1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    1/32

    The Fallacy of the Latest Word: The Case of "Pietism and Science"Author(s): Robert K. MertonSource: American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 89, No. 5 (Mar., 1984), pp. 1091-1121Published by: The University of Chicago PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2779084.

    Accessed: 27/05/2013 17:39

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    The University of Chicago Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    American Journal of Sociology.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpresshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2779084?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2779084?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    2/32

    The

    Fallacy

    of

    the Latest Word: The Case

    of

    "Pietism and Science"'

    Robert K. Merton

    Columbia University

    The resiliency exhibited by some theories or derived hypotheses,

    despite

    their

    periodically

    "conclusive"

    refutation,

    is

    examined

    by

    taking

    the

    generic hypothesis

    on the

    connection between ascetic

    Protestantism and the emergence of modern

    science as a case in

    point. Refutations proposed in the Becker critique of the specific

    instance of Pietism and science strengthen

    rather

    than

    weaken the

    grounds for deepened interest in exploring both the generic and

    specific hypotheses

    insofar

    as

    the

    critique

    exhibits

    the

    fallacy

    of

    the

    latest word. That fallacy rests on three common but untenable tacit

    assumptions: (1)

    that the

    latest word

    correctly

    formulates

    the

    essen-

    tials of the

    preceding word while being immune to the failures

    of

    observation

    and

    inference imputed

    to

    what went before, (2) that

    each

    succeeding

    work

    improves

    on its

    knowledge base,

    and

    (3) that

    theoretically

    derived

    hypotheses

    are

    to

    be

    abandoned as soon

    as

    they

    seem to be empirically falsified. An Appendix examines evidence

    on

    the sociohistorical particulars

    of the case.

    Since it

    appeared

    in

    the

    mid-1930s,

    the

    hypothesis

    connecting

    Puritanism

    with the rise of modern science

    (Merton 1935;

    [1936] 1968; [1938] 1970)2

    1

    This paper was supported

    in part by a grant from the National Science Foundation

    (SES 79 27238).

    I

    am indebted

    to Annette Bernhardt, Karen Ginsberg, and, most

    especially, Alfred Nordmann for research aid and to Harriet

    Zuckerman, Robert

    C.

    Merton, Vanessa Merton, and

    Byron Shafer for thoughtful suggestions. Requests for

    reprints should be sent to Robert K. Merton, Fayerweather Hall, Columbia University,

    New York, New York 10027.

    2

    Begun

    in

    1933, completed

    as a doctoral dissertation in 1935,

    partly published in the

    form

    of

    three selected articles between

    1935 and

    1937,

    this monograph

    was

    fully

    published in 1938, appearing in Osiris: Studies on the

    History and Philosophy of

    Science at the invitation of

    its founder-editor and my teacher, the doyen of historians

    of science, George Sarton.

    The citation

    in

    my

    text

    expressly

    includes the 1935 disser-

    tation, "Sociological Aspects

    of Scientific Development in

    Seventeenth-Century En-

    gland," deposited

    in

    Harvard's

    Widener Library, although

    the Becker critique pays

    no mind to this earliest version of what Kuhn (1977, p. 115-22)

    and other historians

    of science have come to describe

    as

    "the Merton thesis."

    The

    reference to

    the

    1935

    document is intended as a reminder that this and the other formulations of a similar

    hypothesis in the mid-1930s (Stimson 1935;Jones [1936] 1961,

    1939) were independently

    developed and, to this extent,

    were mutually confirming rather

    than any one of them

    being derived from the others.

    (C 1984 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved.

    0002-9602/84/8905-0005$01.50

    AJS Volume

    89 Number 5 1091

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    3/32

    AmericanJournal of

    Sociology

    has

    been frequently

    assessed and

    elaborated. So far as

    I

    know,

    however,

    the

    article by

    George

    Becker

    (1984)

    is

    the first

    critique devoted

    to

    a

    derivative hypothesis briefly set forth in those same writings which pro-

    poses

    similar

    connections

    between

    Pietism

    and

    science.

    The

    Becker cri-

    tique

    serves several

    useful

    purposes. To begin

    with, it provides

    occasion

    for

    reexamining the

    substantive

    sociohistorical

    questions

    which

    it

    raises.

    It

    might also

    lead a few

    dedicated

    readers to

    examine the sources

    listed

    above

    (rather

    than the one

    article

    singled out

    in

    the

    critique) to

    see

    for

    themselves how far

    that

    critique captures

    the basic

    argument and its

    theoretical

    grounding.

    Beyond that

    and

    perhaps

    more

    in

    point

    for

    the

    rapidly developing

    sociology

    of

    science,

    it

    provides

    an

    instance

    of

    the

    workings of the institutionalized norm of "organized skepticism": social

    arrangementsfor the

    critical

    scrutiny of

    knowledge claims

    in

    science

    and

    learning that

    operate

    without

    depending on the

    skeptical

    bent of this or

    that

    individual (Merton

    [1942]

    1973,

    pp.

    277-78, 311, 339,

    467-70; Storer

    1966,

    pp. 77-79,

    116-26;

    Zuckerman 1977,

    pp.

    89-93, 125-27). In

    that

    regard, the

    critique

    affords an

    instructive example

    of the

    "fallacy of the

    latest

    word": the

    tacit

    assumption that the

    latest

    word is the best

    word.

    Elucidation of that

    fallacy,

    which has a

    way of

    turning up with

    some

    frequency

    in

    the

    give-and-take of

    cognitive

    disagreements

    in

    the

    domain

    of science and scholarship, involves the puzzle presented by the Phoenix

    phenomenon in

    the historyof

    systematic thought: the

    continuing resiliency

    of

    theories or

    theoretically derived

    hypotheses such as

    Durkheim's on

    rates of

    suicide

    ([1897] 1951) or Max

    Weber's

    on the role of

    ascetic Prot-

    estantism

    in

    the

    emergence of modern

    capitalism ([1904-5]

    1930)

    even

    though

    they

    have

    been

    periodically

    subjected

    to

    much and

    allegedly

    con-

    clusive

    demolition

    ("falsification").3

    These generic

    problems

    in

    the

    sociology

    of

    science

    provide

    contexts for

    examining the broad

    implications of

    the

    Becker

    critique.

    Instances

    of

    fundamental

    thematic

    relevance-such

    as the place of

    extrascientific

    bases

    in

    the

    legitimation of early

    modern

    science-will be

    considered

    in

    con-

    junction

    with the

    fallacy

    of

    the

    latest word and

    organized skepticism.

    However, Becker's

    specific

    charges of faulty

    readings of the

    evidence by

    the

    mid-1930s author

    of the work under

    examination

    will be

    considered

    3The

    Phoenix phenomenon

    clamors for

    systematic attention from

    historians and so-

    ciologists of science

    concerned to clarify

    the

    significant role of controversy in

    the growth

    of scientific

    knowledge.

    However, limitations of space and

    empathy for

    a

    fellow editor

    forbid analysis of that phenomenon here and now. For contextual observations on the

    social and cognitive

    structure, dynamics,

    functions, dysfunctions, and

    sociology-of-

    knowledge

    significance of

    controversies

    in

    science see Merton

    ([1961] 1973), Nowotny

    (1975),

    Markle and

    Petersen (1981), and Scientific

    Controversies, edited

    by

    A.

    L.

    Caplan and H.

    T.

    Engelhardt, Jr. (1984), especially

    the

    essays by

    Ernan

    McMullin

    ("How Do

    Scientific Controversies End?")

    and Everett

    Mendelsohn ("The Political

    Anatomy of

    Controversies

    in the Sciences").

    1092

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    4/32

    The

    Latest Word

    separately. Since these criticismslargely

    involve

    conflicting interpretations

    of German Pietist history,

    dogma, and practice that have long been de-

    bated by specialists, many may find them of remote interest despite their

    substantive relevance. For

    that reason, the specifics

    in

    Becker's

    bill

    of

    indictment and their rebuttals are

    sequestered

    in

    an

    Appendix

    of

    Socio-

    historical Particulars. It should be said

    that

    the

    Appendix

    took some

    doing

    by way of reassembling the

    evidence

    in

    point. For, as may come as no

    surprise, the author had failed

    to keep the abundant notes prepared for

    a

    dissertation (and the subsequent article and monograph) written half a

    century ago. (Still this episode

    provides

    an

    object

    lesson for

    others:

    do

    not discard library, field, or laboratory notes prematurely; socially or-

    ganized skepticism may operate imperfectly but it can work tenaciously.)

    Anticipating the substance of

    the Appendix,

    I

    must report that Merton

    seems

    to me to have been wrong on some details of exegesis and Becker

    right, while on other and rather

    more frequent details it seems to be moot

    or

    quite

    the other

    way.

    But when it comes

    to the

    fundamental thematic

    components of the hypothesis that relates Pietism to the emerging insti-

    tution of

    science,

    it

    appears

    to

    me

    that

    the

    critic

    is

    on the

    whole

    mistaken,

    not least as a result of having

    overlooked the basic theoretical contexts

    of

    the sociohistorical particulars.

    THEORETICAL CONTEXTS

    AND

    EMPIRICAL

    KNOWLEDGE CLAIMS

    The generic hypothesis under

    discussion holds that at a time

    in

    Western

    society

    when science had

    not

    become elaborately institutionalized,

    it ob-

    tained

    substantial

    legitimacy

    as an unintended

    consequence

    of

    the

    reli-

    gious ethic and praxis of

    ascetic Protestantism.

    In

    developing this

    hypothesis, Merton undertook to examine the linkages of 17th-century

    English Puritanism and science

    in

    some detail and went on to consider,

    as an

    empirical corollary, the possible

    linkages

    of the

    contemporary

    Ger-

    man

    Pietism

    and

    science.

    This

    extension can

    be

    described

    as brief

    if

    it

    is

    agreed that

    a

    total

    of

    three pages (Merton [1936] 1968, pp. 643-45)

    focused

    on

    Pietism

    constitutes brevity. It

    is

    primarily

    those

    three

    pages

    which

    have been subjected to the intensive

    Becker critique.

    The

    critique

    also

    considers

    briefly

    the four

    subsequent pages,

    which

    were given

    over to

    statistical data showing some

    proclivity

    for

    19th-century

    Protestant

    youngsters (not Pietists, since statistical data on detailed sectarian affil-

    iations

    were simply not to be had) to enter the science-and-technology

    oriented Realschulen.

    The

    paucity

    of

    these

    crude

    19th-century

    statistical

    data

    in

    contrast

    to

    the abundance of

    highly

    differentiated data on the

    religious, social,

    and

    economic

    status

    of

    students

    today

    has its own

    interesting theoretical

    im-

    1093

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    5/32

    American Journal

    of

    Sociology

    plication. It suggests that the enduring scholarly

    interest in the proposed

    ascetic Protestantism-science linkage cannot reside

    simply

    in

    that rather

    limited, empirically identified correlation between religious affiliation and

    interest in science. Much more controlled empirical generalizations are

    now so easily come by that a crude statistical report of

    this

    kind

    would

    presumably be given short shrift. It surely would not engender a detailed

    critique

    half a

    century

    later. There must be

    more

    to the

    hypothesis

    than

    the mere

    correlation-as, indeed,

    there is

    when

    one considers

    the

    theo-

    retical contexts of the inquiry instead of confining oneself to

    this

    or

    that

    bit of

    pertinent empirical

    evidence.

    The abiding interest in some empirical generalizations

    and

    lack of

    sustained interest in others stem from the logical location of the particular

    generalization.

    A

    continuing interest

    is more

    apt to

    obtain

    when the

    particular sociohistorical finding is grounded

    in

    a

    broader theoretical

    framework which has proved to be substantively

    instructive and heur-

    istically fruitful. This,

    I

    suggest, is the case with the hypothesized

    linkages

    among Puritanism, Pietism, and science. Yet, having cited Science,

    Tech-

    nology and Society

    in

    Seventeenth Century England

    in

    its

    very

    first sen-

    tence,

    the

    Becker

    critique manages

    to

    maintain

    a

    perfect

    silence about

    parts

    of

    that monograph, readily accessible since

    1938,

    which

    provide

    the theoretical contexts of those three pages devoted to Pietism. It also

    unaccountably ignores the author'spost-1936 indications

    of

    the successive

    levels of theoretical abstraction in the monograph

    that are set forth in

    books

    that Becker cites (Merton 1968, pp. 649-60; [1938] 1970, pp.

    vii-

    xxix) but does not fully utilize, as though amplifications beyond those

    three

    pages

    and the

    handful of

    pages

    on

    religious

    statistics

    which he does

    consider were somehow off limits.

    Owing

    to that

    neglect

    of theoretical

    context,

    the

    critique

    does

    not and,

    more

    important, as a matter of

    prin-

    ciple, cannot strike

    at

    the sociological jugular

    of the

    generic

    hypothesis

    linking religion and science. For a text removed from

    its context cannot

    be

    properly understood

    or

    paraphrased.4 As a result, the Becker

    critique

    can

    at the most correct a

    reading

    of this or that

    specific

    bit of

    evidence

    while

    managing,

    as

    we

    shall

    see

    in

    considering

    the

    fallacy

    of the

    latest

    word,

    to

    introduce

    questionable readings

    of

    other cited evidence and thus

    to

    produce

    an

    appreciated but basically modest

    revision of

    detail.

    4 To reduce, not to obviate, such inadvertent misrepresentations, this paper will quote

    relevant passages at length, since it cannot be supposed that readers will themselves

    uniformly turn to the quoted sources. Indeed, the presumption of general trustwor-

    thiness, rather than total freedom from error, underlies the system of organized skep-

    ticism in science and scholarship. Members of the scholarly community therefore need

    not confront the impossible task of individually studying

    for themselves all the sources

    of collateral interest to them. That function is assigned to peer reviewers

    and

    adopted

    by

    others

    having

    a

    specialized

    interest

    in

    particular subjects

    and

    problem

    areas.

    1094

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    6/32

    The

    Latest Word

    Levels of Theoretical Abstraction in Sociohistorical Inquiry

    Briefly summarized, three levels of substantive theoretical abstraction

    give the original study whatever sociological significance it may have:

    1. Least abstract level: the socio-historical

    hypothesis

    Ascetic Protestantism helped

    [n.b.]

    motivate and canalize the activities

    of men'

    in

    the

    direction

    of

    experimental

    science. This is

    the

    historical

    form

    of

    the

    hypothesis. [Merton 1968,

    p.

    589]

    A critically relevant context describes the logical status of such a so-

    ciohistorical

    idea

    in

    these terms:

    It would have been fatuous for the author to maintain, as some swift-

    reading commentators upon the book would have him maintain, that, with-

    out Puritanism, there could have been no concentrated development of

    modern science in seventeenth-century England [or, mutatis mutandis, with

    regard to Pietism and science in Germany]. Such an imputation betrays a

    basic failure to understand the logic of analysis and interpretation

    in

    his-

    torical sociology.

    In

    such analysis,

    a

    particular concrete historical devel-

    opment cannot be properly taken as indispensable to other concurrent

    or

    subsequent developments.

    In

    the case

    in

    hand,

    it

    is certainly

    not

    the case

    that Puritanism

    [or Pietism] was indispensable

    in

    the

    sense

    that

    if it

    had

    not found historical expression at the time, modern science would not then

    have emerged. The historically concrete movement of Puritanism [or Pie-

    tism] is not being put forward as a prerequisite

    to the

    substantial thrust

    of

    English [or German]

    science

    in that

    time; otherfunctionally equivalent

    ideological movements could have served to provide the emerging science

    with

    widely acknowledged

    claims to

    legitimacy.

    The

    interpretation

    in this

    study assumes

    the

    functional requirement of providing socially

    and cultur-

    ally patterned support for

    a

    not yet

    institutionalized

    science;

    it

    does not

    presuppose that only Puritanism [or Pietism] could have served that func-

    tion. [These preceding italics are added.] As

    it

    happened, Puritanism [and

    Pietism] provided major (not exclusive) support

    in

    that historical time

    and

    place. However, and this requires emphasis, neither does this functional

    conception convert Puritanism [or Pietism] into something epiphenomenal

    and

    inconsequential. It,

    rather than

    conceivable

    functional

    alternatives,

    happened to advance the institutionalization of science by providing a

    substantial

    basis

    for

    its

    legitimacy. [Italics added.]

    But the

    imputed

    drastic

    simplification that would make Puritanism [or Pietism] historically

    indis-

    pensable only

    affords

    a

    splendid specimen

    of the

    fallacy

    of

    misplaced

    ab-

    straction

    (rather

    than

    concreteness).

    It

    would

    mistakenly

    have the author

    undertake

    an

    exercise

    in

    historical

    prophecy (to adopt

    the convenient term

    that Karl

    Popper

    uses to describe

    efforts

    at

    concrete historical forecasts and

    retrodictions), even though the much less assuming author

    himself had

    only

    tried his hand at an analytical interpretation in the historical sociology of

    science.

    [Merton (1938) 1970; preface, pp. xviii-xix]

    5The

    reference

    to "men" sans women in this quoted passage

    is no inadvertent sexist

    statement; there

    simply

    was no

    place

    provided for women during

    the 16th and 17th

    centuries in what

    was known first as "natural philosophy" and

    later as "natural science."

    1095

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    7/32

    American

    Journal of Sociology

    In

    the light of this emphatically formulated

    hypothesis that ascetic

    Protestantism,

    ncluding

    Pietism, served

    to legitimatea nascent

    and

    slightly

    institutionalized science, it is passing strange to find Becker arguing at

    length, as though he were

    making a

    new, different, and

    opposed

    obser-

    vation, that the

    Pietists

    had a

    fundamental

    indifference,

    if

    not

    outright hostility,

    toward

    all

    knowledge,

    in

    whatever

    discipline,

    should

    it

    fail to

    display

    a

    perceptible religious

    con-

    nection.

    As

    Francke

    insisted,

    for

    example,

    "All

    sagacity, by whatever

    name,

    must have the honoring

    of

    God as

    its goal

    and

    purpose

    and it

    must

    employ

    all

    other means

    on

    behalf of

    this

    holy purpose" (in Heubaum

    1893, p. 75).

    [Can

    this be the

    archetypal

    Pietist

    leader Francke

    speaking,

    or is it

    the

    "'most representative Puritan in history,'"Richard Baxter (as quoted from

    Flynn [1920],

    p. 138, by Merton

    [(1938) 1970], p.

    60)?]

    In

    keeping

    with this

    dictum,

    virtually every aspect

    of

    Pietist

    education

    tended

    to

    be

    planned

    and

    legitimated by reference

    to

    religious objectives.

    [Becker 1984, p.

    1075]

    .

    .

    .To be

    certain, the primacy

    assigned

    to the

    religious

    motive was

    not

    entirely negative

    in

    its

    consequences

    for scientific

    education.

    The

    study

    of

    the

    natural

    sciences

    was

    justifiable

    not

    only

    as

    a

    means

    of

    promoting

    re-

    ligious

    conviction but also as

    a

    potential tool

    in

    the

    service

    of

    "good

    works"

    and collective

    well-being.

    Significantly, however,

    this

    same

    religious

    motive

    also

    tended

    to

    impose

    limits on

    the

    study

    of science

    and the

    quest

    for

    new

    scientific

    principles.

    The

    danger

    always

    existed

    that this

    study

    would be-

    come disassociated from religious concerns and that the fruits of such study

    would lead to scientific claims and

    knowledge

    incompatible

    with

    established

    theological

    precepts. [Becker

    1984, p. 1076]

    As for Pietist

    religious

    opposition to immediate

    "scientific

    claims and

    knowledge

    incompatible with

    established

    theological

    precepts," this pat-

    tern,

    too,

    has

    been noted

    concerning the

    great Reformers:

    Luther, Me-

    lanchthon, and

    Calvin. As these

    "attitudes of the

    theologians dominate

    over

    the,

    in

    effect, subversive religious

    ethic-as

    did Calvin's authority

    largely in

    Geneva until the

    first part of

    the eighteenth

    century-scientific

    development may be greatly impeded.

    .

    .

    . The implications of

    these

    dogmas found

    expression

    only with the passage of

    time"

    (Merton

    [1938]

    1970,

    pp.

    100-101). In short-and this,

    of course, is one of

    the principal

    components

    of

    the

    generic

    sociohistorical hypothesis under

    review-de-

    spite such

    immediate opposition to

    seemingly dangerous

    thoughts

    in

    sci-

    ence, the

    long-run consequences of

    the

    "sanctification of science"

    as

    exhibiting the "true

    Nature of the

    Works of God" and

    as

    contributing "to

    the

    Comfort of

    Mankind" became

    thoroughly secularized

    as

    the

    religiously

    legitimated institution and

    practice of science developed. That such sanc-

    tification can

    ultimately

    lead

    to

    secularization

    is

    precisely

    the

    sociohis-

    torical

    irony

    under

    examination.

    2.

    Middle-range

    level:

    dynamic

    interdependence

    of

    the social

    institutions

    of religion

    and

    science

    In its

    more

    general

    and

    analytical

    form,

    it

    [the

    hypothesis]

    holds

    that

    1096

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    8/32

    The

    Latest Word

    science, like all

    other social

    institutions,

    must

    be supported

    by values

    of the

    group

    if it

    is

    to

    develop.

    There

    is,

    consequently,

    not the

    least

    paradox

    in

    finding

    that even so rational an

    activity as scientific

    research

    is

    grounded on

    non-rational values. [Merton

    1968, p.

    589]6

    The

    theme of

    Puritanism-and-science seemed

    to

    exemplify the "ideal-

    istic"

    interpretation

    of history

    in

    which values

    and

    ideologies expressing

    those values are

    assigned a significant

    role

    in

    historical

    development.

    The

    [correlative] theme [in this

    study] of the

    economic-military-scientific

    interplay seemed to exemplify the

    "materialistic"

    interpretation of history

    in which the

    economic substructure

    determines the

    superstructure of

    which

    science is

    a

    part. And,

    as

    everyone knows, "idealistic"

    and "ma-

    terialistic" interpretations

    are

    forever alien to one another,

    condemned

    to ceaseless contradiction

    and

    intellectual warfare. Still, what

    everyone

    should know from the history of thought is that what everyone knows

    often turns out not to be

    so

    at all. The

    model

    of interpretation advanced

    in this

    study does

    provide for the mutual

    support and independent con-

    tribution to the

    legitimatizing

    of science of both

    the

    value

    orientation

    supplied

    by

    Puritanism

    [and

    Pietism]

    and the

    pervasive belief in, perhaps

    more

    than the

    occasionalfact of,

    scientific solutions to

    pressing economic,

    military

    and

    technological problems.

    [Merton (1938)

    1970, preface, p.

    xix;

    italics

    added]

    3. Most

    general

    and abstract level: the

    dynamic interdependence

    of

    social

    institutions

    A

    principal sociological idea

    governing

    this

    empirical inquiry holds that

    the

    socially patterned

    interests,

    motivations and

    behavior

    established

    in

    one institutional

    sphere-say,

    that

    of religion

    or

    economy-are

    inter-

    dependent

    with

    the

    socially patterned

    interests,

    motivations and

    behavior

    obtaining

    in

    other institutional

    spheres-say,

    that

    of science. There are

    various kinds

    of such

    interdependence,

    but we

    need touch

    upon only

    one of

    these here.

    The same individuals have

    multiple

    social

    statuses

    and

    roles

    [status-sets

    and

    role-sets]: scientific and

    religious

    and

    economic

    and

    political.

    This

    fundamental linkage

    in

    social structure in itself

    makes

    for some

    interplay

    between

    otherwise distinct institutional

    spheres

    even

    when

    they are

    segregated

    into

    seemingly autonomous

    departments

    of

    life. Beyond that, the social, intellectual and value consequences of what

    is

    done

    in

    one institutional domain

    ramify into

    other institutions, even-

    tually

    making for

    anticipatory

    and

    subsequent concern

    with

    the

    inter-

    connections of

    institutions.

    Separate

    institutional

    spheres are

    only partially

    autonomous, not

    completely

    so.

    It

    is

    only after

    a

    typically prolonged

    development

    that social

    institutions, including

    the

    institution of

    science,

    acquire a

    significant degree of

    autonomy. [Merton

    (1938) 1970, preface,

    pp. ix-x]

    6

    As early as the mid-1930s, even a logical positivist such as Rudolf Carnap would be

    writing, soon after the Merton 1936 article which he surely did not know, that

    "psy-

    chology and the social sciences . . . must locate the irrational [better: nonrational]

    sources of both rational and illogical thought" (Carnap 1937, p. 118). This is akin to

    the "Copernican revolution" in the sociology of knowledge which consists in the basic

    "hypothesis that not only error, illusion, or unauthenticated belief but also the

    discovery

    of truth is socially (historically) conditioned. As long as attention was focused only on

    the social determinants of ideology, illusion, myth, and moral norms, the sociology of

    knowledge could not emerge" (Merton 1968, pp. 513-14).

    1097

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    9/32

    American Journal of

    Sociology

    This condensed

    sketch of the

    successively abstract theoretical contexts

    of the

    sociohistorical

    hypothesis requires

    some theoretical and

    methodo-

    logical explication. It has, I believe, implications that extend much beyond

    the

    study

    under review.

    A

    Counterintuitive and

    Counterpositivistic

    Hypothesis

    First, it is proposed that continuing

    interest

    in

    the specific sociohistorical

    hypothesis derives from

    its being identified as a case

    in

    point of the

    varied

    nature of dynamic interactions between

    the institutions of

    religion and

    science

    in

    differing

    sociohistorical contexts. It

    is this

    middle-range hy-

    pothesis which was at the bottom of that inquiry mounted half a century

    ago. The

    hypothesis had a

    distinct

    theoretical

    interest

    all

    its own-back

    in

    the

    1930s, since it ran counter to the received

    positivistic lore

    of

    the time

    which

    declared

    as

    virtually self-evident that the

    principal,

    if

    indeed not

    the

    unique, relation between science and

    religion was

    one of

    conflict and

    clash. At least to

    those

    reared on

    such books with their

    positivistic

    titles

    as John W. Draper's

    History of

    the

    Conflict

    between

    Religion

    and

    Science

    (1875

    and many more editions, with

    translations into 10

    languages) and

    Andrew

    D.

    White's

    History of

    the

    Warfare

    of

    Science with

    Theology

    in

    Christendom (1896), it seemed improbable, if not downright absurd, that

    a

    religious

    ethic and

    praxis

    could

    have contributed

    to

    the

    legitimation

    and

    advancement

    of

    science

    which,

    it

    appears,

    was

    steadily

    engaged

    in

    undermining the

    dogmatic foundations of

    theology

    and

    religion. Witness

    only

    the heretical fate of

    Giordano

    Bruno,

    burned alive after trial

    by

    the

    Catholic

    Inquisition,

    and

    Michael

    Servetus,

    denounced

    by

    Calvin and

    burned alive after trial

    by

    the

    magistrates

    of Geneva. In

    good positivistic

    style

    of a

    parochial sort,

    it

    was no

    great leap

    from such

    exemplary episodes

    to

    a belief

    in

    the

    logical

    and

    historical

    necessity

    for

    conflict between

    religion and science in all their aspects.7

    The

    Role of

    Rationality

    in

    Emerging

    Modern

    Science:

    Pietism

    as a

    Strategic Polar Case

    The 1930s study

    undertook the collateral

    inquiry into a possible Pietism-

    science

    connection to

    supplement

    the

    fairly

    detailed and extensive

    inquiry

    into

    the

    Puritanism-science connection. As

    expressions

    of

    ascetic Prot-

    estantism,

    the two had much

    in

    common.

    Indeed,

    the

    17th-

    and

    18th-

    7Since this theoretical

    context is not being

    newly identified,

    the paragraph

    continues

    to draw on

    the 1970 preface to the Merton (1938) monograph.

    The legendary

    aspects

    of the life

    and mind of the

    Hermetic magician

    and

    scientist

    Bruno are handled

    in

    magisterial

    style by Yates (1964);

    Mason

    (1953) deals with the

    relation of

    Servetus to

    Calvin

    in

    connection

    with the new astronomy and

    the

    discovery

    of the lesser

    circulation

    of the

    blood.

    1098

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    10/32

    The Latest Word

    century Cotton Mather, the celebrated

    Puritan minister

    who was

    himself

    deeply devoted to

    the new

    science,8

    had noted the

    close resemblance

    of

    such Protestant movements, remarking that " 'ye American puritanism

    [is] . . . much of a piece with ye Frederician

    pietism'

    "

    (retrieved

    from

    the archives by Kuno Francke

    [1896], p. 63, and quoted by

    Merton

    [(1936)

    1968], p. 643).

    More specifically and more

    in

    point for the sociohistorical

    hypothesis

    under review,

    Pietism

    shared

    all but one of the

    elements of the

    Puritan

    ethos which had been taken to contribute to the rise

    of modern

    English

    science. Briefly itemized, these elements

    of Puritanism were

    (1)

    a

    strong

    emphasis

    on

    everyday

    utilitarianism, (2)

    intramundane interests

    and ac-

    tions (Weber's "inner-worldly asceticism"), (3) the belief that scientific

    understanding

    of

    the world of nature

    serves

    to

    manifest the

    glory

    of God

    as "the

    great Author of Nature," (4) the

    right and

    even the

    duty

    to

    chal-

    lenge various forms of authority, (5) a strong streak of antitraditionalism,

    all

    these coupled with the exaltation of both

    (6) empiricism

    and

    (7)

    ra-

    tionality. Albeit with differing

    degrees of intensity of adherence

    to

    some

    of these

    elements, the

    ethos

    of Pietism was

    significantly equivalent, except

    for

    the strong exception of an emphasis on

    rationality.

    It is

    well known that Pietism,

    in

    its various forms, was given to "en-

    thusiasm and irrationalism,"emphasizing "the emotional as opposed to

    the

    rational"

    (Pinson 1934, chap.

    1

    and

    p. 36). Thus, just

    as

    Quakerism

    and the later "enthusiastic"

    Methodism provided cases that bear on the

    relative significanceof rationality for an emerging interest in science within

    the

    English tradition, so, too,

    it was

    assumed,

    would

    "enthusiastic" Pie-

    tism as a weaker

    counterpart

    in

    Germany.

    Max Weber had

    made

    ana-

    lytical comparisons among the

    varieties of Anglo-American Puritanism

    and Pietism. For the immediate

    purposes of the 1930s study, most in point

    was his conclusion that "all

    in

    all, when we consider German Pietism

    from the

    point of view important for us, we must admit a vacillation and

    uncertainty

    in

    the

    religious basis of

    its

    asceticism which makes

    it

    definitely

    weaker than

    the

    iron

    consistency

    of

    Calvinism,

    and

    which is partly the

    result of Lutheran

    influence and

    partly of its emotional character"(Weber

    [1904-5] 1930, pp. 128-39, at p.

    137;

    italics

    added).

    In

    drawing

    on Weber's

    observations on this emotional element in Pie-

    tism,

    the Becker

    critique apparently

    fails to

    recognize

    that it is

    precisely

    this difference

    from many Puritan sects

    which made Pietism a strategic

    8

    "One of the persistent popular fallacies is the belief that the American pulpit, dom-

    inated

    throughout

    the

    period by New

    England

    Puritanism,

    was

    antagonistic

    to

    science.

    It

    was, on the

    contrary,

    a

    powerful ally

    in

    many

    instances.

    .

    . .

    Increase

    and

    Cotton

    Mather, the foremost

    American

    Puritans . . .

    labored

    earnestly

    to

    use science as

    a

    bulwark for

    religion,

    and in the course of this

    self-appointed

    task

    served an

    important

    educational function"

    (Hornberger [1937], p.

    13;

    for

    details,

    see

    Hornberger

    [1935]

    and

    the

    monumental volumes by

    Perry Miller,

    The

    New

    England Mind

    [(1939) 1954]).

    1099

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    11/32

    American Journal of Sociology

    polar

    case for

    examining

    the relative importance

    of

    rationality

    for

    creating

    an interest

    in science and for

    conferring religiously

    based

    legitimacy

    on

    the emerging science. In this the critique cannot be greatly faulted. For

    though the Merton study of

    the 1930s cautiously qualified

    the similarities

    between

    Puritanism and Pietism

    by alluding

    to the

    variously mystical

    "enthusiasm"

    of the Pietist

    movements,

    it did so much too

    sparingly

    (owing perhaps

    to the

    unimposed

    constraints of that

    three-page

    discus-

    sion). This it did

    in

    the following excessively condensed,

    imperfectly

    expressed, formally unexplicated,

    and therefore rather

    enigmatic

    for-

    mulation of the logic underlying the selection of Pietism

    as a

    potentially

    strategic

    case for

    comparison

    with the more

    thoroughly

    examined case

    of

    English Puritanism: "Pietism, except for its greater 'enthusiasm,' might

    almost be

    termed the continental

    counterpart

    of Puritanism.

    Hence,

    if

    our

    hypothesis

    of the association

    between Puritanism

    and interest

    in

    sci-

    ence and

    technology

    is warranted,

    one would

    expect

    to

    find the same

    [sic]

    correlation among

    the Pietists. And such

    was

    markedly

    the case"

    (Merton

    [1936] 1968, p. 643;

    italics

    added).

    With the wisdom

    of some 50

    years

    of

    hindsight

    and

    selective accu-

    mulation of knowledge (and,

    more dubiously,

    with the alleged wisdom

    of

    age),

    I

    am inclined to fault Merton's

    early study

    at this

    point,

    as Becker

    does not, in three related respects. First, the study could have emphasized

    the

    point

    that the element of

    rationality

    in

    a

    supportive

    religious

    ethos is

    evidently

    not a

    necessary

    condition

    for a derived interest

    in

    science and

    that the other

    elements

    in

    the Pietist ethos

    were robust

    enough

    to

    generate

    such interest.

    Second,

    it

    now seems

    evident that the cases of Pietism

    and

    Puritanism

    could

    have been compared

    in

    detail,

    at least

    in

    qualitative

    fashion, to

    assess the

    relative

    importance

    of

    differing

    intensities of adherence to each

    of the elements and to

    consider

    how each of

    these,

    as well as clusters of

    them, may

    have contributed differentially

    to the

    legitimizing

    of newly

    emerging

    science.

    Third,

    the

    study might

    have taken further advantage of the strategic

    polar

    cases to isolate the role of

    rationality

    in

    affecting

    the kinds of

    science

    that became of

    prime

    interest, instead of confining the

    inquiry to the

    question

    of an interest

    in

    the sciences

    generally.

    That line of

    inquiry

    (suggested

    to me

    by

    Robert C. Merton) would explore the possibility

    that

    Puritanism and Pietism

    might have generated interest in substantively

    differing fields of science and in significantly differing styles of scientific

    work. The streak of antirationalism

    in

    Pietism

    might

    have led to

    prime

    interest

    in

    the

    largely

    descriptive (rather

    than

    analytical)

    kinds of science

    advocated

    by

    Francke

    (cf.

    Merton

    [1936] 1968, p. 643,

    n.

    62)

    and

    might

    have led to a focus on the tinkering technical interest of

    the practical

    inventor rather than on work

    deriving in some deductive style from sci-

    1100

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    12/32

    The Latest Word

    entific theory.

    In

    contrast, the kinds of

    science

    proving

    more

    congenial

    to the Puritan ethos with

    its

    inclusion

    of an

    emphasis

    on

    rationality might

    tend to be, to put it anachronistically, of a more nearly hypothetico-

    deductive sort,

    in

    which

    experiment

    and observation more

    fully

    connect

    with

    an often mathematically expressed sequence

    of

    deductive reasoning.

    However all this may in fact turn out, that study of the

    mid-1930s did

    not venture to consider this kind of query about

    such

    possible

    conse-

    quences

    of the

    presence

    or absence of

    rationality

    as an element

    in

    the

    religious ethos.

    The Pietism-Science Connection as an Unintended Consequence

    Along with being a strategic case for assessing

    the place of rationalism

    in

    emerging types of "new science" and serving

    further to instance the

    perspective that rejects the positivistic view of primarily or wholly con-

    flicting relations between religion and science,

    the Pietism case held a

    third kind of theoretical interest. As was heavily emphasized

    in

    the mono-

    graph in which the pages on Pietism are

    embedded, the hypothesized

    relation

    between

    ascetic

    Protestantism

    and

    the emergence

    of

    modern

    sci-

    ence

    was largely an unintended consequence of

    the

    religious

    ethic and

    related patterns of action (religiously derived practice) instead of being

    only

    the

    result of direct and deliberate support

    of

    science

    by religious

    leaders (Merton [1938] 1970, pp. 79, 100-102, 136). This evidently

    held

    particular

    interest for the author since

    in

    the

    same

    year

    as the article

    "Puritanism, Pietism and Science" was published, he was also arguing

    that the unanticipated consequences of purposive social

    action (Merton

    1936) constitute a principal pattern of social and cultural change.

    As we

    shall see before we examine the differing

    readings

    of the

    specific

    historical

    evidence by Merton and by Becker

    in the

    Appendix, the critique

    fails to

    pay adequate

    attention to these

    (and

    the

    other)

    theoretical

    aspects

    of the

    original study which,

    to

    my mind, give

    it

    any

    but

    the

    most

    parochial

    descriptive interest.

    The

    result

    is

    that

    the

    otherwise well-mounted

    evi-

    dentiary critique reverts,

    rather more than is

    indicated,

    to some of the

    long-standing historical debates over

    the

    character of

    the

    varieties of

    Pietism and of its historical role. The neglect of theoretical contexts pro-

    vides one

    component of the fallacy of the latest word

    in

    scholarly and

    scientific

    controversy.

    THE

    FALLACY OF

    THE

    LATEST WORD

    The

    fallacy consists

    in

    the usually tacit belief that the latest word on a

    given subject

    or

    problem

    is

    necessarily the best word, at least pro tem,

    if

    indeed it is not the definitive, once-and-for-all

    word. Sometimes the

    1101

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    13/32

    American Journal of Sociology

    fallacy is committed by

    the author of the most recent

    word,

    sometimes

    by its readers,

    and sometimes

    by

    both

    in

    an

    unwitting complicity.

    If stated

    explicitly, it is a position that will not readily claim many adherents. Yet

    it has a way of turning up

    implicitly in the course of those scholarly

    controversies which arise regularly

    in

    accord with

    the

    norm and practice

    of socially organized skepticism.

    At

    a

    surface

    glance,

    there

    seems to be

    some merit

    in

    the

    assumption

    that the latest

    scientific or

    scholarly

    word

    is apt to be better than what has gone before. For once a theoretically

    derived hypothesis and

    its supporting evidence

    have been

    put forward,

    each succeeding work on

    the hypothesis can

    draw

    critically

    on the pre-

    ceding materials and thus presumably improve

    on

    them

    by

    rooting

    out

    previous errors and replacing them with new provisional truths. But, I

    suggest,

    that

    surface plausibility

    rests

    on a tissue of

    deep-seated

    and

    questionable assumptions.

    A

    first tacit assumption

    holds that although an author developing

    a

    hypothesis has misperceived, misinterpreted,

    or

    misreported

    the assem-

    bled

    evidence that invites or supports the hypothesis,

    the critic

    accurately

    perceives, interprets, and reports the

    text and the evidence under

    review.

    That assumption is manifested

    in part by the absence of overt signs that

    the critic is critical of his criticism,

    recognizing that it, too,

    is variously

    subject to the risk of faults like those attributed to the earlier text.

    As a case

    in

    point, the Becker critique confidently

    assumes that

    in

    "the

    investigation of sources" the critic's later readings are patently

    more ac-

    curate than readings dating from

    the mid-1930s. Thus the

    critique

    an-

    nounces that "although Merton's

    assertions have some basis in fact, they

    invite distortion because of factual inaccuracies, overstatements,

    and

    omissions

    regarding

    the

    overriding

    objectives

    of education as envisaged

    by

    Pietistic

    pedagogues" (Becker 1984, p. 1072). Here,

    and throughout the

    critique, there

    is

    not

    the

    least

    hint

    that

    the critic's own

    perspectivist

    readings and exegeses of the

    same texts might possibly be subject to

    distortion

    owing

    to "inaccuracies, overstatements, and omissions." Yet,

    as

    is

    suggested by

    the

    details gathered

    in the

    Appendix,

    some matters of

    fact and

    interpretation

    in

    the history

    of

    German

    education singled out

    in

    the

    critique are

    at

    least moot,

    with authorities by now somewhat worn,

    such as Heubaum

    ([1905] 1973)

    and Ziegler (1895), cited by both

    Merton

    and Becker, agreeing

    on some points and being at odds on others instead

    of

    uniformly supporting

    the position set forth

    in

    the critique.

    Since it provides a varied symptomatic instance of the hazard of er-

    roneous readings, damaging omissions, and questionable interpretations

    in

    a critique which is pro tem

    the latest word on its subject,

    I

    shall

    center,

    in

    dogged detail,

    on a

    single

    passage

    that

    deals with the

    sociological

    literature on the central hypothesis

    rather than with the historical

    liter-

    ature

    on

    theology

    and

    German

    pedagogy (which

    I

    examine

    in

    the

    Ap-

    1102

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    14/32

    The Latest Word

    pendix). Contrasting

    that

    passage

    in

    the

    1984

    critique

    with

    a

    related

    passage

    in

    the 1930s study also provides

    a distinct

    side

    benefit

    by collating

    the scattered paragraphs in Weber'swritings which deal with the subject

    at

    hand.

    I

    begin by turning

    to

    Becker's

    conclusion,

    where he

    writes:

    That Pietism failed to provide a

    powerful impetus

    to

    science

    is not

    nec-

    essarily inconsistent with

    Weber's

    observations

    on

    the relation of

    ascetic

    Protestantism and science. Indeed,

    while Weber

    in

    the

    conclusion

    of

    The

    Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of

    Capitalism ([1904-5]

    1930, p. 183)

    ten-

    tatively posited a

    link

    between

    ascetic Protestantism

    and

    science,

    he

    was

    nevertheless aware that ascetic Protestantism

    could

    also

    have adverse con-

    sequences for the

    development of

    science.

    For

    example, he wrote

    in

    General

    Economic

    History ([1923] 1950, p.

    270) that "the ascetic sects

    of

    Protes-

    tantism have also

    been disposed to have

    nothing to do with science, except

    in a situation where material

    requirements of everyday

    life were involved"

    (italics added [by

    GB]). This description appears to apply to

    German

    Pie-

    tism. [Becker

    1984, p. 1088]

    Once

    anatomized,

    this

    passage

    in

    the

    penultimate

    paragraph

    of

    the

    critique illustrates

    amply why the latest word need not be

    the best word.

    The passage exhibits some cognitive

    costs of the critic's

    decision to wear

    blinders

    by confining

    himself to those few

    pages devoted

    to the

    auxiliary

    Pietism-sciencehypothesis while wholly

    ignoring relevant

    contexts. Thus,

    we

    are told that

    the

    critique

    is

    not

    necessarily

    at odds with

    Weber's views

    since he "wrote

    in

    General Economic

    History"

    a

    sentence,

    which the critic

    partly italicizes

    for

    emphasis, declaring that ascetic

    Protestant sects "have

    also been

    disposed to have

    nothing

    to do

    with science,"

    except

    in

    a

    specified

    type

    of

    situation.

    The

    critic might have done well to

    attend

    to

    a

    cautionary

    note about

    Wirtschaftsgeschichte (translated by Frank H.

    Knight as Gen-

    eral

    Economic History)9 appearing in both the

    article and the

    monograph

    under review. He

    might

    then

    have hesitated to

    say

    that

    "Weber

    wrote"

    that sentence. He might instead have gone on to inform readers that this

    book of Weber's

    must

    be

    read with

    caution, particularly when

    it

    seems

    to

    contradict positions Weber repeatedly

    expressed

    in

    books he did write

    with

    typical

    care. For as that

    cautionary

    note

    observed,

    . .

    . it is

    surprising to note the statement

    accredited

    to

    Max

    Weber that the

    opposition

    of

    the Reformers is sufficient reason for not

    coupling Protes-

    tantism

    with scientific interests. See

    Wirtschaftsgeschichte(Miinchen, 1923,

    314).

    This

    remark is

    especially unanticipated since

    it

    does

    not

    at all

    accord

    9

    It may be of

    interest, and not only to

    present-day sociologists

    making

    critical

    sys-

    tematic use of quantitative and qualitative citation analysis, that Frank Knight (in

    Weber

    [1923] 1950) opens

    his

    translator's

    preface by

    noting

    that

    "Max

    Weber is

    probably

    the most outstanding name in

    German social

    thought since Schmoller, and a recent

    survey finds

    him

    the most

    quoted sociologist

    in

    Germany."

    Incidentally, Weber's ci-

    tations were being reported by

    the then young

    Louis Wirth (1926) writing a decade

    before his sterling translation,

    along

    with

    Edward Shils, of

    Mannheim's Ideology and

    Utopia. (See American

    Journal of Sociology,

    November 1926, p.

    464.)

    1103

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    15/32

    American

    Journal of Sociology

    with

    Weber's discussion of the same

    point

    in

    his other works.

    Cf.

    Reli-

    gionssoziologie, I, 141, 564;

    Wissenschaft als Beruf

    (Miunchen, 1921, 19-

    20). The

    probable explanation is that

    the first is not

    Weber's statement,

    since the

    Wirtschaftsgeschichte was

    compiled

    from

    classroom notes

    by

    two

    of

    his students who

    may

    have

    neglected

    to

    make the requisite distinctions.

    It is unlikely that Weber

    would have

    made the elementary error

    of

    confusing

    the Reformers' opposition to certain

    scientific discoveries

    with

    the unfore-

    seen

    consequences

    of

    the

    Protestant

    ethic, particularly

    since he

    expressly

    warns

    against the failure to make such

    distinctions

    in

    his

    Religionssozio-

    logie. [Merton (1936)

    1968, p. 634n; cf.

    slight extensions in (1938) 1970,

    pp.

    100-101n]

    That early

    cautionary note is itself

    incomplete. It

    might have gone on to

    observe that Weber himself had severe misgivings about these lectures

    on

    economic

    history and

    that

    unlike volume

    1

    of the Gesammelte

    Aufsfitze

    zurReligionssoziologie, which he did

    write, gather together,

    and correct

    in

    galleys

    during the last

    year of his life (Marianne

    Weber [1926]

    1975,

    p. 675; Parsons

    in

    Weber

    [1904-5] 1930; Nelson

    1974),

    he

    never

    got

    to

    read and vet

    the

    Wirtschaftsgeschichte since this text based on

    his

    last

    full

    set of lectures at Munich in

    that

    same

    year

    was

    reconstructed and

    published only after

    his

    death.10

    It

    would thus

    appear that that

    lone

    sentence from

    the General Economic

    History

    should

    carry

    rather less

    evidentiary weight than Weber's repeated and considered judgments to

    the

    contrary, from the time of

    the first

    appearance

    of the

    essay

    on

    the

    Protestant

    ethic in 1904-5

    to its final revision in

    1919-20 chiefly in

    the

    form

    of

    footnotes which,

    supplying

    new

    evidence

    and

    rebuttals to criti-

    cisms, run in

    their entirety to about the

    same length as the

    text itself

    (about 50,000 words

    each).

    And

    then, as

    though

    the

    critic were

    in

    collusion to

    help identify the

    fallacy of

    the

    latest word, this

    neglect

    of

    the cognitive status of

    Weber's

    General Economic

    History

    is

    coupled

    with

    other

    neglects. Nary a word

    is provided following up the references to Weberin the same ([1936]1968)

    passage

    and further

    quotations from Weber

    n

    which he

    states

    his

    tentative

    conclusions

    about

    the

    connections between

    early

    modern science

    and

    ascetic

    Protestantism

    generally

    and Pietism

    specifically.

    To be

    sure,

    Weber

    1o

    As the German compilers and editors-the historian Professor S. Hellmann and the

    economist Dr. M. Palyi-observed in their preface, "Even if Weber had lived

    longer

    he would not have given his Economic History to the public, at least not

    in

    the form

    in which we have it here. Utterances of his prove that he regarded the work as an

    improvisation with a thousand defects. .

    . .

    The situation just pictured set the task

    of the editors and made it a difficult one. No manuscript or even coherent outlines by

    Weber himself were available. There were

    found

    in

    his

    papers only

    a bundle of

    sheets

    with notes little more than catchwords set down

    in a

    handwriting hardly legible even

    to those accustomed to it. Consequently, the text had

    to

    be restored from notes by

    students,

    who

    willingly made

    their notebooks available

    for

    several

    months"

    (Weber

    1923, p. xvii). As we see, it was misleading for Merton to suggest that the editors

    reconstructed the text from the notes of only two students.

    1104

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    16/32

    The Latest

    Word

    did not examine

    the

    hypothesis

    in

    detail,

    concluding

    his

    classic

    essay

    programmatically by

    describing one

    of the "nexttasks" as

    that of searching

    out the "significance of ascetic rationalism, which has only been touched

    in the

    foregoing sketch,"

    for a variety of cultural

    and social

    developments,

    among them "the

    development of philosophical and

    scientific

    empiricism

    . . . technical

    development and . .

    .

    spiritual

    ideals"

    (Weber [1904-5]

    1930, pp.

    182-83). This

    programmatic statement is at

    least cited

    in

    the

    critique. But again, nary a

    word about the

    abundant citations

    and quoted

    indications in

    the 1930s

    monograph of how all

    this

    looked to Weber,

    especially after his

    comparative

    sociological studies

    of

    religion.

    One

    of the

    ignored

    references

    in

    Merton's

    cautionary

    passage

    on the

    GeneralEconomic History leads directly to this strong formulation: "Re-

    ligion . . .

    frequently

    considers purely empirical

    research, including that

    of

    natural

    science,

    as

    more reconcilable to

    religious interests than it

    does

    philosophy. This is the

    case above

    all in ascetic

    Protestantism"

    (Weber

    [1920] 1978,

    1:564, as translated by

    Gerth and Mills

    in

    Weber

    [1919]

    1946,

    p. 350).

    Furthermore,

    the

    critique

    has

    nothing

    to

    say

    about Merton's

    observation that

    scientists

    oriented toward

    ascetic

    Protestantism saw the

    study

    of nature as

    enabling

    a

    fuller

    appreciation

    of His

    power

    and cre-

    ation. By an

    extension of this

    religiously

    based definition

    of their

    role,

    "nothingin Nature is too mean for scientific study."Merton observes that

    "Max

    Weber remarks this

    same attitude

    in

    Swammerdam,

    whom

    he

    quotes

    as saying 'Here I

    bring you

    the proof

    of

    God's

    providence

    in

    the

    anatomy

    of

    a

    louse'

    "

    (Merton [1938]

    1970,

    104n, citing Wissenschaft als

    Beruf [Weber1919], p. 19). Here the

    1930s

    author of

    Science, Technology

    and

    Society, then

    writing

    the

    latest word on the

    subject, actually scanted

    Weber's

    position.

    Had

    he foreseen the

    1984

    Becker

    critique,

    he

    might

    have continued

    with the

    quotation from Weber

    who then went on

    to say

    apropos

    Pietism

    and science that

    "you

    will see

    [in

    Swammerdam's state-

    ment]

    what

    the scientific

    worker,

    influenced

    (indirectly) by

    Protestantism

    and

    Puritanism,

    conceived

    to

    be his task: to show

    the

    path

    to

    God.

    People

    no

    longer

    found this

    path among

    the

    philosophers,

    with

    their

    concepts

    and

    deductions.

    All

    pietist

    theology

    of

    the

    time,

    above

    all

    Spener,

    knew

    that

    God was not to be

    found

    along

    the road

    by

    which the

    Middle

    Ages

    had

    sought him.

    God

    is

    hidden,

    His

    ways

    are not our

    ways,

    His

    thoughts

    are

    not

    our

    thoughts.

    In

    the exact

    sciences,

    however,

    where one could

    physically

    grasp

    His

    works, one

    hoped

    to

    come

    upon

    the

    traces of what

    He planned for the world" (Weber[1919] 1946, p. 142).

    These, then,

    exemplify some of the

    pertinent materials

    wholly ignored

    in

    the

    critique,

    presumably

    as

    a

    result of the

    decision

    to confine

    attention

    to

    those

    few

    pages focused

    on

    Pietism

    in

    the

    1936 article

    (and

    thus

    to

    ignore also

    the

    somewhat fuller

    documentation found

    in

    the 1938 mono-

    graph).

    That

    decision

    entailed

    a

    thorough neglect

    of the

    theoretical con-

    1105

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    17/32

    American Journal of Sociology

    texts provided elsewhere in the article and monograph which, as I have

    noted, qualify and specify the generic hypothesis of the connections be-

    tween ascetic Protestantism and science by identifying the basic mecha-

    nisms, such as unintended consequences, rather than only direct doctrinal

    support

    that

    operated to provide those connections. Even so, had the

    critic read even the comparable handful of pages in the monograph, he

    might have had second thoughts about the position he imputes to Weber.

    For he would have found there Weber's virtually last observation on the

    matter-this, in the first volume of the Religionssoziologie ([1920] 1978,

    p. 533),

    which he had

    prepared for publication shortly before

    his

    death-

    to the effect, stated almost

    in

    the vein of the Pietist leader, Francke, that

    useful knowledge, exemplified above all by the orientations of empirical

    natural science and geography which provide a down-to-earth clarity of

    realistic thought and specialized knowledge, was

    first

    systematically

    cul-

    tivated

    as the

    purpose of education

    in

    Puritan circles and

    in

    Germany

    especially

    in

    Pietistic circles (as quoted

    in

    Merton [1938] 1970, p. 124, n.

    50).

    On

    this,

    as

    is

    so

    often

    the

    case

    with related

    matters,

    Troeltsch

    ([1912]

    1931, 2:958) is at one with Weber, writing

    in

    rather strong language,

    "

    '. . .

    the ideals of

    Pietism

    with

    regard

    to education

    are

    exactly

    the same

    as

    those

    of

    Puritanism.'

    "

    Finally, there is evidence that both author and critic are subject to the

    hazard of overlooking highly apposite materials. Merton ([1938] 1970, p.

    59) quotes only a smidgen

    of

    what

    is

    perhaps

    Weber's

    strongest and

    most

    instructive passage on the complex relation between Pietism

    and

    science,

    while Becker

    (1984) says nothing at

    all about

    it.

    The Weber observations

    call

    for

    full

    quotation

    in accord with the

    policy plainly being adopted

    here of quoting key passages at some length in order to avoid the second-

    order hazards of excessively brief paraphrases,which

    can

    easily contribute

    to

    the misinterpretations and misunderstandings that keep

    the

    latest crit-

    ical

    word from being necessarily the best word on a subject, hypothesis,

    or

    conjecture.

    In

    one of those

    long footnotes,

    Weber once

    again

    disowns

    any intention

    of

    conducting

    a

    detailed investigation

    but

    nevertheless

    man-

    ages

    to

    say

    much

    in

    little:

    The decided propensity

    of

    Protestant asceticism

    for

    empiricism,

    rationalized

    on

    a

    mathematical

    basis,

    is

    well

    known,

    but cannot be further

    analyzed

    here....

    For the attitude of Protestant asceticism

    the

    decisive

    point

    was,

    as

    may perhaps

    be most

    clearly

    seen

    in

    [the Pietist] Spener's Theologische

    Bedenken I, p. 232; III, p. 260, that just as the Christian is known by the

    fruits

    of his

    belief,

    the

    knowledge

    of

    God and

    His

    designs

    can

    only

    be

    attained

    through

    a

    knowledge

    of

    His

    works.

    The

    favourite

    science

    of

    all

    Puritan, Baptist,

    or

    Pietist

    Christianity

    was thus

    physics,

    and next

    to

    it

    all those other natural sciences

    which used

    a

    similar

    method, especially

    mathematics.

    It

    was

    hopedfrom

    the

    empirical knowledge of

    the

    divine laws

    of

    nature

    to ascend to a

    grasp of

    the

    essence

    of

    the

    world,

    which

    on

    account

    1106

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    18/32

    The

    Latest Word

    of the

    fragmentary nature

    of

    the divine revelation, a Calvinistic

    idea,

    could

    never be attained by the

    method of metaphysical speculation. The empir-

    icism

    of the seventeenth century was the means for asceticism to see God

    in

    nature. It seemed to lead to God, philosophical

    speculation away from

    Him.

    In

    particular Spener considers the Aristotelean

    philosophy to have

    been the most harmful

    element

    in

    Christian tradition.

    . .

    . The

    significance

    of

    this attitude

    of

    ascetic

    Protestantism

    for

    the development

    of

    education,

    especially technical education, is well known." Combined with

    the attitude

    tofides

    implicita they furnished

    a pedagogical programme. [Weber (1920),

    1:141-42, as translated by

    Talcott Parsons

    in

    Weber ([1904-5] 1930), p.

    249, n.

    145;

    italics

    added]

    Once

    the

    fallacy

    of the latest

    word

    is

    explicitly recognized

    as a

    distinct

    hazard, even in critical accounts of the most civil variety (such as the

    Becker

    critique), that recognition can serve as a prophylaxis

    against a

    second

    assumption underlying the fallacy. That is the

    assumption of an

    inexorable, unilinear progress in knowledge, despite minor

    and temporary

    fluctuations in it.

    Such

    an

    assumption

    of

    steady cognitive

    progress

    holds

    that

    each

    succeeding

    work

    improves

    on what has

    gone before, since

    it

    profits from that prior knowledge

    base. This is one of

    those half-truths

    which,

    especially

    when it remains

    tacit,

    leads

    to

    the naive belief in a

    steady unilinear rather than

    in

    a

    variously

    selective and uneven cumu-

    lation of scientific knowledge. This conception of progress is of a kind

    that was

    being emphatically

    rejected

    in the

    very sociological circles

    in

    which the mid-1930s hypotheses on

    ascetic

    Protestantism

    and

    science

    were

    being

    developed

    in

    detail.

    Perhaps the most

    emphatic

    sociological

    voice of the time

    energetically

    repudiating the naive versions of

    unilinear progress

    in

    knowledge

    was

    Pitirim

    Sorokin's, most particularly in the massive four volumes of his

    Social and Cultural

    Dynamics

    (1937). Assisting

    Sorokin

    in

    exploring

    the

    rival

    hypotheses of fluctuations

    and oscillations

    in the

    historical devel-

    opment of science, the author of "Puritanism, Pietism and Science" traced

    the

    cyclical

    vicissitudes

    of such

    scientific ideas as vitalism,

    mechanism,

    and

    abiogenesis

    in

    biology; wave and corpuscular theories

    of

    light

    in

    physics;

    and cosmogonic theories

    (Sorokin

    and Merton

    1937, chap. 12).

    Of most

    immediate interest

    is the

    observation

    appearing

    in

    the

    original

    protocol by the junior author

    stating with regard

    to the

    fluctuation

    of

    atomic

    doctrines that

    various

    theories "rose and

    gathered

    a

    power

    im-

    "

    The phrase "is well known,"

    here and in

    the first sentence of Weber's long footnote,

    tantalizes rather than informs. The allusion may be to the writings of Troeltsch, but

    it hints at a rather wider scholarly consensus on the posited

    connections

    between

    ascetic Protestantism and science. Perhaps this impression that

    those connections were

    well established and well understood

    lay behind Weber's recurrent disclaimer in his

    sociology of religion; e.g., "We

    cannot

    speak

    here of the

    significance

    [of

    Puritanism]

    for the

    development

    of

    technology

    and natural science"

    (as quoted

    by

    Merton

    1(1938)

    1970], p. 59, n. 9).

    1107

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    19/32

    American Journal of Sociology

    pressive enough to

    be

    accepted as the

    'last word

    of

    science' by the leading

    scientists

    or

    thinkers

    of the

    period.

    At other

    periods they declined and

    sometimes practically disappeared" (p. 445).

    Still, though

    awareness of the

    fallacy

    of the latest

    word

    can

    guard

    against

    a

    naive

    assumption

    of

    steady

    progress

    in which all

    that follows

    improves on what precedes,

    it

    need not

    lead

    us to the

    opposite

    error

    of

    denying

    the selective and uneven

    accumulation of

    various kinds of sci-

    entific knowledge over the centuries.

    To

    discard

    the

    Comtean and

    later

    Edwardian faith

    in

    unyielding intellectual

    progress

    in

    science and

    tech-

    nology does

    not

    require

    us to

    deny

    the

    patent

    advancement of such knowl-

    edge, despite

    all its

    intervening errors, garden

    paths,

    and

    misconceptions.

    To put it concretely, the beautiful Greek mythology could summon up no

    more scientific and technological imagination than to endow the doomed

    Icarus with wings of feathers and wax. And

    though

    we

    may

    not like

    the

    noisy Concorde,

    we must concede that it derives from

    a

    somewhat better

    knowledge of aerodynamics than that.U Still,

    all

    this represents only the

    result of selective accumulation

    of

    knowledge,

    a

    conception

    that allows

    for

    error, misinterpretations, and

    misattributions

    in

    particular

    cases. This

    is consequently remote

    from

    the fallacy of

    assuming

    that

    the latest

    word

    need be

    the

    best and most reliable word.

    A third often tacit but

    sometimes explicit

    premise making

    for the

    fallacy

    of

    the latest word holds that

    a

    hypothesis

    or

    underlying theory

    is

    obviously

    to be

    abandoned as

    soon as

    it appears to have

    been

    empirically

    falsified.

    At the

    extreme,

    this

    premise

    maintains that a

    single counterexample jus-

    tifies

    rejection

    of

    a

    hypothesis.

    Were this

    so

    in actual

    practice,

    as

    distinct

    from certain

    epistemological doctrines,

    the

    mortality

    rate of

    scientific

    ideas, high as it is, would rise

    dramatically.

    But

    the

    critical

    pragmatism

    which

    commonly

    obtains in actual scientific

    practice

    seldom

    operates

    in

    such strong terms of easy falsification. Decades after the beginnings of

    Karl

    Popper's ([1934] 1959; 1963; 1972) powerful and evolving doctrine

    of

    falsification,

    the fundamental

    question

    still

    endures:

    When are

    we

    to

    retain a hypothesis or theoretical conception in the face of facts that seem

    to

    refute

    it?

    In

    short,

    when are we to trust the

    governing idea; when,

    the

    contravening

    "fact"?

    Or,

    as

    applied

    to

    the case

    in

    point,

    does the Becker

    critique require

    us to

    reject

    or

    severely modify

    the

    hypothesis

    of the

    Pietism-science connection as

    tentatively derived

    from

    the generic hy-

    pothesis

    of

    the ascetic Protestantism

    hypothesis?

    This appearsto be an instance in which both the generic andthe specific

    12

    For the welter of recent doctrines

    on scientific

    progress, see, among much else,

    Lakatos (1978); Kuhn (1977), esp.

    chap. 11; Laudan

    (1977); Elkana (1981), pp. 53-

    54. None of these

    deny the palpable

    facts of progress in science

    but

    they variously

    construe its

    character, forms, and mechanisms.

    For

    myself,

    the

    processes

    of selective

    accumulation of scientific

    knowledge provide no basis

    for the kind of inexorable pro-

    gressivism implicit in the fallacy

    of the latest word.

    1108

    This content downloaded from 79.175.121.210 on Mon, 27 May 2013 17:39:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 1984 - The Fallacy of the Latest Word. the Case of 'Pietism and Science'

    20/32

    The Latest Word

    hypotheses continue to remain on probation in the

    sense

    that all such

    interpretations must be

    considered provisional.

    This

    is

    so in

    the light of

    what the differentiated methodological doctrine of Lakatos (1978, 1:8-

    138)

    describes as "sophisticated"ratherthan "naive

    falsification" and

    also

    because

    the questioned evidence in

    this

    case is

    largely

    either

    peripheral

    to the

    hypothesis or, more important, is still on trial

    among specialists.

    Limitations of space preclude an

    attempt to reconstructLakatos's complex

    and detailed argument here (the omission