insecurity): Quinn learned that eating did not necessarily

    solve the problem of food. A meal was no more than a fragile defence against the inevitability of the next meal. Food

    itself could never answer the question of food: it only delayed the moment when the question had to be asked in

    earnest.13 Ole Wver (1996: 122; cited in Fierke, 2001: 119) observes in this context that [m]any [poststructuralist] authors

    including Campbell balance between, on the one hand, (formally) saying that identity does not demand an Other, doesnot demand antagonism, only difference(s) that can be non-antagonistic and, on the other, actually assuming that

    identity is always based on an antagonistic relationship to an other, is always constituted as an absolute difference.

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    13/26

    12

    exclusive towards the other (Wyn Jones, 1999; Wver, 2000). Thus while it is no doubt true that

    the deconstruction of security stories is a necessary precondition for desecuritisation and the

    repoliticising of belonging, it does not in itself provide a guarantee against totalising discourses of

    closure. Hence Derridas claim that deconstruction is, in itself, a positive response to an alterity

    which necessarily calls, summons or motivates it makes little sense as long as it is not

    supplemented theoretically with an account of how to bridge the gap between undecidability on the

    one hand and the actuality of a decision on the other (cited in Campbell, 1998a: 182). For without

    such a theory, deconstructivism risks getting caught on the abstract level of meta-politics in which

    its philosophical preferences for opening up and transgression are translated as something equally

    desirable on the less abstract level of politics (see also Wver, 2000: 283). Which is why Moran

    rightly objects that deconstruction runs the risk of appearing either as a critical Puritanism or as a

    series of empty, if largely unobjectionable platitudes (Moran, 2002: 125).

    Hence the deconstructive emphasis on the importance of undecidability as the necessary

    precondition for every decision needs itself to be supplemented with a theory of the decision if it is

    not appear either as substanceless cant or a new moral absolutism (Moran, 2002: 129). For if

    without the radical structural undecidability that the deconstructive intervention brings about,

    many strata of social relations appear as essentially linked by necessary logics, Laclau correctly

    observes that deconstruction in turn requires hegemony, that is, a theory of the decision taken in an

    undecidable terrain: without a theory of decision, that distance between structural undecidability

    and actuality would remain untheorised (Laclau, 1996: 59-60). In a similar critique, Critchley who agrees with Laclau that deconstruction is a necessary move againstclosure andforpolitics

    has pointed out that making politics possible is not the same as providing a politics. For him, the

    gap between undecidability and actuality points to the limits of deconstructivism as a political

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    14/26

    13

    strategy: Decisions have to be taken. But how? And in virtue of what? How does one make a

    decision in an undecidable terrain? (Critchley, 1992: 199).14

    Prozorov comes to similar conclusions. For him, the idea that any decision presupposes

    contingency and undecidability is not just lamenting the obvious; it is also problematic from an

    ethical point of view. For if it is true that every decision requires undecidability, 15 alldecisions are

    responsible and hence ethical in Derridean terms. Yet, since all decisions effect a closure of the

    radical openness of the perhaps, they are all equally irresponsible and hence unethical. As a result,

    deconstructivism remains frustratingly caught above the abyss of undecidability in the desire to

    refrain from the closure that every decision inaugurates (Prozorov, 2004: 13). What is needed,

    therefore, is not only a position (i.e. deconstruction) that highlights the impossibility of a decision,

    but also a theory that can affirm the decision as an ethical act in a radically undecidable terrain. In

    other words, the problem is that deconstructivism pays too much attention to the substance of the

    decision and less to the ethicality of deciding as such. Thus to move beyond deconstructivism, it is

    necessary not focus too narrowly on the impossible attempt to establish the fact of ethicality of

    decision, but on affirming the decision itself as an ethical act, whose authenticity is conditioned by

    going through both the traversal of undecidability and its closure. The ethical injunction

    concerns not the substance of the decision, but the responsibility for the decision as an act

    (Prozorov, 2004: 13). But what, more precisely, constitutes responsibility for desecuritisation as the

    act? If nothing conclusive can be said about the substance of such an act, then what does such an act

    look like? What form does it assume? In short, what does it mean to propose that a strategy of

    14 It is important, though, not to confuse undecidability (the term used by Derrida) with indeterminacy. Whereas the

    latter insinuates a relativist stance in which no decisions are taken at all, the former functions as the condition of

    possibility for decisions. Thus, Morans (2002: 127) comment that Derrida must constantly be amazed that anything at

    all happens is somewhat off the mark. It should however be emphasised that the value of deconstruction is located

    mainly in its ability to intervene in decisions that are already taken (and which are of course taken all the time) in order

    to interrupt attempts at totalisation and not in its ability to provide for an anti-foundational politics that does not need to

    fall back on safe ontological and epistemological grounds for its ethicality.15 According to Derrida {, #@}, even if a decision seems to take only a second and not to be preceded by any

    deliberation, it is structured by this experience and experiment of the undecidable.

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    15/26

    14

    desecuritisation should not just mark undecidability but also affirm and embrace the decision as an

    ethical act?

    4. Supplementing Deconstructivism: Desecuritisation as an Ethical Act

    In contrast to deconstructivist thought which explicitly separates the ethical (the unconditional

    injunction of undecidability) from the domain of politics (the domain of practical interventions

    which always fail to live up to this ethical injunction), the move towards desecuritisation as an act

    requires that we accept the inherently political character of every ethical act. An essential step

    towards a theory that can affirm the decision as an ethical act that nevertheless recognises the void

    behind every decision requires, first of all, a move away from the deconstructivist view of

    antagonisms as the concrete mediation between friend and enemy. The notion that there is a certain

    nothingness, void or undecidability that functions as the structural background for all decisions

    suggests that there in fact is a more central antagonism one that is not so much the result of some

    blockage by the other but of a radical negativity that is at the heart of the social order as such. The

    everyday security problem of mediating between friends and enemies masks the fact that real

    security is always an illusion. Insecurity is not a temporarily blockage to be overcome but

    constitutes the very core around which the symbolic order is structured (Edkins, 2003; cf.

    Huysmans, 1998c). Hence, the absolute closure of social structures is impossible not because social

    totalities are dependent upon the exclusion of the other but because of a central lack or void thatprecedes every attempt at positive identification:

    The big Other, the symbolic order itself, is barr, crossed-out, by a fundamental impossibility,

    structured around a central lack. Without this lack in the Other, the Other would be a closed

    structure and the only possibility open to the subject would be his radical alienation in the Other

    The thesis of Laclau and Mouffe that Society doesnt exist, that the Social is always aninconsistent field structured around a constitutive impossibility, traversed by a central

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    16/26

    15

    antagonism this thesis implies that every process of identification conferring on us a fixed

    socio-symbolic identity is ultimately doomed to fail (iek, 1989: 122, 126-127).16

    If the void is the domain of the political (the constitutive exteriority of the social order), politics

    consists of those discourses that compete with each other to hegemonise or fill this gap. Here

    security enters the picture as a particular way of filling the gap. The way a politics of security

    performs this function is through displacement. Security displaces the constitutive impossibility at

    the heart of society upon something outside it. In other words, processes of securitisation turn the

    original antagonism or void into a concrete antagonistic relationship between the sound social

    texture on the one hand and the enemy as the force corroding it on the other. Or as iek puts it:

    [I]t is not the external enemy who keeps me from achieving identity with myself, but every

    identity is already in itself blocked, marked by an impossibility, and the external enemy is simply

    the small piece, the rest of reality upon which we project or externalize this intrinsic, immanent

    impossibility (iek, 1990: 251-2).17 As a consequence, the elimination of an enemy does not

    bring about a more harmonious society free from the disturbing presence of the other. Rather, it is precisely in the moment when we achieve victory over the enemy in the antagonistic struggle in

    social reality that we experience the antagonism in its most radical dimension, as a self-hindrance:

    far from enabling us finally to achieve full identity with ourselves, the moment of victory is the

    greatest loss (iek, 1990: 252).

    16 Lacan usefully likens society to a vase that by creating a hole also creates the possibility for filling the hole, for

    making it whole: it creates the void and thereby introduces the possibility of filling it if the vase may be filled, it is

    because in the first place in its essence it is empty (quoted in Stavrakakis, 1999: 44). As any axiom, the notion that

    society is constitutively lacking can of course not be proved in any positivist sense. On the usefulness of this axiom for

    political theorising in general and critical theory more specifically, see iek (1989), Laclau (1990), Stavrakakis (1999)

    and Glynos (2001).17 The idea of an original antagonism also serves as the starting point for ieks (1999a: 29) critique of Carl Schmitts

    notion that the political is defined by the decision on the friend/enemy constellation: Far from simply asserting the

    proper dimension of the political, [Schmitt] adds the most cunning and radical version of the disavowal The clearest

    indication of this Schmittian disavowal of the political is the primacy of external politics (relations between sovereignstates) over internal politics (inner social antagonisms) on which he insists: is not the relationship to an external other as

    the enemy a way of disavowing the internal struggle which traverses the social body?

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    17/26

    16

    The ethicality of an act of desecuritisation, then, consists of a double movement. First, and

    this is the deconstructive moment present in the act, it requires that one comes to terms with the

    original void at the heart of all societies, which means that we need to accept that we never had

    what we were supposed to have lost. Hence we need to get to terms with the fact that the

    securitisation of illegal migration

    is an ideological fantasy about a society that still exists. Its logic is this: if society were not

    threatened or destroyed by the mobile immigrant, we would have a consistent, cosy, and non-

    antagonistic one is tempted to say happily fascist society. Is not this fantasy the kernel of the

    whole immigration debate? I wonder what would be left in the immigration debate if this fantasy

    were taken away. One is tempted to say: nothing! Though, if this fantasy is taken away, what is

    left is of course a series of social problems (Diken, 2002: 9).

    To face the nothingness behind every attempt to articulate a social order thus requires that one

    abandons the idea that the abject other is the positive cause of all social problems. It is a radical act

    in which one comes to acknowledge that there is nothing behind the ideology of security: security is

    just a screen covering the void behind it.18 Instead, it entails one identifies with the abject as the

    point of the political that reveals the truth about the social order. Rather than repressing the other as

    the abject that makes society impossible, we should, in a desecuritising move, identify with the

    abject. Or as Balibar puts it: [W]e must attack the obsessive question of collective insecurity by

    beginning precisely with the situation of the most insecure, the nomadic populations who are thesource of and target of the obsession with law and order that is so closely intertwined with the

    obsession with identity (Balibar, 2004: 177). A desecuritising act thus requires us to take sides

    with the point of negativity and to recognise in this point the true, concrete embodiment of the

    18 Hence iek argues that [t]he duty of the critical intellectual is precisely to occupy all the time, even when the

    new order stabilizes itself and again renders invisible the hole as such, the place of this hole, i.e., to maintain a distancetoward every reigning Master-Signifier The aim is precisely to produce the Master Signifier, that is to say, to

    render visible its produced, artificial, contingent character (quoted in Edkins, 1999: 118).

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    18/26

    17

    universal. In other words, in the current European context illegal migrants should not be considered

    a threat to be hold at bay but as representatives, the stand-ins, for the Whole of Society, for the true

    Universality (we the nothing, not counted in the order are the people, we are All against

    others who stand only for their particular privileged interest) (iek, 1999b: 188). The true

    measurement for the universality of a belonging lies thus not in an abstract ideal (a European

    citizenship in the name of freedom, security and justice) but in the way in which a community

    relates to its lowest part, i.e. the illegal migrant which is securitised and excluded as something

    abject. The only way to be effectively universal is not by imposing a Universal scheme, but by

    taking sides, by locating a concrete universality at the level of the abject that represents the void that

    subverts the positive social order.

    Indeed, to identify with the securitised other means to recognize in the excesses, in the

    disruption of the normal way of things, the key offering us access to its true functioning (iek,

    1989: 128). Whereas the objective of security is to establish a sense ofimmunity vis--vis the abject

    and excluded other, a politics of desecuritisation takes instead point of departure in the abject as the

    point from which to articulate new forms ofcommunity. Thus, in contrast to the security view of

    migration as an emergency that requires extraordinary measures, desecuritisation conceptualises

    migration as the advent oremergence of new political structures (cf. Edkins, 1999: 10). A politics

    of desecuritisation views the symptom as the point where the truth of that particular order is located.

    Hence the illegal migrant should not be understood as responsible for all ills of the polis or as the

    apocalypse on the move but as a symptom that precisely turns we into a problem, perhapsmakes it impossible (Kristeva, 1991: 1). By recognising that the securitised abject is the (w)hole

    that subverts the frame that sustains our understanding of a particular society as a whole, a

    desecuritising act is able to articulate new forms of belonging in an ethical way.

    5. Desecuritising European Belonging: Undocumented Migrants as the Point of the Political

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    19/26

    18

    An act of desecuritisation in the context of the EU, then, entails the identification with the

    securitised, undocumented migrant as the part that is considered to make the full constitution of a

    society impossible. The desecuritising move exists in turning the excluded, securitised illegal

    migrant to the place of the political figure per se, that is, as a constitutive force that can move the

    institutional scheme of belonging beyond the status quo. The desecuritisation of illegal migration

    does consequently not just address the particular demands of a group of people but concerns the

    metaphorical universalisation of their particular interests: the restructuring of the emerging

    European order itself. To desecuritise illegal migration is to link the question about the correct or

    responsible treatment of illegal migrants to the broader question of the way in which EU-identity

    and EU-belonging are constituted (cf. Huysmans, 2000a: 157). In contrast to discourses of security

    which seek to define illegal migration mainly in terms of a managerial problem to the functioning of

    the internal market, desecuritisation politicises illegal migration with the aim of renewing the

    fundament on which political struggle unfolds in the European polity. It is a political activity that

    seeks to constantly (re)articulate public space on behalf of the excluded.

    The struggle of the sans-papiers movement can illustrate this. Originally started as a

    particular French phenomenon, thesans-papiers movement took on a wider European dimension

    when the movement started to demand the regularisation of all the sans-papiers in Europe (cf.

    Hayter, 2004: 142-149). As Madgigune Ciss, one of the leading delegates of the sans-papiers

    movement argues: We demand our regularisation. We are not in hiding. We have come out into the

    daylight (Ciss, 1997). Through identifying with their position as undocumented migrants, thesans-papiers left behind their illegality to claim their place in the social order. In this sense, the

    sans-papiers struggle is not just about the responsible treatment of illegal migrants, but seeks to re-

    imagine the very foundations upon which European belonging is founded. For the political force of

    thesans-papiers movement lays not so much in its demand for the legalisation of illegal migrants;

    rather, the desecuritising force of the sans-papiers movement is located in their demands to be

    granted those rights precisely as undocumented migrants. In contrast to usual forms of resistance

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    20/26

    19

    and protest that claim that Nobody Is Illegal,19 the sans-papiers explicitly identified with their

    abject position (we, the illegal migrants, are the true point of universality!). Thus Ciss argues that

    the struggle taught us first of all to be autonomous:

    There were organizations which came to support us and which were used to helping immigrants in

    struggle. They were also used to acting as the relay between immigrants in struggle and the

    authorities, and therefore more or less to manage the struggle. They would tell us, Right, we the

    organizations have made an appointment to explain this or that; and we had to say, But we can

    explain it very well ourselves. If we had not taken our autonomy, we would not be here today,

    because there really have been many organizations telling us we could never win, that we could

    not win over public opinion because people were not ready to hear what we had to say (Ciss,

    1997).

    Confronted with a strict policing of the boundaries of European belonging, the sans-papiers fought

    thus not only for their inclusion, but also for their illegality to be embraced as the point of inherent

    exception/exclusion, the abject, of the concrete positive order, as the only point of true

    universality (iek, 1999b: 224, emphasis in original). In this sense, the struggle by the sans-

    papiers provides an important counterweight to the current organisation of belonging within the

    EU. Basically, the institutionalisation of European belonging is a top-down process in which

    European citizenship is assigned from above on the basis of belonging to one of the EU nations

    and on the basis of belonging to the European culture under construction (Martiniello, 1995: 46).

    Explicitly distinguishing between EU nationals (citizens) and non-EU nationals (also referred to as

    denizens or margizens), European citizenship contributes to the exclusion and securitisation of

    19 See for example the No One Is Illegal initiatives in the United Kingdom (www.noii.org.uk), Canada

    (http://www.web.apc.org/~ara/OTP/OTP20/noii.htm, http://www.ocap.ca/immigration/legalaid.html) as well as the

    Kein Mensch ist illegal initiative in Germany (http://www.kmii-tuebingen.de), the geen mens is illegaal initiative inthe Netherlands (www.defabel.nl/gmii) and the aden czowiek NIE jest nie legalny initiative in Poland

    (http://www.zcnjn.bzzz.net).

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    21/26

    20

    those who reside in the EU without documents.20 Indeed, insofar as European citizenship

    contributes to confinement of (especially) illegal migrants in their cultural alterity, Martiniello

    argues that only a successful mobilization of the denizens and margizens, together with the full

    citizens, that is a significant pressure from below for a new European citizenship, could bring

    about an extended breach in the nationalist logic and open the way towards post-nationalism in

    Europe (Martiniello, 1995: 49). A desecuritising act does exactly this: it seeks to create a space for

    the unrepresentable within presentation through the admission of negativity into the field of

    normality. To desecuritise illegal migration and to repoliticise European belonging does thus entails

    that one starts from outside the community, i.e. from those whose interests are not accounted for:

    Insofar as it expresses the movement of collective emancipation, the criterion of political

    citizenship is the ability of a polity to free itself from the forms of distribution and redistribution

    (accounting). It does not take as its objective the balance of profit and losses among those who

    already possess something but the constitution of a people (or dmos) that begins as

    nonexistent on account of the exclusion of those who are considered unworthy of the status of

    citizen (depending on the epoch and the circumstances: slaves or servants, workers or paupers,

    women, foreigners, and so on) (Balibar, 2004: 72).21

    20 There is of course a close interplay between restrictive immigration laws, increased border control and other security

    practices on the one hand and the illegal entry of migrants on the other. As Andreas (2000) shows in his empirical study

    of the American-Mexican border, policing in fact helps to create the very conditions (organised crime and the drugs

    trade, human smuggling, illegal immigration, etc.) it seeks to suppress.

    21 In his bookLa msentente, Rancire (1995) argues that the core of a democratic ethos is not just about the

    development of democratic institutions and procedures but, perhaps even more crucially, the suspension and subversion

    of these procedures on behalf of those who are not represented in the social order. According to him, the first true test

    for democracy appeared in ancient Greece where members of the dmos (those that fell outside the hierarchical matrix

    of society) demanded as those who are part of no part to be regarded as the point in which truth and universality

    were located. iek refers to another example: in the demonstrations against the communist regime in East Germany

    protestors shouted Wir sind das Volk!, thereby performing the gesture of politicisation at its purest they, the

    excluded counter revolutionary scum of the official Whole of the People claimed to stand for the people, for all; a

    couple of days later, however, the slogan changed into we are a/one people [Wir sind ein Volk!], clearly signalling theclosure of the momentary authentic political opening (iek, 1999b: 189). A last example this time from popular

    culture can be found in the animation movieAntzabout a colony of ants. Whereas normally every ant has its fixed

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    22/26

    21

    Balibar refers to such a citizenship as a citizenship without community, meaning a form of

    citizenship that develops in conjunction with what is outside (with + out) the community. As such,

    the implications of the sans-papiers struggle have the potential to impinge upon the very

    exclusionary foundations upon which the scheme of European belonging is constituted. Their claim

    is not a claim for an extension of belonging by widening the circle of citizenship and the rights and

    duties that follow from it; rather, it asks for a post-national form of citizenship that is not based on

    the principle of nationality but on residence and the freedom of movement for all people: We

    struggle for freedom of movement in its most concrete meaning, such as the ability to travel and to

    settle, wherever we wish to, without hindrance; because this struggle concerns also the refusal of

    social control which afflicts us all; whether or not we have papers (quoted in Hayter, 2004: 146).

    In contrast to the idea of a European citizenship as an abstract prerequisite for political

    rights, desecuritisation thus refers to the process whereby belonging is mediated in a continuous

    political process that recognises those who have been subjected to securitising processes as part of

    the public sphere of existence. What starts out as a particular struggle for a particular group can,

    through an act of desecuritisation, be politicised as a struggle about the future of Europe itself. For a

    Europe that is still in the process of becoming, the identification of the people with illegal migrants

    can radically redefine the universal scheme of belonging from above in favour of mediating

    belonging from below in the practical confrontation with the securitised other. It is to articulate a

    space in which belonging is not passively imposed upon an already present population; rather,

    belonging is negotiated in the concrete struggle for desecuritisation through which individuals

    actively contribute to the constitution of a European public space.

    6 Conclusion

    place in a colony, the film ends with a successful uprising of the worker ants against the soldier ants, while the workers

    exclaim: We are the colony!

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    23/26

    22

    This paper has sought to outline the contours of a strategy of desecuritisation within the context of

    the emerging European order. Moving beyond the deconstructivist writings on security, it was

    argued that the antagonistic relationship between friend and enemy is not so much an inescapable

    result from processes of identity formation, but a secondary move in which the void at the heart of

    society is displaced upon something outside it. Whereas security is by definition impossible due to

    the inherent openness of all social structures, security politics was represented as a politics of

    belonging that is structured around the fantasy that the other (the symptom of the symbolic order) is

    responsible for the disharmony and anxiety experienced by members of that community. Arguing

    that security is an undesirable form of mediating belonging, this paper has suggested a politics of

    desecuritisation as identification with the symptom. Rather than viewing migrants as responsible for

    all social ills, it was argued that they represent the point that gives body to the failures of the

    symbolic order. Within the context of discussions about European belonging, this paper ended with

    a plea for a European belonging without community, which implies to rethink the question of

    belonging from the point of the most excluded, i.e. the abject of the social order who are denied the

    status of citizenship. Because desecuritisation defined as identification with the symptom cannot be

    legitimised by the rules of the social order itself, it is by necessary subversive and transgressive.

    The point, however, was not so much to argue in favour of subversion and transgression for the

    sake of revolution. Rather, the aim is to illustrate that a more ethical relation between self and other

    can only come about if a community is able, from time to time, to incorporate the revolutionary

    moment, to put itself at stake and rethink itself from the point of the abject. Whereas democraticprocedures are important, perhaps the true test for a democracy is its ability to question itself and

    put itself at stake. Desecuritisation does exactly this and, at a very minimum, it makes us aware that

    sometimes true change can only come about as the result of a shattering experience of self-denial.

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    24/26

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    25/26

    24

    Edkins, Jenny (1999),Poststructuralism and International Relations. Bringing the Political BackIn, London: Rienner.

    Edkins, Jenny (2003), 'Security, Cosmology, Copenhagen', Contemporary Politics 9(4), pp. 361-???Eriksson, Johan (ed.)(2001), Threat Politics: New Perspectives on Security, Risk and Crisis

    Management, Aldershot: Ashgate.Fierke, Karin M. (2001), 'Critical Methodology and Constructivism', in: Karin M. Fierke and Knud

    Erik Jrgensen (eds), Constructing International Relations. The Next Generation, Armonkand London: M.E. Sharpe, pp. 115-135.Geddes, Andrew (2003), The Politics of Migration and Immigration in Europe, London: Sage.Glynos, Jason (2001), 'The Grip of Ideology: A Lacanian Approach to the Theory of Ideology',

    Journal of Political Ideologies 6(2), pp. 191-214.Green, Penny and Mike Grewcock (2002), 'The War against Illegal Immigration: State Crime and

    the Construction of a European Identity', Current Issues in Criminal Justice 14(1), pp. 87-101.

    Guiraudon, Virginie (1998), 'Citizenship Rights for Non-Citizens: France, Germany, and theNetherlands', in: C. Jopke (ed.), Challenge to the Nation-State, Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, pp. 272-318.

    Hansen, Lene (1997), 'A Case for Seduction? Evaluating the Poststructuralist Conceptualization ofSecurity', Cooperation and Conflict32(4), pp. 369-397.

    Hansen, Lene (2000), 'The Little Mermaid's Silent Security Dilemma and the Absence of Gender inthe Copenhagen School', Millennium 29(2), pp. 285-306.

    Hayter, Teresa (2004), Open Borders. The Case Against Immigration Controls, London: PlutoPress.

    Huysmans, Jef (1995), 'Migrants as a Security Problem: Dangers of "Securitizing" Societal Issues',in: Robert Miles and Dietrich Thrnhardt (eds), Migration and European Integration: The

    Dynamics of Inclusion and Exclusion, London: Pinter.Huysmans, Jef (1998a), 'The Question of the Limit: Desecuritisation and the Aesthetics of Horror in

    Political Realism', Millennium 27(3), pp. 569-589.Huysmans, Jef (1998b), 'Revisiting Copenhagen: Or, On the Creative Development of a Security

    Studies Agenda in Europe',European Journal of International Relations 4(4), pp. 479-505.Huysmans, Jef (1998c), 'Security! What Do you Mean? From Concept to Thick Signifier',

    European Journal of International Relations 4(2), pp. 226-255.Huysmans, Jef (2000a), 'Contested Community. Migration and the Question of the Political in the

    EU', in: Morten Kelstrup and Michael C. Williams (eds),International Relations Theory andthe Politics of European Integration. Power, Security and Community , London and NewYork: Routledge, pp. 149-170.

    Huysmans, Jef (2000b), 'The European Union and the Securitization of Migration',Journal ofCommon Market Studies 38(5), pp. 751-777.

    Huysmans, Jef (2002), 'Defining Social Constructivism in Security Studies: The NormativeDilemma of Writing Security',Alternatives 27, pp. 41-62.Huysmans, Jef (forthcoming),Insecurity and the Political. On the Political Significance of

    Securitising Migration.Kristeva, Julia (1991), Strangers to Ourselves, New York: Columbia University Press.Laclau, Ernesto (1990),New Reflections on the Revolution of Our Time, London and New York:

    Verso.Laclau, Ernesto (1996), 'Deconstruction, Pragmatism and Hegemony', in: Chantal Mouffe (ed.),

    Deconstruction and Pragmatism, London and New York: Routledge.Martiniello, Marco (1995), 'European Citizenship, European Identity, and Migrants: Towards the

    Post-national State?' in: Robert Miles and Dietrich Thrnhardt (eds), Migration and

    European Integration: The Dynamics of Inclusion and Exclusion, London: Pinter.McSweeney, Bill (1999), Security, Identity and Interests. A Sociology of International Relations,Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • 8/6/2019 2004 the Case for a European Belonging Without Community

    26/26